Forecasting Subjective Influences on the Learning Sciences by Way of a Historical Analysis of Mental...

Post on 25-Feb-2023

4 views 0 download

Transcript of Forecasting Subjective Influences on the Learning Sciences by Way of a Historical Analysis of Mental...

Running head: FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES 1

Forecasting Subjective Influences on the Learning Sciences

by Way of a Historical Analysis of Mental Testing and John Dewey

Scott Kabel

University at Buffalo

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES2

Introduction

R. Keith Sawyer edited and contributed to The Cambridge

Handbook of The Learning Sciences (The Handbook), recently in its third

edition, an introductory primer to a young and exciting

collective vision, the Learning Sciences. The “Learning

[S]ciences is an interdisciplinary field that studies teaching

and learning” (Sawyer, 2006, p. xi). Undoubtedly, the operative

word here is interdisciplinary. The Learning Sciences provides a

dialogic, iterative space in which scholars from “cognitive

science, educational psychology, computer science, anthropology,

sociology, information sciences, neurosciences, education, design

studies, instructional design, and other fields” can inform each

other’s work, investigating each layer of learning, concrete,

abstract, physical, social, emotional, micro, macro, etc. (p.

xi).

“Learning scientists study learning in a variety of

settings, including not only the more formal learning of school

classrooms but also the informal learning that takes place at

home, on the job, and among peers” (p. xi). These researchers and

practitioners often champion adaptive research models such as

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES3

design-based research and action research, indicating an

understanding of the real-world complexities of human-subject

research. “The goal of the learning sciences is to better

understand the cognitive and social processes that result in the

most effective learning” (p. xi). However, beyond knowledge

synthesis, crucial to the purposes of the Learning Sciences is a

sense of value-addedness and the practical implementation of

Learning Science knowledge in learning environments “so that

people learn more deeply and more effectively” (p. xi).

If the form of the Learning Sciences is essentially fresh,

first taking shape in 1991, many of the goals and foundational

principles and values of the cooperative are not. Nearly as

common as references to cutting edge technological tools and the

latest neuroscience in The Handbook are references to Classical,

Enlightenment and Progressive Era thinkers. The Learning Sciences

is a truly inclusive and expansive blend of ideas and

experiences. However, it is this historical inclusivity that

leads to more questions. Why is it that collaboration feels

fresh? Why were some useful ideas not taken up during the

historical moments in which they were proposed, necessitating

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES4

modern excavation? Why are some historical voices louder in

today’s science of learning than others?

In reality, the Learning Sciences cannot presume to concern

itself only with science. This paper will show that science does

not exist in a political vacuum. Power, ideology, and money can

be as operative in “science” as statistics, surveys, and

discourse analysis. To illustrate this point, I will consider the

treatment of John Dewey’s work in The Handbook with respect to the

ethos and climate into which it was initially introduced,

particularly in relation the work of eugenicists in the creation

and popularization of mental testing. By taking up Dewey and

analyzing the countervailing forces of the Progressive Era and

its legacy, not only is the vetting and unraveling of today’s

American educational system that lie before the Learning Sciences

better framed, but also becomes apparent the necessity to cast a

critical eye over the Learning Sciences in order to ascertain

what and to what extent subjectivities are influencing its

mission and practice today.

The Dewey of the Learning Sciences

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES5

It is clear that the Learning Sciences has taken up and

triangulated important educational insights theorized by Dewey,

as Dewey is reference throughout The Handbook. Dewey understood,

according to Stahl, Koschmann, and Suthers, that education is

more than an “event in which knowledge is inscribed in an

individual mind” or more than the unloading of discreet packages

of information from one mind to another (p. 416). Learning is a

complex, recursive process of interaction with one’s environment

in meaningful ways. This is the main reason that, as Greeno

observed, unlike many of his contemporaries who were “focused on

individuals”, Dewey was concerned with “larger systems” (p. 79).

Individuals exist in living ecosystems of knowledge, communities

of practice, and multilayered environments. A natural outgrowth

of this initial focal point is situated learning, which has been

warmly embraced by the Learning Sciences.

Situated or situative learning, described by Collins as

“having students carry out tasks and solve problems in an

environment that reflects the nature of such tasks in the world,”

was an approach Dewey employed in his Laboratory School. He did

so, in once instance, “by having the students design and build a

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES6

clubhouse, a task that emphasizes arithmetic and planning skills”

(p. 52). As already mentioned, Dewey understood that knowledge is

created by interacting meaningfully with one’s environment. It

follows that the construction of knowledge is largely dependent

on one’s environment, hence the value of situative learning.

Naturally, writes Greeno, “this kind of practice … is a major

focus of learning sciences research and practice” (p. 92).

By learning in context, which typically includes

collaboration (as in the building of the clubhouse), two outcomes

are likely to occur that have become important strands within the

Learning Sciences. First, the individual student is likely to

become engaged. Krajcik and Blumenfeld point out that “Dewey

argued that students will develop personal investment in the

material if they engage in real, meaningful tasks and problems

that emulate what experts do in real-world situations” (p. 318).

When the spotlight turns to engagement, the threads of

motivation, affect, and acculturation become self-evident and

operationalized—these are themes that are also considered

throughout The Handbook. Certainly, when students can maintain

autonomy, for instance, engagement and interest rise. Krajcik and

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES7

Blumenfeld continue, crediting Dewey: “In the last two decades,

learning sciences researchers have refined and elaborated Dewey’s

original insight that active inquiry results in deeper

understanding” (p. 318).

The second outcome involves becoming an active, engaged

member of a learning community and, eventually, the broader

circle of society. Bruckman quotes Dewey, who posits that

“education is not preparation for life; education is life itself”

(p. 461). There is nothing superficial or artificial about a

student’s opportunity of belonging to and learning situatively

within a community. This is genuine citizenship, albeit on a

small scale. Illuminating Dewey’s statement, Bruckman writes that

“Dewey argued that learning communities should not be a world

apart, but instead integrated with the rest of society. Students

should be encouraged to be a part of civil society, pursuing

interests in collaboration with others” (p. 461). What Dewey and

the Learning Sciences offer the student is an opportunity for

autonomous, meaningful involvement in civil life by not only

activating deep learning that draws on a student’s own

experiences and interests, but by empowering the student to

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES8

inject those same experiences into a community on the student’s

terms. The democratic empowerment of students that Dewey dreamed

of has been expressed by the Learning Sciences simply as

effective teaching.

Possibly the most substantial of Dewey’s philosophical

contributions to the Learning Sciences composes both the germ of

individual knowledge and the nature of collective knowledge: “A

theory corresponds to the facts when it leads us to the facts

which are its consequences, by the intermediary of experience …

but they are always subject to being corrected by unforeseen

future consequences or by observed facts that had been

disregarded” (as cited on p. 139). In other words, for Dewey

knowledge is neither complete nor static. Rather, it is to be

continually pursued and reshaped by novel information. According

to his argument, truth emerges over time and in the light of new

experience. When it comes to conclusivity, Dewey continues,

“logically, absolute truth is an ideal which cannot be realized,

at least not until all the facts have been registered, or … until

it is no longer possible to make other observations and other

experiences” (as cited on p. 139). The Learning Sciences has

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES9

taken this statement as something of a charge, as implied in

Confrey’s commentary on Dewey:

[Dewey] recognized that in the beginning, there is only

the indeterminate, which undergoes transformation

through a problematic to a hypothesis, which, by means

of the activity of inquiry, is transformed to a

determinate situation producing a set of knowledge

claims. These claims will only reach the status of

truth if they are borne out in other spheres of

activity. (p. 139)

Consequently, the Learning Sciences regularly employs research

methods like design-based research, which situate research where

true, natural, native learning is taking place—in places of

activity. By studying learning from the center of the action, the

Learning Sciences can be sure to curate a body of knowledge that

is constantly being reformed in light of genuine experience.

Trenches

In sum, both philosophy and practice now considered

essential to deep learning were understood and enacted by Dewey

over 100 years ago. However, based on the form and ethos of

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES10

current educational environments—Krajcik and Blumenfeld complain

“that schools teach superficial knowledge rather than deeper

knowledge—Dewey seems to have been largely ignored. A few of the

authors of chapters in The Handbook hint at the tenor of Dewey’s

philosophical and political rivals. Both these brief references

to contrary popular opinion and the Deweyan values taken up by

the Learning Sciences will be crucial to the following

discussion.

As mentioned previously, Greeno writes that while Dewey

focused on “large systems,” the “mainstream of psychology …

instead focused on individuals” (p. 79). As another example,

after laying out Dewey’s perspective on knowledge formation,

Confrey describes a major competing view held by some of Dewey’s

contemporaries:

By contrast, more behavioristic traditions gauge

learning primarily by measurable effects on performance

on tests or other direct measures of student outcomes,

emphasizing speed, efficiency, persistence, and,

occasionally, the transfer of thought to new settings.

(p. 137)

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES11

The measurement movement, alluded to in Confrey’s statement,

was led by the influential psychologist and educationist E. L.

Thorndike, who “envisioned an educational science in which all

learning is measurable and, on this basis, by which all

educational innovations could be experimentally evaluated,”

according to Stahl, Koschmann, and Suthers (p. 416). They point

out that aspects of popular thought—in this case regarding

knowledge formation—have become “so culturally entrenched that it

is difficult to conceive of learning in any other way” (p. 416).

Undoubtedly, entrenchment is far afield of Dewey’s

indeterminate, provisional knowledge. In considering knowledge

formation, Stahl, Koschmann, and Suthers claim that the

‘entrenched’ viewpoint “rests on established traditions in

epistemology and philosophy of mind” (p. 416). Inadvertently,

these authors have provided a guiding statement for this paper.

For, as historical analysis demonstrates, many of Dewey’s

contemporaries who claimed to be working science were in

actuality digging into ideological trenches.

The New Psychology and Eugenics

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES12

At the turn of the 20th century, the doctrine of mental

discipline, which was popular in the 19th century and held that

mental training in one area generalized to others, was displaced

by new “scientific” approaches to psychology. One of these

approaches, introduced by G. Stanley Hall, was the child study

movement, which concentrated “on delineating the characteristics

of the normal stages of growth” (Applebee, 1974, p. 47). Another

was the work of E. L. Thorndike in the form of the measurement

movement. Recent advances in statistical analysis, Pearson’s work

in correlations, for instance, may have influenced Thorndike as

he initiated the measurement movement, claiming at one point that

“whatever exists at all exists in some amount. To know it

thoroughly involves knowing its quantity as well as its quality”

(as cited in Lagemann, 2000, p. 57). Relying on the study of,

ostensibly, more predictable and measurable phenomena, Hall,

Thorndike, and others ultimately substantiated psychology as a

science.

A major turning point for the field of psychology came with

the mental testing (specifically intelligence testing) of

soldiers during World War I. Psychologists, including Robert

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES13

Yerkes, Henry Goddard, and Lewis Terman, had developed several

variations of intelligence tests by the time of the war. These

men, along with other prominent psychologists of the day, were

commissioned to develop tests specifically for sorting soldiers

into appropriate military roles. By the end of the war, nearly

2,000,000 soldiers had been tested. Gersh writes that “an

indirect outcome of the Army testing program was to bring

together psychologists from all over the United States. This

concentration and cooperation had a qualitative effect on the

field of psychology, especially the testing branch” (Gersh, 1981,

p. 107). Terman (1961) would later recall the significance of

that scene, appreciating “the opportunity they gave me to become

acquainted with nearly all of the leading psychologists of

America” (as cited in Gersh, 1981, p. 107). More to the point,

however, Terman says that “one result of the war experiences was

to confirm and strengthen my earlier belief regarding the

importance of mental tests as an integral part of scientific

psychology” (as cited on p. 107). The Army testing, Gersh claims,

effectively put “psychology on the map of respectability. No

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES14

longer seen as a branch of philosophy, it was now a science.

(Gersh, 1981, p. 107)

Something else brought many of these prominent psychologists

together: eugenics. Eugenics is essentially the intent to control

the genetic quality of the human population by selective breeding

and sterilization. A number of important public figures were

eugenicists, including several leaders of the American

Psychological Association (APA) in its early years. James Cattell

and G. Stanley Hall, active eugenicists, were the founders.

Several other eugenicists cycled through its presidency,

including Robert Yerkes, Joseph Jastrow, Carl Seashore, John B.

Watson, E. L. Thorndike, and Lewis Terman. They would form the

collective impetus behind the adoption of mental testing and

other significant changes in education.

Eugenics was and is by no means innocuous. It carried

intense prejudice, fear, and, with the funding it enjoyed in the

first quarter of the 20th century, great political weight.

Eugenicist Henry Goddard, the first to introduce mental testing

in its modern form to the U.S., was

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES15

an activist who proclaimed, ‘it is hereditary

feeble-mindedness that is the basis of all

problems,’ ... ‘and it is hereditary feeble-

mindedness that we must attack.’ His plan of

‘attack’ against the feeble-minded had two basic

parts. First, society should administer

intelligence tests widely to children; ‘By

suitable mental examination they must be

discovered, and discovered as early as possible.’

Then, through ‘colonization’ (mass custody), as

many of the mentally defective as possible could

be prohibited from procreating. (Ryan, 1997, p.

671)

What is more, “[mental defectives were] not immoral; they [were]

unmoral" (p. 672). Though Goddard would eventually be

disappointed in his efforts, he nearly achieved the legal

equation of poor intelligence test performance and criminality in

Ohio (Ryan, 1997)

G. Stanley Hall once claimed that “’there are certain

safeguards which democracy must more and more recognize and make

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES16

effective. The first of these is eugenics.’ He believed that non-

whites were evolutionally inferior to whites, being ‘the children

and adolescents of the human race’” (Gersh, 1981, p. 16). He

further “argued that the ‘new immigrants,’ those from southern

and eastern Europe, were an ‘army of incapables’ who had inferior

mental abilities and ought to follow a practical curriculum, one

designed for work and not higher education” (Silverberg, 2008,

pp. 28-29). To what Hall is alluding is differentiated education.

While the Learning Sciences also advocates for individualized

education, often in connection to utilizing current technologies,

the spirit is quite different.

Terman and Mental Testing

Lewis Terman, a student of Hall’s who shared his ideological

position, became the strongest force in popularizing mental

testing in America. He adapted the Binet-Simon and standardized

what would become the premier IQ test, the Stanford-Binet.

According to Gersh (1981), “[the Standford-Binet] has served as

the basis for other such tests, the sign of a "good" test being a

high correlation of scores with the Stanford-Binet” (p. 33).

Terman will serve to illustrate eugenics bias. That said, it is

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES17

worth reading two paragraphs of one of Terman’s (1916) early test

standardization studies, which, incidentally, included only

Whites in the sample. Here he describes people of color:

Their dullness seems to be racial, or at least

inherent in the family stocks from which they

come...The fact that one meets this type (IQ 70-80)

with such extraordinary frequency among Indians,

Mexicans and negroes suggests quite forcibly that the

whole question of racial differences in mental traits

will have to be taken up anew and by experimental

methods. The writer predicts that when this is done

there will be discovered enormously significant racial

differences which cannot be wiped out by any scheme of

mental culture.

Children of this group should be segregated in

special classes and be given instruction which is

concrete and practical. They cannot master

abstractions, but they can often be made efficient

workers, able to look out for themselves. There is no

possibility at present of convincing society that they

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES18

should not be allowed to reproduce, although from a

eugenic point of view they constitute a grave problem

because of their unusually prolific breeding. (cited in

Gersh, 1981, p. 42)

The effects these biases had on test results are clear with

a brief look at Terman’s most famous and extensive project,

Genetic Studies of Genius: Mental and Physical Traits of a Thousand Gifted Children

(1925). Jolly (2008) provides the details. His goal was to

collect and study genius subjects. In 1910, he and his assistants

scoured major cities in California for bright youth, testing them

after recommendations for their teachers. Those who scored in the

top 10% on his intelligence test were accepted and analyzed, a

figure amounting to 1,444 by 1924. Terman collected about 16

data points for each child, including a number of IQ and

achievement tests written by him; parent, teacher, and field

worker observations; demographic, ancestral, and economic

information; and even reading logs.

“This initial demographic data yielded a population that was

White, middle class, and with parents holding advanced schooling

when compared to the average population, and an

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES19

overrepresentation of children of Jewish heritage” (p. 30).

Rather than considering the fact that mainly White teachers would

have been recommending students (i.e. teachers may have had a

biased view of which students seemed intelligent) or questioning

whether cultural bias was built into his tests, Terman took the

opportunity to reinforce his prejudice. He “attributed this as

'indirect evidence that the heredity of our gifted subjects is

much superior to that of the average individual'" (p. 30).

Likewise, rather than considering patterns of oppression and

inherited privilege, Terman believed he had found “evidence to

support Galton’s theory of the heritability of genius” when

several families identified “relatives who were Presidents or

Vice-Presidents of the United States, writers, generals,

statesmen, and Supreme Court justices” (p. 30). As a final

example, subjects in his study reported varying household

incomes, with some living in what Terman considered poverty,

lending confidence to Terman’s position that “the causal factor

lies in original endowment rather than in environmental

influences.” Jolly (2008), however, provides important outside

data: “The yearly mean income was $4,705 and the median income

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES20

was $3,333, with 35.3% of the families reporting an income below

$2,500. However, this was well above the reported average annual

salary of $1,236 in 1925,” allowing some room for class to be a

significant factor in the study (p. 29). In this dubious fashion,

“Terman provided scientific confirmation for the nativism and

prejudice of many Americans” (Chapman, 1981, p. 705).

Resistant to Reevaluation

It is crucial to acknowledge that, in contrast to Dewey’s

doctrine of indeterminate knowledge, posing to practice science

assumes no intention of allowing evidence contrary to anticipated

conclusions to alter convictions. This was the case both before

and after the scientific repackaging of psychology. Writing soon

after the height of mental testing foment, Mumford and Smith

(1934) reflect perspicaciously on the resilience of racial bias

during the last century. They mention that humanity has been

considering group differences for millennia; however, the notion

of evolution allowed for a stronger-than-ever rationale for long-

held prejudice. Racial disparity now seemed sufficiently

scientific and spawned various speculations.

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES21

From the physical point of view, for example, those

races whose features more resembled those of early

simian ancestors were adjudged inferior to those with

features less resembling those ancestors: on account of

his protruding mouth and wide nostrils the African was,

therefore, adjudged inferior to the European. (Mumford

& Smith, 1934, p. 46)

Eventually,

it was pointed out that the hair-covered skin of the

European face resembled the hairiness of early simian

ancestors more closely than did the smooth hairless

skin of the African. On these grounds, it was the

European who represented a lower stage of development

than did the African! (Mumford & Smith, 1934, pp. 46-

47)

Unsurprisingly, when the same reasoning that endorsed European

superiority was applied in the opposite direction, such arguments

were conveniently discarded.

The faith in racial differences, however, persisted, “owing

to an incomplete understanding of the theories of evolution which

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES22

Darwin first propounded” (Mumford & Smith, 1934, p. 46). Until

1910, pseudoscientific practices like phrenology and brain

weighing continued to support the theory. Soon, mental testing—

biased though it might be—became the strategy that would “prove”

genetic differences in quality between races.

Gersh (1981) makes it clear that even during mental test

development, there was evidence that mental tests could be

unreliable. Two studies in particular stand out. First, clinical

psychologist J. E. Wallace Wallin, using one of the early and

important mental tests, Henry Goddard’s “Goddard-Binet,” found

that a number of “businessmen, farmers, and a housewife had

scored at the levels of morons and imbeciles,” the complication

being that Wallin knew these individuals as “eminently successful

in their several callings and living moral and respectable lives"

(Gersh, 1981, pp. 35-36). Because those testing as morons,

according to Goddard, were supposed to be amoral paupers and

criminals, Wallin concluded that Goddard’s test was “grossly

inaccurate” (p. 36). Apparently at around the same time, Mary

Campbell found “that both the majority of the Chicago mayor's

cabinet and the candidates for mayor, in the most recent

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES23

election, were morons or imbeciles” (p. 37). In the face of this

negative publicity, two telling moves were made, according to

Gersh: first, the APA “resolved that only properly trained

psychologists be allowed to use the tests” (p. 38) and second,

“the Goddard test had to be jettisoned, and ‘better’ tests

developed to replace it” (p. 38). No indication to abandon mental

tests was given.

Since the early days of mental testing, study after study

has demonstrated that innate intelligence does not differ

dramatically from general group to group, as Franklin (2007) and

many others point out; or, if difference is found, it may be

contrary to popular expectations, with examples cited by Gersh

(1981). Alice McAplin's (1932) study accounted for this major

variation. She argued that, instead of intelligence, “I.Q. tests

measured what children were exposed to, and once they were taught

the material found on the tests, their scores would improve

significantly, even over a short period of time" (Franklin, 2007,

p. 220). Others have cited similar phenomena (see Green, 1974).

At this time the reason as to why Dewey’s praxis ultimately

met with recalcitrance and rejection in his day is more

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES24

comprehensible: to support Dewey would mean to support the

remaking of one’s beliefs in light of new evidence. Because

select influential men of the Progressive Era could not be

persuaded to change their minds about race differences no matter

the data—not to mention that they had often managed to produce

the data they preferred themselves—they could not conceivably

listen to Dewey. The stakes were too high.

The Political Use of Science

During a forty year period straddling the turn of the 20th

century (1880-1920), “the population of the United States doubled

… due in large measure to the arrival of 14 million immigrants”

(p. 4). Reacting to immigrant populations hailing largely from

southern and eastern Europe, the “new immigrants,” “the nativist

was roused by the immigrant’s appearance, short and dark, his

religion, Catholic and Jewish, and his perceived ignorance and

poverty as demonstrated by the way he lived” (Silverberg, 2008,

p. 10). Conservative fears began to take shape. According to E.

P. Cubberly, a prominent eugenicist and educator writing in 1909,

These southern and eastern Europeans are of a very

different type from the north Europeans who preceded

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES25

them. Illiterate, docile, lacking in self-reliance and

initiative, and not possessing the Anglo-Teutonic

conception of law, order, and government, their coming

has served to dilute tremendously our national stock,

and to corrupt our civic life. (as cited in Silverberg,

2008, p. 21)

Around the same time, industrialization was reinventing the

American experience, drawing workers to city factories. “Cities

like Chicago grew enormously over that period, with that city

reaching a million in population by 1900, a growth of about

tenfold in forty years” (Kliebard, 1995, p. 4). Such a change in

the composition of the city populous posed significant challenges

on at least two fronts, schools and traditional social structure.

Mental testing would play a significant role in addressing both.

Schools

According to Herbst (1996), “between 1890 and 1920

enrollment of teenagers into secondary schools increased by over

700 percent, from about 200,000 to over 1.5 million” (as cited in

Silverberg, 2008, p. 17). Incidentally, compulsory education laws

for children, introduced to combat child labor and truancy and

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES26

which would later prove to mitigate educational inequity, also

contributed to the institutional population boom (Provasnik,

2006; Stainburn, 2014).

Leonard Ayres (1909) in his often cited text Laggards in Our

Schools was, essentially, attempting to make sense of the

educational chaos. Two of his observations, among many others,

are alarming: “For each 1000 pupils in the first grade we find

only 263 in the eighth and only 56 in the fourth year of the high

school. These figures represent average conditions in our city

schools” (Ayres, 1909, p. 14). Ayres believed that the major

predictor of student attrition was retardation. Retardation, in

this case referring exclusively to the condition of a “pupil who

is above the normal age for his grade” (p. 7), was endemic: “in

the lower grades, before the process of elimination [attrition]

enters to remove the badly retarded children, the average

progress of the pupils is at the rate of eight grades in ten

years” (p. 5).

It is little surprise that Franklin Bobbitt and the Social

Efficiency Educators stepped in. Along with Frederick Taylor and

the Scientific Management group, they worked to apply a factory-

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES27

like approach to education, championing efficiency and

standardization in schools that were drowning in diversity and

desks (Kliebard, 1995). In light of that era’s societal dynamics,

it appears a predictable shift for two reasons. First, schools

needed efficient and cost-effective methods of controlling and

graduating their students; second, by channeling factory-like

conditions, schools could neatly assimilate “new immigrants” into

the America of the “old immigrants.”

Social Structure

As industry and the promises of the American dream drew

workers to cities, at least two explanations for economic

disparity between the classes had to be contended with. “One,

which increasing numbers of workers and agricultural laborers

adhered to, was that the upper classes were exploiting the lower

classes” (Gersh, 1981, p. 13). Such sentiment led to unionization

and political action on the part of the working class, thus

challenging the social grip of the powerful and threatening to

destabilize long-existing hierarchies. The second explanation was

more palatable and, perhaps, more morally satisfactory to the

elites: “those who were not doing well were incapable of doing

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES28

so, for biological reasons” (p. 14). In other words, according to

Gersh, “the elite was forced by economic and political

circumstances, to support eugenics” (p. 14). This is exactly what

several of them did, most notable of which were “the Carnegie

Corporation, the Rockefeller Foundation, and the Commonwealth

Fund” (Gersh, 1981, p. 123).

By supporting eugenic activities, including the development

and marketing of mental tests, the elites effectively limited the

democratic and economic potential of the working classes,

particularly immigrants and African Americans. Eugenic forces

were “instrumental in the passage of anti-immigration

legislation, in 1924; in the extension of sterilization laws and

laws forbiding [sic] marriage between certain types of

individuals throughout more than half of the United States”

(Gersh, 1981, pp. 130-131), along with “reductions in money spent

on black schools, and support for legal segregation” (p. 102).

The argument here is not that the elites consciously

conspired to suppress the working class. Rather, so social

Darwinian theory would suggest, the elites—genetically superior

by all accounts—were managing to survive by supporting those

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES29

causes that, as Sutherland (1985) observed, “constituted no

challenge to the existing social structure; rather, [they] tended

to endorse it” (as cited in Burnett, 1985, p. 55). Eugenics and

its outgrowth of mental testing were, in other words, worth

supporting—by the tens of millions of dollars.

Dewey, the Learning Sciences and Mental Testing

In considering both schools and social structure, Dewey yet

again was understandably ignored. Situated learning is inherently

inefficient and would have been out of the question for bloated

schools; how many clubhouses could one school afford and have the

time to allow students to design and build? However, Dewey would

not have only been rejected on a practical level, but also on a

philosophical one. His emphasis on inclusive education, on

valuing and activating students’ prior knowledge, would have

inhibited assimilation. Subtractive assimilation, in reality,

devalues one’s past experience and denies one’s voice. The

conservative powers, struggling to maintain control over the

frenetic, kaleidoscopic mélange of that time period, were not

prepared to listen to the voices of immigrants. Furthermore, to

extend democratic powers to the masses (Dewey’s ideal) was not in

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES30

the interests of the wealthy capitalist. The fact that the

eugenics movement was largely privately funded illustrates this

point—see Gersh (1981) for details on funding.

Static Versus Variable Over Time

In essence, mental tests of Dewey’s day were (and to a great

degree today are) the antithesis of Deweyan thought—and the

Learning Sciences, in the aspects for which it relies on Dewey—

for they served to work against the principles heretofore

mentioned. First of all, the subset of mental tests that were

most widely used in the 1920s and 1930s, intelligence tests,

presumed to measure a genetically determined, stable human

capability. This notion led to Thorndike’s statement that “men

are born unequal in intellect, character and skill. It is

impossible and undesirable to make them equal by education" (as

cited in Gersh, 1981, p. 19). The entire enterprise of eugenics

and mental testing required a theory of stable intelligence in

order to act politically. For an interesting anecdote of

resistance against this belief, see Ryan (1997).

As many scholars have made apparent, intelligence tests

largely test experience, exposure, and cultural practice. That

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES31

is, it is now recognized that, in line with Dewey, one’s

knowledge, and therefore often one’s perceived intellect, is

dependent upon and shaped by experience. As such, the mind and

its capabilities are liable to change and develop based on

experience, just as McAlpine’s (1932) study demonstrated. In this

way, a free-standing mental test that presumes to measure an

innate, predetermined condition of mind is incongruous with Dewey

and the Learning Sciences.

In the same vein, an educational system predicated upon test

performance cannot be expected to perceive and fulfill the needs

of its students. Because tests are prone to contain the cultural

biases of their writers, it is likely that some of the important

aspects of students, according the Dewey and the Learning

Sciences, namely their cultural background and general prior

experiences, can be obscured by a test score. It is now clear,

however, that bias is not the only subjective factor in test

performance; motivation, stereotype threat, test anxiety, sleep,

and other environmental dynamics influence student performance—a

term search on the database EBSCO reveals hundreds of articles on

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES32

each item. Test performance, then, could indicate a number of

student characteristics unrelated to intelligence of any kind.

Individual Democratic Potential

Second of all, many scholars have argued that mental testing

can result in social and economic stratification (Chapman ,1981;

Franklin, 2007; Oakes, 1987; Green, 1974). This process can be

achieved through differentiated education, a practice which can

be used to positive ends. However, such altruistic motives are

not always seen. For instance, it is historian Michael Katz’s

position that “industrialists explicitly recognized that the

school served as a means of disciplining the work force" (as

cited in Gersh, 1981, p. 148). One potential way of disciplining

the workforce is by managing student potential, a possible

function of tracking in schools. Chapman (1981) analyzed the

historical California school district records to understand the

role that mental testing played in differentiation.

The City of Oakland, for instance, in 1911 utilized

intelligence tests to sift out the “’subnormal’ children—‘the

absent, the tardy, the sickly, the unruly, the liars, thieves and

cowards"—freeing up teachers to work with the “normal” children

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES33

(Chapman, 1981, p. 706). Oakland city schools diversified greatly

by 1915, offering a variety of school programs to the variedly

performing student population, including “kindergartens,

intermediate schools, and several high schools including a

vocational school a technical school, two comprehensive schools,

and a "university" school exclusively for college preparatory

work (p. 706). Some students were funneled into college, some

into the blue collar workforce.

The whole city of Oakland was functioning on a three-track

system by 1922, tracking “bright, average, and slow students” (p.

708). Chapman makes it clear that those who collectively tested

most regularly on the bottom were immigrants, Italians in

particular. Such results would have validated common prejudices

of the day, per Cubberly’s previously cited comment.

Because of the potential ceiling-setting application of

mental tests, Green (1974), writing presumably to African

American mothers in the popular women’s magazine Ebony, warned

these mothers against allowing their children to be tested by

schools. His statement is unequivocal: "when educators and the

testing industry pretend that tests can accurately measure

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES34

intelligence, they are allowing many children to be sentenced to

a life without opportunity" (Green, 1974, p. 72). Providing

students with the opportunity and freedom to engage in and make

meaningful contributions to a democratic society was a strong

value of Dewey’s. As previously stated, the Learning Sciences

have adopted this tenet of Dewey’s not necessarily for political

reasons, but for pedagogical reasons. It is clear that engaged

students are more motivated, better-performing and more deeply-

learning students. As such, mental tests, especially those

employed consciously or subconsciously to limit the potential of

students, are again incongruous with both Dewey and the Learning

Sciences.

Conclusion

Despite the general misalignment of mental testing with

either ethical or presently-considered reasonable educational

practice, mental testing and tracking became common fair.

During the first ten years of distribution … the Terman

Group Test sold 775,000 copies, which, according to

Paul Chapman’s study of the Terman Tests, meant that

nearly one-fifth of all U.S. high school students took

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES35

the test. … Terman also developed achievement tests,

which also sold well. For example, the Stanford

Achievement Test, which was first published in 1922,

had annual sales of 1,500,000 by 1925. (Lagemann, 2000,

pp. 92-93)

By 1987, Jeannie Oakes could claim in a paper abstract that

tracking, largely facilitated by testing, was “nearly ubiquitous”

(Oakes, 1987). When considering the historical contexts of these

developments, it is not difficult to ascertain why. In light of

the glaring needs of schools, the insecurity of the nativist

elites, and recently scientifically legitimized eugenicists and

psychologists trumpeting individual and group differences and

developing tests to prove them, the political coopting of

“science” would seem inevitable. Consequently, it is arguable

that these moves were not typically made in spite of the scientific

paradigm of the day, but because of it.

There is a cautionary tale in the reading of mental testing

history. The Learning Sciences cannot pretend immunity to social

and political forces. To identify specific strains of philosophy

or world view that guide or contend for control over the Learning

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES36

Sciences will require future investigation. Two brief directions

for future study come to mind. First, student-centered or

constructivist education seems to have become the preferred

approach to education in the Learning Sciences and for many

reasons mentioned here previously (i.e., engagement, motivation,

etc.). In recent years certain branches of theory and philosophy

that also support student-centered education have also gained

traction, Critical Theory as one example among many. Critical

Theory is overtly political, as represented by Freire’s Pedagogy

of the Oppressed, and has found exposure in schools in the form of

Critical Pedagogy. Because popular ideology and philosophy can

assert power and influence over accepted research pathways and

social and academic legitimacy, as evidenced by mental testing,

the growing credence of student-centered education could be a

fine example of the recursive relationship of social change and

science.

At the same time student-centered education is being buoyed

in academic circles, it seems to be under attack—again—in

American schools. Michael Apple (2006) in Educating the “Right” Way

argues that neoliberalism and neoconservatism, among other

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES37

forces, are destroying American education from multiple angles.

Elites, resembling in spirit those of the Progressive Era, are

privatizing schools, commodifying students, and marketizing

education in general. The goal is to produce students who can

strengthen American interests in the world market via the

invention, innovation, and entrepreneurism. Apple argues that

these moves strip students of self-efficacy and opportunity. And

how might these political agendas be affecting the Learning

Sciences? The Handbook produces some evidence. First, while several

portions of the text focus on, for instance, student engagement

(particularly with technology), improving student outcomes, and

altering student misconceptions, all in the areas of technology,

math and science, the Arts are rarely mentioned and only one

chapter is dedicated to the impact of culture on learning. This

cannot be argued as the devaluing of free thinking and culture,

as in the assimilationist agenda at the turn of the 20th century;

however, because of this apparent focus on technology, math, and

science, the text may implicate the Learning Sciences as having

worked to serve political agendas that arise out of globalization

and competition, such as neoliberalism.

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES38

What is not proposed here is the posture of a conspiracy

theorist. However, it is evident that objectivity within the

social sciences is largely a myth. For instance, human nature

does not legitimately fall within the purview of physical

science. It is a social, metaphysical, spiritual construction.

Yet, it is clear from the discussion of mental testing that

assumptions about what it means to be human and what can affect

human capabilities drove the widespread institutionalization of

what can be considered a tool of oppression. No worldview is

essentially politically neutral or universally accepted. The

moment that a scientist consciously or otherwise claims that it

should be universally accepted is the moment that, to quote Stahl,

Koschmann, and Suthers again, the so-called objectivity of

science is replaced by “established traditions in epistemology

and philosophy of mind” (Sawyer, 2007, p. 416). However, this is

not to say that the mission of the Learning Sciences should be

abandoned. Rather, the façade of objectivity should be abandoned

and a dialog of perspective, worldview, and interpretation

embraced. If this were to become the case, our knowledge would

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES39

have the opportunity of being continually remade based on a

diverse and authentic array of experience.

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES40

Bibliography

Applebee, A. N. (1974). Tradition and reform in the teaching of English : a

history. National Council of Teachers of English: Urbana,

Ill.

Ayres, L. P. (1909). Laggards in our schools; a study of retardation and

elimination in city school systems. Charities publication committee

Russell Sage Foundation: New York.

Burnett, J. (1985). History Today, 35(2), 54.

Chapman, P. D. (1981). Schools as sorters: Testing and tracking

in California, 1910-1925. Journal of Social History, 14(4), 701-717.

doi: 10.2307/3787022

Franklin, V. P. (2007). The tests are written for the dogs: The

Journal of Negro Education, African American children, and

the intelligence testing movement in historical perspective.

Journal of Negro Education, 76(3), 216.

Gersh, D. A. (1981). The development and use of IQ tests in the United States

from 1900 TO 1930. (8127117 Ph.D.), State University of New

York at Stony Brook, Ann Arbor.

Green, R. L. (1974). The awesome danger of 'intelligence'

testing. Ebony, 29(10), 68.

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES41

Jolly, J. L. (2008b). Lewis Terman: Genetic Study of Genius--

elementary school students. Gifted Child Today, 31(1), 27.

Kliebard, H. M. (1995). The struggle for the American curriculum, 1893-1958

(2nd ed. ed.). Routledge: New York.

Lagemann, E. C. (2000). An elusive science : the troubling history of education

research. University of Chicago Press: Chicago.

Mumford, W. B., & Smith, C. E. (1938). Racial comparisons and

intelligence testing. Journal of the Royal African Society, 37(146),

46-57. doi: 10.2307/717478

Oakes, J. (1987). Tracking in secondary schools: A contexutal

perspective. Educational Psychologist, 22(2), 129.

Provasnik, S. (2006). Judicial activism and the origins of

parental choice: The court's role in the

institutionalization of compulsory education in the United

States, 1891–1925. History of Education Quarterly, 46(3), 311. doi:

10.1111/j.1748-5959.2006.00001.x

Ryan, P. J. (1997). Unnatural selection: Intelligence testing,

eugenics, and American political cultures. Journal of Social

History, 30(3), 669-685. doi: 10.2307/3789553

FORECASTING SUBJECTIVE INFLUENCES42

Sawyer, R. K. (2006). The Cambridge handbook of the learning sciences

(Second edition. ed.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University

Press.

Silverberg, C. (2008). IQ testing and tracking: The history of scientific racism

in the American public schools: 1890--1924. (3311920 Ph.D.),

University of Nevada, Reno, Ann Arbor.

Stainburn, S. (2014). School-attendance laws linked to rises in

educational equity. Education Week, 33(30), 5.

(Applebee, 1974; Ayres, 1909; Burnett, 1985; Chapman, 1981;

Franklin, 2007; Gersh, 1981; Green, 1974; Jolly, 2008b;

Kliebard, 1995; Lagemann, 2000; Mumford & Smith, 1938;

Oakes, 1987; Provasnik, 2006; Ryan, 1997; Sawyer, 2006;

Silverberg, 2008; Stainburn, 2014)