Dialectical Nihilism: An Essay on Nothing (and its Structure)

20
1 Dialectical Nihilism: An Essay on Nothing (and its Structure) Peter Sas "If you look at zero you see nothing; but look through it and you will see the world." (Robert Kaplan) "We are such stuff as dreams are made on; and our little life is rounded with a sleep." (Shakespeare) Introduction: My painful black ToE The last few weeks I have been toying with a crazy theory that I like to call "dialectical nihilism". I am, in fact, deeply ambivalent about it, unable to decide whether it is just plain crazy or rather the best ToE (Theory of Everything) out there. I like to call it "my painful black ToE" because its ultimate explanation of everything is the total 'blackness' of absolute nothingness. The fact that there nevertheless appears to be something is then explained by the hypothesis that this nothingness is not without structure: it is composed of infinitely many antithetical elements (or polar opposites) that cancel each other out and thus add up to nothing. Obviously, this focus on the mutual cancellation (or "Aufhebung" as Hegel would say) of polar opposites explains one of the senses in which dialectical nihilism is dialectical. In fact, as I intend to show in the following, dialectical nihilism is dialectical in four senses in that it facilitates: (a) a dialectical reversal of everything (that exists) into nothing; (b) a dialectical conception of the nothing as composed of polar opposites; (c) a dialectical "logic of illusion" (Kant) that unmasks the illusory nature of existence under the principle of sufficient reason; (d) a dialectical reversal of negative into positive nihilism, i.e. the reversal of the negation of life as absurd and meaningless into an affirmation of life as a groundless and wonderful gift. In the following I will explain dialectical nihilism more fully, developing in a rough- and-ready form its main theses and the various arguments in favor of it. I should stress, however, that although the term "dialectical nihilism" is my own invention, most of the ideas behind it are not original and have been around since the times of Anaximander, Heraclitus, Laozi and Buddha. Moreover, in recent years the dialectical conception of nothingness as composed of polar opposites has regained a lot of interest due to the emergence of the (in)famous hypothesis of the zero energy universe in physics. The basic idea behind this hypothesis is that since the universe is composed of equal amounts of positive and negative energy amounts that cancel each other out the universe as a whole contains no energy at all. In this way the universe appears to be strangely empty, especially if you consider the fact that matter

Transcript of Dialectical Nihilism: An Essay on Nothing (and its Structure)

1

Dialectical Nihilism: An Essay on Nothing

(and its Structure)

Peter Sas

"If you look at zero you see nothing;

but look through it and you will see the world."

(Robert Kaplan)

"We are such stuff as dreams are made on;

and our little life is rounded with a sleep."

(Shakespeare)

Introduction: My painful black ToE

The last few weeks I have been toying with a crazy theory that I like to call "dialectical

nihilism". I am, in fact, deeply ambivalent about it, unable to decide whether it is just

plain crazy or rather the best ToE (Theory of Everything) out there. I like to call it

"my painful black ToE" because its ultimate explanation of everything is the total

'blackness' of absolute nothingness. The fact that there nevertheless appears to be

something is then explained by the hypothesis that this nothingness is not without

structure: it is composed of infinitely many antithetical elements (or polar opposites)

that cancel each other out and thus add up to nothing. Obviously, this focus on the

mutual cancellation (or "Aufhebung" as Hegel would say) of polar opposites explains

one of the senses in which dialectical nihilism is dialectical. In fact, as I intend to

show in the following, dialectical nihilism is dialectical in four senses in that it

facilitates:

(a) a dialectical reversal of everything (that exists) into nothing;

(b) a dialectical conception of the nothing as composed of polar opposites;

(c) a dialectical "logic of illusion" (Kant) that unmasks the illusory nature of existence

under the principle of sufficient reason;

(d) a dialectical reversal of negative into positive nihilism, i.e. the reversal of the

negation of life as absurd and meaningless into an affirmation of life as a groundless

and wonderful gift.

In the following I will explain dialectical nihilism more fully, developing – in a rough-

and-ready form – its main theses and the various arguments in favor of it. I should

stress, however, that although the term "dialectical nihilism" is my own invention,

most of the ideas behind it are not original and have been around since the times of

Anaximander, Heraclitus, Laozi and Buddha. Moreover, in recent years the dialectical

conception of nothingness as composed of polar opposites has regained a lot of

interest due to the emergence of the (in)famous hypothesis of the zero energy

universe in physics. The basic idea behind this hypothesis is that since the universe is

composed of equal amounts of positive and negative energy – amounts that cancel

each other out – the universe as a whole contains no energy at all. In this way the

universe appears to be strangely empty, especially if you consider the fact that matter

2

is a form of energy as well. According to many physicists – ranging from Alan Guth

and Stephen Hawking to quantum chemist Peter Atkins – the hypothesis of the zero

energy universe explains how the universe could have emerged from nothing, namely,

through a kind of 'splitting' of nothing into positive and negative energy. The

biochemist and popular science(-fiction) writer Isaac Asimov appears to have been

very prescient in this regard, already writing about this in 1974:

"Where did the substance of the universe come from?... If 0 equals ( + 1) + (-1), then

something which is 0 might just as well become + 1 and -1. Perhaps in an infinite sea

of nothingness, globs of positive and negative energy in equal-sized pairs are

constantly forming, and after passing through evolutionary changes, combining once

more and vanishing. We are in one of these globs between nothing and nothing and

wondering about it." (Asimov 1974: 69-70)

Dialectical nihilism latches on that idea but gives it a Buddhist twist. If the universe is

really composed of polar opposites that cancel each other out and thus add up to

nothing, then in what sense can the universe be said to exist at all? If the universe is

just an empirical manifestation of nothingness, doesn't this imply that the existence

of the universe is illusory? Hence the nihilistic aspect of dialectical nihilism. But, as I

suggested above, this nihilism is dialectical also in the sense that it enables a reversal

from negative to positive nihilism. I find the idea of dialectical nihilism strangely

liberating in that it allows you to return to daily life with less attachment and thus

also with less sorrow, since – as the Buddha said – desire is the root of all suffering.

At the same time it allows you to return to life with a fresh sense of (aesthetic)

wonder about this infinitely complex tapestry of appearances we call reality –

appearances in which ultimately nothing appears and where "the rose flowers without

why" as the 17th century mystic Angelus Silesius so aptly put it. In this way dialectical

nihilism can be said to bring about existential illumination or Enlightenment if you

will. But paradoxically the light that illuminates the whole coincides with the absolute

darkness in which the whole dissolves.

Dialectical nihilism: The basic idea

The basic idea behind dialectical nihilism is that existence is really nothing (i.e. in

reality nothing exists) but that this nothing consists of infinitely many antithetical

elements (or polar opposites) that cancel each other out and thus add up to nothing,

like -1+1=0 or equal amounts of positive and negative energy adding up to no energy

at all. Thus these antithetical elements (or "beings and antibeings" as I like to call

them) do not really exist, they have "always already" cancelled each other. Yet as

cancelled they are nevertheless still contained in the nothing to which they add up.

Following Hegelian dialectics we could say that all possible beings and antibeings are

Aufgehoben (sublated) in the nothing, where "Aufhebung" carries the double

meaning of elimination and sublimation (or conservation on a higher level). The

difference with Hegelian dialectics is that whereas for Hegel Aufhebung is always the

result of a logical-temporal process (the march of Spirit through world history), for

3

dialectical nihilism it is a static state of affairs outside of time. Indeed, it is the empty

state of affairs, where nothing at all exists. The whole of reality just is this Aufhebung

that has always already taken place, i.e. the nothing that contains in sublated form all

possible beings and antibeings.

To repeat: as cancelled, these beings and antibeings do not exist. They are no more

than possibilities (potentialities, virtualities) within the nothing. Here dialectical

nihilism relies on an ancient and perhaps also commonsensical idea, namely, that in a

state where nothing exists everything is still possible. The idea is plausible on an

intuitive level: when you have a block of marble still untouched by a sculptor, all

forms are still possible within it, but once the sculptor starts shaping it, actualizing

one of its possible forms, all the other forms thereby become impossible. Now for

dialectical nihilism, the nothing is like an infinite block of pristine black marble in

which all forms are possible. There is only one limitation on these forms: they must

be such that together they form this black marble of nothingness. Hence the stress on

antithetical elements, because these cancel each other out. So everything is possible

in the nothing as long it is composed of antithetical elements that add up to nothing.

Thus, paradoxically, everything is possible as long as it is impossible, i.e. self-

cancelling.

So how do we get from there – where nothing at all exists – to here, our reality, where

there nevertheless appear to exist a great many things, from quarks and quasars to

headaches, the number pi, cheese sandwiches and beautiful women? According to

dialectical nihilism, the keyword here is "appear": there appear to be many things,

including ourselves. And "appearance" can also mean "mere appearance", "illusion".

That things appear to exist doesn't mean they actually exist. In fact, according to

dialectical nihilism, they don't exist: all beings 'are' no more than mere appearances,

illusions, the "veil of Maya" as the Buddhists say. There 'are' appearances but there is

nothing that appears in them. They are literally appearances of nothing. In Kantian

terminology we could say that nothingness is the thing-in-itself behind (or beneath)

the phenomenal world (thus, to paraphrase Kant, we have empirical realism but

transcendental nihilism).

But, so we might ask, can't we then at least say that these appearances exist? Isn't

illusion, however illusory, still something and not nothing? Doesn't the claim that

there are only appearances contradict the other claim that nothing exists? In the

following I will try to answer this objection in a systematic way. I will try to show that

if we conceive of the nothing as composed of all possible beings and antibeings, then

we with our illusory existence must be there enveloped in the nothing as well. We

with all our experiences are also just unactualized possibilities within the nothing;

hence the illusory nature of those experiences. For now, however, it suffices to say

that the mode of existence of appearance/illusion is deeply problematic anyway.

Already the ancient Greek and Indian philosophers recognized that if appearance can

be said to exist at all, then that existence is deeply paradoxical and bordering on non-

4

existence. One problem, of course, lies in the temporal, fleeting, transient nature of

the phenomenal world. When we consider what appears closely, we find that it is

never the same, it continuously changes in a never-ending sensory stream. As Plato

said: "All is flux, nothing stays still." But if it is never the same, if it never endures, if

it always becomes, how then can it ever be said to be? We can say "appearance

exists", but if we can't say what exists – since there is no what, no remaining essence

or identity – then the existence of appearance becomes very thin indeed. Hence Plato

saw the sensory flux as a kind of non-being. Of course, Plato was still able to discern

real enduring being behind the flux in the form of the eternal Ideas, whose timeless

existence was guaranteed by the "light of intelligibility" radiated by the highest Idea,

the Good. But, as we might say, such Platonism has become obsolete for us (post-

)moderns who "don't believe in nothing no more". Indeed, for dialectical nihilism,

nothing exists behind the veil of appearances, nothing but absolute nothingness itself.

The reasons for dialectical nihilism

Up till now I have merely been explicating the idea of dialectical nihilism. But what

are the reasons for it? Why believe in such a crazy theory at all (indeed, I ask myself

this all the time). Well, believe it or not, there are actually good reasons for it. We

have already mentioned one: the problematic 'existence' of the phenomenal world,

the sensory flux. Of course, this doesn't yet justify the conclusion that nothing at all

exists nor that this nothing is the ultimate Aufhebung, the coincidentia oppositorum

of all possible beings and antibeings. To establish these conclusions other arguments

are needed. In the following I will discuss two such arguments. First I will discuss

some contemporary physics and focus on the role played by polarities in physical

reality, polarities which are such that they cancel each other out, thus making the

universe look strangely empty (fermionic polarity and the hypothesis of the zero

universe). Then I will discuss the problematic nature of the concept of existence,

which becomes apparent when one tries to answer Leibniz's famous question "Why is

there something rather than nothing?". The logical impossibility of explaining why

there is anything at all undermines the very idea that there is anything at all.

Thereafter I will discuss the nature of absolute appearance and attempt an

explanation – on the basis of the idea that nothingness is composed of antithetical

elements – why there appears to be something. Finally I will finish up discussing

some theories that look like dialectical nihilism but in fact aren't (negative theology,

the informational theory of nothing) and by spelling out some of the more spiritual

aspects of dialectical nihilism, its closeness to Buddhism, Daoism and all that.

The possibility of empirical evidence for dialectical nihilism

In discussing the empirical evidence for dialectical nihilism, we should beware not to

shoot ourselves in the foot. After all, we have just declared the empirical world to be

an illusion. How then can empirical evidence have any value for us? I think, however,

there is a way out of this conundrum. Remember our earlier Kantian sounding claim

that nothingness is the thing-in-itself behind the phenomena. In the same vein we

said that in the appearances there is nothing that appears. My suggestion now is to

5

take this literally: what appears is the nothing, such that it makes itself apparent in

the appearances. Thus, if the nothing is the coincidentia oppositorum, then this

antithetical structure of the nothing will become apparent in the phenomena. On

could compare this to a doctrine in Schopenhauer's philosophy with which dialectical

nihilism has indeed many things in common (see below on the principle of sufficient

reason and illusory nature of empirical reality). As is well-known, Schopenhauer took

the Kantian thing-in-itself to be an antagonistic, internally divided Will-to-Life. Thus

the bellum omnium contra omnes that according to Schopenhauer characterizes our

empirical world is interpreted by him as expressing on the phenomenal level the

antagonistic nature of thing-in-itself, the Will-to-Life. I suggest that something

similar holds for dialectical nihilism, save that here of course the thing-in-itself is not

rethought as Will-to-Life but as antithetically structured nothingness. Thus the

phenomenal world comes to express this antithetical structure.

One further way to understand this is in terms of what I said above about the nature

of possibility: everything is possible within the nothing as long as it is impossible, i.e.

as long as it is composed of antithetical elements that add up to nothing. Thus, we can

say, the empirical world studied by physics is possible only if it is ultimately nothing,

i.e. only of it is composed of polar opposites that cancel each other out. In this way

the empirical world expresses – in a Schopenhauerian sense – the antithetical

structure of the nothing. In this very general sense, one could say, dialectical nihilism

makes an empirical prediction, namely, that the empirical world is composed of

mutually cancelling polar opposites. And surprisingly, this prediction is confirmed by

contemporary physics as it shows how the physical universe is characterized on a

fundamental level by various polarities, notably the polarity between matter and

antimatter, and between positive and negative energy. Now, according to many

physicists, these polar opposites ultimately cancel each other out, thus adding up to

nothing. According to them, this is precisely what allows us to explain how the

universe could have emerged from nothing, i.e. why the Big Bang occurred, namely,

because nothing somehow 'split' itself into positive and negative energy, and into

matter and antimatter! Clearly, this scientific theory – which is advocated by many

renowned physicists like Alan Guth, Ed Tryon, Stephen Hawking and Lawrence

Krauss – fits dialectical nihilism hand in glove.

Yet there remains a big difference: physics obviously operates under the assumption

that physical reality is real, that it exists, whereas dialectical nihilism claims that the

existence of physical reality is illusory since ultimately nothing exists. Or, to

anticipate conclusions from following paragraphs, physics operates under the

principle of sufficient reason (PSR), the assumption that physical reality can be fully

explained in terms of fundamental causes, whereas dialectical nihilism – following

Kant and Schopenhauer – stresses the logical incoherence of applying the PSR to the

universe (or everything that exists) as a whole. Thus there is no ultimate explanation

of the universe; the chain of causes stretches back to infinity, both spatially (the

infinitely small) and temporally (the infinite past), and the entire causal chain

6

becomes curiously free-floating, suspended in mid-air so to speak, which shows

precisely its illusory nature. Physics, working under the assumption of the PSR, can

think of the relation of the universe to the nothing only as a temporal and causational

relation, such that the universe emerges out of nothing, with the latter acting as a

kind of first cause of the universe (the 'splitting' of nothingness into positive and

negative energy). For dialectical nihilism, however, this is ultimately an incoherent

notion, partly because the temporal chain of causes is necessarily infinite and thus

without a first cause, and partly because the idea that nothingness can cause anything

simply makes no sense (a cause must be something that exist, but the nothing is

precisely the inexistent, so how then could it possible cause anything?). The temporal

origination of the universe out of nothing, therefore, is for dialectical nihilism part of

the illusory appearance of the nothing. In other words: within the empirical world,

the nothing appears as the first cause in time, but in truth the entire temporal chain

of causes (i.e. the empirical world as a whole) is an illusory appearance of the nothing

within the nothing.

Perhaps we can make this more precise in mathematical terms by considering the fact

that zero is the precise sum of all positive and negative numbers. You can picture this

sum as a folding of the real number line onto itself using zero as the hinge, so that

every number on that line meets its negative counterpart: in that way all numbers are

subtracted and only zero remains. Now what if zero, as the sum of all numbers, can

be said to still contain all those numbers within itself in a sublated, cancelled form, as

pure unactualized possibilities? In that sense one could say that zero is the ultimate

coincidentia oppositorum in mathematical form, and the above idea that the nothing

consists of all possible beings and antibeings gains a clear (or perhaps not so clear)

mathematical sense. Add to this the idea that physical reality can ultimately only be

known through numbers (the fundamental formulae of physics), and the conception

of our universe as a possible configuration within the nothingness of zero becomes a

distinct even if speculative possibility on the horizon of science. But for now I must

leave this – admittedly very speculative – suggestion undeveloped.

The hypothesis of the zero energy universe in physics

To repeat: contemporary physics confirms dialectical nihilism in that it pictures the

universe as basically nothing, because the polar opposites that compose it cancel each

other out. This, according to many physicists, is what allows the universe to have

emerged from nothing without violating the common sense principle that from

nothing only nothing can come. In physics, of course, this principle is known as the

law of energy conservation: energy (or its equivalent in mass) can neither be created

out of nothing nor destroyed. Given this law, the only way for the universe to have

emerged out of nothing is if it actually consists of zero energy, which in turn is only

possible if the positive and negative energies in the universe cancel each other

completely. As Hawking and Mlodinow put it: "Bodies such as stars or black holes

cannot just appear out of nothing. But a whole universe can... On the scale of the

entire universe, the positive energy of the matter can be balanced by the negative

7

gravitational energy, and so there is no restriction on the creation of whole

universes." (Hawking and Mlodinow 2010: 227) This obviously requires some further

explanation. Let’s start with the concept of positive energy. This is the energy

invested in matter, both in the constitution of matter itself ('congealed energy') and in

its movement (kinetic energy). Obviously, given the sheer size of the material

universe, there is a tremendous lot of positive energy (though no one is quite sure

how much). At the same time, there appears to be an equal amount of negative energy

stored in the gravitational attraction that exists between all pieces of matter. The

positive energy of matter is therefore precisely balanced by the negative energy of

gravity, so ultimately there is no energy in the universe at all. Here is how Stephen

Hawking explains it:

"[T]he total energy of the universe is exactly zero. The matter in the universe is made

out of positive energy. However, the matter is all attracting itself by gravity. Two

pieces of matter that are close to each other have less energy than the same two pieces

a long way apart, because you have to expand energy to separate them against the

gravitational force that is pulling them together. Thus, in a sense, the gravitational

field has negative energy. In the case of a universe that is approximately uniform in

space, one can show that this negative gravitational energy exactly cancels the

positive energy represented by matter. So the total energy of the universe is zero."

(Hawking 1988: 146)

This is a crucial conclusion. Since everything in the physical universe is in one form

or another made of energy, the fact that that energy is zero implies that in physical

terns there exists nothing at all! As we have noted, this greatly simplifies the task of

explaining how the universe came into existence. Since, energetically speaking, the

universe is nothing, its ultimate cause can be nothing. The well-known quantum

chemist Peter Atkins puts this point as follows: "First, it is important to realize that

there probably isn’t anything here anyway… Of course we are part of and surrounded

by things; but at a deep level there is nothing. I shall now try to resolve this paradox,

for once it is resolved the notion of creation ex nihilo – creation of something from

absolutely nothing – is greatly simplified… The bottom line, prejudiced with a dash of

speculation, is that the initial endowment of energy at the creation was exactly zero,

and the total energy has remained fixed at that value for all time… What we see

around us is in fact nothing, but Nothing that has been separated into opposites to

give, thereby, the appearance of something..." (Atkins 2011: 13, 17)

Fermionic polarities and quantum fluctuations

In physics this idea – that reality emerged out of nothing because the nothing split

into polar opposites – can be found on two levels, firstly in the theory of how matter

and antimatter emerge from quantum fluctuations, secondly in the theory of cosmic

inflation which tells how positive and negative energy became separated during and

immediately after the Big Bang. In the following we will take a short look at both

theories. Let's start with the polarity of matter and antimatter. Since matter consists

8

of particles, this polarity comes down to an opposition between particles and

antiparticles (collectively known as "fermions"). According to quantum physics, for

every type of particle there is a type of antiparticle with opposite properties, such that

when they meet they annihilate each other. In fact, particles and antiparticles can

only come into existence together, in pairs. Here is what John Gribbin writes about it:

"The only way you can make a 'new' fermion, such as an electron, out of energy is if,

at the same time, you make a mirror-image anti-particle (in this case, a positron). The

mirror-image particle has opposite quantum properties (including, in this case,

positive electric charge instead of negative electric charge) so the two cancel each

other out for the purpose of counting fermions, with one negative and one positive

adding up to nothing." (17) Thus "when a positron meets an electron, both particles

disappear in a puff of high-energy photons – gamma rays – as their opposite

quantum properties cancel each other out." (Gribbin 2007: 62)

Electromagnetic polarity is a prime example of fermionic polarity. Positrons have

positive electric charge, they repel each other but attract the electrons which have

negative charge. Since there is a negative charge for every positive charge, all the

charges ultimately cancel each other, so in the final analysis the total electric charge

of the universe is precisely zero. It is important to remember, however, that

electromagnetic polarity is only one example of fermionic polarity. Even the particles

with no electric charge have this fundamental property of being paired to a type of

antiparticle. There is an antimatter counterpart for the neutron, for example, even

though these particles lack electric charge.

As noted above, particles and antiparticles can only be created together, in pairs.

Since a particle and its antiparticle add up to nothing, the crucial question is whether

they can also emerge from nothing. In fact, quantum physics reveals that something

like this does actually happen. This is the so-called quantum fluctuation of the false

vacuum, whereby particle-antiparticle pairs (such as electrons and positrons)

spontaneously pop in and out of existence in empty space. In quantum mechanics,

this is partly explained by Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle, which – among many

other things – says you cannot precisely measure both the value of an energy field

and the rate at which it changes. Knowledge of the one implies uncertainty about the

other. This pretty much rules out the possibility of empty space, which by definition is

a state with zero energy. But Heisenberg’s principle tells us that if the value of a field

is precisely known to be zero, its rate of change is completely random and thus can’t

be zero. So even in ‘empty’ space, the energy level fluctuates randomly. Thus the

vacuum is better described as a false vacuum, since strictly speaking a real vacuum is

impossible, ruled out by the uncertainty principle. In reality, therefore, 'empty space'

is seething with activity on the quantum scale, with particle-antiparticle pairs

popping in and out of existence all the time.

The separation of positive and negative energy in inflation

So here we have one way in which physics countenances the idea of nothing splitting

9

into opposites, namely, into matter and antimatter. However, we are actually

cheating a bit here because the particle-antiparticle pairs do not literally emerge out

of nothing. Rather they emerge out of the fluctuating energy level of empty space,

which may seem rather ephemeral, but it definitely is not absolutely nothing. So

where does the false vacuum come from? Why is there the energy of empty space to

begin with? This is where the theory of cosmic inflation comes in. This theory is

originally due to physicist Alan Guth, who suggested that the early universe during

the Big Bang went through a period of extremely rapid exponential expansion.

According to Guth, the radius of the universe increased by a million million million

million million (1 with eighty zeros after it) times in only a fraction of a second. This

involved a process of repeated doubling of the universe's size; hence the exponential

nature of the growth. Thus the inflationary theory explains why the expanded space

of the current universe is there, how it evolved from an infinitesimally small point

(called the singularity). We are not going to discuss the details of the inflationary

theory here, since that would take us too far afield. What should be noted, however, is

that the inflationary theory involves a weird interplay of positive and negative energy,

a seemingly magical process in which these two opposite forms of energy emerge out

of nothing by becoming separate.

One way to understand this is through Einstein's discovery that space and gravity are

intrinsically linked. On Einstein's general theory of relativity, gravity just is the

curvature of space. But we have also seen how gravity represents negative energy as

opposed to the positive energy represented by matter. The process of the inflationary

expansion of space, therefore, can also be seen as a process in which the negative

energy of gravity increased exponentially. But how is this possible, given the law of

energy conservation, according to which energy cannot be created or destroyed? As

we have already seen, free creation of energy is only possible because of the mutual

cancellation of positive and negative energy. One form of energy can increase

arbitrarily only so long as the opposite form of energy increases with the same

amount, so that the total amount of energy remains constant. This is precisely what

happened during inflation: the exponential increase of the negative energy of

gravity/space went hand in hand with an equal increase of positive energy. Out of this

positive energy then emerged matter and antimatter through quantum fluctuations.

Thus, as Hawking writes about the inflation process: "when the universe doubles in

size, the positive matter energy and the negative gravitational energy both double, so

the total energy remains zero. During the inflationary phase, the universe increases

its size by a large amount. Thus the total amount of energy available to make particles

becomes very large." (Hawking 1988: 147)

The process of inflation, then, involved a separation of positive and negative energy.

The physicist Tegmark (2014: 105) describes this as a kind of "release": the

exponentially increasing negative energy of inflating space "released" an equal

amount of positive energy. But this metaphor of release is misleading insofar as it

suggests that negative energy came before positive energy, as if the increase of the

10

first caused the increase of the latter. The truth is that, according to inflationary

theory, positive and negative energy emerged simultaneously as they separated out of

a state of zero energy. Insofar as talk of release is at all appropriate here, we should

rather say that it was the state of zero energy which released both negative energy

(gravity/space) and positive energy (the source of matter) out of itself. Alan Guth was

well aware of this strange aspect of his theory, which seems to show how the universe

can emerge out of nothing. Hence his famous remark that the universe is "the

ultimate free lunch".

The problem of initial conditions in physics

In sum, dialectical nihilism is confirmed by physics on two counts. Firstly with regard

to the idea that reality is basically a form nothing; this is confirmed by the hypothesis

of the zero energy universe, where the amounts of positive and negative energy cancel

each other out. Secondly with regard to the idea that reality exists because the

nothing split itself into polar opposites; this is confirmed by the spontaneous creation

of particle-antiparticle pairs out of quantum fluctuations, and by the inflationary

theory according to which positive and negative energy separated out of an initial

state of zero energy. Of course, according to dialectical nihilism, there has been no

real temporal origination of the universe out of nothing: the appearance of such a

temporal origination is part of the illusion of existence due to the antithetical

structure of nothing. Because of the regressive nature of the PSR, the temporal chain

of causes is infinite, ruling out a first cause for the universe. In physics this problem is

reflected in the difficulty of finding the initial conditions of the universe. The universe

is said to have emerged from a Big Bang, but what were the initial conditions that

caused the Big Bang? And what in turn caused those initial conditions? Obviously

there is a regress here that precludes the possibility of ever finding an ultimate

explanation for the temporal emergence of the universe. Thus physicists disagree

about which was primary: did a primordial quantum fluctuation first gave rise to the

singularity which was then 'blown up' by cosmic inflation (as argued by physicists like

Page, Filippenko and Pasachoff), or did inflation come first, producing the empty

space needed for quantum fluctuations to occur in (as argued by Guth, Hawking and

Krauss)? According to dialectical nihilism, this problem is insoluble within physics,

simply because there can be no first cause of the universe due to the regressive nature

of the PSR. Indeed, as I will argue in the following paragraph, the regressive nature of

the PSR undermines the very assumption that "existence" is a logically coherent

notion.

The illusory nature of existence under the PSR

Once you start to think about Leibniz's famous question – "Why is there something

rather than nothing?" – you notice that there is something fishy about it. What could

possibly be the reason or cause why anything exists? Wouldn't that reason/cause

itself have to involve something that exists, since ex nihilo nihil fit, from nothing only

nothing comes? But if we already have to presuppose the existence of something to

explain why anything at all exists, then clearly existence as such cannot be explained.

11

And if it can't be explained, if we can give no reasons why anything exists, then how

can we be so sure that anything exists at all? How can we exclude the possibility that

existence is just an illusion? In fact, my contention is that when we think

systematically about this issue, we cannot avoid the conclusion that the very idea of

existence is fraught with paradox and must therefore be rejected – in other words:

the only valid conclusion is that "nothing exists". I think this follows if we accept the

following axioms, which in themselves appear to be straightforward and

commonsensical:

(A1) There appear (to be) beings. A being is anything that exists. If something does

not exist (i.e. is not a being), then it is nothing.

(A2) All beings fall under the principle of sufficient reason (PSR), such that for every

being there is a sufficient reason explaining why it exists and why it is the way it is.

The reason that explains a being must itself also be a being, i.e. something that exists.

No being can be its own reason.

Now, to begin with, it follows from (A1) and (A2) that there can be no totality of

beings, i.e. that that totality is nothing. This can be shown by way of a reductio ad

absurdum: Suppose a contrario that there does exist a totality of beings. In that case

– because of (A1) – the totality would itself also have to be a being, which – because

of (A2) – would fall under the PSR. But then there would have to be another being

outside of the totality of beings (since no being can explain itself), which is

contradictory, since by definition nothing exists outside of that totality. Thus the

totality of beings cannot possibly fall under the PSR and it cannot possibly be a being,

hence it must be nothing. And if there is no totality of beings, then there simply are

no beings whatsoever!

But doesn't this contradict (A1)? No, because (A1) merely says: there appear (to be)

beings. Beings appear to exist, but – given the above argument – they don't really

exist. In truth, nothing exists. Beings are therefore merely appearances, illusions. To

clarify this crazy conclusion, note that it can also be argued for in the following way:

From (A2) it follows that a being exists only if there is a sufficient reason for it, i.e. a

second being that explains it. But then this second being also needs a sufficient

reason to exist, i.e. a third being which in turn requires a fourth being and so forth ad

infinitum. Thus there is a regressive aspect to the PSR, as is of course well-known.

Once you accept the PSR, you are on a potentially infinite regress of beings explaining

beings – a regress that can only be stopped by assuming there is an ultimate being

that explains itself, a 'God' whose essence implies his existence. This traditional

solution, however, is ruled out by (A2) which says that no being can be its own

reason. It is, after all, easy to see that the notion of a self-grounding being is logically

incoherent. For one, such a being would have to exist before it existed. If it didn't

already exist, how could it possibly explain anything else (including itself)? So this

solution to the regress problem is blocked. The regress implied by the PSR is

12

therefore infinite. And this means that ultimately no being is explained by any other

being, since there is no ultimate reason (explanation, cause) that grounds everything

else. And since – because of (A2) – a being can only exist if there is a sufficient reason

for it, this means that no beings at all exist. The causal chain of beings, because it is

potentially infinite, remains curiously free-floating, ungrounded, suspended in mid-

air. In that sense the entire causal chain is illusory. Of course, we see things around

us, or as we said in (A1): there appear to be beings. But nowhere are these

appearances grounded in something that really exists. They are mere illusions.

This analysis of the illusory nature of existence under the PSR brings dialectical

nihilism in the vicinity of Kant's dialectic qua "logic of illusion". In the second part of

his Critique of Pure Reason, Kant develops a "transcendental dialectic" by showing

how human reason entangles itself in illusions and antinomies by tracing the

conditions of the empirical world back to the ultimate conditions or unconditioned.

Basically he develops the aporiae of ultimate explanation under the PSR as we have

done above. His details may differ from our account, but the gist is the same. The

Kantian meaning of "dialectic" as "logic of illusion" is therefore one of the aspects of

dialectical nihilism.

The PSR in Buddhism and Schopenhauer

In Buddhism this conclusion – the illusory nature of existence under the PSR – is

known as the emptiness ("sunyata") of the world due to its dependent origination

("pratītyasamutpāda"). The doctrine of dependent origination is the Buddhist version

of the PSR: it says that all beings arise only in dependence upon prior conditions.

Seeing that this dependence never terminates, that there is no ultimate condition that

grounds the totality of beings, Buddhism concludes that all beings are empty of

intrinsic existence. The world of dependent origination – where, as the Buddha said,

"this is only because that is" – is ultimately unreal, an endless web of illusions, "the

veil of Maya". In Western philosophy the same conclusion was drawn by

Schopenhauer on the basis of his reflections on the PSR. Of course, Schopenhauer

was in this regard strongly influenced by Buddhism, but he also points to classic

thinkers in the Western tradition as anticipating the same conclusion (see the quote

below). For Schopenhauer, the emptiness of the world under the PSR is most clearly

demonstrated by the paradoxical nature of time, where each moment follows from

the preceding one, thus showing the PSR in its most simple form:

"This simplest form of the principle [of sufficient reason] we have found to be time.

In it each instant is only in so far as it has effaced the preceding one, its generator, to

be itself in turn as quickly effaced. The past and the future [...] are empty as a dream,

and the present is only the indivisible and unenduring boundary between them. And

in all the other forms of the principle of sufficient reason, we shall find the same

emptiness, and shall see that not only time but also space, and the whole content of

both of them, i.e., all that proceeds from causes and motives, has a merely relative

existence, is only through and for another like itself, i.e., not enduring. The substance

13

of this doctrine is old: it appears in Heraclitus when he laments the eternal flux of

things; in Plato when he degrades the object as that which is ever becoming but never

is; in Spinoza as the doctrine of the mere accidents of the one substance which is and

endures. Kant opposes what is thus known as the mere phenomenon to the thing in

itself. Lastly, the ancient wisdom of the Indian philosophers declares, "It is Maya, the

veil of deception, which blinds the eyes of mortals, and makes them behold a world of

which they cannot say either that it is or that it is not: for it is like a dream; it is like

the sunshine on the sand which the traveler takes from afar for water, or the stray

piece of rope he mistakes for a snake."" (Schopenhauer 1958: 7-8)

The regressive nature of absolute illusion

So, to summarize, from (A1) and (A2) we derive the nothingness of the totality of

beings and the concomitant conclusion that all beings are nothing more than empty

appearances, illusions. Now, however, one might ask whether these two conclusions

contradict each other. After all, if in truth nothing exists, how then can there be

appearance at all? Isn't even appearance, no matter how illusory, still something that

exists and thus not nothing? Yet this existence of illusion/appearance is very hard to

make sense of. We have already pointed to the fleeting nature of the sensory flux as

something that undermines the existence of appearance. We can now fortify this

conclusion in the following way: insofar as illusion exists, it must – because of (A2) –

fall under the PRS and as such it becomes part of the very same vicious regress that

undermines the notion of real existence. So the only thing we can say, if we insist that

illusion too exists, is that there appears to be illusion, or that we are under the

illusion that there is illusion. And if this illusion of illusion is in turn something that

exists, then we simply get an illusion of illusion of illusion. Clearly, as long as we take

appearance/illusion as something that exists, we get an infinite regress similar to the

regress of beings under the PSR – i.e. we get an illusory appearance that there is an

illusory appearance and so on. Nowhere does this regress terminate in real being,

nowhere can the naked existence of illusion be pinpointed. The existence of illusion

slips through our fingers whenever we try to grasp it. But, so one might ask, can't we

then say that at least this infinite regress of illusions exists? It shall be clear by now

that all we can say is that there appears to be this regress of appearances. Such is the

nature of absolute illusion, which is so all-encompassing that even its own existence

is illusory. Thus our conclusion that nothing at all exists does not contradict our

second conclusion that there are illusions/appearances.

Explaining the illusion of existence

Nevertheless, we still have the feeling that we must explain something, however hard

this 'something' might be to define. We still want to know why – given the conclusion

that nothing at all exists – there nevertheless is (or appears to be) the illusion of

existence. As I indicated in the Introduction, dialectical nihilism explains this illusion

in terms of a dialectical conception of the nothing as consisting of infinitely many

antithetical elements that cancel each other out. Thus in truth nothing at all exists,

but this nothing consists of infinitely many possible beings and antibeings. These

14

beings and antibeings do not exist. They are merely 'present' or 'contained' in the

nothing in a sublated, annihilated, canceled form. As we will say: they inexist in the

nothing, where "inexist" carries the double meaning of "inexistence" and "existing

in". The nothing is the totality of all possible mutually cancelling, inexisting beings

and antibeings. Now the fact that for us there nevertheless appear to exist beings

follows from our finitude as observers, which keeps us from seeing the whole, the

nothing. As finite, limited observers we see only fragments of the whole, not the

whole itself, and these fragments necessarily appear to exist, simply because we

abstract them away from the whole in which they are nothing. It is because we as

finite observers have only a partial view on the whole that beings appear to us. Were

we to see the whole we would see nothing, because then we would see all beings as

cancelled by their antibeings. It is precisely because we are imperfect that we see

something. For a perfect mind, there simply is nothing to see. It would see the whole,

the ultimate coincidentia oppositorum and thus nothing at all. Indeed, such a perfect

mind would see its own non-existence as well: as soon as it sees the whole it becomes

one with it, thereby disappearing altogether.

Now it might be said there is an obvious objection to this story. According to the

above explanation, the illusion arises because we as finite observers see only a

fragment of the totality of all possible beings and antibeings that together add up to

the nothing, and that fragment necessarily appears to exist because it is abstracted

away from the whole in which it is nothing. Now this invites the following critical

question: where do we as finite observers come from? Doesn't dialectical nihilism

presuppose our existence as finite observers to explain the illusion of existence? If so,

then existence is not really (or not totally) an illusion, since we obviously still exist!

This objection, however, is answered very easily, namely, as follows: the existence of

the observer is not presupposed; rather, that (apparent) existence is explained as

following from the antithetical nature of the nothing. The crucial point is that the

nothing, as containing in sublated form all possible beings and antibeings, contains

us as observers as well. We, too, inexist in the nothing, because we too are ultimately

cancelled by antibeings in the nothing. And as a distinct possibility within the

nothing, we have a certain determinacy, a certain possible essence, which includes

consciousness and observation. And that is precisely what our phenomenal world

amounts to: a possible structure of possible observations made by possible observers

who inexist in the nothing – which is simply another way of saying that our

observations are not real but illusory. As merely possible, our observations have no

actual existence, just like we ourselves have no actual existence. And since we as

possible beings within the nothing constitute only an infinitesimally small part of the

nothing, our possible experiences and thoughts can never grasp the nothing as a

whole, i.e. the totality of all possible beings and antibeings. We observe only

fragments of the nothing, fragments which appear to exist because they are

abstracted away from the totality in which they are nothing. So given the antithetical

structure of the nothing, i.e. its consisting of all possible beings and antibeings, the

nothing necessarily contains possible beings with awareness, who appear to be aware

15

of something. In that sense, our (illusory) awareness is just an internal, unactualized,

inexistent possibility within the nothing – one possibility among infinitely many

other unactualized possibilities.

Russell Standish's Theory of Nothing: A critique

In recent philosophy a similar thesis has been advanced by the Australian

computational scientist Russell K. Standish. His 2006 book Theory of Nothing

develops a theory similar to dialectical nihilism in that it describes the ultimate

reality, the totality of beings, as a nothing – a nothing in which there nevertheless

appear to be 'somethings' due to the limited perspectives of observers who are part of

that nothing. Standish's basic argument is that a state where everything possible

exists ("the Plenitude" as he calls it) is so mind-bogglingly huge that it is simply

inaccessible to the human mind. The scientific background to Standish's idea that

everything possible exists is the well-known hypothesis of the infinite multiverse,

which has gained considerable currency in present-day physics for various reasons,

ranging from cosmology (the hypothesis of eternal inflation) to the many worlds

interpretation of quantum mechanics up to more speculative arguments based on

mathematical Platonism, i.e. the claim that all mathematically possible objects exist.

Standish uses mathematical information theory to show that this infinite multiverse

or Plenitude contains zero information and is thus equivalent to nothing. To illustrate

his point, he refers to a famous story by Borges, The Library of Babel. The story

describes a library containing infinitely many books composed of all possible

combinations of letters. Within this fantastic library are the works of all known

authors as well as all the possible masterpieces by unknown authors, but also

infinitely many books that are complete gibberish. Potentially, the library contains all

relevant information, all the answers to our questions. In practice, however, all this

information is inaccessible. If you pick out a book, the chance that the book will mean

something to you will be infinitesimally small. Thus the library contains virtually no

information whatsoever. According to Standish, the Plenitude is like the library of

Babel in that its informational content is zero:

"In the [...] theory I present, all possible descriptions of things exist, of infinite length,

composed of symbols from an alphabet of your choice... As with Borges's library, the

complete ensemble has precisely zero information. The Everything is in fact a

Nothing." (Standish 2006: 15) "[We] note that the collection of all possible

descriptions has zero complexity, or information content. This is a consequence of

algorithmic information theory, the fundamental theory of computer science. There is

a mathematical equivalence between the Everything, as represented by this collection

of all possible descriptions and Nothing, a state of no information." (Idem: 5)

According to Standish, this informational equivalence of everything and nothing then

allows us to answer Leibniz's question and to explain how something emerged from

nothing: "In the beginning, there was Nothing, not even a beginning! From out of this

Nothing emerged everything we see around us today." (Idem: 21) How does he pull

16

off this magic trick? By placing the observer within the Plenitude. Since the Plenitude

contains everything possible, it also contains us, the observers, for whom the

Plenitude as a whole is informationally void. Yet as observers we necessarily observe

something, and this means we must have a partial view of the Plenitude from the

inside. It is because we, as limited observers, observe only part of the Plenitude that

the zero information of the whole gives way to non-zero information. According to

Standish, that is why there appears to be something rather than nothing. As he puts

it: "That some of the descriptions must describe conscious observers who obviously

observe something, gives us a mechanism for getting Something from Nothing:

Something is the "inside view" of Nothing." (Idem: 5)

I like this idea that "Something is the "inside view" of Nothing" very much. It is

basically the same idea that I argued above, namely, that for us – as possible finite

observers within the nothing – things appear to exist because we cannot observe the

whole in which everything is nothing. But this similarity hides a crucial difference.

The trouble comes from Standish's information-theoretic approach. The problem is

that the informational nothing is not a real nothing, i.e. not a complete absence of

existence, but rather a superabundant existence in disguise. Indeed, as Standish

himself stresses, the nothing is really everything, the Plenitude of the infinite

multiverse, which to us appears as nothing because we have virtually no cognitive

access to it. So when Standish claims he can show how something emerged from

nothing through the act of observation, he is clearly cheating, since he is already

presupposing the existence of the Plenitude to which the observer belongs. And it is

only by thus presupposing the existence of the observer that Standish can claim that

the Plenitude is informationally void. The crucial point is, as Standish admits, that

information always presupposes an observer: it is only for a receiver that a source

contains more or less information. As Standish says: "Information is an observer

dependent thing. Shakespeare's "Romeo and Juliet" is nothing more than random

gibberish to someone who doesn't know English." (Idem: 12) Thus it is only for an

observer that the Plenitude is nothing; the Plenitude is not nothing in itself. So if

Standish really wanted to answer Leibniz's question, he should instead have tried to

explain why the Plenitude exists. And that's a pretty tall order, because – as we have

seen – for Standish the Plenitude contains nothing less than the infinite multiverse

from contemporary physics. To explain that, therefore, he would have to fall back on

physical explanations. He would have to answer questions like: what caused the Big

Bang, what caused the inflation of space, why is the universal wave function the way

it is? Thus he would have to fall back on the principle of sufficient reason (PSR). But

as we have seen, the idea that the totality of beings falls under the PSR is simply

incoherent, which in turn undermines the very assumption that there is a totality of

beings. Thus the only consistent answer to Leibniz's question – "Why is there

something rather than nothing?" – is to bite the bullet and admit that in truth there is

nothing at all, and that existence is just an illusion following from the antithetical

structure of the nothing.

17

Dialectical nihilism vs. negative theology

Standish's information-theoretic approach to the everything-is-nothing idea bears a

close (and probably intentional) resemblance to a well-known strategy in classical

metaphysics known as negative or apophatic theology. Thus our critique of Standish's

approach applies equally well to this tradition of negative theology. In the following I

shall say a few words about this, in order to clearly distinguish dialectical nihilism

from negative theology, before moving on to my concluding remarks. The basic idea

behind negative theology is that God – as the ultimate source of reality – transcends

all our cognitive powers: God is so infinitely perfect that we as finite and imperfect

creatures simply cannot conceptualize Him. Since all our concepts derive from our

finite, imperfect existence, we cannot say what God is: we can only say what He is

not. This is the via negativa (negative way) of negative theology: we must progress

towards the true vision of God by negating our concepts as inappropriate to God's

transcendent nature. Thus we say: God is not good (in our human sense), He is

beyond good; God is not infinite (as opposed to and thus limited by the finite), He is

beyond infinite; God is not eternal (in time), God is beyond time, etc. Finally we end

up with a most perfect being that appears to be completely empty, devoid of any

property, an absolute perfection with no determinacy.

Now it is admittedly very tempting to see in this 'empty God' the absolute nothing of

dialectical nihilism. This is especially so since negative theology sometimes proceeds

to such extremes that even our concept of existence (or being) is said not to apply to

God: thus even the proposition that God exists is to be denied! In this way negative

theology comes awfully close to 'heretical' nihilism. Take, for example, the following

extreme sounding remark by the 9th century theologian Eriugena: "We do not know

what God is. God Himself does not know what He is because He is not anything.

Literally God is not, because He transcends being." Is Eriugena here denying that

God exists? If so, then negative theology would truly be nihilistic. But the final phrase

of Eriugena's remark – "because He transcends being" – should make us wary.

Eriugena is not saying that God does not exist, he is saying that God transcends our

limited conception of existence: God's being is so superlative that it can't be captured

by what we mean by "being". Thus in negative theology the via negativa is invariably

complemented by a via eminentiae (way of eminence) in which our finite concepts –

which are denied of God – undergo a process of absolute maximization or

suprematization so as to describe God correctly. In that way we can say: God is not

existent, He is supra-existent; God is not wise, He is supra-wise; God is not good, He

is supra-good, etc. Granted, for negative theology, these suprematized perfections

remain outside the grasp of finite human cognition, but they nevertheless become

accessible to us in a mystical vision of God after our minds have been cleansed from

all finite concepts. Thus it is clear that, even if negative theology appears to approach

nihilism in its negative characterization of God as a 'no-thing', it in fact intends to say

the complete opposite of nihilism. Far from being absolutely nothing, the God of

negative theology is rather the most perfect supra-being, the creative ground of

everything. This dialectical relation to nihilism – where the abyss of nihilism is first

18

approached but then overcome in mystical intuition – is clearly visible in the neo-

Platonism of the 3rd century philosopher Plotinus (arguably the arch-father of

negative theology). In describing the soul's ascend to God (Plotinus speaks of "the

One"), Plotinus clearly recognizes the danger that at first the via negativa results

only in a negative conception of the One, an utter emptiness from which the soul

shirks away in horror, fearing a fall into atheism:

"The soul or mind reaching towards the formless finds itself incompetent to grasp

where nothing bounds it [...]; in sheer dread of holding to nothingness, it slips away.

The state is painful; often it seeks relief by retreating from all this vagueness to the

region of sense, there to rest on solid ground [...]." (Enneads VI.9.3, 1-6)

The scholar John Peter Kenney, in his book Mystical Monotheism, explains this

passage as follows:

"From our position below, the One appears to be empty because we cannot grasp it

within our normal conceptual limits. For this reason the soul fears that the One is

really nothing at all. It is clear from the subsequent discussion that the soul is

mistaken in this, that the One is not lacking; and Plotinus employs the theme of the

One as the archē of all reality to enforce the point [...]. A true philosophical study of

the One would reveal this to the soul [...], and for this reason the soul should not

withdraw from this first principle, the Good." (Kenney 1991: 145)

Thus for Plotinus, nihilism is a mere passageway to the mystical vision of God:

although at first appearing to be nothing, God is in fact the opposite, He is the most

perfect ground of reality. For dialectical nihilism, in contrast, God is really nothing –

or rather: there really is nothing at all, no God, no reality, nothing. Nothingness is the

true nature of (illusory) existence. This difference between negative theology and

dialectical nihilism becomes crucial in the light of Leibniz's question: "Why is there

something rather than nothing?" Here negative theology cannot escape the aporiae of

ultimate explanation under the PSR. Although in negative theology the ultimate

ground of reality appears to be nothing, it most certainly is not nothing. The One is

something, indeed it is the most perfect being. As such its existence needs to be

explained, since all beings fall under the PSR. Here negative theology can only appeal

to a traditional conception of God as causa sui, whose existence is implied in His

essence. But from a rational standpoint, such an explanation cannot hold up, since no

being can explain itself. Again, then, dialectical nihilism comes out as the only

consistent answer to Leibniz's question. Since the totality of beings cannot possibly be

explained, the only rational conclusion is that in truth there is nothing.

Concluding remarks: The spiritual side of dialectical nihilism

If the theory I have presented in the preceding pages sounds just a bit too grim, I

should stress that there is also a positive side to dialectical nihilism, akin to

Buddhism and Daoism. In Buddhism too we find the idea that the whole of existence

19

is nothing but illusion ("the veil of Maya") and that ultimately nothing exists but

nothingness or emptiness ("sunyata"), the "empty fullness" that contains within itself

everything possible as pure potentiality. Although the idea that the ultimate

nothingness is composed of polar opposites is lacking in Buddhism, it does of course

form an essential part of Daoism with its the yin-yang polarity. Though the ultimate

source of reality, the Dao, is in itself empty, it does generate the opposition between

yin and yang which through their dynamic interplay generate everything else.

However, many of the oppositions countenanced by Daoism as manifestations of yin

and yang – e.g. heaven and earth, male and female, light and dark – are not

ontologically fundamental because they are not truly self-cancelling: the polar

opposites do not add up to nothing. The synthesis of day and night, for example, is

not nothing but the grayness of twilight. And what results from the unification of

male and female? A hermaphrodite, perhaps, but most likely you will get a lot of

children, which is as far from nothing as you can get. These dualities, then, are not

ontologically fundamental, i.e. they do not add up to nothing. Rather they are

superficial dualities taken from daily life. This testifies to the ancient mythological

origin of Daoism, which stretches back to shamanism. In contrast, I like to see

dialectical nihilism as a rationalization of Daoism, as the rational core inside its

mystical shell – though perhaps the stress on the illusory nature of the empirical

world brings dialectical nihilism closer to Buddhism than to Daoism, which seems to

have a more optimistic view of life. Not that dialectical nihilism necessarily implies a

pessimistic view of life. To be sure, the idea that our existence is in fact nothing more

than a fleeting illusion, based – literally – on nothing, may not seem very alluring. It

can cause a sense of existential anxiety (Heidegger) or even horror, an existential

horror vacui so to speak, perfectly described by Hegel:

"The human being is this night, this empty nothing, that contains everything in its

simplicity – an unending wealth of many presentations, images, of which none

happens to occur to him – or which are not present. This night, the inner of nature,

that exists here – pure self – in phantasmagorical presentations, is night all around it,

here shoots a bloody head – there another white shape, suddenly here before it, and

just so disappears. One catches sight of this night when one looks human beings in

the eye – into a night that becomes awful..." (Realphilosophie manuscript of 1805–

06)

But maybe this "night of the world" is like the mystic's "dark night of the soul", a

necessary passage through pure negativity in which one has to 'die' in order to be

reborn again into the light of day.

[email protected]

This essay was first published February 13th 2015 on my blog:

http://critique-of-pure-interest.blogspot.nl/

20

References

-Asimov, Isaac (1974), “What is Beyond the Universe?”, in: Science Digest, vol. 69,

69-70.

Atkins, Peter (2011), On Being. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

-Gribbin, John (2007), The Universe: A Biography. Allen Lane, London.

-Hawking, Stephen (1988), A Brief History of Time. Bantam Books: London.

-Hawking, Stephen & Mlodinow, Leonard (2010), The Grand Design. Bantam Books:

London.

Kenney, John Peter (1991), Mystical Monotheism: A Study in Ancient Platonic

Theology. Brown University Press: Providence.

-Schopenhauer, Arthur (1958), The World as Will and Representation, Volume I. The

Falcon's Wing Press: Colorado.

-Standish, Russell (2006), Theory of Nothing. BookSurge Australia.

-Tegmark, Max (2014), Our Mathematical Universe. Alfred A. Knopf: New York.