Aristotle's completeness test as heuristics for an account of dynamicity

25
In: V. Petrov/A. Scarfe (eds.) 2015, Dynamic Being, Cambridge Scholars, 228. 1 Aristotle’s ‘completeness test’ as heuristics for an account of dynamicity Johanna Seibt Aarhus University Abstract: If being were ‘dynamic,’ would it be more amenable to a definition? In this paper I present a number of preliminary considerations for an exploration of this question. Working from the methodological stance of analytical ontology, I assume that the first task for an ontology of dynamic being(s) must be to locate suitable linguistic data that can represent the conceptual content to be modelled by an ontological domain theory. I try to show that Aristotle’s socalled ‘completeness test’ in Metaphysics Θ. 6, and the discussion of this passage in Aristotle scholarship, offers some useful heuristic leads to a class of inferential data (aspectual inferences) that analytical ontologists have all but overlooked so far. In addition, I suggest that the passage also can offer some ideas about how one might formulate, in mereological terms, a component of an implicit definition of dynamicity. The study of dynamic being or ‘dynamicity’ is an unlikely task for a presentday analytical ontologist. Other modes of being, such as actuality, possibility, and necessity, have been dominating the discussion during the early decades of post war analytical ontology, together with a focus on the ontological reduction of universals; even during the last three decades, when the spotlight finally turned onto the category of events, the problem of existence in time, and the ontology of emergence, the investigation of the nature of dynamic being remained outside the purview of the mainstream debate. With the exception of work on verbal aspects, it seems fair to say that analytical ontology so far has been strikingly disinterested in the exploration of dynamicity and the forms of dynamic being. How should one interpret this startling neglect? Is this another instance of the “Werdensvergessenheit” that Nietzsche castigated as the distinctive mindset of Western metaphysics? 1 And if so, is it a purely sociological phenomenon, a case of theoretical habituation that is reinforced and propagated by the review system for professional publications that gained such weight in 20 th century analytical philosophy in general? Or is it rather, as Bergson would have us explain, the inevitable outcome of using the wrong investigative 1 Cf. Nietzsche (1882/1974), 306.

Transcript of Aristotle's completeness test as heuristics for an account of dynamicity

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  1  

 Aristotle’s  ‘completeness  test’  as  heuristics  for  an  account  of  dynamicity  

 Johanna  Seibt  

Aarhus  University    Abstract:  If  being  were  ‘dynamic,’      would  it  be  more  amenable  to  a  definition?    In  this  paper  I  present  a  number  of  preliminary  considerations  for  an  exploration  of  this  question.    Working  from  the  methodological  stance  of  analytical  ontology,  I  assume  that  the  first  task  for  an  ontology  of  dynamic  being(s)  must  be  to  locate  suitable  linguistic  data  that  can  represent  the  conceptual  content  to  be  modelled  by  an  ontological  domain  theory.    I  try  to  show  that  Aristotle’s  so-­‐called  ‘completeness  test’  in  Metaphysics  Θ.  6,  and  the  discussion  of  this  passage  in  Aristotle  scholarship,  offers    some  useful  heuristic  leads  to  a  class  of  inferential  data  (aspectual  inferences)  that  analytical  ontologists  have  all  but  overlooked  so  far.    In  addition,  I  suggest  that  the  passage  also  can  offer  some  ideas  about  how  one  might  formulate,  in  mereological  terms,    a  component  of  an  implicit  definition  of  dynamicity.    The  study  of  dynamic  being  or  ‘dynamicity’  is  an  unlikely  task  for  a  present-­‐day  

analytical  ontologist.    Other  modes  of  being,  such  as  actuality,  possibility,  and  

necessity,  have  been  dominating  the  discussion  during  the  early  decades  of  post-­‐

war  analytical  ontology,  together  with  a  focus  on  the  ontological  reduction  of  

universals;  even  during  the  last  three  decades,  when  the  spotlight  finally  turned  

onto  the  category  of  events,  the  problem  of  existence  in  time,  and  the  ontology  of  

emergence,  the  investigation  of  the  nature  of  dynamic  being  remained  outside  

the  purview  of  the  mainstream  debate.    With  the  exception  of  work  on  verbal  

aspects,  it  seems  fair  to  say  that  analytical  ontology  so  far  has  been  strikingly  

disinterested  in  the  exploration  of  dynamicity  and  the  forms  of  dynamic  being.  

    How  should  one  interpret  this  startling  neglect?    Is  this  another  instance  

of  the  “Werdensvergessenheit”  that  Nietzsche  castigated  as  the  distinctive  

mindset  of  Western  metaphysics?1    And  if  so,  is  it  a  purely  sociological  

phenomenon,  a  case  of  theoretical  habituation  that  is  reinforced  and  propagated  

by  the  review  system  for  professional  publications  that  gained  such  weight  in  

20th  century  analytical  philosophy  in  general?    Or  is  it  rather,  as  Bergson  would  

have  us  explain,  the  inevitable  outcome  of  using  the  wrong  investigative  

                                                                                                               1  Cf.  Nietzsche    (1882/1974),  306.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  2  

instruments,  namely,  theories  that  rely  on  conceptual  cognition  and  codified  

meaning?2    

In  my  view,  the  reasons  for  the  neglect  of  the  category  of  processes  and  

the  dynamic  mode  of  being  lie  in  a  combination  of  sociological  and  conceptual  

factors.    As  I  have  argued  elsewhere,  analytical  philosophy  may  have  shed  the  

“myth  of  the  museum”  (Quine)  and  the  “myth  of  the  given”  (Sellars)  but  it  still  

trades  the  “myth  of  substance,”  a  set  of  about  twenty  traditional  presuppositions  

about  the  features  of  basic  categories  or  types  of  beings.3  While  these  

presuppositions  block  the  introduction  of  the  conceptual  tools  needed  for  a  

theory  of  dynamicity  and  dynamic  entities,  they  are,  as  I  have  tried  to  show,  by  

no  means  ‘laws  of  thought’  or  constitutive  elements  of  conceptualization.      

Equally  important,  in  my  view,  is  the  insight  that  the  neglect  of  dynamic  

entities  and  the  notion  of  dynamicity  is  not  due  to  the  methodological  approach  

that  has  become  characteristic  for  analytical  ontology,  in  particular  the  use  of  

formal  languages  for  the  description  of  ontological  domains,  or  the  use  of  

quantifier  logic  for  the  analysis  of  ontological  commitments.  While  the  

presuppositions  of  the  “myth  of  substance”  have  strongly  influenced  our  

informal  interpretations  and  axiomatizations  of  formal  tools,  there  are  no  

principled  obstacles  against  analytical  process  ontology  in  the  sense  of  a  formal  

theory  of  dynamicity  and  dynamic  entities.4        

My  aim  in  this  paper  is  to  present  some  preliminary  and  heuristic  

consideration  for  a  formal  account  of  the  notion  of  dynamicity.    Process  

philosophers  of  all  stripes  share  the  belief  that  being  is  a  fundamentally  dynamic  

affair,  but  the  sense  of  the  epithet  is  mostly  left  in  the  space  of  the  metaphorical.  

Some  process  philosophers  hold  that  the  notion  of  dynamicity  cannot  be  defined  

or  even  conceptualized.    The  considerations  that  underlie  this  position—I  call  it  

the  ‘ineffability  position’—surely  must  be  taken  into  account  by  any  attempt  to  

situate  the  notion  of  ‘dynamicity,’  ‘dynamic  Being,’  or  ‘dynamic’  (as  predicate  for  

types  of  beings)  within  a  theory.    In  the  following  I  will  address  the  ineffability  

                                                                                                               2  Cf.  Bergson    2002  (The  Idea  of  Duration).  3  Cf.  Seibt  1990,  1995,  1997,  2005,  2008,  2010.    4  For  arguments  in  favor  of  a  pluralist  reading  of  the  existential  quantifier  see  e.g.,  Turner  (2012).    For  sketches  of  a  process  ontology  that  uses  a  non-­‐standard  mereology  as  domain  theory  see  Seibt  1990,  2002,  2004,  2005,  2008,  and  2009.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  3  

concerns  only  obliquely,  however,  by  exploring  the  first  steps  of  a  possible  

strategy  for  an  implicit  definition  of  dynamicity.  

Since  the  study  of  dynamicity  and  its  forms  is  a  new  task  in  ontology,  it  is  

important  to  distinguish  from  the  outset  a  number  of  different  subtasks.    These  

tasks—and  other  tasks  one  might  want  to  add  to  the  list—are  multiply  related,  of  

course,  but  they  are  conceptually  separable  and  much  dialectical  headway  can  be  

made,  I  think,  if  we  consider  them  as  modules  of  a  larger  investigation.      

First,  and  this  is  surely  the  most  significant  distinction,  we  need  to  keep  

ontological  and  metaphysical  investigations  apart.    It  is  a  striking—though  little  

observed  fact—that  during  the  early  phase  of  20th  century  analytical  ontology,  

until  the  1960’s,  ontologists  were  adamant  to  distinguish  ontology  and  

metaphysics,  while  nowadays  the  terms  are  used  almost  interchangeably.5    But  

the  ontological  project  of  devising  a  ‘domain  theory,’  a  rational  reconstruction  of  

the  inferential  commitments  embedded  in  a  natural  or  scientific  language  can  

and  should  be  set  apart  from  metaphysical  project  of  determining  the  status  of  

such  ontological  domain  theories.    Bergson’s  arguments  that  “durée”  or  

becoming  cannot  be  conceptualized  illustrate  the  metaphysical  perspective,  

which  is  driven  by  epistemological  concerns  about  the  significance  of  ontological  

domain  descriptions:  are  these  descriptions  of  reality,  and  if  so,  in  which  sense—

of  reality  in  itself,  reality  for  us,  or  ‘reality’  in  yet  another  sense  that  transcends  

these  traditional  oppositions?  This  is  surely  legitimate  business  in  philosophy,  

and  it  has  particular  traction  on  the  notion  of  dynamicity,  which  lends  itself  

particularly  well  to  a  deconstruction  of  the  traditional  set-­‐up  of  the  skeptical  

dimension.    But  it  is  possible  to  do  category  theory  without  raising  the  questions  

of  the  skeptical  dimensions;  while  Carnap  may  have  been  wrong  in  dismissing  

the  possibility  of  doing  metaphysics,  he  was  right,  in  my  view,  about  the  

possibility  of  doing  ontology  without  metaphysics.    Here  then  is  the  first  task  for  

a  theory  of  dynamicity:  

 (1) A  theory  of  dynamicity  should  position  itself  clearly  with  respect  to  

two  fundamental  investigative  perspectives  that  may,  but  do  not  need  to,  be  combined.    That  is,  a  theory  of  dynamicity  should  clarify  

                                                                                                               5  I  must  omit  here  any  discussion  of  this  terminological  shift,  which,  as  far  as  I  can  see,  has  merely  sociological  reasons.    For  a  presentation  of  the  methodological  insights  of  the  early  analytical  ontologists  see  Seibt  1996,  1997,  and  2000;  for  a  methodological  position  paper  see  Seibt  2001.    

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  4  

whether  it  pursues  an  ‘ontology  of  dynamicity’  or  else  a  ‘metaphysics  of  dynamicity,’  or  both.    An  ontology  of  dynamicity  takes  the  investigative  perspective  of  ontology  and  aims  to  reconstruct  the  inferential  meaning  of  ‘dynamicity’  and  ‘dynamic’    with  the  conceptual  tools  of  an  ontological  ‘domain  theory’  (i.e.,  a  structural  description  of  a  domain  of  truth-­‐makers  for  a  language).    In  contrast,  a  metaphysics  of  dynamicity  either  investigates  the  status  of  a  given  ontological  domain  theory  for  dynamic  beings,  or  else  discusses  the  role  of  dynamicity  in  a  philosophical  account  of  cognition.  

 

Let  us  call  this  first  task  for  a  theory  of  dynamicity  the  task  of  methodological  

positioning.    To  comply  with  it  right  away,  let  me  state  that  my  considerations  in  

this  paper  will  pertain  exclusively  to  the  ontology  of  dynamicity,  in  the  sense  of  

this  term  stated  in  (1).  

    Turning  to  the  ontology  of  dynamicity,  then,  we  can  again  identify  a  

number  of  basic  tasks  among  which  are  the  following  three:  

   (2) An  ontological  account  of  dynamicity  must  suggest  a  direct  definition  

of  dynamicity  in  terms  of  necessary  and  sufficient  conditions,  or  else  an  axiomatic  definition,  or  else  discuss  in  which  sense,  if  any,  dynamicity  can  play  a  role  in  analytical  ontology.    This  task  I  call  the    question  of  the  definability  of  dynamicity.      

(3) It  must  clarify  whether  we  can  make  sense  of  dynamicity  independently  of  temporal  relationships.    In  other  words,  it  must  clarify  whether  it  is  possible  to  claim  that  there  are  dynamic  entities  outside  of  (space  and)  time,  as  Whitehead  notoriously  has  claimed.6    This  task  I  call  the  question  of  atemporal  dynamicity.  

 (4) It  must  clarify  which  modes  of  dynamicity  there  are,  which  are  basic  

and  which  derived,  and  whether  there  is  any  one  basic  mode  of  dynamicity.    This  is  the  question  of  the  primacy  of  directed  dynamicity.  

 The  proximate  target  of  my  following  considerations  is  task  (4),  the  clarification  

of  the  question  of  the  primacy  of  directed  dynamicity,  but  in  the  course  of  the  

discussion  I  shall  also  address  task  (2)  and  propose  a  definition  of  dynamicity.    

 1.  Locating  inferential  constraints        An  ontological  account  of  dynamicity,  if  undertaken  in  the  general  

methodological  paradigm  of  analytical  ontology,  aims  to  reconstruct  conceptual  

                                                                                                               6  But  also,  which  has  hardly  been  noticed  so  far,  by  Wilfrid  Sellars  in  his  1962.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  5  

content  as  manifested  in  (or  constituted  by)  inferential  relations.    If  we  want  to  

explore  what  we  rationally  could  take  ourselves  to  be  committed  to  in  speaking  

about  our  ‘world’  (i.e.,  the  world  of  common  sense  or  the  world  of  physics  etc.)  

we  need  to  begin  by  investigating  the  inferential  commitments  carried  by  

relevant  linguistic  expressions.    The  structure  of  our  world  of  experience—so  

runs  the  basic  methodological  thesis  on  which  neo-­‐Kantianism  and  pragmatism  

could  meet  in  the  1930s—dovetails  with  the  inferential  roles  of  basic  

classificatory  concepts  and  other  linguistic  means  of  encoding  inferential  

knowledge  that  has  been  produced  in  interaction  with  the  world.        

Since,  for  the  analytical  ontologist,  language  is  the  guide  to  the  inferential  

data  that  drive  the  development  of  an  ontological  domain  theory,  it  is  important  

to  focus  on  relevant  linguistic  expressions  and  elements,  and  to  avoid  any  form  

of  linguistic  bias.    For  example,  if  one  were  to  discuss  the  possibility  of  a  domain  

of  ‘dynamic’  entities—as  opposed  to  a  ‘static’  four-­‐dimensional  domain—in  

relation  with  John  McTaggart’s    proof  for  the  impossibility  of  the  A-­‐series,  one  

would  immediately  be  on  the  wrong  track,  no  matter  whether  one  would  argue  

pro  or  contra  dynamicity.    For  the  link  to  McTaggart’s  proof  or  even  his  

terminology  would  create,  first,  a  problematic  tie  between  dynamicity  and  

temporal  flow  or  passage.  Such  a  presuppositional  link  is  to  be  avoided  since  

temporal  passage  does  not  seem  to  be  either  a  sufficient  nor  necessary  condition  

for  dynamicity—temporal  passage  may  be  only  one  special  manifestation  of  

dynamicity.  Only  if  one  could  show  (i)  that  change  is  the  only  type  of  dynamicity,  

(ii)  that  we  must  conceive  of  change  in  terms  of  states  with  contradictory  

features,  and  that  temporal  passage  must    be  conceptualized  in  terms  of  states  

with    contradictory  temporal  features,  such  implications  could  come  into  view.  7      

 Second,  if  we  were  to  begin  a  discussion  of  dynamicity  with  a  reference  to  

the  A-­‐series,  we  would  ,  confusingly,  give  the  impression  that  the  issue  of  

dynamic  being  turns  on  the  question  of  how  to  interpret  tensed  verbal  

predications  or  the  temporal  adjectives  ‘past,’  ‘present,’  and  ‘future.’    But  even  if  

one  could  be  somehow  convinced  that  atemporal  dynamicity  is  not  possible,  or  

even  that  dynamicity  always  requires  temporal  passage,  it  would  be  bizarre  to  

                                                                                                               7  Whether  our  notion  of  temporal  passage  presupposes  (a)  change,  and  (b)  change  in  temporal  characteristics  (‘past,  present,  future’)  is  debatable,  see  e.g.,  Maudlin  2007:  ch.  4.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  6  

assume  from  the  outset  that  tensed  verbal  predications  or  temporal  adjectives  

‘past,  present,  future’  are  the  only  or  even  the  most  relevant  linguistic  aspects  to  

concentrate  on.8  

Such  a  line  of  approach  to  an  analysis  of  the  notion  of  dynamicity  or  

dynamic  being  would  be  a  non-­‐starter  from  the  outset  in  my  view.      I  am  

mentioning  it  here  only  to  draw  attention  that  to  the  fact  that  the  recent  debate  

in  analytical  ontology  on  existence  in  time  has  little  to  offer  for  an  ontology  of  

dynamicity,  even  where  it  nominally  speaks  of  “static”  entities,  of  “events,”  or  

“becoming”.    This  debate  centers  either  explicitly  or  implicitly  around  

McTaggart’s  contrast  between  a  (fourdimensional)  eternalist  universe  and  the  

inconceivable  universe  with  temporal  passage,  where  the  latter  has  been  

replaced  with  the  conception  of  a    “presentist”  universe,  and  the  interpretation  of  

tensed  verbal  predications  and  the  adjectives  of  tense  still  plays  an  important  

role  in  deciding  between  four-­‐dimensionalism  and  presentism.9      

 Instead,  or  so  I  want  to  suggest  here,  an  ontological  account  of  

dynamicity  needs  to  sidestep  contemporary  uses  of  ‘dynamic’  and  ‘static’  in  the  

mainstream  discussion  of  analytical  ontology  and  take  its  bearings  from  other  

sources.    One  possible  heuristics  would  be  to  turn  to  an  analysis  of  scientific  

conceptions  of  dynamic  phenomena  and  to  try  to  identify  relevant  inferential  

constraints  from  the  representational  tools  of  science.    Another  route  towards  

locating  inferential  data  is  to  review  discussions  of  dynamic  being  in  the  history  

of  philosophy.  This  is  the  path  I  shall  follow  here,  turning  to  a  passage  in  

Aristotle  that  contains  central  leads  to  a  general  method  as  well  as  specific  

inferential  constraints.    

The  passage  I  want  to  focus  on  is  Aristotle’s  so-­‐called  ‘completeness  test’  

in  Metaphysics  Φ.  6.    In  this  chapter  Aristotle  comments  on  his  double  distinction  

between,  on  the  one  hand,  dynamis    and  energeia  and,  on  the  other  hand,    

between  kinesis  and  energeia.    The  chapter  can  be  roughly  divided  into  four  

thematic  sections.    (a)  Aristotle  begins  by  announcing  that,  after  treating  dynamis  

in  the  previous  sections,  he  will  now  discuss  energeia;  (b)  he  warns  the  reader  

                                                                                                               8  There  are  languages  with  less  or  more  than  three  forms  of  verbal  tense,  there  are  languages  that  mark  tense  on  nouns  rather  than  on  verbs,  and  there  are  languages  without  adjectives—why  should  English  be  our  guide  to  ontology?  9  Cf.  e.g.  Rudder-­‐Baker  2010.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  7  

that  there  is  merely  an  analogical  unity  among  the  senses  of  energeia;  (c)  then  he  

clarifies  in  which  sense  the  infinite  is  potential,  and  finally  (d)  offers  a  paragraph  

distinguishing  kinesis  and  energeia;  he  concludes  the  chapter  claiming  to  have  

explained  therein  ”what  and  how”  [ti  esti  kai  poion]  energeia  is.        The  relevant  

paragraph  of  section  (d)  runs  as  follows  (cf.  Metaphysics  1048:b18-­‐b35):  

 [1.]  Since  among  actions  [praxeis]  that  have  a  limit  [peras],  none  is  a  completion  [telos],  but  each  is  the  sort  of  thing  relating  to  the  completion—as  e.g.,  slimming  is  to  slimness;  the  [bodily  parts]  themselves  are  in  movement,  though  those  things  which  the  movement  is  for  the  sake  of  [whose  presence  constitutes  slimness]  do  not  yet  belong  [hyparchonta]  to  them—these  things  are  not  action,  or  at  least  not  complete  [teleia],  just  because  it  is  not  a  completion.  But  that  [sort  of  action]  in  which  its  completion  is  contained  [enuparchei]  is  a  [real]  action.10      [2.]    E.g.,  in  the  same  moment  [hama]  one  is  seeing  and  has  seen  [=  “knows”  by  sight],  is  understanding  and  has  understood,  [=possesses  understanding],  is  thinking  and  has  thought  [=  ‘knows’  by  insight].    But  if  you  are  learning,  it’s  not  the  case  that  in  the  same  moment  you  have  learned,  nor  if  you  are  being  cured,  that  in  the  same  moment  you  have  been  cured.  However,  someone  who  is  living  well,  at  the  same  time  has  lived  well,  and  someone  who  is  prospering,  has  prospered.11      [3.]  If  that  were  not  so,  [the  prospering,  e.g.,]  would  have  had  to  come  to  an  end  [pauestai]  at  some  time,  as  is  the  case  with  slimming  [=  when  the  state  of  slimness,  of  one’s  having  completed  an  act  of  slimming  has  been  achieved].  But  in  fact,  it  does  not;  you  are  living  and  have  lived.  [4.]  Of  these  [actions],  then,  one  group  should  be  called  movements  [kineseis],  and  the  other  actualizations  [energeias].12  [5.]  For  every  movement  is  incomplete  [ateles]—slimming,  learning,  walking  [  =  walk-­‐taking],  house-­‐building;  these  are  movements  and  are  incomplete.    [6.]  For  one  cannot  in  the  same  moment  both  be  taking  a  walk  and  have  taken  it,  nor  be  house-­‐building  and  have  housebuilt,  not  be  coming-­‐to-­‐be  and  have  come-­‐to-­‐be,  nor  be  being  moved  [kineitai]  and  have  been  moved  [kekinehtai];  they’re  different,  as  [in  general]  are  moving  [kinei]  and  having  moved  [kekinehken].  But  at  the  same  moment  the  same  thing  has  seen  and  is  seeing,  and  is  thinking,  and  has  thought.13    [7.]  This  …then  I  call  an  actualization  [energeian],  the  other  …a  movement.    What  is  actually  [energeiai],  then,  what  it  is  and  what  sort  of  thing  [poion],  may  be  regarded  as  clear  from  these  and  like  cases.    

This  passage  is  commonly  read  as  containing  an  inferential  criterion  or  ‘test’  for  

distinguishing  two  types  of  occurrences.    Indeed,  if  we  go  by  the  textual  surfaces,  

Aristotle  distinguishes  in  passage  [1]  occurrences  that  cannot  be  called  actions  

because  their  telos,  their  end  or  completion  does  not  belong  to  them,  from                                                                                                                  10  Barnes  (cf.  1984:  1656)  translates  ‘this  is  not  action’,  i.e.,  ‘kinesis  is  not  action’    instead  of    Furth’s  ‘these  are  not  action’,  i.e.,  the  kineseis  of  the  bodily  parts  that  constitute  the  process  of  slimming.      11  Commenting  on  this  translation  with  resultative  perfect,  Furth  notes  that  what  is  at  issue  here  is  not  a  matter  of  tense  but  “what  linguists  call  Aktionsart  or  Behandlungsart,”  also  called  “aspect”  in  a  “terminological  variant”  (1985:  134f.).      12  The  addition  “[occurrences]”  replaces  Furth’s  addition  “[actions]”  which  seems  odd  given  that  Aristotle  just  determined  that  kineseis  are  not  actions;  Barnes  (1984:  1656)  adds  “processes.”  13  Note  the  variation  in  Barnes:  “”it  is  a  different  thing  that  is  being  moved  and  that  has  been  moved,  and  that  is  moving  and  that  has  moved;  but  it  is  the  same  thing  that  at  the  same  time  has  seen  and  is  seeing,  is  thinking  and  has  thought.”  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  8  

occurrences  that  can  be  called  actions  because  they  contain  their  completion.14      

For  convenience  let  us  call  occurrences  which  do  not  contain  their  completion  

‘other-­telic’  and  those  which  do  ‘self-­telic’.    This  difference  in  completedness  is  

explicated  by  means  of  differences  in  the  inferential  role  of  sentences  expressing  

‘cases’  of  energeia  and  kinesis.    Part  [2]  tells  us  that  statements  about  kineseis  

abide  by  the  pattern    

 [8.]    (subject,  Greek  verb  in  present  tense)  implies  the  falsity  of  (subject,    Greek  verb  in  the  Perfect)15  

 while  statements  about  energeia  do  not  govern  such  implications—the  present  

tense  statement  is  compatible  with  the  associated  statement  in  the  perfect.    Most  

commentators  read  the  expression  ‘hama’,  ‘at  the  same  time,’  as  an  inference;  so  

for  statements  about  energeiai  it  holds:  

 [9.]  (subject,  Greek  verb  in  present  tense)  implies  (subject,    Greek  verb  in  the  Perfect).  

 Part  [7]  connects  the  inferential  criterion  for  completion  to  the  natural  temporal  

boundedness  of  occurrences.    Those  occurrences  for  which  implication  [8]  holds  

are  bounded  by  their  completion—it  is  part  of  what  they  are  (since  they  have  

their  completion  not  in  themselves)  that  they  come  to  an  end  some  time.      Part  

[5]  restates  the  inferential  difference  of  [8]  and  [9],  with  the  interesting  variation  

that  in  one  case  the  implication  in  [9]  takes  the  other  direction  –  ‘the  same  thing  

has  seen  and  is  seeing.’    More  importanly,  however,  Aristotle  reformulates  the  

inferential  difference  between  statements  about  kinesis  and  energeia  taking  the  

role  of  the  subject  into  account;  that  is,  [8]  and  [9]  are  amended  to:  [10.]  (subject1,  Greek  verb  in  present  tense)  implies  the  falsity  of  (subject2  Greek  verb  in  the  

Perfect)    [11.]  (subject1  Greek  verb  in  present  tense)  implies  (subject1,  Greek  verb  in  the  Perfect).  

 On  the  background  of  these  restatements  of  Aristotle’s  text,  let  us  now  consider  

its  possible  heuristic  significance  for  an  ontology  of  dynamic  being.  

To  restate,  the  passage  just  set  out  traditionally  has  been  read  as  

providing  a  distinction  between  incomplete  and  complete  occurrences.  In  order                                                                                                                  14  Telos  is  a  relational  noun:  the  ‘for-­‐the-­‐sake-­‐of-­‐which’  or  the  ‘towards-­‐which’  of  an  occurrence.    In  the  present  context  this  metaphorical  characterization  must  suffice.  15  Following  a  linguistic  convention  language-­‐specific  grammatical  forms  are  capitalized  (‘Perfect’)  while  general  tense  or  aspect  labels    are  lower-­‐case  (‘present  tense,’  ‘perfect’).  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  9  

to  appreciate  the  methodological  clues  contained  in  the  passage  we  need  to  

review  for  a  moment  the  development  of  the  traditional  reading  within  the  

interplay  between  philosophy  and  linguistics.    Following  Aristotle’s  observation  

about  a  systematic  difference  in  the  inferential  role  of  certain  Greek  verbs  in  

present  tense,  G.  Ryle  distinguished    between  “verbs  of  activity  or  process”  and  

“achievement  verbs”  (1949:149ff),  in  order  to  contrast  at  the  ontological  level  

activities  and  results.    Inspired  by  Ryle—but  apparently  independently  of  each  

other—Z.  Vendler  (1957)  and  A.  Kenny  (1965)  later  produced  extended  

classification  of  “action  verbs.”    To  illustrate,  in  Vendler’s  fourfold  distinction  

between  “activity  verbs,  state  verbs,  accomplishment  verbs,  and  achievement  

verbs,”  activity  verbs  such  as  “run,  walk,  swim,  push”  fulfill  the  following  four  

conditions:    (C1)  They  take  the  continuous  form  i.e.,  ‘A  is  V-­‐ing’  is  a  well-­‐formed  sentence.    (C2)  Their  denotations  are  unbounded,  i.e.,  the  form  ‘x  finished  V-­‐ing’  cannot  be  supplemented  to  yield  a  true  sentence.    (C3)  [Distributivity  condition]  For  every  temporal  interval  [t],  if  ‘A  V-­‐ed  during  [t]’  is  true  then  ‘A  V-­‐ed’  during  [t’]  for  every  period  [t’]  that  is  part  of  [t].    (C4)    [Homomerity  condition]  Any  temporal  part  of  the  denotation  d    of  V  is  of  the  “the  same  nature”  as  the  whole  of  d.    

In  contrast,  “accomplishment  verbs”  such  as  “paint  a  picture,  build  a  house,  grow  

up,  recover  from  illness,  run-­‐a-­‐mile”  fulfill  (C1)  but  their  denotations  are  

bounded,  they  are  not  distributive  and  their  denotations  are  not  homomerous.  

Since  Vendler’s  classification  of  “action  verbs”  combines  syntactic  and  

semantic  criteria—i.e.,  the  conditions  I  called  ‘distributivity’  and  ‘homomerity’—

in  ways  that  seemed  to  dovetail  directly  with  the  quoted  passages  [2]  or  [6]    

above,  Aristotle  scholars  in  turn  applied  Vendler’s  analysis  to  interpret  the  

distinction  between  energeia    and  kinesis  in  these  sections  of  the  Metaphysics  .    

Just  as  Vendler  sought  to  derive  a  division  in  “types  of  action”  on  the  basis  of  a  

division  of  “action  verbs,”  Aristotle’s  interpreters  now  discussed  whether  the  

energeiai  mentioned  in  paragraphs  [1]  through  [6]  should  be  understood  as  

activities,  achievements,  or  states.16    

 However,  when  Vendler’s  and  Kenny’s  distinctions  became  the  subject  of  

more  comprehensive  investigations  within  linguistic  verb  semantics    (in  so-­‐

called  “aspect  theory,”“aspectology,”  or  theories  of  “Aktionsarten”)  they  soon  

                                                                                                               16  Cf.  Graham  1980,  Hagen  1984,  Ackrill  1965,  Kosman  1984.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  10  

appeared  fundamentally  flawed.    Upon  closer  inspection,  and  taking  a  larger  

sample  of  languages  into  account,  the  differences  in  inferential  roles  that  the  two  

classifications  aimed  to  identify  and  use  for  the  purpose  of  ontological  

classifications  are,  in  fact,  not  carried  by  the  lexical  meaning  of  verbs.    Rather,  the  

processual  information  that  linguists  call  ‘aspectual  meaning’  is  carried  by  entire  

sentences  or  even  small  discourse  section.    Moreover,  the  aspectual  system  of  

different  languages  are  so  different  that  it  seemed  hopeless  to  derive  ontological  

classifications  from  just  English  or  Greek.17      

But  despite  their  shortcomings,  both  classifications—and  in  particular  

Vendler’s  analysis  of  Aristotle’s  original  observations—produced  two  important  

general  insights  for  an  ontology  of  dynamic  being(s).    First,  when  we  try  to  locate  

relevant  inferential  data  that  can  guide  a  classification  of  occurrence  types,  we  

do  not  restrict  ourselves  to  reflecting  on  the  material  inferences  that  are  encoded  

in  the  lexical  meaning  of  the  general  nouns  of  a  language  (e.g.,  ‘development,’  

‘proceedings,’  ‘production,’  ‘oscillation,’  ‘growth,’  ‘expansion,’  ‘transition’  etc.);  

nor  do  we  need  to  limit  ourselves  to  inferential  constraints  encoded  in  the  tense  

of  verbal  predications.      Another  class  of  linguistic  data  for  an  ontological  

classification  of  occurrence  types,  and  perhaps  the  most  relevant  one,  seems  to  

be  provided  by  ‘aspectual  inferences,’  i.e.,  inferences  based  on  the  aspectual  

meaning  of  sentences.      Aspectual  meaning—often  but  not  always  encoded  in  the  

verb  form,  e.g.,  in  the  continuous  form  in  English  or  in  the  English  Perfect—

expresses  a  perspective  onto  the  form  of  dynamicity  of  an  occurrence;  for  

example,  whether  the  occurrence  is  going  on  (“imperfective”  or  “progressive”  

aspect)  or  available  as  result  (“perfective”  aspect),  or  has  just  begun  

(“ingressive”)  or  is  about  to  be  finished  (“egressive”),  or  a  recurrent  feature  

(“habitual”).18    As  it  stands,  Aristotle’s  grammatical  test  in  [2]  and  [6]  for  the  

distinction  between  energeia  and  kinesis  remains  ambiguous;  it  can  be  taken  to  

involve  tense,  or  aspect,  or  tense  and  aspect,  and  it  is  due  to  Vendler  and  Kenny  

that  the  aspectual  reading  of  the  “completeness  test”  came  into  focus.    

                                                                                                               17  Cf.  Verkuyl  1972,  Taylor  1977,  Mourelatos  1978,  Rijksbaron  1989.  For  a  review  of  the  relevant  part  of  the  linguistic  debate  on  Aktionsarten  and  verbal  aspect  Seibt  2004b,  ch.  2.  18  This  is  a  simplified  illustration;  see  Seibt  2004b,  ch.  2  for  a  review  of  various  linguistic  theories  of  aspectual  meaning.    Note,  incidentally,  that  ontologists  so  far  have  been  overlooking  not  only  inferences  based  on  so-­‐called  ‘verbal  aspect,’  but  also  the  aspectual  information  based  on  ‘nominal  aspects’;  see  ibid.  ch.  4  on  this  and  Seibt  201+.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  11  

While  the  pointer  to  aspectual  inferences  is  particularly  pronounced  in    

Kenny’s  analysis,  Vendler’s    analysis  can  be  credited  with  conveying  most  clearly  

the  second  important  insight  I  wish  to  highlight  here,  namely,  the  insight  that  

aspectual  inferences  dovetail  with  mereological  properties.    As  the  conditions  of  

‘distributivity’  and  ‘homomerity’  (C3)  and  (C4)  above  suggest,  implications  

between  sentences  with  different  aspectual  meaning  can  be  used  to  derive  

mereological  features  in  terms  of  which  one  can  introduce  different  types  of  

truthmakers  (occurrence  types)  for  the  sentences  in  question.  

  With  these  credentials  in  place,  let  us  return  to  our  review  of  the  

traditional  reading  of  Aristotle’s  distinction  between  energeia  and  kinesis  as  

occurrence  types.    As  the  discussion  of  Vendler’s  and  Kenny’s  classifications  per  

se,  as  well  as  in  application  to  the  quoted  passage  has  shown,    it  is  not  possible  to  

define  different  occurrence  types  just  in  terms  of  one  aspectual  implication  as  in  

Vendler’s  (C1)  or  Aristotle’s  [8/10]  and  [9/11],  respectively.  For  example,  the  

fact  that  the  sentences  ‘I  am  walking  about’  or  ‘I  am  swimming’  both  allow  for  an  

aspectual  inference  in  the  sense  of  [9/11]  are  not  sufficient  to  claim  that  they  

denote  “activities,”  if  the  latter  are  taken  to  be  characterized  by  homomerity  

alone—as  has  been  observed  by  a  number  of  authors,  what  ontologists  call  a  

‘state  of  affairs’  (e.g.,  a  exemplifies  the  (possibly  complex)  property  F  )  would  

seem  to  fulfill  the  homomerity  condition  just  as  well.    Moreover,  it  is  

questionable  whether  an  occurrence  denoted  by  a  sentence  that  licences  the  

aspectual  inference  in  [9/11]  and  fulfills  what  Vendler  calls  the  “time  schema”  

associated  with  this  inference,  here  listed  as  the  ‘distributivity  condition’  (C3),  

should  at  all  be  labeled  an  ‘activity’—some  authors  have  argued  that  the  notion  

of  an  activity  does  allow  for  some  temporal  granularity,  i.e.,  for  some  short  

phases  that  do  not  satisfy  the  predicate  in  terms  of  which  the  activity  is  

characterized.19      

In  reaction  to  these  difficulties  one  might  (a)  develop  alternative  ways  of  

making  use  of  aspectual  inferences  for  the  definition  of  occurrence  types,  and  (b)  

search  for  an  alternative  interpretation  of  Aristotle’s  ‘completeness  test’  in  

                                                                                                               19  For  a  discussion  of  such  challenges  to  the  distributivity  of  activity  predicates  see  Seibt  2004a  and  2004b  ch.  2.    

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  12  

Metaphysics  Θ.6.    Elsewhere  I  have  explored  (a),  20  here  I  want  to  offer  a  

suggestion  following  line  (b).    

 

 

 

 

2.  Two  modes  of  dynamicity  

 

 As  I  want  to  argue  now,  drawing  on  the  larger  context  of  Aristotle’s  writings,  the  

passage  I  quoted  in  the  previous  section  contains  a  definition  not  of  occurrence  

types  but  of  two  modes  of  dynamicity.  Consider  the  following  four  predicates:    [12]  Likepartedness  or  homomerity:  An  entity  of  kind  K  is  likeparted  iff  some  of  its  spatial  or  temporal    parts  are  of  kind  K.    [13]  Strict  likepartedness  or  strict    homomerity:  An  entity  of  kind  K  is  likeparted  iff  all  of  its  spatial  or  temporal    parts  are  of  kind  K.    [14]  Self-­containment  or  automerity:    An  entity    E  is  self-­‐contained  iff  the  spatiotemporal  region  in  which  all  of  E  occurs  has  some  spatial  or  temporal  parts  in  which  all  of  E  occurs.21    [15]  Strict  self-­containment  or  automerity:    An  entity    E  is  self-­‐contained  iff  the  spatiotemporal  region  in  which  all  of  E  occurs  has  only  spatial  or  temporal  parts  in  which  all  of  E  occurs.  

 

An  action  is  complete,  Aristotle  says  in  section  [2]  of  the  quotation  in  the  

previous  section,  if  is  completed  “at  the  same  time”  (“hama”)  at  which  it  is  going  

on.    This  can  be  read  in  three  ways:  ‘at  the  same  time’  (i)  for  some,  or  (ii)  for  any,  

or  (iii)  for  all  of  the  of  the  times  at  which  it  is  going  on.      If  we  take  the  first  

reading  we  can  claim  that  energeiai  are  homomerous  or  automerous.    If  we  take  

the  second  or  the  third  reading,  we  can  claim  that  energeiai  are  strictly  

homomerous  or  strictly  automerous.    Since  Aristotle  in  no  place  introduces  a  

qualification  of  ‘the  same  moment’  that  would  suggest  a  restriction  from  ‘any’  to  

‘some,’  I  take  the  second  or  third  reading  as  the  more  plausible  one.    As  far  as  I  

can  see,  all  of  the  commentators  of  the  passage  agree  on  this  point.    Remarkably,  

however,  the  difference  between  homomerity  and  automerity  seems  to  have                                                                                                                  20  For  example,  I  have  suggested  a  classification  of  sentences  about  activities,  accomplishments,  states,  and  achievements  in  terms  of  small  networks  of  aspectual  inferences,  see  ibid.  21  The  condition  of  automerity  is  fulfilled  by  any  kind  of  repetitive  occurrence,  whether  it  be  an  ‘activity’  or  a  sequence  of  Vendler  ‘accomplishments’  or  ‘achievements’.      

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  13  

gone  unnoticed.    Or  to  put  it  more  precisely,  it  seems  to  have  gone  unnoticed  that  

Aristotle  commits  himself  by  the  combination  of  [1]  and  [2]  to  the  claim  that  

energeiai  are  strictly  automerous.    For  in  [1]  Aristotle  explains  that  the  telos  

(completion)  of  an  action  is  that  ‘for-­‐the-­‐sake-­‐of-­‐which’  the  action  is  undertaken.    

If  we  were  to  take  the  telos  of  an  ongoing  action  α  to  be  the  result  of  α,  taking  the  

result  or  upshot  of  α  to  be  different  from  α  as  ongoing,  then  no  ongoing  action  

could  contain  literally  “its”  completion.  For  an  ongoing  action  to  contain  its  

completion  we  need  to  assume  that  the  telos  of  α  as  ongoing  is  α  as  ongoing,  not  

the  result  of  α.    Consider  the  following  contrast:  

 [16]  Intelicity  (self-­directedness  or  upshot  completion):  An  action  α  is  intelic  iff  α  is  done  for  the  sake  of  α’s  having  been  done.    A  non-­‐agentive  occurrence  α  is  intelic  iff  the  telos  of  α  is  α’s  having  occurred.  [17]  Autotelicity  (strict  self-­directedness  or  occurrence  completion):  An  action  α  is  autotelic  iff  α,  while  going  on,  is  done  for  the  sake  of  the  ongoingness  of  α.  A  non-­‐agentive  occurrence  α  is  autotelic  iff  if  the  telos  of  α,  while  going  on,  is  the  going-­‐on  of  α.

 

 If  we  take  Aristotle’s  text  literally  we  must  adopt  the  view  that  an  ongoing  

occurrence  that  contains  its  completion  is  autotelic  in  the  sense  specified,  which  

means  that  it  contains  literally  itself.    In  other  word,  then,  we  must  read  Aristotle  

as  holding,  or  being  committed  to  holding,  that  energeiai  are  strictly  automerous  

in  the  sense  stated  above.  

Before  we  investigate  the  predicate  automerity  in  greater  detail,  let  us  

consider  in  which  way  the  difference  between  autotelic  and  ‘other-­‐telic’  /allotelic  

occurrences    (i.e,  occurrences  the  telos  of  which  is  not  reached  while  they  are  

going  on,  cf.  [1])  could  steer  us  towards  an  new  understanding  of  energeia  and  

kinesis.    In  other  places  (cf.  De  Anima  417a2ff,  Physics  193b7)  Aristotle  uses  the  

contrast  between  dynamis  and  energeia  to  characterize  the  difference  between  

changes  and  activities.    He  presents  these  not  merely  as  different  occurrence  

types  (e.g.,  actions  vs.  events)  but  as  two  fundamentally    different  genres  of    

occurrences.    Changes  realize  dynameis  for  becoming  F—for  example  the  

dynamis    for  becoming  a  human  organism  or  a  flute  player.    The  realization  of  

such  a  dynamis    for  becoming  F,  also  called  a  ‘potency’  or  ‘first  level  potentiality,’  

brings  about  a  dynameis  for  being  F,  also  called  a  ‘capacity’  or  ‘second  level  

potentiality’.    The  realization  of  a  potency  for  becoming  F  is  a  transition  which  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  14  

results  in  the  capacity  for  being  F;      the  latter  are  the  telos  of  the  transition  but  

are  not  included  in  the  transition.    As  Aristotle  emphasizes  in  Nicomachian  Ethics  

1174a25-­‐14,  occurrences  of  this  genre,  changes,  are  characterized  by  inherent  

and  ubiquitous  difference,  with  each  part  being  “different  in  kind”  from  the  

other.      In  contrast,  the  realizations  of  capacities  (e.g.,  of  the  dynamis  of  being  a  

human  being  or  a  flute  player)  are  characterized  by  inherent  sameness;  they  are  

‘self-­‐realization’  structures  since  the  telos  of  this  genre  of  occurrence  is  the  

realization  of  the  capacity  itself.22  Since  Aristotle  calls  the  first  genre  of  

occurrences    kineseis  and  the  second  energeiai  one  might  at  first  form  the  

impression  that  these  passages  confirm  the  traditional  reading  of  kinesis  and  

energeia  as  occurrence  types.    All  that  this  larger  context  of  the  completeness  

test  reveals,  one  might  argue,  Aristotle’s  target  is  not  a  distinction  between  

‘species’  of  occurrences  (‘actions’  vs  ‘non-­‐actions)  but  a  division  at  a  much  more  

fundamental  level  between  different  ‘genera’  of  occurrences.      

However,  this  adjustment  of  the  traditional  reading  does  not  square  well  

with  the  fact  that  Aristotle  characterizes  energeia  as  a  form  of  kinesis,  calling  a  

capacity    a    

 [18]  “principle  of  movement  (kinesis)…in  the  thing  itself  qua  itself”  (Metaphysics  1049b9).      

 

More  importantly,  he  even  defines  kinesis  in  terms  of  energeia:  

 [19]  [T]he  energeia  of  the  buildable  as  the  buildable  is  the  house-­‐building  (Physics  

201b6-­‐14)  

 

[20]  I  call  the  energeia  of  the  potential  as  such  kinesis  (Metaphysics  K  1065  b16)    

 

                                                                                                               22  In  the  case  of  living  organisms  the  exercise  of  the  capacity  for  being  F  is  not  only  self-­‐realizing  in  the  sense  that  this  capacity  for  being  F  is  realized  as  an  exercizable  capacity  for  being  F,  but  here  the  capacity  in  question  is  (a)  for  being-­‐an-­‐organism-­‐of-­‐this-­‐kind  or  (b)  for  being-­‐this-­‐organism-­‐of-­‐this-­‐kind.    In  this  way  the  self-­‐directed  is  even  stronger,  it  does  not  only  pertain  to  the  capacity  qua  capacity  but  also  to  the  ‘content’  of  the  capacity.    Aristotle  calls  self-­‐directness  in  the  sense  of  (a)  physis—the  nature  of  an  organism  is  to  realize  this  nature;  it  is  controversial  whether  the  notion  of  physis  also  can  be  read  as  self-­‐directedness  in  the  sense  of  (b),  as  the  self-­‐realization  of  an  individual  instance  of  this  nature.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  15  

Passages  [19]  and  [20]  state  that  kinesis  is  a  certain  ‘way  of  the  being-­‐there’  of  a  

potency,  namely,  the  way  in  which  the  potency  is  there  if  its  potentiality  for  

generating  a  change  or  transition  is  no  longer  dormant  but  going  on  (and  not  yet  

actualized).    The  potency  for  becoming  a  house  is  in  bricks,  beams,  and  tiles  even  

if  these  never  become  a  house;  but  for  this  ‘dormant’  productive  potency  to  

become  ‘manifest’  it  needs  to  attain  a  mode  of  being-­‐there  that  realizes  it  as  

productive  potency—the  potency  needs  to  ‘go  on’.  Kinesis,  the  occurrence  of  the  

development  or  movement,  is  thus  the  going  on  of  the  potential  as  potential.      But  

then  kinesis  is  not  an  occurrence  type,  not  a  development,  but  the  mode  of  

occurrence  of  such  an  occurrence  type:  coming  about.    Coming  about  is  a  

distinctive  mode  of  occurrence  or  mode  of  dynamicity  that  always  strives  

beyond  itself,  a  continuous  tendency  towards  difference,  until  a  definite  endpoint  

is  reached.          

In  contrast,  when  a  capacity,  a  dynamis  for  being-­‐F,  is  going  on,  the  

occurrence  generated  has  another  mode  of  dynamicity—it  is  the  continuous  

expression  of  the  capacity-­‐for-­‐being-­‐F  to  express  itself.          Aristotle  calls  that  

mode  of  dynamicity  energeia.      

If  kinesis  and  energeia  are  modes  of  dynamicity,  however,  one  might  have  

some  qualms  about  the  role  of  energeia    in  quotations  [19]  and  [20].      There  the  

term  energeia  is  used  to  characterize  a  ‘way  of  being-­‐there’  (‘going-­‐on’)  of  a    

dynamis  .    On  the  other  hand,  if  energeia    were  a  mode  of  dynamicity,  it  should  be  

the  result  of  the  ‘going  on’  of  a  dynamis  (i.e.,  of  a  dynamis    for  being  F).      Some  

scholars  thus  have  suggested  that  energeia  is  simply  ambiguous  and  in  certain  

contexts  means  ‘activity’  (occurrence  type)    and  in  other  contexts  ‘actuality’(way  

of  being-­‐there  of  a  dynamis).23  I  believe  that  when  Aristotle  reminds  his  readers  

at  the  beginning  of  Metaphysics  Θ.  6  that  the  meaning  of  energeia  can  shift  

(1047a30)  he  does  not  intend  to  announce  an  ambiguity.    We  can  work  towards  

a  more  interesting  resolution  of  the  double-­‐functionality  of  the  term  if  we  

translate  it  into  ‘logical  grammar’.    In  [19]  and[20]  energeia  appears  both  in  the  

logical  position  of  a  function  (or  operator)  on  dynameis;  in  other  contexts  it  

appears  in  the  role  of  the  ‘value’  (or  outcome):    

                                                                                                                 23  Cf.  Chen  1965.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  16  

[21]    going-­‐on  (dynamis  to  become  F)  =  coming  about,  kinesis  

[22]  going-­‐on  (dynamis  to  be  F)  =  self-­‐expression,  energeia  

 

To  achieve  a  uniform  reading  of  energeia  we  might  try  then  to  understand  ‘going  

on,’  which  I  so  far  characterized  as  a  ‘way  of  being-­‐there’  of  a  dynamis,  to  amount  

structurally  to  the  self-­‐expression  of  a  capacity  for  being  F.    In  other  words,  

applying  the  operator  ‘self-­‐expression’  to  the  dynamis  to  become  F  would  

express  this  dynamis  as  itself,  the  potential  as  the  potential,  as  stated  in  [19]  and  

[20].    Applying  the  operator  ‘self-­‐expression’  to  a  dynamis    to  be  F,  to  a  capacity  

for  expressing  F,    would  again  express  this    dynamis  as  itself,  namely,  as  the  

capacity  of  expressing-­‐F,  which  means  the  continuous  self-­‐expression  of  that  

capacity,  and  the  continuous  expression  of  F  in  the  course  of  it.  

  Where  does  this  interpretation  leave  us?  We  started  this  section  in  search  

of  an  interpretation  of  distinction  between  kinesis  and  energeia  that  would  not  

associate  it  with  a  division  in  occurrence  types  and  arrived  at  a  reading  in  terms  

of  a    contrast  of  two  modes  of  dynamicity—coming  about  and  going-­‐on-­‐by-­‐self-­‐

expression.    However,  in  the  course  of  motivating  this  reading  we  also  

discovered  that  energeia  is    also  used  in  ways  that  seem  to  go  beyond    the  label  

for  a  mode  of  dynamicity  (see  [19]  and  [20]).    Can  we  equate  ‘ongoingness’  with  

‘self-­‐expression’  to  achieve  a  unified  reading  of  energeia  in  two  roles,  as  mode  of  

dynamicity  and  as  mode  of  existence  of  a  dynamis?  Is  energeia  then  simply  the  

primary  mode  of  dynamicity,  is  it  tantamount  to  being  understood  as  an  dynamic  

affair?  Should  we  say  then  that  in  Aristotle’s  ontology  all  that  is  is  going-­‐on-­‐by-­‐

self-­‐expression  and  once  a  potency  ‘is’  in  this  way  we  get  something  occurring  in  

another  mode  of  dynamicity  that  is  a  variation  of  the  underlying  basic  form  of  

dynamic  being?    

Before  we  can  explore  these  questions,  one  might  object  at  this  point,    we  

should  investigate  whether  we  can  all  think  the  mode  of  dynamicity  of  self-­‐

expression.    In  the  Nicomachian  Ethics    (1174b10-­‐13)  Aristotle  emphasizes  that    

the  mode  of  dynamicity  of  energeia  is  strictly  without  developmental  phases:    [23]  From  these  considerations  it  is  clear,  too,  that  these  thinkers  are  not  right  in  saying  there  is  a  movement  or  a  coming  into  being  of  pleasure.    For  these  cannot  be  ascribed  to  all  things,  but  only  to  those  that  are  divisible  and  not  wholes;  there  is  no  coming  into  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  17  

being  of  seeing  nor  of  a  point  nor  of  a  unit,  nor  is  any  of  these  a  movement  or  coming  into  being;  therefore  there  is  none  of  pleasure  either;  for  it  is  a  whole.24  

 

But  to  think  self-­‐expression  as  an  unstructured,  non-­‐developmental  whole  seems  

quite  impossible  and  so  we  have  arrived  at  what  one  could  call  the    riddle  of  

’dynamicity.’    It  appears  that  we  can  somehow  ‘fathom’    two  forms  of    

’dynamicity.’      First,  there  is  the  ’stretched’  developmental  variety,  as  a  ’push  

from  here  to  there,’  as  continuous  becoming  different—the  mode  of  dynamicity  

of  coming  about  (kinesis).    Second,  there  is  ’dynamicity’  in  the  form  of  going-­‐on  as  

self-­‐propagation—the  mode  of  dynamicity  of  self-­‐expression  (energeia).      But  

this  mode  of  dynamicity  also  appears  to  have  wider  scope  than  the  other—it  

appears  to  articulate  a  notion  of  dynamicity  or  dynamic  being  in  general.    

Anything  in  the  mode  of  coming-­‐about,  any  development  ‘is’  in  a  dynamic  

sense—i.e.,  is  in  sense  of  being  as  self-­‐expression.    And  yet,  while  we  somehow  

can  ‘fathom’  self-­‐propagation,  we  cannot  think  nor  represent  symbolically  self-­‐

expression  as  an  unstructured  whole—we  cannot  think  it  without  thinking  a  

production  or  coming  about  that  is  somehow  ’collected’  into  a  point.    This  creates  

a  curious  interdependence:  the  second  mode  of  dynamicity,  going  on  or  self-­‐

expression,  is  the  way  in  which  the  first  mode  of  dynamicity  is  there—coming  

about  is  there  by  the  going  on  of  some  dynamis  to  become-­‐F.    On  the  other  hand,  

it  appears  that  we  can  only  understand  the  mode  of  dynamicity  of  self-­‐

expression  by  contrasting  it  with  coming  about.  

 

 

3.  The  riddle  of  dynamicity  

 

What  to  do  with  the  interdependence  between  the  two  modes  of  dynamicity  I  

called  ‘coming  about’  and  ‘going-­‐on  by  expressing-­‐itself’?    There  are  four  possible  

reactions  all  of  which  are  exemplified  in  the  history  of  metaphysics.    First,  one  

might  give  up  on  the  ontology  of  dynamic  being,  since  it  does  not  bring  us  any  

further  with  respect  to  the  overall  ontological  project  of  defining  being.      

Ongoingness  is  as  indefinable  as  being,  so  there  is  little  use  in  claiming  with  the  

process  metaphysicians  that  being  consists  in  ongoingness.                                                                                                                  24  1174b10-­‐13.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  18  

Second,  one  might  reject  Aristotle’s  idea,  expressed  in  [19]  and  [20],  that  

the  dynamic  being  of  coming  about  somehow  would  need  to  be  conceived  as  

ongoingness.    Dynamic  being  can  be  coming  about  and  nothing  else.      When  a  

house  is  being  built,  what  there  is  at  any  moment  during  which  that  coming  

about  occurs  is  itself  a  ’temporally  unextended’  coming  about.    So  at  any  moment  

there  is  a  coming  about  of  coming  about—any  temporally  extended  coming  

about  is  the  sequence  of  temporally  punctiform  coming  abouts  which  do  not  

happen  over  time.    This  one  could  consider  to  be  Whitehead’s  solution  to  the  

riddle  of  dynamicity;    the  basic  entities  of  Whitehead  process  metaphysics,  so-­‐

called  ’actual  occasions,’  all  have  the  structure  of  kineseis,  i.e.,  they  are  all  

becomings,  which  do  not  happen  over  time  but  constitute  that  which  happens  

over  time.  

Third,  one  might  claim  that  the  interdependence  is  not  symmetric.    To  use  

a  distinction  by  W.  Sellars,  self-­‐expressing  depends  on  coming-­‐about  in  the  

”order  of  understanding,”  while  coming-­‐about  depends  on  self-­‐expressing  in  the  

”order  of  being.”    In  order  to  make  descriptive  sense  of  being  as  going-­‐on  or  self-­‐

expressing,  i.e.,  in  order  to  render  going  on  a  concept  that  is  not  only  ’clear’  but  

also  ’distinct’  in  the  rationalist’s  classification,  we  need  to  resort  to  the  contrast  

with  coming  about.    But  this  does  not  detract  from  the  fact  that  ongoingness  is  

the  way  in  which  coming  about  is  there.    In  Bergson’s  pregnant  articulation  of  

this  third  reaction  to  the  ‘riddle  of  dynamicity,’  process-­‐metaphysical  inquiry  

finds  itself  in  a  tragic  situation.    It  aspires  to  conceptualize  something  that  is  

outside  of  the  very  domain  of  conceptualization.    What  can  be  conceptualized  of  

a  coming  about  is  the  pair  of  initial  state  and  end  state;  the  transition  between  

these  states,  however,  the  ongoingness  of  coming  about,  entirely  eludes  any  

effort  of  descriptive  conceptualization.    Dynamicity  or  ongoingness  is  something  

we  can  only  experience  in  ”duration,”    as  plenum  without  separable  components,  

and  can  only  approach  as  the  ever  fleeting,  ever  evanescent  object  of  an  

attempted  conceptual  reflection  of  that  experience.  

Fourth,  and  this  appears  to  be  the  most  popular  reaction  among  process  

metaphysicians,  one  might  deny  that  self-­‐expressing  is  descriptively  dependent  

on  coming-­‐about,  because  the  metaphor  of  self-­‐directedness  (self-­‐production  

etc.)    is  a  definiens  in  its  own  right.    A  number  of  metaphysicians  have  played  on  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  19  

the  intimate  connection  between  ’dynamicity’  and  self-­‐directedness  and  the  

curious  self-­‐validation  that  occurs  when  we  think  that  connection.    Fichte  and  

Hegel  went  so  far  as  to  take  the  performative  validation  of  the  thought  of  self-­‐

production  to  be  the  metaphysical  ’core-­‐relation’  on  which  a  whole  system  could  

be  ’grounded.’    While  Descartes  provided  the  model  of  performative  self-­‐

validation  of  thinking,  Fichte  and  Hegel  noticed  that  something  metaphysically  

even  more  powerful  is  to  be  gained  along  these  lines.    The  attempt  to  think  self-­‐

production  results  not  only  in  the  performative  validation  of  one  specific  type  of  

process  (thinking)  but  of  a  way  of  being  there,  of  actual  existence.    The  thinking  

of  self-­‐production  (self-­‐directness)  as  an  item  of  ”objective  reality”  not  only  

brings  about  self-­‐production  as  an  item  of  ”formal  reality,”  but,  together  with  a  

view  of  knowledge  as  perfect  ’adequatio,’  it  also  suggests  itself  as  the  situation  in  

which  the  correlativity  of  thinking  and  being  is  fully  exhibited.25    

Instead  of  embracing  any  of  these  four  reactions  here,  I  want  to  suggest  a  

fifth  option,  namely,  a  standard  implicit  definition  of  ongoingness  of  ‘dynamicity’.      

By  an  implicit  definition  we  can  skirt  the  ‘riddle  of  dynamicity’  I  just  drew  

attention  to,  i.e.,  we  can  dodge  the  difficulties  in  having  to  conceive  of  dynamicity  

via  negativa  as  an  ‘other-­‐directed  movement  rolled  back  onto  itself.’      The  above  

                                                                                                               25  The  concept  of  self-­‐production  forces  us  to  conceive  of  a  unity  which  generates  and  cancels  a  relationship  to  itself,  and  this  peculiar  dynamic  structure—vide  Fichte’s  notion  of  an  ”Ego”  as  ”setting  the  Non-­‐Ego”  or  Hegel’s  ”identity  of  identity  and  non-­‐identity”—can  be  used  to  undercut  the  traditional  dichotomy  between  thinking  and  being,  ”subject”  and  ”object.”    In  Fichte’s  and  Hegel’s  scheme,  the  thinking  of  self-­‐production  thus  fulfills  three  functions:  it  generates  (a)  a  case  of  self-­‐production,  (b)  a  definition  for  a  dynamic  account  of  being  correlative  to  the  structure  of  thinking,  and  (c)  a  model  for  the  relationship  between  thinking  and  being:  a  unity  that  is  both  identity  and  difference,  that  generates  and  cancels  its  own  relatedness.    Is  there  anything  in  this  approach  that  could  invite  further  exploration  from  the  perspective  of  the  analytical  ontologist?    Let  us  briefly  look  at  (b).    Hegel’s  insists  that  normal  predications  are  not  suited  to  express  “speculative  truths”  (definitions  of  dialectical  relationships)  but  must  be  articulated  by  means  of  a  “speculative  sentence,”  a  special  linguistic  form.      This  can  be  understood  as  a  precursor  to  the  idea  that  not  all  definitions  have  to  be  explicit  definitions.    In  essence,  then,  it  is  the  proposal  of  grounding  self-­‐expression  and  other  self-­‐referential  terms  in  what  one  might  call    ‘performative  constitutions.’      Such  performative  constitutions  capitalize  on  the  self-­‐similarity  of  content  and  form,  which—in  first  approximation—we  might  conceive  of  the  self-­‐similarity  of  performative  constitutions  on  the  model  of  the  ‘triangle  of  triangles’,  i.e.,as  the  similarity  of  the  nature  of  the  items  arranged  and  the  mode  of    arrangement.    Hegel’s  focus  is  on  connections  between  an  item  (e.g.,  the  subject)  and  that  which  is  other  to  it  (e.g.,  the  object)  in  various  ‘modes’  (e.g.  epistemic  modes)  that  he  characterizes  themselves  in  terms  of    such  connections.    For  example,  if  we  let  subscripts  representing  the  ‘mode’  of  presentation,  the  following  complex  structure—which  corresponds  to  Hegel’s  characterization  of  self-­‐consciousness    in  the  Phenomology    and  his  definition  of  “something”  (“Etwas”)  in  the  Science  of  Logic—  has  a  mode  of  interrelatedness  that  mirrors  the  interrelatedness  of  its  components  and  their  respective  “one-­‐sided”  modes  of  presentation:          ‘((S  ⇔  ∼  S)  S  ⇔  ∼  S  ⇔  ∼  (S  ⇔  ∼  S)  ∼(S  ⇔  ∼  S))  (S  ⇔  ∼  S)  ⇔  ∼  (S  ⇔  ∼  S)’  .      

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  20  

rehearsed  historical  reactions  to  the  riddle  of  dynamicity    all  proceed  from  the  

assumption  that  if  dynamicity  has  no  explicit  definition  it  must  be  indefinable,    or  

even  inconceivable  .    But  once  we  admit  of  the  idea  that,  within  a  suitable  system,  

a  condition  can  set  sufficient  constraints  to  ensure  that  dynamic  entities  are  

among  its  models,  a  new  path  opens  up.        

I  suggest  that  we  take  the  feature  of  strict  automerity  as  an  inferential  

constraint  that,  in  combination  with  additional  restrictions  within  a  formal  

system,  all  and  only  ongoing  or  ‘dynamic’  entities  fulfill.      The  general  strategy  of  

my  proposal  can  be  summarized  into  the  following  four  claims.  (i)  Dynamicity  or  

dynamic  being  is  ongoingness  by  expressing  itself—to  be  is  to  go  on.  (ii)  Self-­‐

expression  is  reflected  in  a  characteristic  structure  in  the  description  of  an  entity.    

(iii)  For  example,  if  we  describe  an  entity  E  in  terms  of  a  partition  that  specifies  

what  is  ‘part  of  being  that  entity’  (i.e.,  we  specify  its  spatial,  function,  material  etc,  

parts  within  one  partition  using  a  generic  part  relation),  the  fact  that  E  is  

dynamic  will  be  reflected  in  the  partition  in  the  form  of  certain  distinctive  

patterns  representing  self-­‐expression.    (iv)  Self-­‐expression  is  mereologically  

reflected  in  strict  automerity,  which  generates  self-­‐similar  patterns  within  a  

partition.    

Above  I  argued  that  autotelicity  (self-­‐expression)  dovetails  with  strict  

automerity.    Let  us  turn  to  a  closer  look  at  automerity  then.    I  have  been  using  the  

predicate  without  discussing  whether  this  predicate  is  at  all  conceptually  

coherent.  How  can  a  whole,  E,  contain  itself  as  a  part?    Indeed,  if  we  interpret  the  

expression  ‘is  part  of’  on  the  basis  of  the  axiomatization  of  Classical  Extensional  

Mereology  (or,  in  fact,  any  axiomatization  that  operates  with  a  transitive  part  

relation),  then  the  only  way  in  which  an  entity  could  be  automerous  is  by  having  

no  spatial  and  temporal  parts  at  all.    Since  the  classical  part  relation  is  transitive  

and  irreflexive,  no  part  of  E  can  have  E  as  part—by  the  transitivity  of  ‘is  part  of’  

we  receive  the  statement  that  E  is  part  of  itself,  which  is  in  conflict  with  the  

irreflexivity  of  the  part  relation.    

However,    we  are  by  no  means  bound  to  the  interpretation  of  ‘is  part  of’  as  

axiomatized  by  Classical  Extensional  Mereology.  There  are  at  least  two  varieties  

of  non-­‐standard  mereologies  both  of  which  allow  for  ‘mereological  loops’:    one  

can  either  relinquish  anti-­‐symmetry  (Cotnoir  2010),  or,  as  I  have  suggested,  one  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  21  

can  give  up  on  transitivity.  Classical  Extensional  Mereology  axiomatizes  in  effect  

the  natural  language  expression    ‘x  is  a  spatial  /temporal  part  of  the  spatial/  

temporal  region  occupied  by  y’;  in  contrast,  ‘is  part  of’  in  the  commonsensical  

usage  is  not  a  transitive  relation.  The  switch  from  a  transitive  to  a  non-­‐transitive  

part-­‐relation  betokens  that  ‘is  part  of’  must  be  defined  relative  to  partition  levels.    

The  parts  of  an  entity  α  are  a’s  1-­‐parts,  the  parts  of  the  parts  of  α  are  at  α’s  2-­‐

parts,  and  so  on—in  general,  the  nth  iteration  of  the  part-­‐relation  yields  one  of  

α’s  n-­‐parts.      This  implies  a  profound  change  in  the  expressive  power  of  a  

mereological  system;  as  I  have  argued,  however,  the  shift  to  “Leveled  Mereology”  

is  for  many  purposes  in  ontology  quite  advantageous.  26        

One  of  these  advantages  is  the  fact  that  in  a  mereological  system  with  a  

non-­‐transitive  part-­‐relation  there  is  a  non-­‐vacuous  reading  for  strict  automerity.  

In  ‘Leveled  Mereology’  not  only  parthood  is  relativized  to  partition  levels,  also  

identity  (i.e.,  coreferentiality)  is  defined—via  the  Proper  Parts  Principle—

relative  to  a  certain  level  of  depth—briefly,  α  and  β  are  identical  just  in  case  they  

have  the  same  1-­‐through-­‐n-­‐parts,  for  a  given  n.    Assume  that  n  =1,  which  means  

that  two  entities  are  identical  just  in  case  their  share  the  same  1-­‐parts.  If  β  and  γ  

are  the  1-­‐parts  of  an  entity  α,  and  α  and  δ  are  1-­‐parts  of  β,  then  α  can  be  a  2-­‐part  

of  itself.    In  other  words,  provided  a  partition  has  self-­‐similar  structure  relative  

to  the  level  n  for  which  the  identity  principle  has  been  fixed,  such  a  partition  can  

represent  an  entity  E  that  contains  itself  or  is  (strictly)  automerous  in  the  sense  

that  if  R  is  the  spatial/temporal  region  that  contains  E  as  a  whole,  the  some  (all)  

subregions  ri  of  R  contain  E  as  a  whole.    For  example,  in  Figure  1  the  entity  α  is  

identified  via  its  1-­‐parts  β  and  γ;  both  of  these  parts  contain  α,  even  though  they  

not  directly,  but  as  part  of  a  part.    If  we  were  to  supplement  the  figure  by  

assuming  that  also  δ,  k,  ε,  and  θ  have  α  as  a  part,  it  would  represent  a  strictly  

automerous  entity.  

 

                                                                                                               26  See  Seibt  2004b,  2009  and  2015.      

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  22  

   

 

 

 

4.  Conclusion  

 

In  this  paper  I  have  presented  reactions  to  Aristotle’s  so-­‐called  ‘completeness  

test’  in  Metaphysics  Θ.6  that  were  to  serve  heuristic  purposes  only.    Whether  the  

suggested  interpretation  of  energeia  as  the  ‘dominant’  of  two  modes  of  

dynamicity  is  at  all  tenable,  can  remain  open.    My  main  aim  was  to  use  Aristotle’s  

text  as  a  foil  for  a  discussion  of  the  most  basic  concepts  within  an  ontology  of  

dynamic  being,  concepts  like  coming  about  and  going  on,  that  remain  

presupposed  in  more  specific  and  more  easily  analyzable  notions  for  

occurrences  and  dynamic  features  in  the  science  (e.g.,  production,  motion,  

causation,  reaction,  feedback,  self-­‐maintenance,  autopoiesis  etc.).      I  have  tried  to  

highlight  that  Aristotle’s  text  provides    us  with  two  very  useful  methodological  

pointer.    First,  it  can  direct  analytical  ontologists  to  a  more  careful  investigation  

of  aspectual  inferences  as  the  relevant  linguistic  data  for  an  ontology  of  dynamic  

beings  or  occurrence  types.  I  have  argued  here  that  the  single  aspectual  

inference  used  in  the  completeness  test  does  not  suffice  for  a  distinction  between  

occurrence  types,  which  are  to  be  correlated  with  more  complex  dynamic  

information,    but  it  can  be  used  to  fix  a  contrast  between  two  basic  modes  of  

dynamicity,  coming  about  and  going  on.    The  second  important  pointer  that  

γ  

Figure  1    

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  23  

Aristotle  has  left  us  with  is  to  mereology  as  a  tool  for  a  formal  ontology  of  

dynamic  beings  and  modes  of  dynamicity.    Within  a  non-­‐standard  mereology,  or  

so  I  tried  to  illustrate  in  the  final  section,  we  can  formulate  the  self-­‐referential  

structures  that  seem  to  be  the  hallmark  of  any  attempt  of  conceptually  

characterizing  dynamicity.    

 

References:  

Ackrill,  J.  (1965)  Aristotle’s  distinction  between  Energeia  and  Kinesis.  In  Bambrough  R.,  (ed.),    New  Essays  on  Plato  and  Aristotle,  London:  Routledge  &  Kegan  Paul,  53-­‐74.    

Barnes, J. (ed.)(1984) The Complete Works of Aristotle, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Bergson,  H.  (2002).  Henri  Bergson:  Key  Writings.  Bloomsbury  Publishing.  Chen, C.H. (1956) Different Meanings of the Term Energeia in the Philosophy of

Aristotle” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 17, 56-65. Cotnoir,  A.  J.  (2010).  Anti-­‐Symmetry  and  Non-­‐Extensional  Mereology.  The  

Philosophical  Quarterly  60,  396-­‐405.  Furth, M. (1985) Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Book VII-X, Indianapolis: Hackett. Graham.  D.   (1980)   States   and  Performances:  Aristotle’s  Test.  Philosophical  Quarterly  

30,  117-­‐130.  Hagen,  C.  (1984)  The  Energeia-­‐Kinesis  distinction  and  Aristotle’s  Conception  of  Praxis.  

Journal  of  the  History  of  Philosophy  22,  263-­‐280.  Kosman,  L.  (1984)  Substance,  Being,  and  Energeia,  Oxford  Studies  in  Ancient  

Philosophy  2:  121-­‐149.  Maudlin,  T.  (2007).  The  metaphysics  within  physics.  Oxford  University  Press.  Mourelatos,  A.  (1978  )  Events,  Processes,  and  States.  Linguistics  and  Philosophy  2:  

415-­‐434.  Nietzsche,  F.  (1974)  The  Gay  Science.  Trans.  Walter  Kaufmann.  New  York:  

Random  House,  1974.    Turner,  J.  (2010).  Ontological  pluralism.  Journal  of  Philosophy,  107,  5-­‐37.  Rijksbaron,  A.  (1989)  Aristotle,  Verb  Meaning  and  Functional  Grammar.    Towards  

a  New  Typology  of  States  of  Affairs,  Amsterdam:  J.  C.  Gieben.  Rudder-­‐Baker,  L.  (2010)  Time  and  Identity.  In  Campbell,  J.  et  al.  (Eds.),  Time  and  

Identity,  Cambridge,  MA:MIT  Press,  27-­‐49.  Seibt,  J.  (1990) Towards Process Ontology: A Critical Study of Substance-

Ontological Premises. (Ph. D. Dissertation at the University of Pittsburgh, Michigan: UMI Publications).

-- (1995) "Individuen als Prozesse: Zur prozeß-ontologischen Revision des Substanzparadigmas," Logos 2, 352-384.

-­‐-­‐   (1996)    Der  Umbau  des  'Aufbau':  Carnap  und  die  analytische  Ontologie,  Deutsche  Zeitschrift  für  Philosophie  44,  807-­‐835.  

-­‐-­‐   (1997a)      Existence  in  Time:  From  Substance  to  Process.  In  Faye,  J.  et  al  (Eds.),  Perspectives  on  Time.    Boston  Studies  in  Philosophy  of  Science,  (Dordrecht:  Kluwer),  143-­‐182  

-­‐-­‐   (1997b)  The  'Umbau':  From  Constitution  Theory  to  Constructionism.  History  of  Philosophy  Quarterly  14,  305-­‐351.  

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  24  

-­‐-­‐   (2000)  Constitution  Theory  and  Metaphysical  Neutrality:  A  Lesson  for    Ontology?  The  Monist    83,  161-­‐183.  

-­‐-­‐   (2001)  Ontological  Categories:  the  Explanation  of  Categorial  Inference.    In  Greiman,  D.    (Ed.)  Wahrheit—System¬  –  Struktur:  Auseinandersetzungen  mit  Metaphysik.  Frankfurt:  Olms-­‐Verlag,  272-­‐297.  

-­‐-­‐   (2004a) Free Process Theory: Towards a Typology of Processes. Axiomathes 14: 23-57.

-­‐-­‐   (2004b)  General  Processes-­A  Study  in  Ontological  Theory  Construction,  Habilitationsschrift  at  the  University  of  Konstanz,  Germany.  

-- (2005) Der Mythos der Substanz. In Käthe Trettin (ed.) Substanz—Neue Überlegungen zu einer klassischen Kategorie des Seienden. Klostermann, Frankfurt. 197-229

-- (2008) Beyond Endurance and Perdurance: Recurrent Dynamics. In Christian Kanzian (ed.), Persistence. Ontos Verlag. 121-153.

-­‐-­‐   (2009) Forms of emergent interaction in General Process Theory. Synthese 166, 479-512.

-- (2010) Particulars. In Poli, R. et al. (Eds.) Theory and Applications of Ontology: Philosophical Perspectives. Vol. 1 New York : Springer Publishing Company, 23-57.

-- (2015) Non-transitive Parthood, Leveled Mereology, and the Representation of Emergent Parts of Processes. Forthcoming in Grazer Philosophische Studien.

-- (201+) Ontological Scope and Linguistic Diversity. Under submission. Sellars,  W.,  1962,  Time  and  the  World  Order.  In  Feigl,  H.,  M.  Scriven,  and  G.  

Maxwell  (Eds.),    Minnesota  Studies  in  the  Philosophy  of  Science,      Volume  III,  University  of  Minnesota  Press,  Minneapolis,  pp.  527-­‐616.  

Taylor,  B.  (1977)Tense  and  Continuity.  Linguistics  and  Philosophy  1:  199-­‐220.  Verkuyl,    H.  (1972)  On  the  Compositional  Nature  of  the  Aspect,  Dordrecht:  Reidel.      

   

             

In:  V.  Petrov/A.  Scarfe  (eds.)  2015,  Dynamic  Being,  Cambridge  Scholars,  2-­‐28.  

  25