Abraham Ibn Ezra

21
Abraham Ibn Ezra First published Tue Dec 19, 2006; substantive revision Wed Feb 19, 2014 All histories of Jewish philosophy include an entry on Abraham Ibn Ezra, and, judging from his impact on the field, he certainly deserves the recognition that he has received. Just how he earned it, however, poses a difficult historical problem. Ibn Ezra contributed virtually nothing to any of the branches of philosophy; he authored little in the way of strictly philosophical tracts and, indeed, there is no reason for us to suppose that he enjoyed any rigorous training in philosophy. Yet he certainly left his mark on Jewish thought, and his pronouncements are recorded and treated with respect by those who came after him. Ibn Ezra's philosophical legacy consists in the main of the following, rather short list of doctrines. The deity governs the terrestrial world by means of the heavenly bodies. Humans toil under astral destiny; though the stars are subservient, formally at least, to God, their domination over the material universe is for all practical purposes complete. Neither the precise structure of the human soul, nor the mode of its bonding with the body, may be known with certainty. However, one component or aspect of the human soul is of the same fiber as the supernal realm that is above the stars; nothing in existence is more similar to God. Nurturing this spiritual component offers the one hope of refuge from this world. Ibn Ezra's poetry in particular gives very powerful expression to the themes of the soul's alienation and longing to return to its heavenly abode. To be sure, weighty questions are involved in all of these teachings, but Ibn Ezra does not take any of them up in depth. In sum, it appears that Ibn Ezra, much like Sa‘adiah—the Jewish thinker who influenced him most stronglyadopted a mix of kalam and philosophical doctrines. There simply is no evidence that he trained in philosophy or studied anything more than a small sampling of the literature available in his day, which was considerable. His acknowledged sources are nearly all brief, gaonic, writings, which display the first grapplings of medieval Jewry with theological issues. Nonetheless, Ibn Ezra achieved the status of the sage whose remarks, curt and enigmatic thought they may be, carry weight and authority. In a way, his role in philosophy, or, perhaps better put, in spreading certain philosophical teachings, is not that different from the one he played in mathematics, astronomy, and astrology. His copious writings on those subjects are not distinguished by any depth or originality; yet there can be no doubt that their role was pivotal in the spread of knowledge throughout Europe, most especially within the Jewish communities, though by no means limited to them. While not pretending to offer a complete and completely satisfying answer, we suggest a combination of factors that facilitated his success: industriousness, wide travels, the very popular vehicle of bible commentary, rational thought that gives a prominent place to astrology, and a soteriology that focuses upon the individual rather than the collective.

Transcript of Abraham Ibn Ezra

Abraham Ibn Ezra

First published Tue Dec 19, 2006; substantive revision Wed Feb 19, 2014

All histories of Jewish philosophy include an entry on Abraham Ibn Ezra, and, judging

from his impact on the field, he certainly deserves the recognition that he has received.

Just how he earned it, however, poses a difficult historical problem. Ibn Ezra contributed

virtually nothing to any of the branches of philosophy; he authored little in the way of

strictly philosophical tracts and, indeed, there is no reason for us to suppose that he

enjoyed any rigorous training in philosophy. Yet he certainly left his mark on Jewish

thought, and his pronouncements are recorded and treated with respect by those who

came after him.

Ibn Ezra's philosophical legacy consists in the main of the following, rather short list of

doctrines. The deity governs the terrestrial world by means of the heavenly bodies.

Humans toil under astral destiny; though the stars are subservient, formally at least, to

God, their domination over the material universe is for all practical purposes complete.

Neither the precise structure of the human soul, nor the mode of its bonding with the

body, may be known with certainty. However, one component or aspect of the human

soul is of the same fiber as the supernal realm that is above the stars; nothing in existence

is more similar to God. Nurturing this spiritual component offers the one hope of refuge

from this world. Ibn Ezra's poetry in particular gives very powerful expression to the

themes of the soul's alienation and longing to return to its heavenly abode. To be sure,

weighty questions are involved in all of these teachings, but Ibn Ezra does not take any of

them up in depth.

In sum, it appears that Ibn Ezra, much like Sa‘adiah—the Jewish thinker who influenced

him most strongly—adopted a mix of kalam and philosophical doctrines. There simply is

no evidence that he trained in philosophy or studied anything more than a small sampling

of the literature available in his day, which was considerable. His acknowledged sources

are nearly all brief, gaonic, writings, which display the first grapplings of medieval Jewry

with theological issues.

Nonetheless, Ibn Ezra achieved the status of the sage whose remarks, curt and enigmatic

thought they may be, carry weight and authority. In a way, his role in philosophy, or,

perhaps better put, in spreading certain philosophical teachings, is not that different from

the one he played in mathematics, astronomy, and astrology. His copious writings on

those subjects are not distinguished by any depth or originality; yet there can be no doubt

that their role was pivotal in the spread of knowledge throughout Europe, most especially

within the Jewish communities, though by no means limited to them. While not

pretending to offer a complete and completely satisfying answer, we suggest a

combination of factors that facilitated his success: industriousness, wide travels, the very

popular vehicle of bible commentary, rational thought that gives a prominent place to

astrology, and a soteriology that focuses upon the individual rather than the collective.

1. Life and Works

2. Astrology

3. Impact

4. Emphasis upon the Individual

5. Characterizations of his Thought

6. What is Philosophy for Ibn Ezra? Who are his philosophers?

7. Ibn Ezra and Judah Halevi

8. Poetry and the Science of the Soul

9. Excursus on the Soul in a Comment to Ecclesiastes

10. Rationale for the Commandments: Yesod Mora

11. Philosophical Allegory: Hayy ben Meqitz

Bibliography

o Primary Sources

o Secondary Sources

Academic Tools

Other Internet Resources

Related Entries

1. Life and Works

Ibn Ezra was likely born in or around 1093 in Tudela, at that time within the northern

reaches of Muslim Spain. There he passed the first five decades of his life, apparently

eking out his living as a poet. Like so many other Jews, he fled Spain in the face of the

Almohade onslaughts of 1140. For the next three decades he wandered through Europe,

spending time in Rome, Lucca, Rouen, London, and Béziers. Nearly all of the substantial

body of writing that he left behind dates to this period. The names of a few of his

students, correspondents, rivals, and patrons are known. We are rather well-informed

about Ibn Ezra's relationship with Judah Halevi; their exchanges are very instructive for

the history of Jewish philosophy, and we will return to them below. On the other hand,

none of his disciples (who in any event do not seem to have been numerous) has clarified

for us any of the “secrets” that Ibn Ezra is fond to refer to.

Ibn Ezra's literary legacy consists of short and extremely popular handbooks in a wide

variety of fields: grammar and poetics, astrology and arithmetic, astronomy and religious

speculations, as well as both short and lengthier biblical commentaries. Most of his

astrological tracts circulate in at least two versions; their Latin versions played a pivotal

role in the spread of that art throughout Christian Europe. Manuscripts number in many

dozens. The biblical commentaries are also found in very manuscripts, and they are

included in the margins of numerous printings. On the other hand, there are relatively few

critical editions of his writings. This situation has been largely rectified for his

astrological writings, surely the most important part of his corpus, due to the untiring

work of Shlomo Sela. Moreover, Sela's highly praised editionsand translations have

brought to light even more texts, in both Hebrew and Latin. (For the most recent

inventory of primary sources and secondary studies, see Sela and Freudenthal 2006;

newer editions by Sela are listed in the bibliography.) Several long excursuses, for

example to Exodus 3:15 or Exodus 33:21, recap his statements on the main issues. Yesod

Mora, a monograph on the rationale underlying the biblical commandments written very

late in his life, also contains a full statement of Ibn Ezra's teachings.

Two other short treatises have each a peculiar focus. Sefer ha-Shem is an enigmatic

treatise on God's proper names written out with the Hebrew letters AHYH and YHWY.

The basic idea is that the special properties of the numbers associated with these letters,

their phonetic qualities, grammatical functions and graphic representations, all convey

information about the godhead. Thus, for instance, one (A, aleph) is the foundation of

number, but not a number itself; both five (H, heh) and six (W, waw) repeat themselves

as the final digit in all higher powers; and ten (Y, yod) is the beginning of the next order

in the decimal system. All this seems to indicate the unchanging aspect of the divine in its

successive manifestations. The same collection of ideas is found in non-philosophical

writings, for example, the grammatical treatise Sefer Zahut.

Indeed, if Ibn Ezra can be located within any of the major philosophical traditions, his

place is among the Pythagoreans. Sefer ha-Ehad is Ibn Ezra's venture in arithmology.

Like the writings of Nicomachus of Gerasa and Philo, as well as a relatively short list of

medieval Muslim and Jewish authors, Sefer ha-Ehad follows the Pythagorean tradition of

listing which natural, mathematical, and other items, come in two's, three's, etc. As we

have seen in the preceding paragraph, Ibn Ezra pressed especially the theological

implications of these arithmetic properties.

The two most “philosophical” of his writings are Hayy ben Meqitz, a poetic visionary

recital to be discussed in a separate section below, and Arugat ha-Bosem. The latter is

also poetic in style. The doctrine it presents, for example atomism, is very much part and

parcel of the kalam tradition, rather than philosophy, strictly speaking. For that reason,

Ibn Ezra's authorship has been called into question (Greive 1973, 181–189, including

German translation of the entire text). However, even such a committed neoplatonist as

Isaac Israeli had no compunction about contributing to the kalam, and there is no reason a

priori to think that the situation would have been different for Ibn Ezra. Allegiances to

streams of thought in that period were not necessarily exclusivist.

The two strongest influences on Ibn Ezra's thought are the anonymous tract known as

Sefer Yesira and Sa‘adiah Gaon. The former is his acknowledged source for surveying

reality according to three parallel schemes: Hebrew letters, numbers, and the cosmos.

Sa‘adiah is cited very frequently, over thirty times in the commentary to the Torah alone.

Some medieval writers cite from a commentary to Sefer Yesira that they ascribe to Ibn

Ezra. Paul Fenton [2001] has recently argued that the text in question is a Hebrew

condensation of the commentary by Dunash Ibn Tamîm, originally written in Arabic, and

that Ibn Ezra may indeed have prepared the Hebrew version. However, Dunash was a

student of Isaac Israeli, who strongly criticized Sa‘adiah's commentary to Sefer Yesira.

Thus Ibn Ezra may, unwittingly, have drawn most heavily upon two divergent streams of

thought. As we have seen, this is not as shocking as it may seem. Ibn Ezra was interested

in ideas, but not in putting them all together into one tight and fully coherent system.

A few other sources are named in Yesod Mora: Shi‘ur Qoma, a cryptic writing that, like

Sefer Yesira, nourished a good deal of speculation, much of it mystical, and a certain

Sefer ha-Yihud, which is not extant. These works date to the gaonic period which, in

Jewish historiography, corresponds to very late antiquity and the early Middle Ages. All

in all, then, the sources that Ibn Ezra cites by name are a mix of gaonic kalam and proto-

kabbalistic mysticism. Ibn Ezra adopted the literary format of early gaonic texts for those

of his writings that can be called philosophical. Yesod Mora and Sefer ha-Shem, “The

Book of the [Divine] Name”, are dense and cryptic, much like Sefer Yesira and Shi‘ur

Qoma.

Throughout his life Ibn Ezra continued to write poetry in a wide variety of styles. Some

of his liturgies make use of concepts drawn from medieval psychology. However, it is not

so much the display of terminology, as it is the deep, powerful and sincere longings for

liberation and the divine that are instructive for an appreciation of his thought. Ibn Ezra

was no schoolman, but he certainly experienced, and expressed in rich and evocative

Hebrew, a deep alienation from mundane reality and passionate longing to return to the

spiritual realm.

2. Astrology

The central place of astrology in Ibn Ezra's thought must be singled out here. The query

of the rabbis of Provence to Maimonides about the legitimacy of astrology was most

likely prompted by the spread of Ibn Ezra's astrological teachings (Sela 2004). Though

the query and Maimonides' response both turned upon the interpretation of traditional

texts and their legal implications, de rigueur in correspondence of this sort, one finds here

new probings into issues such as free will and divine governance. Ibn Ezra spurred a

reassessment of Jewish positions on these points.

Astrology was one of Ibn Ezra's major interests, and it plays an important role in his

thought (Sela 2001, mainly for bibliography; Goldstein 1996, for precise contents

analysis). Briefly—in fact, as we have repeatedly noted, Ibn Ezra's expositions are always

brief, with little argumentation—Ibn Ezra considers the material universe to be divided

into celestial and terrestrial realms, the latter totally under the sway of the former.

Humans can link up to a third, divine and super-celestial realm, thus outmaneuvering the

stars, so to speak. However, more often than not, this will bring no relief to one's earthly

plight; in any case, pessimism of this sort informs Ibn Ezra's commentary to Ecclesiastes.

Ibn Ezra advocates a Stoic-like faith: the connection to the world “above the stars”

affords one the spiritual stamina to endure whatever earthly misery the stars may dish out

(Langermann 1993).

There is no difference between Jews and non-Jews with regard to astral governance. Here

again, Ibn Ezra, in his biblical commentaries, was vague enough to give the impression

that Jews alone are exempt from the decrees of the stars, thus ingratiating himself to those

many of his readers who were disposed to thinking that way. However, in his astrological

writings, the Jews are no different from other peoples, in that they too are associated with

certain planets and signs; this point was not lost upon his super-commentators. Ibn Ezra's

astrology, like his philosophy overall, is humanist and universal, not Jewish and

particularist. (See on this point, from a different perspective, Hughes 1999.)

Astrology offered a rational explanation for some biblical commandments, particularly

animal sacrifices. True, over a millennium had passed since the Temple temple rituals

had ceased. However, new conceptions of worship led Jews to wonder why such acts had

ever been needed. In addition, new conceptions of Scripture caused Jews to ask why the

details of the sacrifices had been recorded in the Torah, all of whose teachings were

thought to be of permanent value, even if the rites themselves were no longer performed.

Astrology provided a rationale: a practical reason for doing these performances as long as

the Temple stood, and a lesson in the way the cosmos functions whose value endures

even after the Temple's destruction. It should be added, however, that there is no

evidence at all that these explanations inspired calls for the restoration of sacrifice. Ibn

Ezra's followers were content merely to ponder these truths. Ironically, perhaps, the

messianic drive exhibited itself more in the thought of Judah Halevi whose basic outlook,

as we shall see, was diametrically opposed to that of Ibn Ezra.

3. Impact

Ibn Ezra's impact was swift and powerful. In the various communities through which he

sojourned, the Arabic learning which he was able to present in consumable form was

widely read. As a cultural mediator, particularly of astronomy and astrology, his

contributions to Christian civilization were no less remarkable than those to his

coreligionists. [See in particular Burnett 1997] Indeed, Ibn Ezra may well be the most

important cultural broker of the medieval period. His writings in astrology, arithmetic,

Hebrew grammar and poetics, and Jewish thought all fall far short of the highest

achievements set by Judaeo-Arabic culture in al-Andalus. Yet no one succeeded more

than Ibn Ezra in spreading the fruits of this culture so widely and deeply.

This seems to be the main reason why he has secured his place in the history of Jewish

philosophy. Even in those domains where he has relatively much to say, for example, the

theory of the soul, he draws upon stock notions that were widespread (especially among

poets), and which by no means demonstrate a thorough education in philosophy, let alone

the skill and propensity to philosophize. Historians of Jewish liturgy such as Jefim

Schirmann have pointed out that Ibn Ezra was harping on themes that had been favorites

of Jewish poets for generations. He exhibits a familiarity with many technical terms, and

on occasion broaches some issues; however, he has left us no penetrating discussions, or

anything of the sort that would demonstrate his mastery of the subject. Thus, for example,

in his gloss to Exodus 23:30, he observes that we do not whether the soul is substance or

accident, whether it survives the death of the body, nor why it has been bonded to the

body in the first place. However, one can hardly find, if at all, any substantive discussions

on any of these three questions; he tells us nothing about the options, their implications,

or why the inquiry must end at an impasse.

For many Jews, Ibn Ezra was the spokesman of Hispano-Jewish culture, the

personification of the “Sefardi” sage. His readers were led to believe that the prestige of

Andalusian culture stood behind Ibn Ezra's pronouncements on issues such as the nature

of the soul or free will, and that the Torah could and should be read in a manner that

accommodates Ibn Ezra's views.

Ibn Ezra's use of the biblical commentary as a vehicle for the dissemination of his

teachings was undoubtedly a major factor in his success. His commentary (actually two

are preserved for several books) was a concise gloss, offering to his audiences a witty and

critical selection of lexical and grammatical insights concerning the “plain” meaning of

the text; this is the mode of interpretation that he expressly endorses. Ibn Ezra spiced his

commentary with occasional references to a sod, meaning either (or both?) a secret, i.e.

esoteric message ensconced in the bible—Ibn Ezra will teasingly pull at the veil, but

never remove it—or a fundamental belief (sod thus being equivalent to yesod). Ibn Ezra

prefaced his commentary with a lengthy essay on the four improper, and the one proper,

way to go about interpreting the Torah. Finally, he dispersed a number of fairly long

digressions, self-standing essays in their own right, in which, in which he generally

rehearsed the gamut of his trademark views on grammar, arithmology, and astrology.

Ibn Ezra's commentary, mostly by virtue of the terse, enticing, yet thoroughly obtuse

sodot, spawned a huge satellite literature (Simon 1993). These “supercommentaries”

constitute one of the major branches of Jewish philosophical literature of the fourteenth

century. As a rule, they tend to interpret Ibn Ezra along similar lines, emphasizing, for

example, astral governance and the magical aspects of ritual. Yet Ibn Ezra succeeded in

some sense in making himself all things to all people. The supercommentators as a rule

find Ibn Ezra to be expounding a univeralist, or humanitarian, philosophy that shares

much with, and draws much from, non-Jewish thought. On the other hand, Moses

Nahmanides, an important exegete in his own right, a very astute reader of texts, and a

staunch opponent of Aristotle, professed his “open hostility and concealed love” for Ibn

Ezra. He loved many of Ibn Ezra's “hints” which, Nahmanides felt, were in line with his

own kabbalistic tendencies.

Estimations of Ibn Ezra as a philosopher peaked in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries.

Glosses to his Torah commentary, some of them quite extensive, were written throughout

the Mediterranean basin (Simon 1993). Ibn Ezra's writings became known within Arabic

speaking communities as well. At least one of these supercommentaries was written in

Judaeo-Arabic, and Ibn Ezra is cited, for example, by Abraham Maimonides in his own

commentary to the Torah. Byzantine Jewish scholars in particular applied themselves to

the entire corpus of Ibn Ezra's philosophical writings. Mordecai Khoumtianou

(Comteano) wrote commentaries to Yesod Mora and Sefer ha-Shem, doing his best to

read Ibn Ezra along the lines of the (basically Aristotelian) philosophy that he felt most

comfortable with.

Levi ben Gerson, certainly one of the most systematic and original thinkers in the

medieval Jewish tradition, will cite Abraham Ibn Ezra just as respectfully as he does

Moses Maimonides. Consider, for example, his discussion of God's knowledge,

especially the thorny question whether God knows a particular event befalling an

individual per se, or whether He knows that event only “generally”, that is, by way of His

knowledge of the “ordering of events, insofar as these events are ordered.” Levi argues in

favor of the second option, and at the end of the chapter, suggests that both Maimonides

and Ibn Ezra would agree with him. For Maimonides' view Levi can refer to the sustained

discussion in Guide of the Perplexed 3.20; but for Ibn Ezra, he cites only the laconic

comment to Genesis 18:21, which states: “The truth is that He knows every particular

generally, not as a particular.”[1]

It seems particularly noteworthy that Levi musters both

Maimonides and Ibn Ezra for support for the claim that his own view does not contradict

the Torah; both authorities are exploited, not for their argumentation on the issue, but

rather for their reputation as exegetes.

Ibn Ezra never fell into oblivion, and his writings generated interest in a wide variety of

cultural and historical settings. However, there were significant shifts in the perception of

his place in Jewish thought. Thus Judah Moscato, the sixteenth century Venetian savant

and author of a very learned commentary to Halevi's Kuzari, arrays Ibn Ezra together

with Gersonides against Maimonides and Halevi—the former denying creation ex nihilo,

the latter defending it (Langermann 1997, 517).

Spinoza singled out Ibn Ezra for being the first, as far as he knew, to question the Mosaic

authorship of the Pentateuch (Harris 1993, 130–132). This observation greatly enhanced

Ibn Ezra's stature as an exegete, especially among Christians. Ibn Ezra's emphasis on

peshat, the “natural” interpretation of the Bible founded on philology and free of rabbinic

interpretations, gained thereby considerable prestige. To be sure, Spinoza's view of Ibn

Ezra was not uniformly positive, and, for his part, Ibn Ezra makes it quite clear that his

philological tools are not to be applied against tradition, but only where there is no

tradition, and, especially, where no normative practices are at stake. However, as we have

already seen, there have been wide fluctuations in the image of Ibn Ezra and the

interpretation of his legacy.

The modern Jewish philosopher most indebted to Ibn Ezra is Nahum Krochmal. Jay

Harris has argued persuasively that “Krochmal's understanding of Ibn Ezra, and his

motivation for that understanding, can only be understood as the fashioning of a response

to the most interesting and serious philosophical critique of Judaism the nineteenth

century produced” (Harris 1993, 144)—that is, the critiques of Hegel and Schelling.

Krochmal also influenced the philological side of Ibn Ezra scholarship, for example, by

casting doubt upon the authenticity of Arugat ha-Bosem; there is as yet no consensus on

this issue [Greive 1973, 175–177].

4. Emphasis upon the Individual

A very important feature of Ibn Ezra's philosophy is its focus upon the salvation of the

individual. His expressions mark a major shift in religious attitude. Traditional rabbinic

Judaism, especially as reflected in the liturgy, had been concerned above all with the

collective redemption of the Jewish people. Sophisticated circles in Judaeo-Arabic

culture of al-Andalus had, for at least a century before Ibn Ezra, focused their soteriology

instead on the ultimate felicity of the individual. It is very probable that in this issue, as in

so many others, Ibn Ezra's role was that of the transmitter. The crisp formulations

scattered throughout his biblical commentaries and topical booklets were far more

accessible to the Jews of Christian Europe than the writings of other Jewish Andalusians,

and they were pivotal in the spread of this key idea.

The focus upon the salvation of the individual comes out clearly in the opening sections

of Yesod Mora. Ibn Ezra critically reviews the different motivations people have for

gaining expertise in the Law. Some do it for prestige, but this leads to social friction.

Others study the Law in order to improve society. This is commendable; however, this

implies that in a just society, the Law would be superfluous. We can carry Ibn Ezra's

reasoning further: the Law must have some ultimate justification that is invariant over

any and every social or historical situation. With this in mind, we can see the connection

to the next point raised in the passage, which is this: many laws of the Torah are rarely if

ever applied. How, then, the reader is led to wonder, can the Law be an end in itself for

Jewish life? Moreover, Ibn Ezra asks, how many legal experts do we need anyway?

Two conclusions follow from this series of arguments. First, Torah study, in the sense of

mastery of all the fine points of the Law, can not be the ultimate purpose of our existence.

Second, the ultimate purpose does not lie in one's contribution to the community. Ibn

Ezra is now ready to state what the goal of life is:

“The person (ha-adam) must set himself aright. He must know the commandments of

God, Who created everything. He must try with all of his strength to understand [God's]

works—then he will know his Creator…and when he knows Him he will find favor in

His eyes.” After citing some biblical prooftexts—standard fare by then in the Arabic

speaking communities for the view that knowledge is the true form of worship, Ibn Ezra

sums up: “It is for this reason that man was created. Once one has rectified oneself, he

may set others aright, if this be possible” (Cohen 2002, 83–84).

On the face of it, then, Ibn Ezra conforms to the tradition that the Torah gives meaning to

life. However, the Law is now just one of God's handiworks, and not necessarily the most

important of them. Ibn Ezra clearly subscribes to the view then current among

philosophers that the purpose and goal of human existence is to know God. This

responsibility devolves upon each individual; it is not a communal project and, indeed,

Ibn Ezra evinces no interest in the “ideal city”. However, he merely states this goal; he

has no theory of the intellect, no refined or even coarse epistemology. He has in effect

grossly devalued Torah study, but he has done this in a way that is not abrasive. (In fact,

there is a long-standing controversy as to how much “Torah” Ibn Ezra himself knew.)

This is a classic example of the way Ibn Ezra quietly if not elegantly insinuates radical

views into the tradition.

5. Characterizations of his Thought

Ibn Ezra's thought has been located (or fitted) into three traditions. Many medieval

philosophers, and opponents of philosophy as well, sensed a commonality of purpose as

well as the sharing of basic doctrines between Ibn Ezra and Maimonides. Joint allegiance

to Maimonides and Ibn Ezra was particularly strong in the fourteenth century. The

principle vehicle for this trend of thought was the supercommentary to Ibn Ezra, which

number a few dozen. These authors were particularly impressed by the willingness of

both sages to appeal to sources beyond the traditional rabbinic corpus in order to

understand the biblical narratives and commandments. Rationality (in the sense of

seeking a ratio for Judaism, its beliefs and precepts) bonded Ibn Ezra and Maimonides,

blurring the differences between the two, even on such basic questions as the legitimacy

of astrology.

The pseudepigraphic testament of Maimonides, in which he expresses his admiration in

the strongest terms for Ibn Ezra's Torah commentary and the “great and deep secrets” that

he revealed there, is most likely a product of this same trend. However, as Isadore

Twersky has pointed out, the fact that the “testament” is said to have been written by

Maimonides at the end of his life, after he had already written his own works, indicates

that its author wants us only to take note of the literary and notional parallels between the

two thinkers; the forger is not prepared to make any stronger claims of influence

(Twersky 1993, 39–40).

Just how much, if anything, Maimonides owes to Ibn Ezra has been debated for over a

century, without any clear resolution. The survey of Twersky (1993) covers the ground

well. The strongest claims extend Ibn Ezra's influence even to the realm of legal theory,

asserting that the fourteen principles enunciated by Maimonides at the beginning of his

Book of Commandments were inspired and to a degree modeled upon the principles set

down by Ibn Ezra in Yesod Mora. Since, by most modern accounts, Maimonides is to be

classified as an Aristotelian (or perhaps neo-Aristotelian), it should stand to reason that,

were he really a follower of Ibn Ezra, the latter would also be an Aristotelian. Histories of

Jewish philosophy, as we shall see, unanimously locate Ibn Ezra in the neoplatonic camp.

However, Yosef Cohen has recently argued that Ibn Ezra indeed fits more comfortably

into the Aristotelian tradition (Cohen 1996).

Generations of scholars have found the “neo-platonist” label to be most appropriate.

Julius Guttmann, who may well be responsible for defining medieval Jewish

neoplatonism as a historical category, declared Ibn Ezra to be “the last in the line of

Jewish Neoplatonists”. Guttmann was fully aware, like all historians of Jewish thought,

that Ibn Ezra was not a systematic thinker, and he was more precise than any later

historian in pinpointing the agreements and disagreements between Ibn Ezra and what

may be called standard neoplatonic teachings. Nonetheless, he averred that “Ibn Ezra was

moved more profoundly than most of his Jewish predecessors by the mysterious depths

of Neoplatonism, approaching its metaphysical content more closely than any of the

others except Gabirol” (Guttman 1973, 134).

Isaac Husik marks Ibn Ezra's role in the transmission of Andalusian wisdom, which

consists of “grammar… mathematics and astronomy…the philosophy of Neo-Platonism,

and the scientific and rationalistic spirit generally” (Husik 1969, 187). Like Guttmann,

Husik calls attention to the affinity between Ibn Ezra and Ibn Gabirol. In 1973, Hermann

Greive published a book-length study of Ibn Ezra under the title, Studien zum Jüdischen

Neuplatonismus. Greive paid particular attention to Ibn Ezra's psychology; this is indeed

the branch of philosophy to which Ibn Ezra was most strongly attracted, and the topic

exploited most intensively by recent investigations into Ibn Ezra's philosophy

(Tanenbaum 1990; Levin 1992). However, Greive is well-aware that the presence of

neoplatonic teachings in Ibn Ezra's writings does not mean that Ibn Ezra's allegiance was

limited to that school exclusively.

The trend is continued in the latest history of Jewish philosophy, that by Colette Sirat,

who discusses Abraham Ibn Ezra at the end of the chapter on “The Neoplatonists”.

However, cognizant of the rich Hebrew literature of the later medieval period (much of

which was as yet unstudied and thus inaccessible to Guttmann), Sirat does not make Ibn

Ezra into the last neoplatonist. Instead she observes, “The neoplatonic influence clearly

marked in the Jewish philosophers of the of the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries was

essentially expressed in terms and ideas drawn from Ibn Ezra” (Sirat 1985, 104).

Aaron Hughes acknowledges the problematic nature of the label "neoplatonic"; in a note

he registers his preference to the view that “the Neoplatonic “system” to which he

subscribed permitted one to have many divided, and often competing, loyalties” (Hughes,

2002, n. 13). Nonetheless, Hughes too cannot resist the label.

One term in particular found in some key passages, kol or “all”, has attracted a good deal

of attention of late. Building on the observations of several scholars, Elliot Wolfson

(1990; see esp. p. 80, nn. 14–16, for references to earlier work on the topic) examines

closely the two different senses in which Ibn Ezra uses the term. At times it refers to the

totality of created entities, but in other passages it refers to an entity that comprises all

things within itself in ideal form—not God, but the demiurge (yoser bereishit). This dual

meaning can be traced back to Proclus, and its usage highlights the neoplatonic trend in

Ibn Ezra's thought. Howard Kreisel [1994] has rejected this interpretation. Kreisel

criticizes the emphasis upon “neoplatonism” here; he encloses the term in quotation

marks, as the present writer tends to do, and for much the same reasons. Medieval Jewish

neoplatonism is an ill-defined term, and all attempts to explicate Ibn Ezra's

“neoplatonism” are problematic, forcing scholars to note numerous points of agreement

between Ibn Ezra and the Aristotelians—which, in turn, cannot be divorced from the

neoplatonic interpretations informing Islamic Aristotelianism in general. Kreisel argues

that, when read closely in context, the texts in question display one meaning only for

kol—God, the Creator God, and not the demiurge.

Hence there seems to be little profit in belaboring Ibn Ezra's supposed neoplatonism. On

the other hand, Ibn Ezra's affinities to Ibn Gabirol (Avicebron to the Latins, and a

neoplatonist for sure) are relevant. Some of Ibn Gabirol's allegorical readings of the Bible

are cited by Ibn Ezra—indeed, he is our only source for them. Ibn Gabirol's Fons Vitae

certainly belongs to the neoplatonic tradition. Significantly, however, that work (which

Ibn Ezra would presumably have seen in the original Arabic) is not mentioned by Ibn

Ezra at all. By all indications, he would not have had the patience or disposition for that

text's scholasticism.

The role of Ibn Gabirol is indeed pivotal. Ibn Gabirol was accused by his contemporaries,

and credited by modern scholars, with introducing “Greek” notions into his poetry. All

the great Andalusian poets, were to some degree—Ibn Ezra, quite substantially—students

and imitators of Ibn Gabirol. The link between Ibn Ezra and Ibn Gabirol is significant,

but the common thread running between the two, and other Andalusian Jewish poets as

well who plunged into “the mysterious depths of Neoplatonism”, is to be found in their

poetry, rather than in prose expositions of philosophy. The soul's longing for release from

this world and liberation, or obliteration, in the divine, are themes which found powerful

expression in their liturgies, and which bond them to at least one important facet of

neoplatonism and to each other more truly than any specific doctrines that they may hold

concerning the origin of matter or the nature of prophetic inspiration.

Historians of Jewish philosophy label Ibn Ezra's thought “neoplatonic” also on the

strength of his deep involvement in astrology and arithmology, as well as his deep

longing for release from this world. However, the very term “neoplatonic” is applied

imprecisely in the history of medieval Jewish philosophy, and it usually indicates little

more than a gross bifurcation between “Aristotelians” and all of the rest who, as a rule,

are labeled neoplatonic. It is therefore appropriate to take note of Ibn Ezra's divergence

from some widely accepted neoplatonic teachings. Ibn Ezra denies the existence of

demons. He says nothing of the soul's descent through the celestial orbs, though this

teaching was known to his contemporary pseudo-Bahya, and would perhaps naturally

have appealed to an astrologer. Finally, he says nothing of musical harmonies—despite

the clear Pythagoreanism of his Sefer ha-Ehad (Langermann 1993, 66). In sum, then, it

seems most prudent to observe that Ibn Ezra makes use of mostly stock notions, such as

the three “worlds”, that inform what has come to be known as Islamic and Jewish

neoplatonism. However, he had no direct acquaintance with Plato, Plotinus, or Proclus,

nor any inkling of the full richness of the Hellenistic neoplatonic tradition, the one

possible exception being arithmology.

The least well-known characterization, but one which has a lot to argue in its favor, is

given by Abraham, son of the illustrious Moses Maimonides. In his refreshing

perspective Ibn Ezra finds his place within a list of rabbis who taught the fundamental

doctrines that God is not a body; that God does not manifest any of the properties of

bodies; and that all problematic biblical verses must be (re)interpreted in order to

conform to these doctrines. It is interesting to note the other names on Abraham

Maimonides' list: Sa‘adiah Gaon, Samuel ben Hofni, Isaac Alfasi, Joseph Ibn Migash.[2]

Only the first of these is regarded today as a philosopher, and then only in the wider sense

of the word. It seems that Abraham, like his father, looked upon the whole lot—Ibn Ezra

included—as mutakallimūn, that is, religious thinkers who taught an acceptable (though

not necessarily correct) theology, which, however, lacked philosophical rigor, and which

contained some grave errors.

Indeed, Sa‘adiah's Beliefs and Opinions is the only extant, substantive work on Jewish

philosophy that Ibn Ezra mentions by name. The citation occurs at the very end of the

first chapter of Yesod Mora; Ibn Ezra observes that some portions of Sa‘adiah's book are

correct, but others are baseless. However, he never tells us exactly which portions are

acceptable and which not, nor does he engage Sa‘adiah in a pointed debate on any issue.

Throughout his opus, but most notably in his biblical commentaries, Ibn Ezra mentions

Sa‘adiah dozens of times; though he rarely mentions the specific source, he seems to be

referring most often to Sa‘adiah's own biblical commentaries. On the basis of this

statistic, at least, Sa‘adiah is, as noted above, the most important “influence” upon Ibn

Ezra.

6. What is Philosophy for Ibn Ezra? Who are his

philosophers?

The abundance of Hebrew terms in Ibn Ezra's writings that may refer to “philosophers”

or “philosophy”—none of them very precise, some of them perhaps coined by Ibn Ezra

itself—afford an additional perspective upon the peculiar nature of Ibn Ezra's

“philosophy”. The Hebrew homonyms for “philosophy” or “philosophers” (which

entered the language by way of the Arabic) never appear in the biblical commentaries. In

the single instance cited in Klatzkin's Lexicon, Ibn Ezra is reported to have used the word

in the restricted sense of astronomers, in a manner similar to that of his predecessor

Abraham bar Hiyya (whose astronomical writings he studied closely). This is not

necessarily the case; in the single instance cited by Klatzkin, filosofim is appears in

apposition to hakhamim, an all-purpose word meaning scholar or master of any of the

seven or ten sciences.[3]

Nonetheless, it does seem clear that Ibn Ezra has no concept of

falsafa in the sense that it was used in Arabic philosophy, that is, in the restricted sense of

Platonic and Aristotelian traditions.

The term shiqqul ha-da‘at (rational analysis, literally, “weighing [in the balance of]

reason”) is used in the broad sense of reason or rationality. In the introduction to his

commentary to the Torah, Ibn Ezra writes: “rational analysis (shiqqul ha-da‘at) is the

foundation, because the Torah was not given to those devoid of reason; and the go-

between (mal’akh, “angel” or “messenger”) between man and his God is his intellect.”

Soon after (gloss to Genesis 1:2) the same term is used in what could again be taken as a

strictly astronomical or scientific context: “People who employ rational analysis have

sure proofs that there is only one earth.” Ibn Ezra's main training was in the exact

sciences, and this fact is reflected in his usage of filosofim and shiqqul ha-da‘at.

In some cases, it is possible to narrow the sense of terms used by Ibn Ezra. An example is

“the scholars who [base their claims upon] proofs” (hakhmei ha-ra’ayot), which is found

in an excursus upon psychology, which we shall scrutinize below. Joseph Ibn Aqnin

employs a very similar expression: “logicians, who adduce proofs (ra’ayot) to strengthen

the Islamic religion, and the Ishmaelites call them mutakallimūn.”[4]

Given Ibn Ezra's

attachments to kalam, some of which have already been noted, it seems clear that the

term in question here, and perhaps others as well, refers to the doctors of the kalam.

References here and elsewhere to logic and proofs thus stand, in fact, for disputations that

are carried out on a rational basis, but not necessary by the rules of Aristotelian logic.

Another term employed by Ibn Ezra is hakhemei (or: anshei) ha-mehqar, literally

“scholars (or: people of inquiry). Bar Hiyya uses the term hakhemei ha-mehqar in the

sense of philosophers: “the form concerning which the hakhemei ha-mehqar said that it is

neither body nor attached to a body.”[5]

Tushiyya is yet another term. In one place Ibn Ezra contrasts the views of the people of

mehqar with those of the people of tushiyya, in a way that suggests that the former are

mutakallimûn and the latter fâlasifa. In his gloss to Psalms 104:30 he notes: “The people

of mehqar say that every living being will rise after his death; the people of tushiyya say

that the universals are preserved, but individuals perish.” The choice of this term clearly

derives from Sa'adiah's translation of tushiyya (Job 26:3) as falsafa. However, this usage

is neither statistically significant nor totally consistent.

Ibn Ezra notes (gloss to Eccelsiastes 7:9; see below) that one must read “many books” in

order to master psychology, but he does not name a single one of them; this observation

as well holds throughout his opus, where, to the best of my knowledge, not a single

textbook on psychology, metaphysics, or logic is ever mentioned by name. However,

formal study of scientific texts was only one means of access to the philosophy of the

day. By the late eleventh century Andalusian Jewry had drunk deeply from the fountain

of Greco-Arabic science, and Ibn Ezra could certainly have achieved some familiarity

with psychology and other fields without having undergone any formal course of study.

As we shall see, Ibn Ezra certainly read Ibn Sînâ's philosophical allegory, Hayy bin

Yaqzân. In general, it would seem that he was attracted to short, tantalizing and cryptic

expositions, rather than lengthy, discursive prose.

7. Ibn Ezra and Judah Halevi

The most interesting and truly philosophical chapters in his writings have nothing to do

with recycling and restyling doctrines of the soul, but rather with frank discussions

concerning fundamental questions of Jewish identity. In a lengthy gloss to the first of the

ten commandments (Exodus 20:1), Ibn Ezra records a conversation he held with his close

friend and fellow poet Judah Halevi. Why, Halevi wants to know, did God choose to

reveal himself on Mount Sinai as the God Who took the Jews out of Egypt? Why didn't

He instead reveal Himself as the God Who created heaven and earth, and created man as

well? Why did He identify Himself with an event important to Israel alone, rather than

with an event of universal significance? The implied criticism of the standard

philosophical viewpoint, to which Ibn Ezra adheres consistently throughout his oeuvre, is

transparent. If Creation is the most manifest and convincing indication for the existence

of the deity, as the philosophers aver; if God reveals Himself to us through His works—

why, then, does He choose to reveal Himself at Sinai as the God of history, the God of

the Exodus?

Ibn Ezra begins his reply with the observation that people differ in the nature of their

belief. Some believe in God because they have heard about Him or read about Him in the

Bible; but should that belief be challenged in any way, they are immediately stymied. By

contrast, those who have chosen the path of knowledge will work their way up from the

study of mineral and animal kingdoms to the structure and functions of the human body,

and thence to a study of the heavens. Thus will the scholar ascend from God's “ways” to

an understanding of the divine name. According to Ibn Ezra, the first two words of the

commandment (“I [am] YHWH”) hint at the knowledge of God that one obtains from

creation; it would thus be superfluous to add “Who made heaven and earth”.

Thus far Ibn Ezra has reiterated, and endorsed, the view of the philosophers. Now,

however, he parts ways with them; astrology plays a key role in this turn of thought. The

intellectuals who follow this path, observes Ibn Ezra, deny divine intervention in worldly

matters. Israel's astral destiny was such that she should not have been freed from bondage

at that particular time. God however can overrule the stars, and His doing so precisely at

that astrally inauspicious moment is compelling proof, not only for His existence, but for

the operation of the cosmos that He created.

God's self-introduction as the One Who took you out of Egypt connects to the truth of

God's existence, as evidenced by the cosmos. It adds, however, the important detail that

the Creator is also the Redeemer. In sum, God's self-revelation as “the one Who took you

out of Egypt” does not contradict the tenet that God reveals Himself through His works;

it rather adds to it an important point, either overlooked or denied by the philosophers.

Immediately afterwards, however, and quite characteristically, Ibn Ezra continues his

exposition in a somewhat different vein. He observes that the next word, “your God”,

conveys our obligation to worship; finally, the remainder of the sentence, “Who took you

out of Egypt”, simply hints at the miracles that are all the simple folk have to lean upon

in their belief.

We have extracted here the main points from one of the longest excursuses in Ibn Ezra's

biblical commentary. It does not require any great stretch of the imagination to suppose

that the dry and concise resumé that Ibn Ezra chose to include in his gloss summarizes

what must have been a lengthy debate, perhaps even a series of encounters, between the

two poets. In fact, in his commentary to Daniel 9:2, Ibn Ezra describes more fully an

exchange with Halevi over an issue of biblical chronology, recording several barbs and

retorts until, in the end, Halevi fell silent. Perhaps, then, Ibn Ezra chose to abridge the

conversation over the first commandment because that encounter did not exactly leave

Halevi speechless. Quite the contrary: Halevi expanded upon his theme of Jewish

particularism in his Kuzari, one of the most resonant works ever of Jewish thought.

Armchair philosophy this may be, but it concerns one of the most fundamental questions

of the Jewish experience. Is Judaism just one set of directives among many for achieving

one and the same spiritual objective, which is the goal of all humans? Are Jews one

people among many, or do they occupy a special place in the scale of existents? Better

analytic minds may have been tested in replying to these questions, but perhaps not two

more vibrant, passionate souls than these two Hebrew poets. The “philosopher” of

Halevi's Kuzari presents a point of view that coincides on major points with that of Ibn

Ezra, most notably in the universalism of his program for humanity, and the relativism of

his approach to ritual and praxis (Langermann 1993, 70–74). For his part, Halevi

demands a much more real and meaningful cleavage between Jews and the rest of the

nations.

8. Poetry and the Science of the Soul

For Ibn Ezra, the human soul is the only unchanging, eternal entity in the universe; it is

the only thing that can be said to be similar, in some sense, to God. For example, the

opening sentence in Sefer Tzahut (a grammatical treatise!) states: “Because the human

soul was created in the image of God, her actions are similar to his” (Levin 1985, 379).

At the end of Yesod Mora (Cohen 2002, 200–201) he cites the five points of resemblance

between the soul and God noted in the Talmud; and he implies that Shi‘ur Qoma

professes a similar doctrine. Ibn Ezra takes these similarities rather literally, as it seems.

Given this state of affairs, it is no surprise that “the science of the soul” is the branch of

philosophy concerning which Ibn Ezra has the most to say. Ibn Ezra evinces little interest

in the metaphysics of the theologians—that is, questions of divine attributes, substance

and accident, and so forth. Psychology was his metaphysics; it and it alone delved into

questions beyond the material world and approaching the godhead. It comes as no

surprise, then, that penetrating studies of Ibn Ezra's thought, such as Wolfson [1990] and

Tanenbaum [1990], dwell at length on the Ibn Ezra's conceptions of soul.

Ibn Ezra's attitude towards psychology emerges mainly from his poetry; it is not simply

copied from some sterile classification scheme. His poetry, more than anything, has

nourished his image as a neoplatonist in the scholarly literature. In fact, psychology was

one arena of sharp conflict between philosophers and mutakallimûn. If, as we have

suggested, Ibn Ezra was mainly influenced by Sa‘adiah and other gaonim—and thus also

by the kalam—many of his ideas about the soul derive from the traditions of Hebrew

poetry in Spain. Unlike the kalam, which has little interest in psychology, and is not

obsessed with release from this world, the Hebrew poets as a rule identify with the

classical neoplatonists in seeking salvation and release of the soul from its mundane

captivity.

Even Ibn Ezra's prose pronouncements concerning the soul's longing to return to her

source tend towards the lyrical (and in fact has some small but clear borrowings from a

long liturgy by Halevi). Consider this passage from the introduction to the commentary to

Ecclesiastes:

Just as the passerby, who has been taken prisoner, longs to return to his homeland and to

be with his family, so does the intellectizing spirit yearn to grab hold of the higher rungs,

until she ascends to the formations of the living God, which do not dwell in material

houses…This will transpire if the spirit whitens, sanctifying herself above the impurities

of disgusting bodily lusts which sully what is holy…then what is distant will be like what

is near, and night like day; then she will be configured to know the real truth, which will

be inscribed upon her in such a way so as not be erased when she departs the body, for

the script is the writing of God. She was brought here in order to be shown, and for that

reason she was imprisoned until the end of her term….(Levin 1985, 288)

This prose exposition is replete with imagery but devoid, like similar accounts in Ibn

Ezra's writings, of any thorough discussion of the soul's structure, origins, and path to

liberation, of the kind that one does find in the Islamic neoplatonic tradition, including

Jewish works such as pseudo-Bahya. It is really a reworking in rhymed prose—the

medium of Ibn Gabirol's liturgical masterpiece, Keter Malkhut—of the same themes that

inspire Ibn Ezra's poems. Nonetheless, Ibn Ezra undoubtedly impresses his readers with

the great pathos and obvious sincerity of his liturgies. His hymn, “Tzom’ah nafshi” (“My

soul thirsts”) is one of the most powerful expressions of longing for the divine in Hebrew

letters. Ibn Ezra experienced deeply and fully the soul's alienation in this world and her

longing for divine redemption, and his poetic expressions of these awesome feelings

served better as credentials for his expertise in matters of his soul than could any

academic diploma.

9. Excursus on the Soul in a Comment to Ecclesiastes

The best way to grasp all that has been said so far about Ibn Ezra's interests, influences,

and style, is to have look at a sample passage, where the peculiarities of his writing and

the difficulties of piecing together his “philosophy”, can be examined in situ, so to speak.

The lengthy excursus on the structure of the human soul in his commentary to

Ecclesiastes 7:9 offers such an opportunity. Ibn Ezra briefly notes the tri-partite division

of the soul into vegetable, animal, and rational. This, he tells us, is the scheme adopted by

“the scholars who [base their claims upon] proofs” (hakhmei ha-ra’ayot). One can

achieve a full understanding only after reading “many books”. There is no specific lexical

or grammatical problem that requires the exegete to go to any length here. However, an

inquiry into the soul is mandated because this verse is one of the places in Ecclesiastes

where King Solomon has, on the face of it, contradicted himself, and therefore the verse

requires explication. After citing at length some of the apparent contradictions, Ibn Ezra

proposes an alternative psychology to that of the “scholars”, employing a different

tripartite scheme and different terminology: nefesh (appetite and lust), ru’ah (sensation

and domineering), and neshamah (wisdom). He intimates that this switch is only for

convenience's sake, though the truth appears to be otherwise. Ibn Ezra notes in passing

that Sa‘adiah too employed this second classification.

10. Rationale for the Commandments: Yesod Mora

The most systematic formulation of Ibn Ezra's philosophical ideas is found in Yesod

Mora (The Foundation of Reverence) (Cohen 2002). Significantly, this is a monograph

on the rationale of the commandments, perhaps the key field (along with biblical

interpretation, with which it overlaps somewhat) for the development of a specifically

Judaic philosophy. Like his other writings, it is very short, contains not a few cryptic

passages whose meaning has never been satisfactorily fleshed out, and does not always

jive well with his pronouncements in other writings. There is good reason to believe that

Yesod Mora was written shortly before Ibn Ezra's death, and it thus may comprise his

final statement on the issues.

The beginning of Yesod Mora contains a valuable survey of the sciences. This is not a

formal classification of the type written by al-Fârâbî and many others, whose aim is to

put in their proper place all of the sciences. Instead, Ibn Ezra critically reviews the

various branches of learning which are favored by groups of Jewish scholars. There are

those whose “entire wisdom” consists in masora, the traditional inventory of letters and

phonetic markings in Scripture. Some are interested only in Hebrew grammar; others

study only the Bible, yet others are interested only in the Talmud. None of these groups

can achieve the wisdom they seek, however, without studying astronomy (hokhmat ha-

mazalot). Astronomy in turn requires a foundation in geometry (hokhmat ha-middot).

Also mandatory are psychology (hokhmat ha-nefesh), which in turn has a perquisite

physics, or perhaps more accurately, physiology (toledet ha-shamayim, literally “that

which is produced [or induced] by the heavens”; toledet refers generally to

transformations of matter, but, in Ibn Ezra's usage, it is almost always applied to

biological processes). Finally, logic (hokhmatha-mivta), “the balance of all wisdom” is

also indispensable.

Towards the end of this disquisition, theosophy of some sort (sod ha-merkaba, shi‘ur

qoma) is mentioned; Ibn Ezra seems to approve of it, if approached properly. At the very

end of the passage, Ibn Ezra tries to tie everything together into a coherent study plan:

“How can someone attempt to know something more sublime than he, if he knows

neither his soul nor his body? Only he who knows physics (or physiology?) and all of its

proofs and logic can know the universals that are preserved like a seal. Astronomy can be

known by means of clear proofs drawn from arithmetic (hokhmat ha-heshbon), geometry

(hokhmat ha-middot), and proportions (hokhmat ha-‘arakhim). Only then will he be able

to ascend high above, and to know the secret of the soul, the supernal angels, and the

world to come.” The plan calls for study of the body and soul, and astronomy as well,

with the aim of securing universals. One can then move beyond the stars to “the secret of

the soul” and the world or worlds beyond our own. The order in which the sciences are to

be studied is clear enough, the connection between them far less so.

Ibn Ezra never makes a clean break between traditional or religious sciences; quite the

contrary, he urges all along that the sciences that we would call secular are mandatory for

understanding scriptural, legal, and other issues of concern to Jews, not the least of

which, of course, is self-fulfillment. In the course of a long list of examples that

illustrating this need, astrology (mishpatei ha-mazalot) is mentioned only once. Clearly,

in this key text at least, Ibn Ezra does not accord to astrology the major standing it holds

in his legacy. Moreover, none of the disciplines named seems to stand for “philosophy”,

though psychology, some sort of natural philosophy, and theosophy are all mentioned

separately. (See: What is “Philosophy” for Ibn Ezra?) In any case, the separate listing of

psychology lends credence to our claim that Ibn Ezra's clear interest in the science of the

soul is independent of, and by no means indicative of, any strong interest in philosophy in

general.

The second chapter begins with an encomium to logic: “How noble is the science of

logic, and it commences with knowledge of the five words (millot).” Ibn Ezra seems to be

referring to the quinque voces; he names here “high universal”, “lower universal” or

“high species”, and “low species”. Understanding species and other such groups are of

great use in classifying commandments, as well as in resolving some apparent

contradictions between biblical texts. However, the logic applied is extremely basic, and

once again, we have no evidence that Ibn Ezra knew more than the basic terminology.

The discussion then moves on to commandments that are contingent, insofar as they

depend upon, or are limited to, a certain group (e.g. priests), an institution (e.g. temple

sacrifices), gender specific (e.g. circumcision). This sifting allows Ibn Ezra, in chapter

five, to get at those commandments that are absolute, “principles that do not depend upon

a given time, a given place, or anything else.” These commandments, “planted in the

heart”, were known by means of reason even before the giving of the Torah. Ibn Ezra

himself thus inserts, at the heart of this very Jewish, and legalistic, treatise, the rational,

humanistic outlook that marks his philosophy: the core demands of Judaism depend not

upon revelation but upon innate human reason, and they are no different from the rules

that must govern every human.

11. Philosophical Allegory: Hayy ben Meqitz

Ibn Ezra has left us one writing that undoubtedly fits into a very special medieval

philosophical tradition: a visionary recital, or initiatory tale, in rhymed Hebrew prose,

Hayy ben Meqitz (Levin 1985, 119–132). The great tenth century philosopher Ibn Sina

wrote a philosophical allegory Hayy bin Yaqzân, and the Andalusian Ibn Tufayl, as well

as the Persian expatriate Suhrawardi penned distinct versions, each tale suited to the

message that its author wished to convey. Ibn Ezra's Hebrew composition fits into this

special theme of philosophical allegory.

In Ibn Ezra's version, Hayy is the guide—an old man on whom time has not taken its toll.

The narrator, who has fled his home, meets Hayy, who enchants him with words of

wisdom, then invites him to immerse himself in the fountain of life and imbibe its waters.

Hayy then guides the narrator through eight “kingdoms,” that is, the stellar spheres,

describing their astrological associations in vivid imagery, then to the angelic realm. The

narrator asks if is there anything beyond, something that he cannot see? Hayy replies

positively; there is “the One, who has no second”, sublime and invisible. However, he

continues, if the narrator will follow in Hayy's path, he will yet be able to know and see

Him.

This philosophical tale further complicates the question of Ibn Ezra's doctrinal

allegiances. Issues such as the structure of the soul or the contours of union with the

divine, which are not treated systematically or uniformly elsewhere, cannot be fully

harmonized with Ibn Ezra's pronouncements elsewhere. Hayy is the only one of Ibn

Ezra's philosophical ventures that has no intrinsic connection to Judaism. Snippets of

biblical verses are skillfully woven into Hayy, making the poem amenable to the Jewish

reader and making it easier for the reader to answer the invitation—if one is indeed

extended—to join the excursion under Hayy's guidance. On the other hand, the ritual

immersion in the nude that the narrator performs, while not totally foreign to Judaism,

must have seemed to carry Christian overtones to some readers. It should be borne in

mind that Ibn Ezra wrote Hayy at the request of Samuel Ibn Jami, a learned and

philosophically inclined North African Jew, himself a poet. Is Hayy the response to a

literary challenge?

Greive [1973, 103–114] characterizes Hayy as “a religious-philosophical work, expressed

in a mystical fashion.” It is part of a tradition of Himmelsreisen that stretches back to

antiquity and is open to a number of interpretations. Three central moments can be

discerned: (1) The soul's imprisonment in the terrestrial world, which is foreign to her;

(2) the role of self-knowledge (i.e. coming to know one's true, other-worldly self) in the

process of liberation; (3) wisdom as the means to this liberation. Greive explores in

particular, the literary connections with Avicenna's recital, also called Hayy, as well as

Ibn Gabirol's liturgical masterpiece, Keter Malkhut.

More recently, Aaron Hughes [2004, 186] has strongly emphasized the neoplatonic

aesthetics at play in Hayy, asserting that aesthetics and poetry are “currency whereby the

imagination and philosophy are able to tease out and subsequently map the various

relationships between the physical and the metaphysical”.

Bibliography

Primary Sources

Cohen, J., with Simon, U. (eds.), 2002, R. Abraham Ibn Ezra. Yesod Mora ve-Sod

Torah, Ramat-Gan: Bar- Ilan University Press.

Levin, I., 1985, Abraham Ibn Ezra Reader: Annotated texts with Introductions

and Commentaries, New York and Tel Aviv: Israel Matz.

Sela, S., 2007, Abraham Ibn Ezra: The Book of Reasons. A Parallel Hebrew-

English Crirical Edition of the Two Versions of the Text, Leiden: Brill

–––, 2010, The Book of the world. A parallel hebrew-english critical edition of the

two versions of the text., Leiden: Brill

–––, 2011, Abraham Ibn Ezra on Elections, Interrogations, and Medical

Astrology: A Parallel Hebrew-English Critical Edition of the Book of Elections (3

Versions), the Book of Interrogations (3 Versions), and the Book of the

Luminaries., Leiden: Brill

–––, 2013, Abraham Ibn Ezra on Nativities and Continuous Horoscopy: A

Parallel Hebrew-English Critical Edition of the Book of Nativities and the Book

of Revolution., Leiden: Brill

Weinberger, L., 2010, Twilight of a Golden Age: Selected Poems of Abraham Ibn

Ezra, Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

Secondary Sources

Burnett, C., 1997, The Introduction of Arabic Learning into England, London:

The British Library.

Cohen, J., 1996, The Philosophy of R. Abraham Ibn Ezra, Rishon le-Zion: Shai

[Hebrew].

Fenton, P., 2001, “Abraham Ibn Ezra, a-t-il composé un commentaire sur le Livre

de la Création?” Revue des études juives, 111: 33–59.

Goldstein, B.R., 1996, “Astronomy and Astrology in the Works of Abraham ibn

Ezra,” Arabic Sciences and philosophy, 6: 9–21.

Greive, H., 1973, Studien zum jüdischen Neuplatnismus. Die Religionsphilosophie

des Abraham Ibn Ezra. Berlin-New York: De Gruyter.

Guttmann, J., 1973, Philosophies of Judaism, New York: Schoken.

Harris, J.M., 1993, “Ibn Ezra in Modern Jewish Perspective,” in Rabbi Abraham

ibn Ezra: Studies in the Writings of a Twelfth-Century Jewish Polymath, I.

Twersky and J.M. Harris (eds.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Hughes, A., 1999, “Two approaches to the love of God in medieval Jewish

thought: The concept of devequt in the works of Ibn Ezra and Judah Halevi,”

Studies in Religion/Sciences Religieuses, 28: 139-151.

–––, 2002, “The Three Worlds of ibn Ezra's Hay ben Meqitz,” The Journal of

Jewish Thought and Philosophy, 11: 1-24.

–––, 2004, The Texture of the Divine, Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

Husik, I., 1969, A History of Mediaeval Jewish Philosophy, New York:

Atheneum.

Kreisel, H.T., 1994, “On the term ‘kol’ in Abraham Ibn Ezra: a reappraisal,”

Revue des études juives, 153: 29–66.

Lancaster, I., 2002, Deconstructing the Bible: Abraham Ibn Ezra's Introduction to

the Torah, London: Routledge.

Langermann, Y.T., 1993, “Some Astrological Themes in the Thought of Abraham

ibn Ezra,” in Rabbi Abraham ibn Ezra: Studies in the Writings of a Twelfth-

Century Jewish Polymath, I. Twersky and J.M. Harris (eds.), Cambridge, U.S.A:

Harvard University Press.

–––, 1997, “Science and the Kuzari,” Science in Context, 10: 495–522

Levin, I., 1992, “‘Cling to the Ladder of Wisdom’ (The Influence of Neoplatonic

Psychology on the Poetry of Abraham Ibn Ezra),” in Te‘udah, vol. 8 (Studies in

the Work of Abraham Ibn Ezra), I. Levin (ed.), Tel Aviv: Tel Aviv University

Press, 1992 [Hebrew].

Sela, S., 2001, “Abraham ibn Ezra's Scientific Corpus—Basic Constituents and

General Characterization,” Arabic Sciences and philosophy 11:91–149.

–––, 2004, “Queries on Astrology sent from Southern France to Maimonides:

Critical edition of the Hebrew Text, Translation, and Commentary,” Aleph 4:89–

190.

Sela, S., and Freudenthal, G., 2006, “Abraham Ibn Ezra's Scholarly Writings: A

Chronological Listing,” Aleph, 6: 13–55.

Simon, U., 1993, “Interpreting the Interpreter: Supercommentaries on Ibn Ezra's

Commentaries,” in Rabbi Abraham ibn Ezra: Studies in the Writings of a Twelfth-

Century Jewish Polymath, I. Twersky and J.M. Harris (eds.), Cambridge, U.S.A:

Harvard University Press.

Sirat, C., 1985, A History of Jewish Philosophy in the Middle Ages, Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

Tanenbaum, A., 1990, “Beholding the Splendor of the Creator: Conceptions of

the Soul in the Poetry of Abraham Ibn Ezra,” in Abraham Ibn Ezra y su tiempo,

F.D. Esteban (ed.), Madrid: Asociación Espanola de Orientalistas.

Twersky, I., 1993, “Did R. Abraham Ibn Ezra Influence Maimonides?” in Rabbi

Abraham ibn Ezra: Studies in the Writings of a Twelfth-Century Jewish Polymath,

I. Twersky and J.M. Harris (eds.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press

[Hebrew].

Wolfson, E.R., 1990, “God, the Demiurge and the Intellect: on the usage of the

word ‘kol’ in Abraham Ibn Ezra,” Revue des études juives, 149: 77–111.

Academic Tools

How to cite this entry.

Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.

Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).

Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Related Entries

Arabic and Islamic Philosophy, historical and methodological topics in: Arabic and

Islamic Theological Philosophy (Kalam) | Arabic and Islamic Philosophy, historical and

methodological topics in: influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on Judaic thought |

Halevi, Judah | Ibn Gabirol, Solomon [Avicebron] | Maimonides | Neoplatonism | Saadya

[Saadiah]

Copyright © 2014 by

Tzvi Langermann <[email protected]>