A Brief Note About Rott Contraction

8
A Brief Note About Rott Contraction EDUARDO L. FERM ´ E and RICARDO O. RODRIGUEZ, Departamento de Computaci´ on, Universidad de Buenos Aires, Pabell´on I Ciudad Universitaria (1428), Buenos Aires, Argentina. E-mail: {ferme,ricardo}@dc.uba.ar Abstract One of the ways to model contraction functions for belief sets is epistemic entrenchment. The first step was provided by G¨ardenforsin [5], who defined epistemic entrenchment and a contraction function in terms of it and related the latter with the AGM contraction function. Later Hans Rott in [16] presented an entrenchment based contraction function that does not satisfy recovery. In this paper we provide an axiomatic characterization of Rott Contraction. 1 Keywords : AGM, belief contraction, recovery postulate, Rott contraction. 1 Introduction “Even if all sentences in a knowledge set are accepted or considered as facts, this does not means that all sentences are of equal value for planning or problem solving purposes. Certain pieces of knowledge and belief about the world are more important than others when planning future actions, conducting scientific investigations or reasoning in general. We will say that some sentences in a knowledge system have a higher degree of epistemic entrenchment than others. The degree of entrenchment will, intuitively, have a bearing on what is abandoned from a knowledge set and what is retained, when a contraction or revision is carried out.” [6] This is the key idea of epistemic entrenchment introduced by G¨ ardenfors in [5]. Using epistemic entrenchment, G¨ardenfors defines an operation of contraction that satisfies the entire set of AGM contraction postulates [5, 6]. However, epistemic entrenchment also allows us to define entrenchment based con- traction functions that do not satisfy all the AGM postulates. One of the more important such functions in the literature was proposed by Hans Rott in [16] and has been called Rott contraction. This contraction differs from the G¨ ardenfors con- traction in not satisfying the controversial postulate of recovery. For discussions of recovery see [3, 12, 9, 10, 11, 7, 15, 14, 13]. In [11] Lindstr¨ om and Rabinowicz suggest that any realistic entrenchment-based contraction operator should lie between those of Rott and G¨ ardenfors. 1 Full version of a contributed paper presented at the 4th Workshop on Logic, Language, Information and Compu- tation (WoLLIC’97 ), http://www.di.ufpe.br/ wollic97, held in Fortaleza (Cear´a), Brazil, August 19–22 1997, with scientific sponsorship by IGPL, FoLLI and ASL, and organised by Univ. Federal do Cear´ a (UFC) and Univ. Federal de Pernambuco (UFPE). 835 L. J. of the IGPL, Vol. 6 No. 6, pp. 835–842 1998 c Oxford University Press

Transcript of A Brief Note About Rott Contraction

A Brief Note About Rott

Contraction

EDUARDO L. FERME and RICARDO O. RODRIGUEZ,Departamento de Computacion, Universidad de Buenos Aires, PabellonI Ciudad Universitaria (1428), Buenos Aires, Argentina.E-mail: {ferme,ricardo}@dc.uba.ar

Abstract

One of the ways to model contraction functions for belief sets is epistemic entrenchment. Thefirst step was provided by Gardenfors in [5], who defined epistemic entrenchment and a contraction

function in terms of it and related the latter with the AGM contraction function. Later Hans Rottin [16] presented an entrenchment based contraction function that does not satisfy recovery. In this

paper we provide an axiomatic characterization of Rott Contraction.1

Keywords : AGM, belief contraction, recovery postulate, Rott contraction.

1 Introduction

“Even if all sentences in a knowledge set are accepted or considered as facts, thisdoes not means that all sentences are of equal value for planning or problem solvingpurposes. Certain pieces of knowledge and belief about the world are more importantthan others when planning future actions, conducting scientific investigations orreasoning in general. We will say that some sentences in a knowledge system havea higher degree of epistemic entrenchment than others. The degree of entrenchmentwill, intuitively, have a bearing on what is abandoned from a knowledge set and whatis retained, when a contraction or revision is carried out.” [6]

This is the key idea of epistemic entrenchment introduced by Gardenfors in [5].Using epistemic entrenchment, Gardenfors defines an operation of contraction thatsatisfies the entire set of AGM contraction postulates [5, 6].However, epistemic entrenchment also allows us to define entrenchment based con-traction functions that do not satisfy all the AGM postulates. One of the moreimportant such functions in the literature was proposed by Hans Rott in [16] andhas been called Rott contraction. This contraction differs from the Gardenfors con-traction in not satisfying the controversial postulate of recovery. For discussions ofrecovery see [3, 12, 9, 10, 11, 7, 15, 14, 13]. In [11] Lindstrom and Rabinowicz suggestthat any realistic entrenchment-based contraction operator should lie between thoseof Rott and Gardenfors.

1Full version of a contributed paper presented at the 4th Workshop on Logic, Language, Information and Compu-

tation (WoLLIC’97), http://www.di.ufpe.br/∼ wollic97, held in Fortaleza (Ceara), Brazil, August 19–22 1997, with

scientific sponsorship by IGPL, FoLLI and ASL, and organised by Univ. Federal do Ceara (UFC) and Univ. Federal

de Pernambuco (UFPE).

835L. J. of the IGPL, Vol. 6 No. 6, pp. 835–842 1998 c© Oxford University Press

836 A Brief Note About Rott Contraction

We give here an axiomatic characterization for Rott’s entrenchment-based contractionoperator, i.e. a characterization of the lower limit of what Lindstrom and Rabinowiczregard as reasonable contraction.

In Section 2 we recall AGM contraction functions, introduce epistemic entrench-ment, relate it to AGM contraction, and also present Rott contraction. In Section 3we provide the promised axiomatic characterization of Rott contraction. Proofs arein the appendix.

After this work was finished we were informed that another axiomatic character-ization has been independently obtained by Hans Rott and Maurice Pagnucco andwill be published in a joint paper by these authors [17].

2 Background

2.1 AGM contraction

The logic of theory change was introduced into philosophical logic and artificialintelligence a little over a decade ago. The initial step was provided by Alchourron,Gardenfors and Makinson in [1] (commonly called the AGM model). Basically, in theAGM model the beliefs of a rational agent are represented by a belief set K, closedunder logical consequence Cn, where Cn satisfies the Tarski conditions K ⊆ Cn(K)for any set K of propositions, Cn(Cn(K)) ⊆ Cn(K) and Cn(K) ⊆ Cn(H) if K ⊆ H. We assume that Cn includes classical logical consequence, satisfies the rule ofintroduction of disjunction into premises and is compact. We write ` x for x ∈ Cn(∅).

A theory is understood to be any set K of proposition closed under Cn, i.e. suchthat Cn(K) = K.

Let L be the set of all the sentences of the language. Let K the set of all theoriesof the language. The expansion function + from K×L to K is defined by (K + x) =Cn(K ∪ {x}). The postulates for the AGM contraction are:

(K − 1) K− x is a theory whenever K is a theory (closure)(K − 2) K− x ⊆ K (inclusion)(K − 3) If x 6∈ K, then K − x = K (vacuity)(K − 4) If x 6∈ Cn(∅) , then x 6∈ K − x (success)(K − 5) If x ↔ y ∈ Cn(∅) then K − x = K − y (extensionality)(K − 6) K ⊆ (K − x) + x whenever K is a theory (recovery)(K − 7) K− x ∩ K− y ⊆ K − (x ∧ y) (conjunctive overlap)(K − 8) If x 6∈ K− (x∧ y), then K− (x∧ y) ⊆ K−x (conjunctive inclusion).

2.2 Epistemic entrenchment

The idea of entrenchment for theories was introduced by Gardenfors in [5] torepresent formally a preference ordering between formulae in a theory. He attemptedto define the contraction of a theory by a sentence in terms of an order of thesentences, and identify the properties that the order must satisfy for the generated

2. BACKGROUND 837

contraction to satisfy the AGM postulates.

Gardenfors proposed the following set of axioms for the order among sentences:

(EE1) If x ≤K y and y ≤K z, then x ≤K z (transitivity)(EE2) If x ` y, then x ≤K y (dominance)(EE3) x ≤K (x ∧ y) or y ≤K (x ∧ y) (conjunctiveness)(EE4) If K 6= K⊥, then x 6∈ K if and only if x ≤K y for all y (minimality)(EE5) If y ≤K x for all y, then ` x (maximality)

A relation satisfying (EE1) − (EE5) is a standard entrenchment ordering. Fur-thermore, he showed that entrenchment orderings can be connected with contractionfunctions by the following equivalences 2:

(C ≤) x ≤K y if and only if x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y) or ` (x ∧ y).

Gardenfors’ entrenchment-based contraction(−G) y ∈ K−x if and only if y ∈ K and, either ` x or x <K (x ∨ y).

Observation 2.1 ([5, 6]) Let ≤K be a standard entrenchment ordering on a consis-tent belief set K. Furthermore let −G be the Gardenfors entrenchment-based contrac-tion on K defined by condition (−G) from ≤K. Then −G satisfies the eight AGMpostulates, and (C ≤) also holds.

Observation 2.2 ([5, 6]) Let − be an operation on a consistent belief set K thatsatisfies the eight AGM postulates. Furthermore let ≤K be the relation defined from− by condition (C ≤). Then ≤K satisfies the standard entrenchment postulates and(−G) also holds.

Hans Rott [16] has remarked that the comparison x <K (x ∨ y) is not intuitive,and proposed the following alternative definition of a contraction operation from anentrenchment ordering:

Rott’s entrenchment-based contraction(−R) y ∈ K−x if and only if y ∈ K and, either ` x or x <K y.

Rott also provided the following result:

Observation 2.3 Let ≤K be a standard entrenchment ordering on a consistent beliefset K. Furthermore let −R be the Rott entrenchment-based contraction on K defined bycondition (−R) from ≤K. Then −R satisfies all the AGM postulates except recovery.

Rott [16, p. 169] proved that for all x, K−Rx ⊆ K−Gx. Lindstrom and Rabinowicz[11] have proposed that a reasonable entrenchment based contraction operation −should lie between Rott’s operation and Gardenfors’ operation, in the sense thatK −R x ⊆ K− x ⊆ K −G x.

2We write x <K y to denote x ≤K y and y 6≤K x.

838 A Brief Note About Rott Contraction

3 An axiomatic characterization of Rott contraction

In section 2.2 we recalled that Hans Rott proved that his contraction satisfies all theAGM postulates except recovery. In this section we provide it with an axiomaticcharacterization. We make use of the following postulates:

If K− (x ∧ y) ⊆ K − y then y 6∈ K−x or ` x or ` y (Converse ConjunctiveInclusion).

If x ∈ Cn(∅) then K−x = K (Failure) [4].

If x 6∈ K−y then K−y ⊆ K−x (Strong Inclusion)

Now we can characterize Rott Contraction in terms of postulates:

Theorem 3.1

1. Let ≤K be a standard entrenchment ordering on a consistent belief set K. Further-more, let −R be Rott’s entrenchment-based contraction on K, defined from ≤K

by condition (−R). Then −R satisfies closure, inclusion, success, extensionality,conjunctive overlap, failure, strong inclusion and converse conjunctive inclusion,and (C ≤) also holds.

2. Let − be an operation on a consistent belief set K that satisfies closure, inclusion,success, extensionality, conjunctive overlap, failure, strong inclusion and converseconjunctive inclusion. Furthermore let ≤K be the relation that is defined from −by (C ≤). Then ≤K satisfies the standard entrenchment postulates, and (−R) alsoholds.

Other interesting postulates are:

If 6` x and 6` y, then either x 6∈ K−y or y 6∈ K−x (Expulsiveness)[8].

K−(x ∧ y) = K−x or K−(x ∧ y) = K−y (Linear Hierarchical Ordering)

K−y ⊆ K−x or K−x ⊆ K−y (Linearity)

The following relations hold:

Observation 3.2 Let K be a belief set and − an operator from K× L to K. Then:

1. If − satisfies strong inclusion then it satisfies conjunctive inclusion.

2. If − satisfies inclusion, failure and strong inclusion then it satisfies vacuity.

3. If − satisfies closure, success and strong inclusion then it satisfies expulsiveness.

3. AN AXIOMATIC CHARACTERIZATION OF ROTT CONTRACTION 839

4. If − satisfies inclusion, failure, strong inclusion and expulsiveness then it satisfieslinearity.

5. If − satisfies closure, success, extensionality and strong inclusion then it satisfieslinear hierarchical ordering.

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Sven Ove Hansson and David Makinson for valuable commentson an the earlier version of this paper. We are also indebted to the anonymous refereesfor corrections, suggestions and incisive remarks on a draft.

Appendix: Proofs

Proof of Theorem 3.1Part 1: Closure, inclusion, success, extensionality and conjunctive overlap followfrom observation 2.3.

Converse conjunctive inclusion: Let K−(x ∧ y) ⊆ K−y. We have two cases: 1.y ∈ K−y: It follows from success that ` y. 2. y 6∈ K−y: then y 6∈ K−(x ∧ y). Itfollows from (−R) that y 6∈ K or (y ≤K x ∧ y and 6` x ∧ y). We have two subcases2.1. y 6∈ K: then by inclusion (see observation 2.3) y 6∈ K−x. 2.2. y ∈ K: theny ≤K x ∧ y. By (EE2) x ∧ y ≤K x and by (EE1) y ≤K x hence by (−R) y 6∈ K−xor ` x .

Failure: It follows trivially, since if ` x, then by (−R) y ∈ K−x if and onlyif y ∈ K.

Strong inclusion: Let x 6∈ K−y. By (−R) x 6∈ K or (6` y and x ≤K y).We have two subcases: 1. x 6∈ K: then K−x = K (since by observation 2.3, −satisfies vacuity); then K−y ⊆ K−x (since by observation 2.3, − satisfies inclusion).2. x ∈ K: then (6` y and x ≤K y) Let z ∈ K−y, then (by (−R)) z ∈ K and y <K z.By (EE1) x <K z then by (−R) z ∈ K−x hence K−y ⊆ K−x.

(C ≤)3: For one direction let x ≤K y and x ∈ K−(x ∧ y). We need to prove` x ∧ y. By (−R) we have: x ∈ K−(x ∧ y) if and only if x ∈ K and either ` x ∧ yor x ∧ y <K x. Therefore: ` x ∧ y or x ∧ y <K x. Let x ∧ y <K x: then, by (EE3),y ≤K x ∧ y; and since x ≤K y, we have by (EE1) that x ≤K (x∧ y), contradiction,hence ` x ∧ y.For the second direction we have two subcases: 1. x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y): Then by (−R),x 6∈ K or 6` x and x ≤K x ∧ y. If x 6∈ K, x ≤K y follows (by (EE4)). If x ≤K x ∧ y,by (EE1), (since by (EE2) x ∧ y ≤K y), x ≤K y. 2. ` x ∧ y, then ` y, hence by(EE2), x ≤K y. This completes the proof.

3The idea for this proof was provided by an anonymous referee.

840 A Brief Note About Rott Contraction

Part 2: (EE2) − (EE5) are proved by Gardenfors and Makinson from closure,inclusion, success, extensionality, failure and (C ≤) in [6], pp. 93-94.

• (EE1)

We demonstrate by reductio ad absurdum. Let x ≤K y, y ≤K z and x 6≤K z.It follows by (C ≤) that: (a) either ` x ∧ y or x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y); (b) either ` y ∧ z ory 6∈ K−(y ∧ z); and (c) 6` x∧ z and x ∈ K−(x ∧ z).1. Let ` x ∧ y: then ` x and ` y. By closure y ∈ K−(y ∧ z), then by condition (b)` y ∧ z, so ` z, and ` x ∧ z; contradiction.2. Let ` y ∧ z: then ` y and ` z. By closure z ∈ K−(x ∧ z), then by condition (c)and closure x ∧ z ∈ K−(x ∧ z); hence by success ` x ∧ z; contradiction.By 1. and 2. (a), (b) and (c) are reduced to x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y), y 6∈ K−(y ∧ z), 6` x ∧ zand x ∈ K−(x ∧ z).3. By strong inclusion K−(x ∧ y) ⊆ K−x, then by converse conjunctive inclusionwe have ` x or ` y or x 6∈ K−y. But since x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y) and y 6∈ K−(y ∧ z), byclosure 6` x and 6` y. Then x 6∈ K−y and by strong inclusion we have K−y ⊆ K−x.4. y 6∈ K−(y ∧ z) implies by strong inclusion that K−(y ∧ z) ⊆ K−y, then byconverse conjunctive inclusion we have ` y or ` z or y 6∈ K−z; by closure 6` y and6` z (since by success, closure and condition (C), z 6∈ K−(x ∧ z)). Then y 6∈ K−zand by strong inclusion we have K−z ⊆ K−y.5. It follows from success that z 6∈ K−z, so by closure (x ∧ z) 6∈ K−z; andsince z 6∈ K−(x ∧ z) we obtain by strong inclusion that K−z = K−(x ∧ z). Sox ∈ K−(x ∧ z) = K−z ⊆ K−y ⊆ K−x. Hence by success ` x; contradiction.

• −R

⇒)

Let y ∈ K−x and 6` x. It follows by inclusion that y ∈ K. We have twocases: 1. ` y: By closure y ∈ K−(x ∧ y), then by (C ≤), y 6≤K x. By success andclosure x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y); then, by (C ≤), x ≤K y. Hence x <K y.2. 6` y: By converse conjunctive inclusion K−(x ∧ y) 6⊆ K−y, then by strong inclu-sion y ∈ K−(x ∧ y); then by (C ≤), y 6≤K x. By success and closure x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y);then, by (C ≤), x ≤K y. Hence x <K y.

⇐)

1. Let y ∈ K and ` x. By failure K−x = K then y ∈ K−x.2. Let y ∈ K and x <K y. By (C ≤) x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y), then by strong inclusionK−(x ∧ y). For reductio ad absurdum let y 6∈ K−x; then y 6∈ K−(x ∧ y) then by(C ≤), y ≤K x. Contradiction.

3. AN AXIOMATIC CHARACTERIZATION OF ROTT CONTRACTION 841

Proof of Observation 3.2

1. If − satisfies strong inclusion then it satisfies conjunctive inclusion:Let x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y). Then by strong inclusion K−(x ∧ y) ⊆ K−x.

2. If − satisfies inclusion, failure and strong inclusion then it satisfies vacuity:Let x 6∈ K and ` y. Then by failure x 6∈ K−y = K; by strong inclusionK = K−y ⊆ K−x. Hence by inclusion K−x = K.

3. If − satisfies closure, success and strong inclusion then it satisfies expulsiveness:Let 6` x and 6` y. By closure and success x ∧ y 6∈ K−x and x ∧ y 6∈ K−y, then bystrong inclusion K−x ⊆ K−(x ∧ y) and K−y ⊆ K−(x ∧ y). Let y ∈ K−x, theny ∈ K−(x ∧ y), then by success x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y); hence x 6∈ K−y.

4. If − satisfies inclusion, failure, strong inclusion and expulsiveness then it satisfieslinearity:If ` x then by failure K−x = K, and by inclusion K−y ⊆ K−x. By the samereasoning if ` y then K−x ⊆ K−y. Let 6` x and 6` y, then by expulsivenessy 6∈ K−x or x 6∈ K−y. Hence by strong inclusion K−x ⊆ K−y or K−y ⊆ K−x.

5. If − satisfies closure, success, extensionality and strong inclusion then it satisfieslinear hierarchical ordering:If ` x or ` y then ` (x ∧ y) ↔ x or ` (x ∧ y ↔ y), then by extensionalityK−(x ∧ y) = K−x or K−(x ∧ y) = K−y. Let 6` x and 6` y. By closure and successx ∧ y 6∈ K−x and x ∧ y 6∈ K−y, then by strong inclusion K−x ⊆ K−(x ∧ y) andK−y ⊆ K−(x ∧ y). By success x 6∈ K−(x ∧ y) or y 6∈ K−(x ∧ y). Then by stronginclusion K−x ⊆ K−(x ∧ y) or K−y ⊆ K−(x ∧ y) Hence K−(x ∧ y) = K−x orK−(x ∧ y) = K−y.

References

[1] Carlos Alchourron, Peter Gardenfors, and David Makinson. On the logic of theory change:

Partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50:510–530, 1985.

[2] Carlos Alchourron and David Makinson. On the logic of theory change: Contraction functions

and their associated revision functions. Theoria, 48:14–37, 1982.

[3] Eduardo Ferme. Five faces of recovery. (manuscript), 1998.

[4] Andre Fuhrmann and Sven Ove Hansson. A survey of multiple contraction. Journal of Logic,

Language and Information, 3:39–76, 1994.

[5] Peter Gardenfors. Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States. MIT Press,Cambridge, 1988.

[6] Peter Gardenfors and David Makinson. Revisions of knowledge systems using epistemic en-trenchment. In Moshe Y. Vardi, editor, Proceedings of the Second Conference on Theoretical

Aspects of Reasoning About Knowledge, pages 83–95, Monterey, California, March 1988. MorganKaufmann.

[7] Sven Ove Hansson. Belief contraction without recovery. Studia Logica, 50:251–260, 1991.

[8] Sven Ove Hansson. A Textbook of Belief Dynamics. Kluwer Academic Publisher, Dordrecht, InPress.

[9] Isaac Levi. The fixation of belief and its undoing: changing beliefs through inquiry. Cambridge

University Press, Cambridge, 1991.

842 A Brief Note About Rott Contraction

[10] Isaac Levi. Contraction and informational value. (manuscript, fifth version), August 1997.

[11] Sten Lindstrom and Wlodzimierz Rabinowicz. Epistemic entrenchment with incomparabilitiesand relational belief revision. In Fuhrmann and Morreau, editors, The Logic of Theory Change,

pages 93–126, Berlin, 1991. Springer-Verlag.

[12] David Makinson. On the status of the postulate of recovery in the logic of theory change. TheJournal of Philosophical Logic, 16:383–394, 1987.

[13] David Makinson. On the force of some apparent counterexamples to recovery. InE. Garzon Valdez et all, editor, Normative Systems in Legal and Moral Theory: Festschrift

for Carlos Alchourron and Eugenio Bulygin, pages 475–481, Berlin, 1997. Duncker & Humblot.

[14] Abhaya Nayak. Foundational belief change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23:495–533, 1994.

[15] Reinhard Niederee. Multiple contraction. a further case against Gardenfors’ principle of recovery.

In Fuhrmann and Morreau, editors, The Logic of Theory Change, pages 322–334, Berlin, 1991.Springer-Verlag.

[16] Hans Rott. Two methods of constructing contractions and revisions of knowledge systems.Journal of Philosophical Logic, 20:149–173, 1991.

[17] Hans Rott and Maurice Pagnucco. Severe withdrawal (and recovery). (manuscript), 1997.

Received 4 October 1997. Revised 6 May 1998