The Rights and Responsibilities of Biotech Patent Owners

38
U.B.C. LAW REVIEW Volume 40 · Number 1 · May 2007 Published by the U.B.C. Law Review Society University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada Website: www.ubclawreview.org · E-mail: [email protected]

Transcript of The Rights and Responsibilities of Biotech Patent Owners

U.B.C. LAW REVIEW

Volume 40 · Number 1 · May 2007 Published by the U.B.C. Law Review Society

University of British Columbia, Vancouver, Canada Website: www.ubclawreview.org · E-mail: [email protected]

©2007 U.B.C. Law Review Society. All rights reserved. Permission to use excerpts from any issue of the U.B.C. Law Review must be obtained in advance from the U.B.C. Law Review Society.

The U.B.C. Law Review is a peer-refereed journal published biannually by students in the Faculty of Law at the University of British Columbia. The opinions expressed in the contributions that appear are those of the individual authors and are not to be taken as representative of the views of the Editors, the Faculty of Law, or U.B.C. The U.B.C. Law Review is in the Index to Canadian Legal Literature, as of Volume 19 (1985) (cited as U.B.C. L. Rev.).

SUBSCRIPTIONS—Each volume of the U.B.C. Law Review consists of two issues. Periodically, there are additional special issues, which are received by subscribers at no extra cost. The annual subscription price is $40 in Canada, $45 elsewhere, and $25 for students (postage paid). These prices are subject to GST and may change without notice. PLEASE NOTE: U.B.C. Law Review subscriptions are automatically renewed annually. Notice of termination is required to cancel a subscription.

PROFESSIONAL NOTICES AND ADVERTISING—Notices of any size may be placed in the U.B.C. Law Review. The current rates per issue are: $175/quarter page; $275/half page; $450/full page; $550/inside cover; and $650 for the outside back cover. These prices are subject to change. Please visit our website (www.ubclawreview.org) for the most current information.

PATRONS—Donations are important in defraying costs and are greatly appreciated. Patrons’ contributions also support the annual law scholarship offered in their name, and entitle the donor to a complimentary subscription to the U.B.C. Law Review.

GRANT—The U.B.C. Law Review holds a four-year publication grant awarded by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

TABLE OF STATUTORY LIMITATIONS—The U.B.C. Law Review Society also publishes the Table of Statutory Limitations (TSL) for British Columbia. This looseleaf publication contains the verbat-im limitation provisions of all statutes for the commencement of actions and appeals, applications for judicial review, and numerous other notices required by statute. The 31st edition of the TSL (updated to 1 July 2006) is available at a cost of $60 (postage paid). Updates are automatically sent to existing subscribers. Prices are subject to GST and may change without notice.

COMMUNICATIONS—Please forward business and editorial communications to the Editor-in-Chief, U.B.C. Law Review Society, 1822 East Mall, Room 175, Vancouver, B.C., Canada, V6T 1Z1. Telephone: (604) 822-3066. Fax: (604) 822-4633. E-mail: [email protected]. Website: www.ubclawreview.org.

SUBMISSIONS—Articles should not exceed 15,000 words or approximately 60 pages, double- spaced. Case Comments should be between 4,500 and 10,000 words. Book Reviews should not exceed 3,500 words. Recent Legislation or Law Reform Comments should be between 4,500 and 8,500 words. An electronic copy in MS Word must accompany each submission and should include a 100-250 word abstract. References must conform to the Canadian Guide to Uniform Legal Citation (6th Edition) (the “McGill Guide”); references must be made using footnotes (in-text citations are not acceptable). The Canadian Oxford Dictionary is used as a reference for spelling and the New York Public Library Writer’s Guide to Style and Usage is used as a grammatical and stylistic reference. Manuscripts will not be returned. The Editors reserve the right to make such editorial changes in manuscripts as are necessary to ensure correctness of grammar, clarification of obscurities, conformity to style, and to the Canadian spelling of words. Please note that the U.B.C. Law Review does not accept simultaneous submissions.

BACK ISSUES—Copies of back issues can be obtained from: William S. Hein & Co., Inc., 1285 Main Street, Buffalo, NY 14029, U.S.A. Back issues are also available in electronic format on the company’s website (www.heinonline.org).

ISSN 0068-1849

PRINTED IN CANADA BY MORRISS PRINTING COMPANY LTD., VICTORIA, B.C.

PATRONS

The U.B.C. Law Review Society wishes to extend its sincere thanks to the following patrons for their generous support

BLAKE, CASSELS & GRAYDON LLP

DAVIS & COMPANY LLP

FASKEN MARTINEAU DUMOULIN LLP

LAWSON LUNDELL LLP

MCCARTHY TÉTRAULT LLP

MILLER THOMSON LLP

STIKEMAN ELLIOTT LLP

HARPER GREY LLP

Winner of the Patrons of the U.B.C. Law Review Scholarship 2006: JENNIFER WOODRUFF

AWARD

The U.B.C. Law Review Society gratefully acknowledges the generous financial assistance of the Social Science and Humanities

Research Council of Canada

U.B.C. LAW REVIEW

Volume 40 · Number 1 · May 2007

BOARD OF DIRECTORS EDITOR-IN-CHIEF: Jennifer Woodruff

ARTICLES EDITORS: Laura Duke, Veronica Tang CASE COMMENTS & BOOK REVIEWS EDITOR: Jeffrey Morton RECENT LEGISLATION & LAW REFORM COMMENTS EDITOR: Carolyn MacDonald PRODUCTION EDITOR: Tom Horacek REFEREE COORDINATOR: Tracey Stott TSL EDITOR: Owen Elliot BUSINESS MANAGER: Nafeesa Kara SECRETARY-TREASURER: Hilary Thomson SPECIAL PROJECT COORDINATORS: Annie Chen, Grant Foster

MEMBERS

ASSISTANT EDITORS: Greta Airhart, Claire Bennett, Mitch Dermer, Ian Graf, William Haworth, Laura Hodgins, Shane Hopkins-Utter, Krista Johanson, Eileen Keast, Graham Kosakowski, Jeff Langlois, Emilie LeDuc, Matthew Levine, J. Jeffrey Locke, Greg McMullen, Sarah Ng, Candice Peskett, Anthony Purgas, Anthony Seepish, Darren Stewart, Jennifer Winstanley, Jeff Yuen

ASSISTANT TSL EDITORS: Jeff Babcock, Nicole Choolun, Tamar Meshel, Kerri-Ann Reid

ASSISTANT BUSINESS Sungkeun Kim, Allyson Marta, MANAGERS: Douglas McLeod, Robert

Penkala, Belinda Schubert,

Victor Tsao, Matthew Voell, Michael Yun

ASSISTANT SPECIAL PROJECT Eiad El Fateh, Eric Heath, COORDINATORS: Margaret Mackie, Kevin

McKee, Troy McLelan, Marega Medlicott, Jacky Sin

FACULTY ADVISORS Dean Mary Anne Bobinski Professor Elizabeth Edinger Professor Bruce MacDougall Professor Donn Short

CONTENTS VOLUME 40, NUMBER 1, 2007

ARTICLES

Accommodating Ethnic and Cultural Factors in Damages for Personal Injury Jeff Berryman 1 Protecting the Social Value of Privacy in the Context of State Investigations Using New Technologies Arthur J. Cockfield 41 Resisting “Sweat” and Refusing Feist: Rethinking Originality after CCH Carys J. Craig 69 The Arctic Council at 10 Years: Retrospect and Prospects Timo Koivurova & David L. VanderZwaag 121 Judicial Selection: Trust and Reform Ron Levy 195 SPEECH Sustainability, Globalization, and the Rule of Law: Keynote Address at the 2006 Canadian Institute for the Administration of Justice Annual Conference Introduction by The Honourable Bruce I. Cohen The Honourable John A. Fraser 251

CASE COMMENTS The Protection of Famous Marks in Canada: Mattel and Veuve Clicquot Daniel R. Bereskin, Q.C. 277

Tsunami in a Teapot: Leskun v. Leskun John-Paul Boyd 293 The Constructive Taking at the Supreme Court of Canada: Once More, Without Feeling Russell Brown 315 LAW REFORM COMMENTS The Rights and Responsibilities of Biotech Patent Owners Jeremy de Beer 343 Canadian Taxation of International Mobile Workers: A Case for Reform Jinyan Li 375 RECENT LEGISLATION COMMENTS Recent British Columbia Legislation: The Community Charter Donald Lidstone 401 Totems and Teapots: The Royal British Columbia Museum Corporation Robert K. Paterson 421 BOOK REVIEW The Companies We Keep: Corporate Governance for a Democratic Society, by Allan C. Hutchinson Micah B. Rankin 439

LAW REFORM COMMENTS

THE RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES OF BIOTECH PATENT OWNERS

JEREMY DE BEER†

I.

INTRODUCTION

One thing about biotechnological innovations that sets them apart from traditional objects is that they can, and do, copy themselves. Transgenic organisms—plants and animals that have had their genes molecularly engineered with recombinant DNA technology—are impulsively self-propagating. This fact has created some legal challenges.

Property law, specifically intellectual property (IP) law, has had to face questions such as: What rights does a patentee have concerning the second, third and subsequent generations of progeny of transgenic organisms containing a patented biotechnological invention? Among the questions faced in tort law is the inverse: What are the responsibilities of a patentee when such things cause harm to persons, property or economic interests? Both questions are reflective of the social, legal, ethical

† Assistant Professor, University of Ottawa, Faculty of Law. Thanks to the

Law Foundation of Ontario and the University of Ottawa, Faculty of Law (Common Law Section) for funding this research, to Matthew Rimmer, Karthik Ashwin Thiagarajan, Katharine Garforth, Keith Ferguson, Jennifer Chandler, Heather McLeod-Kilmurry, Martin Phillipson, participants at various conferences/seminars where this work was presented, and several anonymous peers for their comments, and to Mark Magro, Saleh Al Sharieh, Patrick Cleyn, Katrina Marciniak, Alison Minard, Livia Aumand, Tim Jolly, Mary Mitsios, Jeff Murray, Mary Auxi Guiao, Natasha Palaccio, David Lam, Annette Uetrecht, and Adrienne Moir for their research assistance on this and closely related projects.

344 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

and commercial controversies that permeate the topic of biotechnology.

These questions were considered, separately, in two recent Canadian cases about agricultural biotechnology. In Monsanto v. Schmeiser,1 Monsanto argued successfully that ownership of a patent for a molecularly engineered plant gene and transgenic plant seed entitled it to full control over stray plants and progeny containing the gene, even though a plant itself is not patentable subject matter under Canadian law. In Hoffman v. Monsanto,2 a group of organic farmers argued unsuccessfully that patent ownership also entails responsibility for damages to organic crops and crop markets caused by straying genetically modified organisms. In short, Canadian courts have held that a patent entitles its owner to all of the rights but none of the responsibilities of ownership.

These two cases demonstrate why biotechnology issues must be studied as part of a bigger picture. Looking at them through the lens of patent law or tort law in isolation is inadequate, yet little work has been done on the link between IP rights and tort liabilities in the field of biotechnology.3 Only a handful of scholars have juxtaposed these issues.4 No judge has yet

1 Monsanto Canada Inc. v. Schmeiser, 2004 SCC 34, [2004] 1 S.C.R. 902,

239 D.L.R. (4th) 271 [Schmeiser (SCC) cited to S.C.R.] aff’g (2002), 2002 FCA 309, [2003] 2 F.C. 165, 218 D.L.R. (4th) 31 (F.C.A.) [Schmeiser (FCA)]; 2001 FCT 256, 202 F.T.R. 78, 12 C.P.R. (4th) 204 (F.C.T.D.) [Schmeiser (FCT) cited to F.T.R.].

2 Hoffman v. Monsanto Canada Inc., 2005 SKQB 225, [2005] 7 W.W.R. 665 [Hoffman (QB)], aff’d 2007 SKCA 47 [Hoffman (CA)].

3 According to Philippe Cullet, “Monsanto v Schmeiser: A Landmark Decision concerning Farmer Liability and Transgenic Contamination” (2005) 17 J. Envtl. L. 83 at 102. See also Timothy A. Caulfield and E. Richard Gold, “Genetic Testing, Ethical Concerns, and the Role of Patent Law” (2000) 57:5 Clinical Genetics 370 at 370.

4 Excellent work has been done by e.g. Jane Matthews Glenn, “Genetically Modified Crops in Canada: Rights and Wrongs” (2003) 12 J. Envtl. L. & Prac. 281 [Glenn, “GMOs in Canada”]; and Martin Phillipson, “Giving Away the Farm? The Rights and Obligations of Biotechnology Multinationals: Canadian Developments” (2005) 16:2 The King’s College Law Journal 362 [Phillipson, “Giving Away the Farm?”].

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 345

conducted a thorough and comprehensive legal analysis.5 Questions about rights and responsibilities are too often examined independently of each other. Moreover, extra-legal considerations, including philosophical, ethical, economic, environmental and other social concerns, are too often ignored.6

Seen in a broader light the lack of legal liability that results from the Hoffman decision is part of a trend away from accountability for technological innovation. At the same time, there is a trend toward according technological innovators more numerous and powerful property rights. Patentees are quick to invoke the power of property rhetoric to expand and protect their rights, but when it comes to the liabilities ordinarily associated with ownership, the tune suddenly changes.

Agricultural biotechnology companies are not unregulated. Biotechnological innovations exist in a complex policy matrix of legal regulation, social norms and economic realities. Legal regulations cut across intellectual property, contract, tort, environmental law, competition law, trade law, food labeling and other forms of specialized rules. But in terms of ownership duties specifically, patent owners have, at least according to two recent cases, broad rights and few or no property-related responsibilities.

Comparing and contrasting the Schmeiser and Hoffman decisions reveals the existence of a legal disequilibrium. There are various ways to restore equilibrium. One option is to narrow the scope of patent rights. Another is to recognize responsibilities. For reasons discussed below, the latter is the more realistic way to remedy the current imbalance.

I suggest the reason that Canadian courts, thus far, have been unable to appropriately balance rights and responsibilities stems from conceptual ambiguity about the relationship between

5 This is perhaps understandable as a result of the nature of the litigation and adjudication processes, which often turn on particular facts and pleadings, and are unsuited to addressing broader issues.

6 But see e.g. Gold, Castle & Cloutier, “Ag-biotech in the Courts: Patents, Privileges and Presumptions” (Paper presented to the International Consortium on Agricultural Biotechnology Research 8th ICABR International Conference on Agricultural Biotechnology, International Trade and Domestic Protection, (July 2004) [unpublished, available online: ICABR 2004 Conference Papers <http://www.economia.uniroma2.it/conferenze/icabr2004/papers/default.asp>].

346 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

principles of property, intellectual property and tort law. It must be understood specifically which facts are linked to which causes of action. The existence of a patent, for example, is immaterial to a finding of negligence, especially a products liability claim. Negligence in this context is based upon the principle that the designer, manufacturer or distributor of transgenic crops has created an unreasonable risk. Other torts, however, impose liability based on the principle that a patent owner has control, through a combination of patent and contract law, over the object causing harm. These ownership obligations are most appropriately enforced through causes of action such as nuisance, trespass, the rule in Rylands v. Fletcher7 or breach of statute.

This novel insight explains why courts and commentators are often overwhelmed and confused when multiple causes of action are applied to multiple different parties. An appreciation of the principles at stake will lay the foundation for a more precise analysis leading to more satisfactory results. The practical result will be to encourage biotech companies to own up to their ownership obligations.

II.

DISEQUILIBRIUM

A. MONSANTO V. SCHMEISER8

Monsanto markets agricultural systems—the farmer provides land and labour, and the company provides seeds, chemicals, or other tools for crop growing.9 Monsanto’s system involves Roundup glyphosate herbicide, which, in short, kills plants. Monsanto has also engineered a gene that causes a plant and its progeny to be glyphosate-resistant. Farmers can therefore spray Roundup on a growing crop, killing weeds but leaving the transgenic plants

7 (1868), L.R. 3 H.L. 330, aff’g (1866) L.R. 1 Ex. 265. 8 The discussion in this section draws on my earlier work in Jeremy F.

deBeer, “Reconciling Property Rights in Plants” (2005) 8 J. World Intellectual Property 5 [deBeer, “Reconciling Property Rights”].

9 Jack Ralph Kloppenburg, First the Seed: The Political Economy of Plant Biotechnology, 1492-2000 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988) at 282-83, quoting Dr. Klaus Saegebarth of Du Pont and Howard Schneiderman of Monsanto.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 347

unharmed. Monsanto has a Canadian patent for glyphosate-resistant plants, including Roundup Ready canola.10

Monsanto accused Percy Schmeiser, a Saskatchewan farmer, of making, using and selling its patented invention without licence. Monsanto’s private investigators discovered glyphosate-resistant canola in Schmeiser’s 1998 crop, which he had planted with seed saved from the previous year, as was his customary practice. Schmeiser never purchased seeds from Monsanto; that would have required contracting not to save new seeds generated from his crop.11 He argued that he was not responsible for, nor did he want, Roundup Ready canola on his land. He proposed various explanations for its presence, including adventitious spread by wind or insects.

Justice McKay of the Federal Court Trial Division did not accept Schmeiser’s explanations. However, he declined to decide how and why Monsanto’s gene did appear in Schmeiser’s crop. He held that this was “really not significant” because Schmeiser knew or should have known the seeds he saved and replanted were glyphosate-resistant.12 Planting and growing transgenic seeds under these circumstances made Schmeiser liable for infringement of Monsanto’s patent.13 A unanimous panel of the Federal Court of Appeal, and five of nine Justices of the Supreme Court of Canada upheld this ruling.

Schmeiser made several arguments to the Supreme Court.14 First, he argued that Monsanto’s patent was invalid, as it concerns a higher life form, which is not patentable in Canada.15 Second, because he did not spray his crop with Roundup herbicide, he

10 “Glyphosate Resistant Plants”, Can. Patent No. 1, 313,830, (6 August

1986). Generally, the claims pertain to a molecularly engineered gene, a molecularly engineered gene expressed in a glyphosate-resistant plant cell and, more particularly, in a glyphosate-resistant rape seed (canola) cell.

11 Licensed growers must sign a technology use agreement. See Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at para. 11.

12 Schmeiser (FCT), supra note 1 at paras. 119–20. 13 Ibid. at para. 127. 14 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 (Factum of the Appellant at paras. 44-78

and 132-46 [FOA]). 15 Harvard College v. Canada (Commissioner of Patents), 2002 SCC 76,

[2002] 4 S.C.R. 45, 219 D.L.R. (4th) 577 [Harvard College].

348 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

claimed he did not “use” or exploit the patent’s only novel utility. Schmeiser also argued that the correct damages, if any, represent only his enrichment from exploiting the patent (that is, nothing), not his entire profit.

The majority of the Supreme Court held that the patent was valid, as it did not concern a higher life form, but merely a gene and cell contained within a higher life form.16 The majority also found that possession of a plant containing a patented gene constitutes “use”, and therefore infringement.17 Schmeiser’s failure to spray his crop with herbicide was immaterial because of the patent’s “stand-by utility”.18 The majority did, however, accept Schmeiser’s argument regarding damages.19 The dissent’s solution to the whole dilemma would have been to uphold the patent’s validity insofar as it protects only the gene as used in a laboratory setting, which would in effect give Monsanto a monopoly vis-à-vis industry competitors but leave farmers free to use the plants and seeds that they own.20

In describing Monsanto’s patent rights, the Trial Division, Court of Appeal and Supreme Court all embraced the loaded language of classic property. The Supreme Court called Monsanto Canada and Monsanto the “licensee and owner, respectively, of Canadian patent No. 1,313,830.”21 According to the Court, “The Patent Act confers on the patent owner ‘the exclusive right, privilege and liberty of making, constructing and using the invention and selling it to others to be used’.”22 To determine infringement, one must ask: “did the defendant’s activity deprive the inventor in whole or in part, directly or indirectly, of full

16 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at paras. 17–24. See further, Norman

Siebrasse, “Comment on Monsanto Canada Inc. v. Schmeiser” (2004) 83:3 Can. Bar Rev. 967.

17 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at para. 58. 18 Ibid. at paras. 47, 50, 83–85. 19 Ibid. at paras. 98–105, citing N. Siebrasse, “A Remedial Benefit-Based

Approach to the Innocent User Problem in the Patenting of Higher Life Forms” (2004) 20 C.I.P. Rev. 79.

20 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at paras. 140–163. 21 Ibid. at para. 8. 22 Ibid. at para. 25.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 349

enjoyment of the monopoly conferred by law?”23 The Court went on to say that “the main purpose of patent protection is to prevent others from depriving the inventor, even in part and even indirectly, of the monopoly that the law intends to be theirs: only the inventor is entitled, by virtue of the patent and as a matter of law, to the full enjoyment of the monopoly conferred.”24 Such a broad interpretation of the rights conferred upon patent owners was surprising, given the Supreme Court’s balanced reading of other intellectual property rights in recent cases.25

When the time came to consider Mr. Schmeiser’s argument that he also had an ownership interest at stake—what I have called a “classic” property right in the seed itself26—the Courts paid little attention. Schmeiser had argued that Monsanto forfeited its IP rights by virtue of the unconfined release of its product into the environment; that innocent bystanders should not suffer from the adventitious spread of Monsanto’s gene; and that the solution to this dilemma is through the doctrines of waiver or implied licence. The upshot was that Schmeiser’s classic property rights in the plants and seeds should not be subordinated to Monsanto’s IP rights. Schmeiser tried to show how the law traditionally reconciles competing property claims by citing the basic law of

23 Ibid. at para. 35 [emphasis in original]. 24 Ibid. at para. 43 [emphasis in orginal]. See also paras. 46, 49, 54, 71, 72,

79, 80 and 85. 25 In the context of copyrights, see e.g. Théberge v. Galarie d’Art du Petit

Champlain inc., 2002 SCC 34, [2002] 2 S.C.R. 336, 210 D.L.R. (4th) 385; CCH Canadian Ltd. v. Law Society of Upper Canada, 2004 SCC 13, [2004] 1 S.C.R. 339, 236 D.L.R. (4th) 395; and Canadian Assn of Internet Service Providers v. Society of Composers, Authors and Music Publishers of Canada, 2004 SCC 45, [2004] 2 S.C.R. 427, 240 D.L.R. (4th) 193. Regarding trade-marks, see e.g. Kirkbi AG v. Ritvik Holdings Inc., 2005 SCC 65, [2005] 3 S.C.R. 302, 259 D.L.R. (4th) 577; Mattel, Inc. v. 3894207 Canada Inc., 2006 SCC 22, [2006] 1 S.C.R. 772, 268 D.L.R. (4th) 424; Veuve Clicquot Ponsardin v. Boutiques Cliquot Ltée, 2006 SCC 23, [2005] 1 S.C.R. 824, 270 D.L.R. (4th) 1.

26 De Beer, “Reconciling Property Rights”, supra note 8.

350 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

admixture,27 and referencing well established case law dealing with ownership of the progeny of stray bulls.28

The Courts were unwilling to accept these analogies. Both the Trial Division and the Court of Appeal disposed of Schmeiser’s classic property claim in a few lines.29 The Supreme Court missed the point entirely, bluntly and ineloquently30 remarking: “the issue is not property rights, but patent protection. Ownership is no defence to a breach of the Patent Act.”31 In short, the Court broadly interpreted Monsanto’s rights as a patent owner so as to trump Schmeiser’s rights as a classic property owner. Monsanto has been granted a sort of super-property right that overrides all others.

In a postscript to the Schmeiser case, it was recently reported that Schmeiser has again discovered Roundup Ready canola growing in his fields.32 Monsanto had promised the Supreme Court that problems involving volunteer plants are “quickly and satisfactorily resolved by Monsanto and the farmer”,33 and that those “who notified Monsanto of the undesired presence of Roundup Ready canola on their property were dealt with fairly and responsibly by Monsanto. The occasional and limited Roundup Ready canola plants, growing on their property were removed by Monsanto on terms satisfactory to the farmers.”34 But the company’s lawyers told Schmeiser that Monsanto would only hand-pick offending plants if he signed a contract that forever releases Monsanto from any lawsuits associated with their

27 Colwill v. Reeves (1811), 2 Camp 575, 577, cited in Schmeiser (SCC)

FOA, supra note 14 at para. 119. 28 Schmeiser (SCC) FOA, ibid. at para. 116, citing Popowich v. Letweniuk,

[1972] 1 W.W.R. 641 (Sask. Dist. Ct.); Weeks v. Weeks (1977), 81 D.L.R. (3d) 371 (P.E.I. S.C.); Neeb v. Hoffman, [1989] O.J. No 302 QL (Ont Dist.Ct.).

29 Schmeiser (FCT), supra note 1 at paras. 91–92; Schmeiser (FCA), supra note 1 at para. 51.

30 Bruce Ziff, “Travels With My Plant” (2005) 2:2 U.O.L.T.J. 493 [Ziff, “Travels with My Plant”].

31 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at para. 96 (emphasis added). 32 Sean Pratt, “Roundup Ready Canola back in Schmeiser’s field”, The

Western Producer (26 October 2005). 33 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 (Factum of the Respondents at para. 5). 34 Ibid. at para. 103.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 351

products and forbids him from disclosing the terms of that settlement.

Monsanto’s spokesperson defended the company’s offer by saying that it was under no legal obligation to assist in the first place. Monsanto’s attitude raises an interesting question for discussion: what exactly are its legal obligations concerning its patented genes? In Hoffman v. Monsanto, a group of Saskatchewan organic farmers tried to find out.

B. HOFFMAN V. MONSANTO

On 10 January 2002, Larry Hoffman and Dale Beaudoin made an application to the Saskatchewan Court of Queen’s Bench to certify a class action lawsuit on behalf of organic farmers against Monsanto Canada and Bayer CropScience (BCS). Because canola is an open-pollinating crop, Monsanto’s “Roundup Ready” and BCS’s “Liberty Link” brands of canola drifted predictably onto organic farmers’ fields and into their organic crops. As a result, these farmers allegedly incurred substantial losses. Damages included the loss of ability to use canola in crop rotations without risking contamination, the loss of ability to participate in a certified organic canola market and past and future cleanup costs such as identifying and removing transgenic plants and seeds from fields and equipment.35

To be certified as a class, the plaintiffs had to show that there was a cause of action, an identifiable class, common issues best resolved through a class action, and a suitable representative plaintiff.36 In a 177-page judgment on this preliminary application for certification, Madam Justice Smith rejected the plaintiffs’ application on nearly every point.

The most controversial aspects of the decision relate to the Court’s attitude toward possible causes of action. The Court held, in effect, that it was plain and obvious there was no reasonable prospect for success establishing a cause of action based on the plaintiffs’ pleadings.37

35 Hoffman (QB), supra note 2 at para. 39. 36 Class Actions Act, S.S 2001, c. C-12.01. 37 Hoffman (QB), supra note 2 at paras. 38-195.

352 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

The core negligence claim was rejected because the plaintiffs conceded that this was a novel case requiring the creation of a new duty of care.38 According to the Court, the plaintiffs’ pleadings failed to establish that the alleged harms were foreseeable.39 The Court decided that there was no proximate relationship between organic farmers and these agrichemical corporations.40 Finally, in any event, the Court felt that there were policy reasons to negate a duty to take reasonable care in these circumstances.41 Other allegations of negligence, based on a duty to warn and/or reliance on undertakings by Monsanto and BCS, were similarly rebuffed.42

The Court decided that this was not an appropriate case to impose strict liability under the rule of Rylands v. Fletcher.43 The plaintiffs submitted that the defendants engaged in a non-natural use of the land during field trials of transgenic crops and in that process allowed the escape of something likely to do mischief and damage.44 The Court, however, concluded that there was no reasonable way it could be argued that testing and commercial release of transgenic canola could be an escape of a substance within the meaning of the rule.45

The Court acknowledged that liability for nuisance is not limited to occupiers of adjoining land, but questioned settled authorities on this point.46 Justice Smith speculated as to the reasons for imposing such liability before considering American jurisprudence,47 and consequently introduced into Canadian law the idea that independent malfeasance or direct causation is required in cases where the defendant does not occupy nearby

38 Ibid. at paras. 52, 57, 59, 81. 39 Ibid. at paras. 61-66. 40 Ibid. at paras. 67-70. 41 Ibid. at paras. 71-80. 42 Ibid. at paras. 57-51 and 82-88. 43 Ibid. at paras. 89-97. 44 Ibid. at paras. 89. 45 Ibid. at paras. 95-97. 46 Ibid. at paras. 115-116. 47 Ibid. at paras. 117-121, considering In re StarLink Corn Products

Liability Litigation, Marvin Kramer v. Aventis CropScience USA Holding Inc., 212 F. Supp.2d 828 (N.D. Ill. 2002).

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 353

land.48 She concluded that the implications of holding Monsanto and BCS liable in nuisance would be too sweeping, and thus rejected the plaintiffs’ arguments as plainly and obviously flawed.49

The Court rejected the trespass argument because, according to the Court, any interference was indirect.50 It was in this context that the Court rejected an analogy to case law imposing strict liability for damages caused by stray bulls. According to the Court, the plaintiffs could point to no public policy reason why the defendants should not have commercially released transgenic canola.51

According to the Judge, no cause of action could be founded on the Environmental Management and Protection Act52 before it was amended, because it could not be shown that the defendants were owners or in control of a pollutant before its discharge. But the EMPA as amended in 2002 did create a possible albeit limited cause of action. Similarly, the plaintiffs’ claim under the Environmental Assessment Act53, which alleged that the defendants’ development of molecularly engineered genes and genetically modified seeds required ministerial approval, was not clearly unreasonable.

In sum, the Court rejected nearly all of the plaintiffs’ arguments regarding potential causes of action. The plaintiffs were also unable to convince the Court that they satisfied any of the other prerequisites to certification.

On the issue of whether there was an identifiable class, the Court concluded, among other things, that there were many reasons why an organic farmer might choose not to grow canola, which vary according to the circumstances of the farmer, and there were no objective criteria with which to distinguish those farmers who would have grown canola but for the risk of

48 Hoffman, supra note 2 at para. 122. 49 Ibid. at para. 124. 50 Ibid. at para. 133. 51 Ibid. at para. 132. 52 S.S. 1983-84, c. E-10.1 [EMPA]. 53 S.S. 1979-80, c. E-10.1 [EAA].

354 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

transgenic contamination.54 There was no evidence that the same problems were widespread among members of the proposed class,55 and most of the members of the proposed class did not share in the causes of action asserted in the statement of claim.56

The Court found that many of the common issues among the proposed class related to the causes of action that had just been rejected.57 Any other proposed common issues, the Court held, could not be identified without individual inquiry.58 Furthermore, with a degree of circularity, the Court reasoned that it was difficult or impossible to establish commonality of issues since there was no identifiable class.59

When considering whether a class action was the preferable procedure for the action, the Court concluded that the proceeding would inevitably break down into individual proceedings, requiring full rights of discovery and a trial to resolve many unique factual issues.60

The Court also found flaws with the representative plaintiffs because they had assigned significant rights and duties to the Saskatchewan Organic Directorate. In effect, these plaintiffs were not directing the litigation but had relinquished control to a committee that was not answerable to the court, in a way that was inconsistent with their fiduciary duties to the proposed class.61

There is no doubt that on balance the plaintiffs were handed an overwhelming defeat. Martin Phillipson has characterized the denial of certification as “an enormous blow” that “may well bring an end to the lawsuit”.62 After, the Saskatchewan Court of Appeal upheld nearly every aspect of the Queen’s Bench decision and dismissed the farmer’s appeal. Only leave to the Supreme Court of Canada could breathe life back into this case.

54 Hoffman (QB), supra note 2 at paras. 218, 234. 55 Ibid. at para. 242. 56 Ibid. at para. 243. 57 Ibid. at para. 310. 58 Ibid. at paras. 244 and 324. 59 Ibid. at para. 310. 60 Ibid. at para. 326. 61 Ibid. at paras. 329 -339. 62 Phillipson, “Giving Away the Farm”, supra note 4 at 368.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 355

III. RESTORING EQUILIBRIUM

When the results of the decisions in Schmeiser and Hoffman are juxtaposed, a serious problem becomes apparent. Entities that patent biotechnological innovations have all of the rights associated with property ownership, yet have been relieved of the responsibilities traditionally imposed upon property owners.

The most obvious problem with this legal disequilibrium is the injustice done to farmers who are harmed, economically or otherwise, by transgenic organisms. Another problem is the hostility toward the biotechnology industry, and the agricultural biotechnology industry in particular, stemming from the current legal imbalance. Farmers, consumers, non-governmental organizations and the public understandably resent the contradictory positions taken by agrochemical firms like Monsanto. Perceived and actual inequities generate disdain for these firms and undermine consumer confidence in their products. This, in turn, further hinders social acceptance of transgenic organisms, undermining biotechnology’s potential benefits. Moreover, hostile attitudes toward biotechnological innovations help to create an unstable legal, economic and political environment. The associated uncertainty creates unnecessary risks for biotechnology firms.

Therefore, the disequilibrium identified above is a problem, not just for organic farmers, but also for agrochemical companies. Indeed, this imbalance affects the whole biotechnology industry as well as society at large.

Equilibrium could be restored in several ways. One option is to narrow or eliminate patent rights in respect of biotechnological innovations. Another possibility is to preserve patent rights but recognize corresponding responsibilities.

A. LIMITING RIGHTS

It is possible to balance the rights and responsibilities of patent owners by adjusting the rights side of the equation. This would require revisiting the scope of patentable subject matter and/or the scope of patent rights.

The evolution of Canadian law on the patentability of higher life forms has been complicated, controversial, and at times

356 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

contradictory. In 1982, Canada’s Patent Appeal Board held that living organisms are patentable.63 For the next 20 years, the Supreme Court managed to duck the issue,64 but in Harvard College65 dealt with it head on. A five-to-four majority of the Supreme Court held that a higher life form is not a patentable invention.66 In Schmeiser, all judges purported to agree that higher life forms are not patentable in Canada, but a five-to-four majority rendered this proposition meaningless. The decision allowed for patents on the genes and cells that constitute higher life forms, and held that the patent protects the whole of any organism containing patented genes and cells.

So, the current law in Canada is that life is not patentable per se, but its building blocks are. It is notable, however, that three of nine judges on the Court have been replaced since Schmeiser, one of whom sided with the majority and two of whom dissented. To add yet another variable, the newest appointee, Justice Rothstein, presided over the Harvard College case at the Federal Court of Appeal and ruled in favour of the patentee.67 Those who might have thought that it does not matter which judges would decide the next biotechnology patent case before the Supreme Court received a lesson in legal realism following the Harvard College and Schmeiser decisions.

Nevertheless, in the future, significant legal changes in this area would probably come from Parliament and not the courts. Both the majority and minority decisions in Schmeiser and Harvard College acknowledged that Parliament could change Canadian patent law if it wishes.68 Canada’s international IP treaty obligations would permit Parliament to do so.

63 Re Application of Abitibi Co. (1982), 62 C.P.R. (2d) 81 (P.A.B.). 64 In Pioneer Hi-Bred Ltd. v. Canada (Commissioner of Patents), [1989] 1

S.C.R. 1623, 60 D.L.R. (4) 223, 25 C.P.R. (3d) 257, the Supreme Court of Canada could have tackled the question, but instead decided only that the patent at issue in that case was invalid because of insufficient disclosure.

65 Harvard College, supra note 15. 66 “Invention” is defined in section 2 of the Patent Act, R.S.C. 1985, c. P-4. 67 [2000] 4 F.C. 528. 68 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at paras. 93-94, 159; Harvard College,

supra note 14 at paras. 114, 206.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 357

Under the Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights69 members of the World Trade Organization must make patents available for any invention, whether products or processes, in all fields of technology provided the inventions are new, result from an inventive step, and are capable of industrial application.70 There are, however, exceptions to this general rule. Member states can exclude inventions from patentable subject matter if doing so is necessary to protect ordre public or morality, human, animal or plant life, health or the environment.71 Moreover, member states can also exclude from patentability plants and animals other than micro-organisms, as well as naturally occurring breeding methods, but there must be an effective sui generis system in place.72 Canada has such a system in the Plant Breeders’ Rights Act.73

Rather than excluding higher life forms from patentability altogether, it is also possible for Canada to enact limited exceptions to the exclusive rights conferred by a patent.74 In making a limited exception, member countries must not unreasonably interfere with the normal exploitation of the patent and must not prejudice the legitimate interests of a patent owner.

Although the TRIPs Agreement would permit Canada to narrow the scope of patent law, multilateral treaties also affect this debate. Specifically, legislative reform could constitute an

69 Set out as Annex 1C of the Marrakesh Agreement establishing the World

Trade Organization, 15 April 1994, 33 I.L.M. 1125 [TRIPs Agreement]. 70 Ibid., art. 27. 71 Ibid., art. 27:2. 72 Ibid., art. 24:3(b). Member countries are required to allow the patent-

ability of non-biological and microbiological processes such as biotechnological gene manipulation, gene transfer and so on, but other patent exceptions are permitted for diagnostic, therapeutic and surgical methods for the treatment of humans or animals. Ibid., art. 27:3(a). Also, general exceptions to the IP regime under the TRIPs Agreement would permit measures “consistent with the TRIPs Agreement” necessary to protect public health and nutrition, to promote the public interest in sectors of vital importance to socio-economic and technological development or to prevent practices that unreasonably restrain trade or adversely affect the international transfer of technology.

73 S.C. 1990, c. 20. 74 TRIPs Agreement, supra note 69, art. 30.

358 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

expropriation of foreign investors’ property rights under the North American Free Trade Agreement.75 Bruce Ziff explains:

Under article 1110 of NAFTA, foreign investors from the signatory states are protected against both direct and regulatory takings. Legislation that terminates extant patents such as the one for Round-Up Ready Canola triggers a right of compensation in favour of Monsanto, a foreign investor. So, it is true that Parliament is free – as in libre – to reverse the Supreme Court of Canada ruling tomorrow. Such legislation would be unimpeachable. Nonetheless, it would not be free—as in gratis—since the measure would cost Canadians billions if enacted.76

Therefore, the government must be cautious before taking away foreign biotechnology firms’ IP rights. This makes a lengthy discussion of whether or not it would be an appropriate policy to curtail patent rights somewhat moot. Even if such a move were politically saleable, it would not be economically feasible in the short-term. A longer-term solution might be to deny or limit patent rights prospectively, although that would not address the pressing issue of imbalanced rights and responsibilities.

In sum, judicial narrowing of the scope of patent law is possible but unpredictable. Parliament is the appropriate venue in which to debate the rights of patentees, but policy questions about legislative changes to patent law are dwarfed by the practicalities of narrowing the scope of protection. Canadian law concerning the rights of patentees is unlikely to undergo significant change anytime soon.

B. RECOGNIZING RESPONSIBILITIES

If, for reasons just discussed, rights granted under Canadian patent law are unlikely to change, equilibrium could be obtained by recognizing corresponding ownership obligations. After all, property rights normally entail responsibilities as well.

75 North American Free Trade Agreement Between the Government of

Canada, the Government of Mexico and the Government of the United States, 17 December 1992, Can. T.S. 1994 No. 2, 32 I.L.M. 289 (entered into force 1 January 1994) [NAFTA].

76 Bruce Ziff, “Travels with My Plant”, supra note 30.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 359

As a preliminary matter, it could be suggested that patents and other IP rights are not really “property” rights, and that patentees are not really “owners”. Although Monsanto pitched this as a self-serving argument in the Hoffman case,77 sometimes IP critics take this view in order to undermine the rhetorical use of powerful property metaphors.78 The proposition that IP is not really property might help to rationalize the combined result of Schmeiser and Hoffman, and therefore deserves careful consideration.

There are important theoretical and practical differences between IP and classic property. The fundamental distinctions relate to the inherent characteristics of ideational resources: they are not scarce, rivalrous or possessable.79 It is somewhat awkward, therefore, to transpose classic property theory onto public goods such as ideas, although there have been numerous attempts to do so.80 No doubt the distinct characteristics of ideational resources go the heart of why we recognise IP rights, and how we define the scope of IP protection. However, looking closely, they actually have little to do with whether IP is a type of property. That is a subtle but crucial distinction, which helps to highlight the importance of property-related responsibilities in IP law.

In Schmeiser the Supreme Court interpreted the scope of patent protection like a typical classic property right. Patents, according to the Court, provide their owners with full monopoly

77 Hoffman (QB), supra note 2 at para. 132. 78 R. Polk Wagner, “Information Wants to be Free: Intellectual Property

and the Mythologies of Control” (2003) 103 Colum. L. Rev. 995. 79 See further de Beer, “Reconciling Property Rights”, supra note 8 at 14,

and the sources cited therein. 80 Some of the many notable works on point include e.g. J. Hughes, “The

Philosophy of Intellectual Property” (1988) 77 Georgetown L. J. 287; E.C. Hettinger, “Justifying Intellectual Property” (1989) 18 Philosophy & Public Affairs 31; T.G. Palmer, “Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? The Philosophy of Property Rights and Ideal Objects” (1990) 13 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 817; W.J. Gordon, “On Owning Information: Intellectual Property and the Restitutionary Impulse” (1992) 78 Va. L. Rev. 149; W.J. Gordon, “A Property Right in Self-Expression: Equality and Individualism in the Natural Law of Intellectual Property” (1993) 102 Yale L.J. 1533; Peter Drahos, A Philosophy of Intellectual Property (Aldershot: Dartmouth Publishing Company, 1996).

360 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

powers, which cannot be interfered with in whole or in part, directly or indirectly.81 Patent owners have, among other things, broad rights to exclude others from the resource in question, to use the resource and to transfer such rights by way of sale or gift. The rights may be time limited and the resource intangible, but many other classic property rights, such as a life estate or a chose in action, share these features.

Patent rights are at least as strong as many other classic private property rights. The essential characteristics of patents bring them within almost every conception of the concept82 of property to clearly resemble a “full-blooded ownership”83 interest.84 The most popular definitions of property either consider exclusivity as its sine qua non,85 or view it as comprising a variety of sufficient but not necessary features.86 Some authors have defined a property right as a state-endorsed dictum from a private citizen to the world at large, demanding that everyone keep off a given resource unless permission is granted.87 On any widely accepted definition, a patent is a property right.

81 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at paras. 35, 43, 46, 49, 54, 71, 72, 79, 80,

85. 82 Jeremy Waldron, The Right to Private Property (Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 1998) at 47-53. [Waldron, “The Right to Private Property”]. 83 James Harris, Property and Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press,

1996) at 29-30. 84 See generally David Lametti, “The Concept and Conceptions of

Intellectual Property as seen through the Lens of Property”, in G. Comandé & G. Ponzanelli, eds., Scienza e Diritto nel Prisma del Diritto Comparato (Torino: Giappichelli, 2004).

85 T.W. Merrill, “Property and the Right to Exclude” (1998) 77 Neb. L. Rev. 730.

86 Merrill, ibid., calls this school of thought “multiple variable essen-tialism.” Merrill’s taxonomy also includes “nominalism”, which sees the term property as merely a malleable shell.

87 Professor Farnese reaches the conclusion that patent owners have property rights by citing Felix Cohen’s famous definition of property: “To the world: Keep off (X) unless you have my permission, which I may grant or withhold. Signed: Private Citizen. Endorsed: The state.” See Felix S. Cohen, “Dialogue on Private Property”, (1954) 9 Rutgers L. Rev. 357 at 374, cited in Patricia L. Farnese, “Patently Unreasonable: Reconsidering the Responsibility of Patentees in Today’s Inventive Climate” (2004) 6 Tulane J. Tech. & Intellectual Property 1 at 4.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 361

Patentees cannot, therefore, escape their responsibilities by arguing that to label them as property owners is “a misunderstanding of the nature of their interest under patent law.”88 That position is untenable as it is inconsistent with assertions patentees typically make when it comes to enforcing their IP rights. More importantly, from a philosophical, legal and ethical perspective, the argument that patentees are not owners is patently wrong.

Ownership of property entails both rights and duties. Often when we talk theoretically about property-related duties we mean to say that non-owners owe a duty not to interfere with property owners’ correlative rights, as explained in Hohfeld’s seminal work on jural relations.89 But also, property owners themselves have duties associated with the things that they own.90

The most dominant property metaphor, which views ownership as a “bundle of rights”,91 acknowledges the existence of various rights and responsibilities. Unfortunately, restating Honoré’s “standard incidents” of “the full liberal concept of

88 Hoffman (QB), supra note 2 at para. 132. 89 See e.g. Wesley N. Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions, as Applied

in Judicial Reasoning, and Other Legal Essays, W.W. Cook, ed., (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919).

90 Bruce Ziff, Principles of Property Law (Scarborough, ON: Carswell, 2000) at 3; Eric T. Freyfogle, “The Construction of Ownership” (1996) U. Ill. L. Rev. 173-187; Eric T. Freyfogle, “Context and Accommodation in Modern Property Law”, (1988-89) 41 Stan. L. Rev. 1529 at 1540-1544, 1553; David Lametti, “Property and (Perhaps) Justice. A Review Article of James W. Harris, Property and Justice” (1998) 43 McGill L.J. 663; David Lametti, “Coming to Terms with Copyright” in M. Geist., ed., In the Public Interest: The Future of Canadian Copyright Law (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2005) at 487, citing J.W. Singer, Entitlement: The Paradox of Property (New Haven, Yale University Press, 2000); Gregory Alexander, Commodity & Propriety: Competing Visions of Property in American Legal Thought 1776-1970 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997); W.N.R. Lucy & C. Mitchell, “Replacing Private Property: The Case for Stewardship” (1996) 55 Cambridge L.J. 566; K. Gray, “Equitable Property” (1994) 47 Curr. Legal Probs. 157; E.G. McCaffery, “Must We Have the Right to Waste?” in S.R. Munzer, ed., New Essays in the Legal and Political Theory of Property (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001) at 76. But cf. e.g. A. Ryan, Property (Minneapolis, University of Minneapolis Press, 1987) at 54-5.

91 James E. Penner, “The Bundle of Rights Picture of Property” (1996) 43 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. 711 at 712-24 [Penner, “The Bundle of Rights Picture”].

362 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

ownership”92 as a bundle of rights tends to downplay the importance of property duties.93 Remember that one of Honoré’s standard incidents is “the duty to prevent harm”.94 Jeremy Waldron states this as “a duty to refrain from using X in a way that harms others”.95 James Penner characterizes it as a prohibition on the harmful use of property.96 The essential point, as Ziff explains, is that “the bitter accompanies the sweet”, and “it is common to find a large number of ownership-based duties, scattered though they may be throughout the law.”97

Although the precise nature of property-related rights and duties varies depending on the object of social wealth in question, basic responsibilities apply to both tangible and ideational resources.98 In other words, ownership obligations attach to both classic and intellectual property rights.

Before shifting from a theoretical discussion of property responsibilities to an analysis of specific legal doctrines under which liability is imposed, it is worthwhile to consider this debate from an even wider perspective. Recognizing that IP ownership, like property ownership generally, entails both rights and responsibilities is part of a broader reconstitution of the modern liberal rights-based paradigm.99 Subjecting rights to internal responsibilities as well as external duties protects a multiplicity of interests that are not otherwise safeguarded.

The traditional liberal framework would acknowledge the interests of those who are harmed by the exercise of another’s

92 A.M. Honoré, “Ownership” in A.G. Guest, ed., Oxford Essays in

Jurisprudence (Oxford: O.U.P., 1961) 107 [emphasis added]. 93 See further J.L. Schroeder, “Chix Nix Bundle-O-Stix: A Feminist

Critique of the Disaggregation of Property”, (1994) 93 Mich. L. Rev. 239. 94 A.M. Honoré, “Ownership” in A.G. Guest, supra note 92 at 113

(emphasis added). 95 Waldron, The Right to Private Property, supra note 82 at 49. 96 Penner, “The Bundle of Rights Picture”, supra note 91 at 761. 97 Ziff, Principles of Property Law, supra note 90 at 3. 98 David Lametti, “The Concept of Property: Relations Through Objects of

Social Wealth” (2003) 53 U.T.L.J. 325; David Lametti, “Coming to Terms with Copyright”, supra note 90 at 486-89.

99 See e.g. Leon Trackman and Sean Gatien, Rights and Responsibilities (Toronto: U of T Press, 1999).

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 363

rights only to the extent they have countervailing rights of their own. Conflict is resolved by reordering competing rights in a hierarchical fashion. In the context of transgenic crops, this would mean that the rights of a patent owner might be checked by other rights, such as a farmer’s classic private property rights.100 Rights with responsibilities, however, take account of important social values and other interests not necessarily crystallized as countervailing rights.101 Responsibilities are simply an inherent aspect of rights, including IP rights such as patents. This view suggests that patent owners may have responsibilities in addition to and beyond those discussed here. For example, there may be a responsibility to preserve biodiversity or there may be other obligations of environment stewardship.

Responsibilities also flow inevitably from Canada’s attitude toward biotechnological risks and our implementation of the precautionary principle in this context. In general, North American law and policy reflects the belief that transgenic organisms are “substantially equivalent” to non-transgenic organisms unless proven otherwise.102 Although there is not yet reliable scientific evidence of increased health risks associated with transgenic organisms, other sorts of concerns have begun to be realized. The Hoffman case, for instance, illustrates some of the social, cultural and economic risks of biotechnology.

Canada has chosen to accept these risks, in order to encourage economic development and scientific progress through biotechnological innovation. The primary beneficiaries of Canadian biotechnology policy, biotechnology firms, cannot now say in good faith that they bear no responsibility when accepted risks eventually materialize. As Patricia Farnese puts it: “there is no justification for allowing a patentee to profit, without consequence, from the state-granted monopoly over her technology and then leave society with the long-term consequences of the technology’s introduction.”103

100 See e.g. de Beer, “Reconciling Property Rights”, supra note 8. 101 Ibid. 102 This contrasts with, for example, the European approach, which

presumes the opposite. 103 Farnese, supra note 87 at 3.

364 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

Such a problem is not unique to the agricultural biotechnology industry. Helen Nissenbaum has identified a similar lack of accountability in the software engineering business. She notes that software patent owners tend to claim broad IP rights yet typically try to disclaim any liabilities normally associated with ownership.104

Jaqueline Lipton also notes that we tend to adopt property language when talking about rights in information, but overlook property duties when talking about “information property” generally.105 She says that information property law has “borrowed too little” from traditional notions of property, by failing to notice that: “traditional Property rights entail significant concurrent obligations or responsibilities imposed on the proprietary owner as an incident of their Property ownership.”106 She agrees that we need to start thinking about an overarching framework for information property that incorporates concurrent legal duties.107

Lipton talks about the duty to mitigate harms such as inhibited access to information resources. Although the duties addressed in this article are more like the concerns discussed by Nissenbaum, a common thread can be identified. There is a trend toward establishing stronger property rights in ideational resources and a simultaneous trend away from recognizing basic ownership obligations. IP owners have been allowed to shirk their property-related duties.

The systemic imbalance is, in part, a natural consequence of the technology product development cycle. The promise of IP rights tends to precede research, development and commercialization, and liabilities tend to accrue following distribution and use. This has led to a lag between the granting of proprietary rights in respect of technological innovations and the imposition of responsibility for harms caused by such products.

104 Helen Nissenbaum, “Accountability in a Computerized Society” (1996)

Science and Engineering Ethics 2, 25-42. 105 Jaqueline Lipton, “Information Property: Rights and Responsibilities”,

(2004) 56 Fla. L. Rev. 135. 106 Ibid. at 148. 107 Ibid. at 165.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 365

However, there are good economic reasons to attempt to crystallize property rights and liabilities simultaneously, or at least as early as possible. Clear IP rights are designed to facilitate investment in the development and marketing of new and useful products. The predictability of potential liabilities would seem to be an equally important consideration for would-be investors. This underscores the need to ensure insofar as possible that traditional rules are applied, and if necessary adapted, to technology industries if and when harms are realized.

One commentator has dismissed the fear that imposing liabilities upon patentees might diminish incentives to invent, and therefore contradict the basic purpose of patent law. That argument was premised on the beliefs that some people would still invent out of pure pleasure, and that “as long as there is a potential for economic gain, invention will occur notwithstanding economic risks.”108 This underestimates the economic complexity of the patent regime, and overlooks the tremendous financial importance of patent protection to biotechnology industry investors.

I agree, however, that ownership obligations will not undermine investment incentives and are not inconsistent with the purpose of patents. The reason is that if patentees’ rights and responsibilities are appropriately correlated at an early stage, fair and predictable obligations can actually enhance, rather than undermine, the economic incentives to invest in technological innovation. It is not just the existence but also the clarity of these rights and responsibilities that creates investment incentives. If economic risks are predictable, it will be possible to plan for and insure against these risks.

Continuing with a consequentialist perspective, there are moral and ethical reasons to recognize patentees’ property-related duties. Professors Gold and Caulfield have argued that imposing liabilities on patentees is a useful deterrent against harmful and unethical behaviour in the biomedical context.109 This insight would seem to be equally applicable to agricultural biotechnology

108 Farnese, supra note 87 at 30. 109 Caulfield & Gold, supra note 3 at 373.

366 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

companies. There is a need for moral accountability in this industry.110

All of the macro concerns discussed above are intimately related to the more concrete legal question of patent owners’ responsibilities toward farmers in cases involving transgenic crop drift. In light of the foregoing contextual discussion, it is not surprising that most of the commentators who have studied this issue have concluded that companies like Monsanto bear some responsibility in such circumstances.

One can discern in the literature several different approaches that have been used to reach that conclusion. Some authors have looked at a number of different torts and different parties, and appraised various potential liabilities.111 Some authors have focused their analysis on a specific cause of action, such as nuisance,112 breach of statute,113 or the rule in Rylands v. Fletcher.114 Others have looked exclusively at negligence including strict products liability, or have concluded that an action in negligence is most likely to succeed.115

The general legal consensus that patent owners may be liable for harms caused by patented biotechnological innovations is correct. However, in my view, patent owners ought to be held

110 See e.g. Gold, Castle & Cloutier, “Ag-biotech in the Courts: Patents,

Privileges and Presumptions”, supra note 6. 111 See e.g. Jane Matthews Glenn, “Footloose: Civil Responsibility for

GMO Gene Wandering in Canada” (2004) 43 Washburn L.J. 547. 112 See e.g. Christopher P. Rodgers, “Liability for the Release of GMOs

into the Environment: Exploring the Boundaries of Nuisance” (2003) 62 Cambridge L.J. 371; and Thomas Redick and Christina Bernstein, “Nuisance Law and the Prevention of ‘Genetic Pollution’: Declining a Dinner Date with Damocles” (2000) 30 Environ. L. Rep. 10328.

113 See e.g. Jodi McNaughton, “GMO Contamination: Are GMOs Pollutants under The Environmental Management and Protection Act?” (2003) 66 Sask. L. Rev. 183 (QL).

114 See e.g. J.W. Loone, “Rylands v. Fletcher Revisited: A Comparison of English, Australian and American Approaches to Common Law Liability for Dangerous Agricultural Activities” (1996) 1 Drake J. Agric. L. 149.

115 See e.g. Farnese, supra note 87; Sharon Mascher, “Sowing the Seeds of Discontent? Australia's New Gene Technology Act” (2003) 12 J. Envtl. L. & Prac. 341 at 371; and Gold, Castle & Cloutier, “Ag-biotech in the Courts: Patents, Privileges and Presumptions”, supra note 6.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 367

liable not necessarily on the basis of negligence, but rather pursuant to other causes of action, such as nuisance, trespass, breach of statute or the rule in Rylands v. Fletcher. This is an important distinction.

Liability for negligence is most likely to succeed as a claim under the existing category of products liability, or perhaps other existing categories such as cases of reliance, or the duty to warn. In this light, the Hoffman case is just a simple twist on well-settled legal principles. That the product in question is a biotechnological product is not significant. The key fact in establishing products liability is that the defendant was the designer, manufacturer or distributor of the product in question. The designer, manufacturer or distributor’s liability arises in part because that person was in a position to avoid creating a risk of harm, either by producing a product that would not cause harm or by warning potential victims of the harms that might occur.

The existence of a patent is immaterial to a finding of liability for negligence. It may be that a person who is liable for creating an unreasonable risk happens to have obtained a patent, but it may also be that the designer, manufacturer or distributor is not the patentee. Products liability for negligence is entirely unrelated to whether the designer, manufacturer or distributor has applied for, obtained or enforced a patent. In light of this, it makes perfect sense that no court has yet considered whether a patentee owes a duty of care to a consumer who is injured by the patented invention.116

The existence of a patent is, however, material to finding liability on other grounds. The maxim sic utere tuo ut alienum non laedas, meaning use your own property so as not to harm others is often associated with the law of nuisance, although the law of trespass also imposes obligations upon property owners, as does the rule in Rylands v. Fletcher. Even more precisely, these causes of action are premised less on ownership per se than on the degree of control that property owners, by definition, exercise over the source of the harm.117 For that reason, liability may

116 Farnese, ibid. at 10-11. 117 Ownership and/or possession inevitably involve some level of control.

Control, on the other hand, does not always amount to ownership.

368 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

attach to the occupier or possessor of property, in addition to or instead of the owner. Likewise, liability may be imposed upon a patentee in the right circumstances.

The reason a patentee might be held liable for damages caused by a patented invention is because, as explained above, a patent provides its owner with exclusive control over making, constructing, using and selling the invention.118 According to the Supreme Court of Canada, the patentee is entitled to fully enjoy this right, privilege and liberty, and cannot be deprived of the monopoly, in whole or in part, directly or indirectly.119 Moreover, a patentee is entitled to protect and enforce these rights both under the Patent Act and through the common law of contract. Put briefly, a patentee may exercise an extraordinary degree of control over their patented invention. If a patentee chooses to exercise its rights of control after a product has been manufactured and distributed to the public, it is appropriate to impose liability on that basis.

It is crucial to be precise about how and why liability might arise. The particular principle underpinning legal liability has significant implications in terms of the existence, scope and duration of legal responsibilities. For example, if the existence of a patent were material to establishing liability for negligence, such liability could conceivably cease to exist following the expiration of the patent 20 years from the date the patent application was filed. Similarly, failing to appreciate this distinction could result in variable liability depending on whether the product’s inventor had rights under the Plant Breeder’s Rights Act or other IP regimes. What if a defendant had chosen not to seek patent protection but instead guarded its intangible assets as trade secrets? Unless we are clear about the basis for imposing liabilities, the fact that an inventor has never sought or enforced patent rights could eliminate legal responsibility altogether.

The facts of the Hoffman case underscore these points. Monsanto is the owner of Canadian Patent No. 1,313,830, and has rigorously asserted its rights via contract and patent law. In

118 Patent Act, supra note 66, s. 42. 119 Schmeiser (SCC), supra note 1 at paras. 35, 43, 46, 49, 54, 71, 72, 79,

80, 85.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 369

Schmesier, the Supreme Court of Canada vindicated Monsanto’s property interest in the molecularly engineered gene and transgenic seeds that caused damage to the Hoffman plaintiffs. On the other hand, Monsanto’s co-defendant in the Hoffman case, BCS, is arguably in a somewhat different position. The BCS product in question, Liberty Link canola, is hybrid seed. Its rights, therefore, are likely more limited than Monsanto’s. Moreover, it seems that BCS has not pursued its IP rights in the courts as aggressively as Monsanto has.

Consequently, depending on the principle underpinning the causes of action invoked by the plaintiffs, the two co-defendants in Hoffman might find themselves facing different legal liabilities. As product designers, manufacturers and distributors, both defendants may be equally liable. If, however, one is considering their respective liabilities based upon the existence and enforcement of patent rights, it may be appropriate to treat these defendants somewhat differently.

It is true that there may be overlap between liability in negligence, nuisance, trespass, the rule in Rylands v. Fletcher and various statutory causes of action. Yet fundamentally, there are two related but separate legal principles regarding liability for harms done by transgenic crops. Liability may be premised upon the basis of “control over property” and/or “creation of risk”.

In general, property-related responsibilities are reflected through causes of action other than negligence, such as breach of statute, nuisance, trespass, and/or the rule in Rylands v. Fletcher. Unlike negligence, these other torts do not require a finding of fault in order to impose liability. Liability is based upon control rather than fault.

Some might see aspects of the law of negligence as founded on the principle of control over property, rather than or in addition to creation of risk. The doctrine of occupier’s liability is one possible example, although the rules governing occupiers of property have been largely subsumed by statute.120 Employers or parents may be held vicariously liable on the basis of control over their employees or children, but those examples involve control over

120 See Linden, Canadian Tort Law, 7th ed., (Markham, Ont: Butterworths, 2001) at 650-82.

370 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

persons, not property. Product manufacturers do, of course, exercise control over the design and manufacture of a good. Again, however, this control is not over property but over a process. Simply put, control over property is not a typical basis for a finding of liability in negligence. In cases where negligence and property issues happen to be found together, liability can usually be attributed to principles other than ownership.

This insight represents a breakthrough in analyses of liability for harms caused by transgenic crops. The temptation in the past has been to look at the applicability of particular torts to particular parties using fairly traditional doctrinal methodologies. Common law rules or statutes have been explained and applied somewhat blindly, without asking how or why the rules are the way they are.

The shotgun approach, splattering causes of action around in the hope that something will stick, has proved to be overwhelming and confusing. As a proposition of fairness and equity, the idea that patent owners have both rights and responsibilities should be relatively non-controversial. The broader contextual factors discussed above also confirm this. Yet at the concrete stage of legal analysis, in the Hoffman case for example, particular rules were applied with unsatisfactory results.

The judge was confused about which specific facts are relevant to which specific causes of action. For instance, when analyzing the nuisance claim, the judge stated that: “The implications of holding a manufacturer, or even inventor, liable in nuisance for damage caused by the use of its product or invention by another would be very sweeping indeed.”121 When later summarizing her conclusion about liability in nuisance, Justice Smith said: “There is simply no legal basis for claiming that mere ownership…, let alone mere patent protection, without more, creates liability for nuisance….”122 She was seemingly unaware of the importance of distinguishing between the defendants’ roles as inventors and patentees, and manufacturers and distributors. Similarly, she dismissed the argument the defendants could be liable for trespass for “merely marketing GM canola.”123 In this respect, she failed to

121 Hoffman (QB), supra note 2 at para. 122 [emphasis added]. 122 Ibid. at para. 301. 123 Ibid. at para. 131.

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 371

appreciate the relevance of the control the defendants exercise through patents and contract.

One reason for the confusion may be that farmers lack access to the legal resources necessary to tackle the tangled web of transgenic crop liability issues. In fact, it was the same lawyer from Saskatoon who acted for Schmeiser in the first case and the organic farmers in the second. He has likely staked much on these cases, and his diligence and dedication is admirable. But it is unreasonable to expect that individual farmers, or even a group of farmers, are able to match the wealth of subject-specific experience and expertise retained in the deep pockets of opposing parties in both cases.

Of course, the complex interrelationship between principles of tort and property is difficult to for anyone to distil adequately in the space allotted in trial or appellate pleadings, when there are so many other issues that must be addressed. Hopefully, my analysis here will assist policymakers, practitioners and judges grappling with the nuances of these issues.

In my view, the solution to the problem of establishing the proper cause of action lies in formulating more precisely the basic principles and policies at issue, and situating these within the socio-legal landscape. As a practical matter, this may mean that plaintiffs should resist the tendency to plead everything and offer courts a litany of legal claims from which to choose. Or it may mean that only certain causes of action are appropriate for certification on facts alleged in a particular class action. It does not mean that plaintiffs should not plead and judges should not consider multiple or alternative causes of action.

Arguments and decisions should be made based upon first principles. These principles can then be aligned with the concepts underpinning specific legal rules to demonstrate why liability should be imposed. This is not a purely property-based, IP-based or tort-based approach. The analysis requires a far more textured and nuanced understanding of the relationship between these legal rubrics. There must be an appreciation of the subtleties amongst the principles underlying the legal rules, and how these might affect the particular defendants in a particular case. When one appreciates the subtle relationships between socio-legal context,

372 U.B.C. LAW REVIEW VOL. 40:1

basic principles and specific rules, it becomes much easier to see how the existing law is capable of balancing IP rights and responsibilities. The result should be a demonstrable difference in the outcome of cases such as Hoffman.

IV. CONCLUSION

There is an imbalance between the rights and responsibilities of biotech patent owners. The legal disequilibrium is demonstrated through two recent Canadian cases: Schmeiser and Hoffman. In Schmeiser the Supreme Court of Canada expansively construed patent rights in respect of transgenic crops. In Hoffman a Saskatchewan court narrowly construed liabilities for harms caused by such products.

There are several ways to restore equilibrium. It is possible to narrow the scope of patent rights. Judicial reconsideration of Canadian patent law is a possibility, but is more likely that potential changes will come from Parliament. Although Canada’s obligations under the TRIPs Agreement would permit adjustments to the nature of patent rights in Canada, the need under NAFTA to compensate foreign investors for interference with their interests renders this solution problematic.

Alternatively, obligations can be more clearly recognized. Patent rights are property rights, and property rights also entail responsibilities. Recognizing rights with responsibilities is part of a reconstitution of the liberal rights-based paradigm. Responsibilities are also an inescapable consequence of Canada’s implementation of the precautionary principle. Shirking responsibility is not unique to the agricultural sector or even the biotechnology industry. There is a trend among IP owners generally toward arguing for greater property rights yet fewer ownership obligations. There are economic and ethical reasons to recalibrate rights and responsibilities, which can only be accomplished through a clearer understanding of the principles underpinning liabilities.

Ownership obligations are most appropriately enforced through causes of action such as nuisance, trespass, the rule in Rylands v. Fletcher or breach of statute. The existence of a patent is immaterial to a finding of negligence, especially a products

2007 RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 373

liability claim. Negligence in this context is based upon the principle that the designer, manufacturer or distributor of transgenic crops has created or failed to warn about an unreasonable risk. Other torts impose liability based on the principle that a patent owner has control over property. This unique insight explains why courts and commentators are often overwhelmed and confused when multiple causes of action are applied to multiple different parties. An appreciation of the relevant principles should help to restore the balance between rights and responsibilities.