Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler, David ...

394
Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler, David Wagner (Eds.) Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts. Volume 2

Transcript of Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler, David ...

Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler, David Wagner (Eds.) Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts. Volume 2

Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society.

New Series

Volume 17

Richard Heinrich • Elisabeth Nemeth

Wolfram Pichler • David Wagner (Editors)

Image and Imaging in Philosophy,

Science and the Arts. Volume 2

Proceedings of the 33rd

International Ludwig Wittgenstein-Symposium in Kirchberg, 2010

Bibliographic information published by Deutsche Nationalbibliothek

The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliographie; detailed bibliographic data is available in the Internet at http://dnb.ddb.de

Gedruckt mit Förderung der Universität Wien,

Fakultät für Philosophie und Bildungswissenschaft, und des Bundesministeriums für Wissenschaft und Forschung in Wien

North and South America by

Transaction Books Rutgers University

Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042 [email protected]

United Kingdom, Ire, Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by Gazelle Books Services Limited

White Cross Mills Hightown

LANCASTER, LA1 4XS [email protected]

Livraison pour la France et la Belgique: Librairie Philosophique J.Vrin

6, place de la Sorbonne ; F-75005 PARIS Tel. +33 (0)1 43 54 03 47 ; Fax +33 (0)1 43 54 48 18

www.vrin.fr

2011 ontos verlag

P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm www.ontosverlag.com

ISBN 978-3-86838-116-0

2011

No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted

in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use of the purchaser of the work

Printed on acid-free paper

ISO-Norm 970-6 FSC-certified (Forest Stewardship Council)

This hardcover binding meets the International Library standard

Printed in Germany by CPI buch bücher.de

Table of Contents

v Preface Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler, David Wagner

Otto Neurath’s Visual Language

1 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath — Popularising or Humanising Knowledge?

Friedrich Stadler

31 The Linguistic Status of Isotype Christopher Burke

59 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language. Otto Neurath on Visualisation in Social Sciences

Elisabeth Nemeth

85 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’ Otto Neurath’s Pictorial Statistics in Historical Context

Sybilla Nikolow

99 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact? Sophie Hochhäusl

137 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond: On Otto Neurath’s Isotype Contributions

to Visual Communication and Museum Learning Hadwig Kraeutler

175 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West Eric Kindel

195 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

Karl H. Müller & Armin Reautschnig

215 Out of the Wild Bart Lootsma

On the Theory and History of Diagrams

229 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

Steffen Bogen

249 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive? Bill Hillier

275 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

Sybille Krämer

295 Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen Andreas Roser

305 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment. Corrollarial and Theorematical Experiments with Diagrams Frederik Stjernfelt

341 Figurenbild und Diagramm. Lot und seine Töchter (Louvre, RF 1185)

Felix Thürlemann

365 Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps David Wagner

377 List of Authors

Preface

This is the second of two volumes containing the proceedings of the conference ‘Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science, and the Arts’, which was organised by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth and Wolfram Pichler, and held as the 33rd International Wittgenstein Symposium in Kirchberg (Austria) in August 2010.

The image, and in particular the status of images and diagrams as cultural and historical phenomena, as artifacts, as objects, or as tools of scientific inter-est, has for some decades been one of the most popular topics in interdisci-plinary academic research. The aim of the Kirchberg conference was to pro-vide a critical survey of the development of, as well as an occasion for more profound investigation into important issues that have been raised in the field. This is not necessarily best achieved by searching for a homogeneous perspec-tive from a single vantage point. Philosophy has still to react to many recent developments in the sciences, in cultural studies and art history which address the topic of the image from different directions. Nonetheless, the significance that the concept of the image has throughout Wittgenstein’s own philosophy, the varieties of aspects of images and diagrams which he discussed or used as examples, gave us important clues for the structuring of both the symposium and the proceedings. The proceedings attest, we think, to the important role played by notions such as ‘seeing-as’, ‘saying/showing’, and ‘image-games’ in various debates on images—debates which are, of course, only in part directly related to Wittgenstein’s work.

The contributions collected in these two volumes cover a wide range of disciplines, from philosophy, psychology, and sociology to history of sci-ence, art history, and poetology. The first volume consists of (1) papers dedicated to various aspects of Wittgenstein’s philosophy, especially but not

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, v–vi.

vi Preface

exclusively to questions of picture-theory, (2) further studies in the history and theory of the image. This second volume is also structured in two parts. Its philosophical protagonist is Otto Neurath, and it addresses more generally the expanding field of ‘diagrammatology’ (to use Tom Mitchell’s neologism). It contains (1) papers first presented at the workshop ‘Picturing Social Facts. Otto Neurath’s Visual Language’, organised by Elisabeth Nemeth and Friedrich Sta-dler. This first part begins with two papers discussing Neurath’s concept of a visual language and its historical background. The following papers present, in chronological order, some specific applications of the Isotype method, while the last two contributions draw our attention to possible further applications of Neurath’s ideas. In addition, this volume also includes (2) papers which were delivered in sections on the topics of diagrammatic representation, mapping and modelling.

Inevitably, there are thematic overlaps between the two volumes, and not every decision which had to be taken in view of their composition was an obvious one. Besides, technical considerations had to be given their due (illus-trations in colour had to be restricted to the second volume). We are nonethe-less confident that, in the majority of cases, contributions of related interest are neighbours in the volumes’ topology.

Our thanks go to Friedrich Stadler for co-organising the workshop on Neurath’s visual language, to the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society (ALWS) for its confidence and organisational support, and last but not least to the authors for their participation, enthusiasm, and many inspiring insights.

Vienna, February 2011

Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler, David WagnerUniversity of Vienna

Otto Neurath’s Visual Language∂

Otto Neuraths Bildsprache

Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath—Popularising or

Humanising Knowledge?

Friedrich Stadler, Vienna

The ‘Vienna method of pictorial statistics’, created by Otto Neurath (1882–1945) and his team in the Social and Economic Museum in Vienna (1925–1934) and developed, after his forced emigration, into the ‘Isotype’ (International System Of TYpographic Picture Education), constitutes to this day a relevant contribution to educational work and the communication of knowledge and science. The reconstruction and renewing of this Enlightenment concept through both pictures and writing, within the context of a ‘scientific world conception’ and the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, offers a fruit-ful perspective on the current possibilities and limits of visual communication between ‘science and the public’.

The integration, as pushed for by Neurath, of this picture language of ‘figurative constructivism’ (Gerd Arntz) into a comprehensive critical concept in the tradition of Comenius, Leibniz and the French encyclopédistes, run-ning all the way to the Vienna Circle, leads to a remarkable, but unfortunately incomplete treatise on ‘Visual education: humanisation versus popularisation’ (Neurath 1945) as a model for a modern museology. Neurath’s posthumous publication, a comprehensive sketch of a cultural history of Visual Education (excerpts of which were printed in 1973, the complete version in 1996), served as an illustration of this topic and can in hindsight be fairly judged a concrete contribution towards highlighting the relation between science, politics and the public. Fortunately, his visual autobiography was published in the meantime and is accompanied by recent research.1

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 1–30.

2 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

The fact that, at present, written and picture languages are mostly con-ceived of as alternatives only has not been offset by a noticeable trend towards a ‘visual turn’ either:2 an interdisciplinary ‘visualistics’ as the study of images, or imaging science, seems more like a compensation for the powerful influ-ence of communication, and an appendix to computer sciences, than a well-founded investigation of the two correlative areas of word and image taking place within the context of public demand for the popularisation of knowledge and science.3 The tension and complex relations between science and public are also impacted upon by the method of imparting knowledge and infor-mation, in which—similar to the TV and the Internet—visualisation brings about a strong polarisation between producers and consumers.4 It seems all the more surprising that a comprehensive practical and theoretical contribution to picture language and museology has only been noticed by a small number of experts—a contribution which is associated with the life and work of Otto Neurath. There may be historical reasons for this, to do with Neurath’s being driven into exile three times and his early death, but also to do with theoretical reservations and deficiencies grounded in ahistorical specialisation and typologising of language and its research. Against this backdrop, a critical reconstruction of Neurath’s ‘visual education’ is not only a contribution to the history of education and science but also constitutes an assessment relevant to today’s discourse on the ‘knowledge society’. It can both help prevent a nostalgic enshrining of ‘Austrian intellectual history’ and break up a perspective rigidly fixed on individual disciplines.5

Historical Interconnections

The ‘Vienna method of pictorial statistics’ constituted a significant attempt to generate knowledge about socio-economic correlations for a broad public using picture language and diagrams, and was intended to serve as a communi-cative medium within the wider framework of the associated ‘Social and Economic Museum’. However these phenomena of ‘Red Vienna’s’ education movement were not intended to be isolated instruments of popularisation following the motto ‘knowledge is power’ but were rather always designed to be a part of a neo-enlightenment ‘scientific world-view’, which must be under-stood as an essential component of the encyclopædia movement up until the outbreak of the Second World War. We are therefore dealing with a thematic

3Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

development of Jan Amos Comenius’s Orbis Pictus such as was intended by its author, and of the French Encyclopédie. (Incidentally, the latter’s image plates alone guarantee a certain æsthetic pleasure, but they offer no purposeful over-view of the corpus of referential knowledge. 6) Furthermore it seems that the mature versions of picture language, in the form of Isotype, made a fruit-ful contribution to the debate on popularisation, challenging all ‘top-down’ models of didactics in terms of epistemology and education policies.

Neurath described the typical ‘Vienna atmosphere’, which would be partly responsible for the development of logical empiricism.

While the idea of German nationalism was dominant in university circles, there were among other intellectuals many who stood apart from the nationalist way

Fig. 1

Precursor of the modern schoolbook:

Jan Amos Comenius’s Orbis Sensualium Pictus

(1685)

Fig. 2

Image plates as æsthetic add-on:

Denis Diderot‘s Encyclopédie

(1772)

4 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

of thinking and who subscribed mainly to the ideas of Liberalism, but later also to those of socialism, of utilitarianism, pragmatism, and empiricism, in a mixture of varying proportions.’ 10

With this, people such as Rudolf Goldscheid, Theodor and Heinrich Gomperz, Friedrich Jodl, Wilhelm Jerusalem or Friedrich Adler represented both the ‘opponents of traditional thinking’, but also intellectuals of (mostly anti-Kantian) modern ‘scientism’ in Austria, which sprang from four roots: anti-metaphysics, empiricist views of a general sort, the inclination towards the systematic inclusion of logic, and the mathematization of the sciences. This self-conception is already reflected in the programme of the Vienna Circle (1929):11

Thanks to this spirit of enlightenment, Vienna has been leading in a scien-tifically oriented people’s education (Volksbildung). With the collaboration of Victor Adler and Friedrich Jodl, the society for popular education was founded and carried forth; ‘popular university courses’ and the ‘people’s college’ were set up by the well-known historian Ludo Hartmann whose anti-metaphysical attitude and materialist conception of history expressed itself in all his actions. The same spirit also inspired the movement of the ‘Free School’ which was the forerunner of today’s school reform.11

This was not just a declaration of intent; we have documentary evidence of the vital participation of Vienna Circle members (especially Hans Hahn, Viktor Kraft, Otto Neurath, Friedrich Waismann, Edgar Zilsel) in adult education and school reform in Vienna (Edgar Zilsel and Karl Popper) from the turn of the twentieth century.12 The most effective manifestation of this cooperation was unquestionably the work of the ‘Social and Economic Museum in Vienna’ founded by Neurath, which—together with the Ernst Mach Society—both aided the development of a specific picture language, and served as a platform for discussion circles on the periphery of the Vienna Circle. Here, in theory and in practice, social reform and work on education merged to form a creative field of experimentation within modernity that lasted until the wrecking of democracy starting in 1933–34.

One tried and tested thought experiment, using a counterfactual method, is to reflect on what could have been expected of Neurath and his colleagues had they lived longer, especially with regards the catastrophic outcome of

5Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Fascism and National Socialism: as left-wing and enlightened intellectuals of Jewish origin, they would have been forced to reorient themselves and take stock of the situation; in the case of Neurath, in exile in Holland and England, this had already led to concrete answers (for example with his planned book on ‘Persecution and Tolerance’). And in the case of all of these leading figures the project of an ‘enlightenment in Viennese modernity’ is a topic of discussion even now in the postmodern present.13

On Otto Neurath (1882–1945): Between Encyclopædia and Utopia

The research on one of the most brilliant all-round intellects of modern Vienna meanwhile amounts to a substantial sum total, which can hardly be given in a brief account.14 Neurath’s life and work between ‘encyclo-pædia and utopia’ points to the continuities and breaks in social development since the turn of the century (during the struggle between revolution and reform) and the project of creating a scientific picture of the world in the spirit of the Enlightenment and in the context of modern civil society. In historicising this exemplary life-story of Austrian intellectual emigration,

Fig. 3Otto Neurath

(c. 1938)

6 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

there emerge relevant and essential elements of his future work in educa-tion and understanding of science, which can be outlined only by a few key words: a non-hierarchical picture of science (for instance the allegory of the ship’s captain popularised by Quine) together with a relativistic and non-reductionist epistemology, an empiricism (naturalism) that regarded the difference between everyday and scientific knowledge as one of degree, a single overarching perspective on specialisation and popularisation in words and pictures, and, especially, research and education as the subject and object of a cooperative scientific praxis with a constant demand for societal change. Accordingly, this unfulfilled and fragmentary project of modernity is thematised, in all its facets, in the present day: in the philosophy of science and science research, in the ecological perspective in political economy, in architecture and the social housing movement, in modern commercial art and typography, and finally in the present-day construction of museums as social ‘museums of the future’.15

It is no accident that the most recent literature on Neurath’s life’s work is international and inter-disciplinary and, similarly, lies at the interstitial points of tension between modern and postmodern diction.16 These disparate perspectives, which demonstrate the absurdity of the long-prevailing quarrel about positivism, are gradually providing the building blocks for his concep-tion of his own life and research, understood as a dynamic undertaking in his contemporary environment such that the ‘producers’ of science were them-selves made part of the epistemological process (the ‘Republic of Letters’), abandoning an absolute meta-perspective. From this vantage point alone it is easy to imagine how this conception would have interfered in past debates on the ‘science wars’. In view of the limitations and fragility of our context-dependent knowledge it would not have been an ‘Enlightenment dialectic’ but rather a critique of it as a partial answer to the experience of totali-tarianism and the Shoah.17 At the same time, this epistemological approach means renouncing every secure system of science and knowledge, connected with thinking in alternative utopias of science/society, which certainly corresponds with a conception of possibility according to Robert Musil. This is the background to the vociferous Anti-Spengler’s postulating a plan for the establishment of freedom, happiness, and prosperity.18 Today—after the economic crisis and in an age of globalisation and corporate planning—this is, again, a highly topical demand, appealing both as an alternative to laissez-faire capitalism, and to a challenged New Economy.

7Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

‘Words divide—pictures unite’: on the ‘Vienna method of pictorial statistics’ up to Isotype (Vienna – Holland – England)

In 1925 on Otto Neurath’s initiative the ‘Social and Economic Museum of Vienna’ (Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum in Wien, or GWM) was founded.19 The members of this association were the Municipality of Vienna, the Free Trade Unions, the Chamber of Workers and Employees, the Cooperative Societies, the social security institutions, and the Workers’ Bank. This new kind of institution, which was to be an ‘educational museum of the present day’ for the knowledge and understanding of socio-economic correl-ations, ran regular exhibitions in the Festival Hall of the new city hall, as well as in the first and twelfth districts of Vienna. Up to 1933 thirty-six national and international exhibitions were organised there or supplied with material.

Fig. 4

One of the first

advertisements for the

Social and Economic

Museum of Vienna

(1925)

8 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

The topics presented there convey an impressive picture of systematic encyclopædism, the work towards popular education that had been carried out in the spirit of social reform: health, women and children, social poli-tics, housing and urban planning, peace education, schooling, the workers’ movement, art, social security, architecture, etc. Along with this there were independent touring exhibitions at home and abroad, as well as separate publications and articles in various periodicals and books. In 1927 Josef Frank, brother of Philipp Frank, was acquired for the museum as an architect, and a year later Neurath employed the artist and designer Gerd Arntz, who drew the characteristic symbols and systematised the production techniques. The scientific department under Aloys Fischer, the ‘Transformation’ department under Marie Reidemeister (later Marie Neurath) and the technical collaborators completed the team. For several years the innovative Social and Economic Museum cultivated a working partnership with Otto Glöckel’s social-democrat school-reform movement. This enabled the GWM to contribute to the cultural life of Vienna by making an impact on visual education. Additionally, in Holland in 1931 the ‘Mundaneum’ was founded with the aim of inten-sifying international collaboration. Branches were set up in Berlin, Amster-dam, Prague, New York, London, and the Soviet Union.20 Following this phase of productive work at home and abroad came the end of the GWM after the political events of 12th February 1934. Several functionaries were arrested, and valuable fittings were confiscated. The renamed ‘Austrian Institute for Pictorial Statistics’ remained under the control of the Austro-fascist corporative state, until the National Socialists seized this institution for their own propaganda purposes. Despite these confiscations Neurath was able to transfer a large amount of valuable holdings to Holland and England.

The fundamental objective of the ‘Vienna method of pictorial statistics’ was to represent socio-economic facts and correlations, particularly with regard to their historical development, in a simple, easily graspable system of symbolic figures.21 A range of real things and complex facts was to be re- presented by means of a fixed range of signs and symbols, in which the same sign would always be used for the same object. This method of visualisa-tion therefore arose from the coinciding of content and size as well as from a mapping of sets, such that a larger set of objects was represented by a larger set of signs without perspective. In this way—said Neurath—the facts about society could be reflected quantitatively.22 The method, developed and improved following his emigration to Holland, was, with the change in

9Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

circumstances, renamed the International System of Typographic Picture Education, with the acronym Isotype (which was also the Greek for ‘always the same sign’).23

In a memorandum (1924) Neurath developed his concrete ideas of an ‘educational museum of the present day’, which would facilitate knowledge and understanding of societal correlations. The (epistemological-)theoretical background of pictorial statistics possibly lies in the visualisation of logical empiricism, as the arrangement of images was meant to portray facts about society quantitatively. Likewise deserving a mention as part of the background knowledge are the ‘empirio-criticism’ of Mach and physicalism, since the non-dialectical form of representation—as expression of abstract sociological categories—was to correspond to the unemotional and neutral description of relations demanded by logical empiricism.24 At the same time, both picto-rial statistics and Isotype must be seen as part of a broader nexus within the context of Neurath’s work: his greatest interest was in making a comprehen-sive contribution to general, international education. Corresponding to this cosmopolitan and egalitarian claim was the idea of an encyclopædia, which following his emigration Neurath attempted to put into practice through the Unity of Science movement. This aim formed no less a part of his emanci-patory concept of social enlightenment through visual education, being a necessary premise for the ‘humanisation’ of life.25 For that reason pictorial statistics was only a part of the wider work in general education, and school and adult education only one of the contexts in which it was applied.

In Holland further well-attended exhibitions were organised, but—because of the impending Second World War—despite significant publications26 the mass impact that had been hoped for was no longer achievable. The escape of Neurath and Marie Reidemeister to England in 1940 brought an end to activity on the continent, while Gerd Arntz remained in Holland where he continued to work alone after 1945.27 After the death of her husband, Marie Neurath continued this productive work in Oxford with the newly founded ‘Isotype Institute’ and moved to London in 1948. Despite the unfavourable circumstances this was not entirely in vain, as today teaching and research in the tradition of the Vienna method of pictorial statistics and Isotype con-tinues at the University of Reading in a department dedicated exclusively to modern typography and visual communication.28

In 1928 Otto Neurath engaged the German Gerd Arntz as a designer, which signalled the beginning of an innovative collaboration that was to last

10 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Fig. 5

Diagram designed by Gerd Arntz,

originator of a ‘figurative-constructivist

graphic style’

Fig. 6

Survey

depicting the

international

activities of

Isotype

11Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

many years.29 Before this period Arntz had already marked himself out in the art world of the Weimar Republic as a member of the ‘Rhine Group of Progressive Artists’ (1918–1933) with an original socio-critical, figurative- constructivist graphic style. After the First World War he benefited from a specialist education amid the post-revolutionary climate of the young repub-lic (especially in Düsseldorf) and came into contact with Cologne’s circles of artists. After that Arntz collaborated again with Peter Alma and August Tschinkel, among others, at the GWM, and from 1919 to 1933 published work in a-z, the theoretical mouthpiece of the Constructivists. There followed further international exhibitions and—as a corollary of the GWM’s activi-ties in Moscow at the beginning of the thirties—contacts with the Russian avant-garde. Following the events of February 1934, and finding himself in danger, the artist emigrated with Neurath to the Hague and, alongside his demanding work at the Mundaneum Institute there, took part in the anti- fascist opposition movement (as well as in an exhibition in London and the Amsterdam exhibition De Olympiade Onder Dictatuur [‘The Olympic Games under the Dictatorship’]). It was in Holland that Arntz, together with Neurath, was able to achieve the apogee of the Bildstatistik output with the success of the book Modern Man in the Making (1939). During the war Arntz continued to work as lead designer for the ‘Dutch Foundation for Statistics’ (Nederlandse Stichting voor Statistik). Following his conscription by the Germany army he escaped to the Resistence in Paris, and was held as a prisoner of war. After the Second World War Arntz, now in changed circumstances, again resumed his commercial and artistic graphic work. Alongside the usual social commentary of his work there was also pictorial-statistical work for UNESCO, while from the end of the sixties his political graphic work would receive renewed inter-national interest.

If Arntz’s first woodcuts were still located in the expressionist tradition, his work from the twenties was already abstract-constructivist. He integrated elements of the French Cubists (Ferdinand Leger) until he came to achieve a distinctive profile of his own within the ‘Group of Progressives’. The com-mon characteristics of this Cologne group—among them Heinrich Hoerle, Franz W. Seiwert, Hans Schmitz, August Tschinkel, among others—were an æsthetic affinity centred on the use of figurative-constructivist picture-forms, a shared political (liberal-communist) outlook with a programmatic yoking of art and politics, the cultural background of the Rhine region, and finally the members’ conception of themselves as forming a coherent whole.30

12 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

In accordance with the intensive response to the Russian revolution (Lunatscharski, Bogdanov, El Lissitzky, among others) joint exhibitions were organised in the Weimar Republic, which were marked by the post- revolutionary spirit. In their periodical the Constructivists also critiqued the New Objectivity (Neue Sachlichkeit), but they cultivated close contacts with Bauhaus artists—as did, incidentally, Neurath, Carnap and other members of the Vienna Circle. Here we must also mention another co-founder of modern typography, Jan Tschichold, whose influence can be detected in the typical figurative-constructivist picture-forms of Gerd Arntz and in the graphic design of the pictorial statistics. The principle held by Arntz, who opposed, for instance, the ‘psychologism’ of an Otto Dix or George Grosz, went thus: ‘make everything impersonal, use templates, be a constructor.’ In this we can detect the influence of the Japanese woodcut, the French purists, and the Dutch group ‘de Stijl’ (Piet Mondrian) between realism and objectivity.

Figs. 7 & 8

Principles and application of

the ‘Vienna method of pictorial

statistics’

13Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

As already mentioned, pictorial statistics were especially suited to pedagogic reform, such that for many years Neurath and his co-workers nurtured a productive collaboration with the Vienna school-reform movement. The school reform from 1918 to 1934, initiated by Otto Glöckel, represented an attempt to reform the traditional school system, with its state and church-dominated drill schools, and to set up secular ‘labour schools’ elsewhere, in which teaching would be carried out according to egalitarian and socially just methods. Here the educational principles of intellectual autonomy and practical relevance, of clarity and conciseness in education, as well as of an æsthetic education with a scientifically thorough under-pinning played a large role. Pictorial statistics very much complied with these objectives. As early as the 1920s Neurath had stressed grasping the notion of the ‘statistical age’ as a teaching objective, and, subsequently, in a handful of articles and with systematic treatment in his 1933 book Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule (The Vienna Method of Pictorial Statistics in School), summarised the methods and principles, as well as the possibilities of applying them in a school setting. Practical cooperation culminated in the decision of the Vienna municipal school council to have pictorial statistics tested in a special experi-mental school.

This was preceded by the steady work of the GWM:31 statistics was included as a subject in school syllabuses on a trial basis, and the GWM itself had already made ‘intellectual life and schools’ a permanent topic area within its ‘contexts and culture’ department. Various school classes visited this educational museum, and visual-education experiments were carried out as early as the nursery stage. The collaboration also bore fruit in terms of pub-lications, particularly with the periodical Das Bild im Dienste der Schule, with a GWM supplement that ran from 1927 to 1930. The use of pictorial statistics was articulated most impressively by the publications Die bunte Welt (1929) and Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft. Bildstatistisches Elementarwerk des GWM in Wien (1930). In the Ernst Mach Society and in various newspaper articles Neurath tried in addition to disseminate these reformist ideas. With the start of the school experiments further activities were set,32 until February 1934 saw the final failure of the school reform project; the above-mentioned dissolution of the GWM, as it then existed, soon followed.

The contribution of the GWM to didactic methodology and visual education had already been laid out by Neurath in his book Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule (1933): social enlightenment through training of

14 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

the intellect along with the nurturing of children’s drawing and design skills. His pictures of sets were successfully trialled at the Montessori Kindergarten and Montessori school in Vienna. The emphasis on praxis also led to affin-ity with the Freinet system of pedagogy that was then being developed in France, which put into practice the idea of ‘labour schools’, particularly by means of their school printing presses. The objective of the didactical experi-ments begun in the school years 1930/31 and 1931/32 was to optimise ‘ways and means’ in concrete educational environments across different subjects. They covered four classes of schoolchildren, and the experiences were shared during many conferences, so that numerous parties interested from home and abroad came to visit these classes. The conclusion of this project took the form of an exhibition on the pictures of sets that had been made as well as the teachers’ final reports. Here it was established that an introduction and a certain amount of time would be needed. Across all subjects multiple methods were used, from the presentation of prepared pictures of sets to their produc-tion by the pupils themselves. The disadvantages reported were, according to subject, the necessity of drastically rounding up the numbers, the amount of work required, as well as its unsuitability for the teaching of German. The advantages mentioned were the scope for working autonomously, the consoli-dation of the pupils’ knowledge of the material at the end of the problem-solving, the connecting of different subjects, the increase in motivation, and, in particular, its usefulness in the subject of history.

The key to the long-overdue reconstruction and updating of both writing and image, in the context of the scientific world-view, is Neurath’s publica-tions on visual education.33 Using them we can systematically pursue both the theoretical development and the development of the picture language of this inter-disciplinary and collaborative educational undertaking, and link current revisiting of this potential to the methods, principles and contents of pictorial statistics. Neurath’s writings on visual education similarly represent an excel-lent field of study for inter-disciplinary and collective work on science and education. In numerous illustrated articles, brochures and books Neurath describes the history of the Social and Economic Museum as an organisa-tion, and also the concomitant story of the internal theoretical and practical development of picture language from pictorial statistics to a visual peda-gogy integrating writing and symbols. Here we can see the connections at its origin with the Vienna cultural movement as well as the interlinking of the principles of this popular education project with the logical empiricism of

15Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

the Vienna Circle and with the artistic work of the figurative constructivists around Gerd Arntz.

The programmatic titles of Neurath’s specific writings alone convey a sense of the intentions and socio-political orientation of this conception, which became an international one from 1930.34 The pictorial representa-tion of social facts with the help of ‘statistical hieroglyphs’ would concisely and informatively explain society in all its aspects with a view to improving ‘living conditions’. The scope of topics therefore extends from home, the real-ity of the world of work, housing and urban planning, to economic considera-tions on social welfare. From a modern-day perspective the monographs Bild-statistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule (1933), Internationale Bildersprache/ International Picture Language (1936), and finally his most mature work Modern Man in the Making (1939)/Auf dem Weg zum modernen Menschen (1991) are of special interest. In these numerous pictograms are used to treat the theory and application of picture language along with written language. In addition, with his essay ‘Museums of the Future’ (1933) Neurath laid out a programme for a modern sociological and economic museum that remains impressive to this day, and which can be interpreted as the antithesis of the postmodern ‘hands on’ museums, the collections of devotional objects, and the contrived ‘total works of art’:

From Comenius’ Orbis Pictus an uninterrupted movement leads to modern visual education. A picture made according to the Vienna method shows at the first glance the most important aspect of the subject; obvious differences must be at once distinguishable. At the second glance, it should be possible to see the more important details; and at the third glance, whatever details there may be. A picture that has still further information to give at the fourth and fifth glance is, from the point of view of the Vienna school, to be rejected as pedagogically unsuitable. Thus a new clarity and purposefulness is developing in communication that may be regarded as preparation for more incisive social planning. Teachers and other groups of people concerned in social education, directors of museums, and editors of periodicals are confronted with the responsibility of placing their energies at the service of this common international task.35

The all too early death of Neurath prevented the completion of his socio- historical monograph on picture language, which was published posthumously

16 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Fig. 11

Advertising leaflet to promote the

use of Isotype in the 15-volume

Compton Pictured Encyclopedia,

Chicago 1939 (F. E. Compton & Co.)

Fig. 10

Social criticism by means

of graphic art: work by Gerd Arntz (1927/28)

Fig. 9

One of the few articles written

by Gerd Arntz explaining the

‘Vienna method’ (1930)

17Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

only in 2010. With these publications we can reconstruct the aims of this eman-cipatory visual education and evaluate the road ahead that was implied by ‘From hieroglyphics to Isotype’ 36 (1946) as well as an unfinished manuscript titled ‘Visual Education: Humanisation versus Popularisation’.37 The latter discusses the possibility of a non-hierarchical international picture language, which through its neutrality imposes tolerance on education and at the same time makes possible a humanisation in opposition to authoritative popularisation:

We must begin our explanations in accordance with the knowledge and vocabu-lary already familiar to the people. Gradually simple traditional expressions in more complicated combinations and perhaps some more advanced terms may be introduced. But in principle, one should try to build up more comprehensive knowledge by simply looking at the environment, and by using the language of daily life and its derivatives. This procedure from the simplest to the most complicated, I shall call humanisation. Generally speaking, the average books destined for children and the man in the street start in a different way. They try to simplify the highest level of scientific formulation, presented in scientific books. Sometimes writers think

Fig. 12

Contents page of Neurath’s

unfinished manuscript “Visual

Education: Humanisation versus

Popularisation” (1946)

18 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Fig. 10

Cover and double spread (pages 20 to 21) of International Picture Language (1936)

Fig. 9

Cover of Society and Economy, a publication containing 100 coloured plates of

pictorial statistics developed for the GWM (1930)

19Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

that a translation of well selected terms into popular terms is sufficient, whereas it is common knowledge that the insufficiency of these terms was the main reason for the introduction of scientific terms. This kind of translation from the complicated to the simple, from top to bottom, as it were, I shall call popularisation of knowledge. In the humanisation of knowledge one tries to avoid what may be called an inferiority complex as well as all kinds of frustration which so often appear when people try to grasp a piece of knowledge in vain. Looking at a book often creates a kind of fear. There are not a few people who become uneasy when confronted with a general term like ‘magnetism’ but who would not be irritated by hearing about magnets and iron. Humanisation implies avoiding technical terms before they are really needed. The question is how far we can go without using more complicated expressions. […]All statements which speak of seeing, hearing, touching, tasting, etc., appeal to the average man, because every sensual statement is possible in the common neutral and democratic language.38

Here, visualisation is presented as an essential means of aiding cross-cultural communication, which takes as its starting point people’s everyday con-crete world and, acting as a building block, enables the construction of a social museum of the present that is, as it were, cosmopolitan in character (‘Mundaneum’). Equally apparent was the cooperative and international element of such an educational project, and this—against the spirit of the times—expressed the democratic idea of a ‘plan for freedom’:

Visual education leads to internationalisation much more than word education does. One can use the same visual arguments, connected with different words for explanation in various languages; one can even vary the remarks on the same visual material. Visual education is related to the extension of intellectual democracy within single communities and within mankind, it is an element of international social planning and engineering. This is a period of planning, planning for getting something done, where without planning defects are manifest, such as destruction of coffee, un- employment, etc. But we can remove all this without regional planning, without city planning; we can imagine a nation with planned production as far as raw materials are concerned, but also building up ‘planning for freedom’, which signifies intentionally not interfering. Much city planning is full of pomposity,

20 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Fig. 11

Covers of Fernunterricht, a subscription magazine for distance learning,

each dedicated to an individual topic. (1931/32)

21Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

with a totalitarian undercurrent, pressing forward some way of life. Perhaps people want to do so; but the dictatorship of planning is a danger in itself and is not connected with planning against want. You may be in security, but free to choose your kind of life within this security. The either-or is important. We may create certain conventions in language without unifying the laws; a world language does not imply a world dictatorship but may help world understand-ing. For a democratic society it is important to have a common language.39

While the Vienna Method of Pictorial Statistics was relatively well known in its theoretical and practical application in school contexts, a parallel initiative in adult education received little attention: from 1931 to 1933 the GWM in Vienna regularly published the Fernunterricht (retitled Bildstatistik from 1932), a series of distance education booklets issued as subscriptions, with each dedi-cated to an individual topic.40 As this series of publications for popular educa-tion was not reprinted in the Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften, due to its purely non-theoretical, applied approach, a brief characterisation is pre-sented below. From today’s perspective one can treat these brochures with their changing topics as foundation stones, or defining landmarks, in the field of social history. As it emerges from the preface, there was particular emphasis on user-friendly orientation and the invitation to provide feedback, which helps in creating an interest-oriented mode of communication that puts the participants on an equal footing:

Der Fernunterricht is dedicated to anyone endeavouring to acquire new know-ledge, and especially to adult educationalists and teachers who impart their knowledge to a narrower circle. Newspapers and periodicals are not able to devote their attention to the systematic training of the readers; the former give us ephemeral information on the day’s events, the latter thorough discussion concerning specific questions. Not everyone has the time and energy to form this into a well-ordered overview and to acquire the necessary information to complement his/her knowledge. This is what der Fernunterricht intends to do. Lack of time compels learners and teachers to look for concise summaries. For this pictures are a great advantage. They demonstrate, clearly and quickly, even to those with the little preliminary knowledge, what is essential. The ‘Vienna Method of Pictorial Statistics’, which has already proved its worth interna-tionally, combines objectivity and easy memorability. In view of all this, der Fernunterricht offers not prettily written articles, detailed discussions, but very

22 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

concise substantial material and images, which will not be easily forgotten. The reader can gradually construct his own compilations of individual issues of der Fernunterricht to suit his own particular purposes. Der Fernunterricht can be easily cut up, as every section ends with a full page. Society, life, engineering and science are covered, and the reader can find out which path he should take to obtain specific information, and what shortcuts are possible. Students of the Arbeiterhochschule (Vienna College for Workers), whose colleagues far from Vienna suffer from a lack of educational resources, turned to the ‘Social and Economic Museum of Vienna’, which has a scientific department, and suggested the creation of a distance learning course which is hereby published, in expanded form, for a wider circle. 41

Neurath then goes on to give an account of the connectedness between science and popular education, which, according to his thinking, could be brought about through the empirical view of science.42

The Fernunterricht magazine was especially important in publishing the GWM’s pictures of sets, such as those, for instance, from the elementary work in pictorial statistics Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft (Society and Economy, 1930); they were accompanied by introductions and explanations, which could be obtained by post as transparencies and off-prints. An inserted page for questions and suggestions from readers facilitated free correspond-ence concerning particular issues of the magazine, and hence regular feedback from subscribers. Selected questions were answered in writing in the following issues. Going by reactions to it, the undertaking was a success, which was also noted abroad. The political turning points of 1934 and 1938 finally brought about the disappearance of this enlightenment tradition in Austria, and after 1945 it fell into oblivion. It is no coinci-dence that it was in England, where the bourgeois enlightenment brought about egalitarian concepts of education, that Neurath’s ambitions struck fertile soil. Thus Neurath was able to present the importance of visual education vis-à-vis popular education in several articles in the periodicals of adult education organisations.43 Above all the article ‘Visual aids in adult education’ (1944) ran the gamut from Comenius to modern picture language and its role in the struggle against superficial knowledge, illiteracy and the confinement to simplistic reading material; his argument was supported by a web of various ‘visual arguments’, and ended with a perfectly realistic, but still unrealised vision:

23Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

It seems to be within the reach of our generation to support a future commonwealth in a practical manner. Of course the network of argu-ments conveyed by means of Isotype is much smaller than that conveyed by literature, but it may be of a similar kind. Should all these international day-dreams of an intellectual world of the common man not be realized, the introduction of visual education in schools and adult education classes seems nevertheless to promote an atmosphere of argumentative meditation and of some peacefulness.44

Current international research into the field of visual communication and general semiotics confirms to an impressive degree the viability of develop-ing Neurath’s approach further.45 Following the further development made in the Anglo-American world, slowly but surely in German-speaking areas, too, attention is turning to this innovative tradition of the ‘Vienna Method’, as demonstrated by the new discoveries, and the rediscovery, of Neurath’s life and work.46

Outlook

The contemporary relevance of picture language after Otto Neurath in the context of science, politics and the public can only be outlined here. His model of a combined visualisation and museology, against a linear and hierarchical popularisation of knowledge and science, is manifest in at least four overlapping research areas:

1. In perception research, starting from the static diagram (as a ‘visual argument’) all the way to the TV screen and film application.47

2. In reconstruction within a general inter-disciplinary semiotics which had begun to show itself at the time in the cooperation with the Dutch significs around Gerrit Mannoury for the journal Synthese.48

3. In the critical assessment of the correlative relationship between society and science which is apparent, for instance, in the new works on the potential of the encyclopædist project.49

4. In its applicability in the area of the social sciences and the alternative political economy, which does not restrict the criteria for progress and wealth to money alone.50

24 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Concerted work on this loose programme after Neurath would once more show the limits and possibilities of building and rebuilding a ship, a task which would only be possible through cooperation and a continuous division of labour in a joint and endless project. But that, of course, is the fate of every conception of science, which is in principle sceptical vis-à-vis the demands for a single method and a single rationality. The late W. V. O. Quine recognised this fact as far as philosophy is concerned, when he used Neurath’s sailor simile—outside its historical and thematic context—as a motto for his book:

Wie Schiffer sind wir, die ihr Schiff auf offener See umbauen müssen, ohne es jemals in einem Dock zerlegen und aus besten Bestandteilen neu errichten zu können.

We are like sailors who must rebuild the ship on the open sea, never able to dismantle it in dry-dock and to reconstruct it there out of the best materials.51

25Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Notes

This article is a translated and revised version of my ‘Schriftsprache und Bildsprache nach Otto Neurath—Popularisierung oder Humanisierung des Wissens?’, in: Wissenschaft, Politik und Öffentlichkeit. Von der Wiener Moderne bis zur Gegenwart. Edited by Mitchell G. Ash and Christian H. Stifter (Wien: Facultas, 2002), 267–303. I am grateful to Naomi Osorio-Kupferblum (Vienna) and Bryn Harris (Oxford) for their valuable translation work.

1 Otto Neurath, From Hieroglyphics to Isotype. A Visual Autobiography, edited by Christopher Burke and Matthew Eve (London: Hyphen Press, 2010). Also: Hadwig Kraeutler, Otto Neurath and Exhibition Work. Spaces (Designed) for Communication. (Frankfurt/M.-Berlin-Bern-Bruxelles-New York-Oxford: Peter Lang, 2008). The most sytematic documentation and research is done at the University of Reading, Department of Typography and Graphic Communication, especially the ‘Isotype revisited’ project: www.isotyperevisited.org

2 As an example of the growing interest in visualisation see the series Philosophie & Repräsentation/Philosophy & Representation, edited by Petra Gehring/Jörg Maas (Amsterdam-Atlanta, GA: Rodopi, 1992 ff.). Also: Johanna Hofbauer, Gerald Prabitz, Josef Wallmansberger (eds.), Bilder–Symbole–Metaphern. Visualisierung und Informierung in der Moderne (Vienna: Passagen, 1995).

3 Symptomatic for a rather naïve euphoria, the description: ‘Die Wissenschaft von der visuellen Wende’ (‘The study of the visual turn’), in: Die Zeit, 6 December 1996, 35. A more recent, trans-disciplinary discussion in the context of Science Studies: Caroline A. Jones, Peter Galison (eds.), Picturing Science–Producing Art (New York-London: Routledge, 1998).

4 As a general discussion of the cultural position of visualisation see: Johannes Domsich, Visualisierung. Ein kulturelles Defizit? Der Konflikt von Sprache, Schrift und Bild. Vienna-Cologne-Weimar: Böhlau 1991.

5 Still a fruitful gloss: Karl H. Müller, Symbole, Statistik, Computer, Design. Otto Neuraths Bildpädagogik im Computerzeitalter (Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1991).

6 Neurath himself referred to this connection time and again in his writings. For a systematic comparison of the relationship between pictorial statistics and Neurath’s modern encyclopædia, see Karl H. Müller, Symbole, 10, and Dahms ‘ “Interna-tional Encyclopedia of Unified Science” als Torso’ in Elisabeth Nemeth/Richard Heinrich (eds.), Otto Neurath: Rationalität, Planung, Vielfalt (Berlin: Oldenburg und Akademie Verlag, 1999), 184–227. For a research-oriented history of his life and

26 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

work, see Kurt Blaukopf, ‘Kunstforschung als exakte Wissenschaft. Von Diderot zur Enzyklopädie des Wiener Kreises’, in: Friedrich Stadler (ed.), Elemente moderner Wissenschaftstheorie. Zur Interaktion von Philosophie, Geschichte und Theorie der Wissen-schaften (Vienna-New York: Springer, 2000), 177–211.

7 For the few biographical details we have cf. the entry on him in Philosophen-Lexikon. Handwörterbuch der Philosophie nach Personen, edited by W. Ziegenfuss (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1949), 395: ‘Goldscheid, Rudolf, born 12th August in Vienna, died 6th October 1931 in Vienna. Sympathised with Monism. In 1909 he founded the German Sociological Association.’—With regard to the current research on Goldscheid, who was also a founder member of the Vienna Sociological Associa-tion in 1907, on social reform and social sciences see: Christian Fleck, ‘Rund um Marienthal’ Von den Anfängen der Soziologie in Österreich bis zu ihrer Vertreibung (Vienna: Verlag für Gesellschaftskritik, 1990). And on fiscal sociology see especially: Rudolf Goldscheid and Josef Schumpeter, Die Finanzkrise des Steuerstaates. Beiträge zur politischen Ökonomie, edited by Rudolf Hickel (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1976). Ingrid Belke, Die sozialreformerischen Ideen von Josef Popper-Lynkeus (1838–1921) im Zusammenhang mit allgemeinen Reformbestrebungen des Wiener Bürgertums um die Jahr-hundertwende (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 1978).

8 Triggered by his article ‘Die Pflanzstätten der Wissenschaft als Brutstätten der Reaktion’, first published in: Monistische Monatshefte (Hamburg 1923), later in: Arbeit und Wirtschaft (Vienna 1926, vol. 4, issue 4). Also on this cf. Wiener Inter-nationale Hochschulkurse 1922–1971 (University of Vienna, undated).

9 Friedrich Stadler, ‘Spätaufklärung und Sozialdemokratie in Wien 1918–1938’ in: Aufbruch und Untergang. Österreichische Kultur zwischen 1918 und 1938 (Vienna-Munich-Zürich: Europa Verlag, 1981). For a portrait of Goldscheid as part of the Vienna social and culture movement see the still valid Michael Hubenstorf, ‘Sozialmedizin, Menschenökonomie, Volksgesundheit’ in: Aufbruch und Untergang, 247–266.

10 Otto Neurath, ‘Die Entwicklung des Wiener Kreises und die Zukunft des Logischen Empirismus’, in: Neurath, Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische Schriften, vol. 2, edited by Rudolf Haller and Heiner Rutte (Vienna: Verlag Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1981), 691 f.

11 ‘The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle’, in Otto Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology edited by Marie Neurath & Cohen Robert (Dordrecht-Holland: Reidel, 1973), Chapter 9.

12 Friedrich Stadler, Studien zum Wiener Kreis. Ursprung, Entwicklung und Wirkung des Logischen Empirismus im Kontext (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1997), (English edition:

27Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Vienna-New York: Springer 2001). Especially ch. 12 and the list of the Vienna Circle members who participated in the adult education in Vienna. On the early Vienna Circle before the First World War regarding popular education and social reform cf. particularly: Thomas Uebel, Vernunftkritik und Wissenschaft: Otto Neurath und der erste Wiener Kreis (Vienna-New York: Springer, 2000).

13 For a full account of the research on this see: Wissenschaft, Politik und Öffentlichkeit im Kontext der „Wiener Moderne“, 1890–1930. Literatur und Forschungsbibliographie, edited by Österreichisches Volkshochschularchiv (Vienna, 2000). On this see also the periodical of the ÖVA: Spurensuche. Zeitschrift für Erwachsenenbildung und Wissen-schaftspopularisierung. Vienna. See also: Heureka! Das Wissenschaftsmagazin im Falter. Vienna: Falter Verlag, and the series of publications (Vienna: Passagen Verlag) and the Newsletter Moderne. Zeitschrift des Spezialforschungsbereichs Moderne—Wien und Zentraleuropa um 1900. University of Graz. Especially: Günther Sandner, Engagierte Wissenschaft. Austromarxistische Kulturstudien und die Anfänge der britischen Cultural Studies (Wien-Berlin: Lit Verlag, 2006).

14 On his life and work see: Arbeiterbildung in der Zwischenkriegszeit. Otto Neurath – Gerd Arntz, edited by Friedrich Stadler (Vienna-Munich: Löcker, 1982). Otto Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology, edited by Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen (Dordrecht-Boston: Reidel 1973); Paul Neurath/Elisabeth Nemeth (eds.), Otto Neurath oder Die Einheit von Wissenschaft und Gesellschaft (Vienna-Cologne-Weimar: Böhlau 1994); Elisabeth Nemeth and Friedrich Stadler (eds.), Encyclopedia and Utopia. The Life and Work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945) (Dordrecht-Boston-London: Kluwer 1996); Nancy Cartwright, Jordi Cat, Lola Fleck and Thomas E. Uebel, Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science and Politics (Cambridge University Press 1996); Elisabeth Nemeth and Richard Heinrich (eds.), Otto Neurath: Rationalität, Planung, Vielfalt (Berlin-Vienna: Oldenbourg und Akademie Verlag 1999); Elisabeth Nemeth, Stefan W. Schmitz and Thomas Uebel (eds.), Otto Neurath’s Economics in Context (Dordrecht: Springer 2007). Most recently on Isotype: Otto Neurath, From Hiero-glyphics to Isotype. A Visual Autobiography edited by Christopher Burke and Matthew Eve (London: Hyphen Press 2010).

15 Cf. Otto Neurath, ‘Museums of the Future’, in: Survey Graphic, 22/9 (1933). Published in Rudolf Haller/Robin Kinross (eds.), Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften (henceforth: GbS) (Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1991), 244–257.

16 On current research see: Thomas Uebel, Vernunftkritik und Wissenschaft: Otto Neurath und der erste Wiener Kreis (Vienna-New York: Springer, 2000).

17 Cf. Friedrich Stadler, ‘Elemente einer zukünftigen Wissenschaftstheorie: Zur Inter-aktion von Philosophie, Geschichte und Theorie der Wissenschaften’, in: Stadler,

28 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

Elemente moderner Wissenschaftstheorie, vii–xxvi.18 ‘Otto Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology’, Chapter 11, as well as the correspond-

ing work on the theory of science from the perspective of the ‘scientific world-view’ up until the Encyclopædia in: Otto Neurath, Gesammelte philosophische und metho-dologische Schriften, (henceforth: GpmS ) 2 vols. edited by Rudolf Haller and Heiner Rutte (Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1981); Otto Neurath, Philosophical Papers 1913–1946, edited by Robert S. Cohen and Marie Neurath (Dordrecht-Boston-Lancaster: Reidel, 1983).

19 This section essentially restates my Studien zum Wiener Kreis, ch. 12.3. On the growth and influence of pictorial statistics see: Gerd Arntz, Kritische Grafik und Bildstatistik (The Hague: 1976); Gerd Arntz, Monographie-Reihe Remscheider Künstler 2 (Remscheid, 1982); Robin Kinross, Otto Neurath’s Contribution to Visual Communication 1925–45 (Mphil. Thesis. Reading, 1979); Stadler (ed.), Arbeiterbildung in der Zwischen-kriegszeit, 1982. For Otto Neurath’s primary literature see: M. Neurath/R. S. Cohen (eds.), Empiricism and Sociology; Rudolf Haller/Robin Kinross (eds.), Gesammelte bild-pädagogische Schriften (GbS) (Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1991). For an over-view on this see: Otto Neurath. Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung, Sozialismus und Logischer Empirismus edited with an introduction by Rainer Hegselmann (Frankfurt/M.: Suhrkamp, 1979).

20 Otto Neurath, International Picture Language/Internationale Bildsprache. Facsimile reprint of the English edition of 1936 (Department of Typography & Graphic Commu-nication: University of Reading, 1980). Graphic Communication through ISOTYPE. (Department of Typography & Graphic Communication: University of Reading, 1975).

21 On the biography specifically, and particularly on the ‘Vienna Method’, cf.: Paul Neurath, ‘Otto Neurath (1882–1945). Leben und Werk’, in: Neurath/E. Nemeth (eds.), Otto Neurath oder die Einheit, 13–96.

22 Otto Neurath, Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule (Vienna-Leipzig: Deutscher Verlag für Jugend und Volk, 1933). Published in GbS, 265–336.

23 Otto Neurath, International Picture Language; Neurath, ‘Visual Education’ (1937). Both in GbS.

24 Cf. E. Gillen’s article in: Politische Konstruktivisten. Die „Gruppe Progressiver Künstler“. (Cologne-Berlin: Neue Gesellschaft für bildende Kunst, 1975).

25 O. Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology, 227–248.26 Particularly Neurath, Modern Man in the Making.27 Gerd Arntz, Zeit unterm Messer. Holz- und Linolschnitte (Cologne: Leske Verlag,

1988).

29Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

28 Michael Twyman, ‘Isotype und die Universität Reading’, in: Arbeiterbildung in der Zwischenkriegszeit, 185–189.

29 Gerd Arntz, Kritische Grafik und Bildstatistik (The Hague-Cologne, 1976).30 Politische Konstruktivisten, H. U. Bohnen, Das Gesetz der Welt ist die Änderung der Welt.

Die rheinische Gruppe progressiver Künstler (1918–1933) (Berlin: Karin Kramer Verlag, 1976).

31 Arntz, Kritische Grafik, 47.32 Especially with the periodical Fernunterricht and with articles in: Die Volksschule and

Die Quelle.33 Neurath, GbS 1991 (all subsequent references are taken from this).34 Neurath, GbS (particularly the relevant publications of 1925–1946).35 Neurath, ‘Museums of the Future’ (1933), in: Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology edited by

Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1973), 218 ff.36 Neurath, ‘From Hieroglyphs to Isotypes’ (1946), in: Neurath, Empiricism and Soci-

ology edited by Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1973), 4–6. Now published as separate publication as Neurath (2010), see note 14.

37 Otto Neurath, ‘Visual Education. Humanisation versus Popularisation’, edited by Juha Manninen, in: Nemeth/Stadler, Encyclopedia and Utopia, 245–336. Following on from this is an overview by Reinhard Fabian on Otto Neurath’s Nachlass in Haarlem (NL), 337–355.

38 Quoted from Neurath, Empiricism and Sociology edited by Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1973), 231 f.

39 Empiricism and Sociology, 231 f.40 Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum in Wien (Leipzig-Vienna): Fernunterricht

(1931/32), continued under the name Bildstatistik (1932/33).41 Fernunterricht, 1 February 1931.42 Ibid., 11.43 For instance in: Bulletin of the World Association for Adult Education (London, 1942).

Highway (London, 1944): The New Era (London, 1944). Health Education Journal (London, 1944). The Lancet (London, 1945).

44 Otto Neurath, ‘Visual Aids and Arguing’ The New Era in Home and School, April 1944, vol. 25, no. 3, 51–61.

45 Cf. the corresponding articles in Section III. ‘Pictorial Statistics – Isotype – Museology’ in: Nemeth/Stadler, Encyclopedia and Utopia.

46 David Skopec, ‘The Changing Media of Visual Statistics’, and Angela Jansen, ‘Isotype and Infographics’, in: ibid., 143–166; Nader Vossoughian, Otto Neurath. The Language of the Global Polis (Rotterdam: NAi Publishers, 2008).

30 Written Language and Picture Language after Otto Neurath

47 Along with his Isotype Institute in England Neurath had already produced Isotype filmstrips and films and Isotype animations in collaboration with Common Ground and Paul Rotha Productions. For current media research cf.: Kurt Blaukopf, ‘The Shortcomings of the TV-Screen in Cultural Communication’, in: Daniel Green-berger/Wolfgang Reiter/Anton Zeilinger (eds.), Epistemological and Experimental Perspectives on Quantum Physics (Dordrecht-Boston-London: Kluwer, 1999), 317–336.

48 Jeff Bernard/Gloria Withalm (eds.), Neurath. Zeichen (Vienna: ÖGS/ISSS, 1996). Jeff Bernard/Gloria Withalm/Karl H. Müller (eds.), Bildsprache – Visualisierung – Diagrammatik (Vienna: ÖGS, 1995 = Semiotische Berichte vol. 19, 1–4/1995). Jeff Bernard/Friedrich Stadler (eds.), Neurath: Semiotische Projekte und Diskurse (Wien: ÖGS, 1997 = Semiotische Berichte, vol. 21, 1/1997).

49 Cf. particularly the publications already mentioned above in note 13.50 Robert Leonard, ‘“Seeing Is Believing”: Otto Neurath, Graphic Art, and the Social

Order’, in: Economic Engagements with Art, edited by Neil De Marchi and Craufurd D. W. Goodwin (Durham and London: Duke University Press, 1999), 452–478. The 7th European Conference on the History of Economics 2001 in Montréal was likewise dedicated to the topic ‘Economic Science and Visual Representation’. John O’Neill, The Market. Ethics, Knowledge and Politics (London-New York: Routledge, 1998). In May 2000 at the Vienna University of Economics and Business, during a symposium on ‘European Society of Ecological Economics’ there was a separate session on ‘Concepts of Knowledge and Economic Thought by Otto Neurath and Josef Popper-Lynkeus’.

51 Motto to his book dedicated to ‘Rudolf Carnap, teacher and friend’: Willard Van Orman Quine, Word and Object (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1960).

The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Christopher Burke, Reading

In a thorough study titled ‘Neurath’s theory of pictorial-statistical represen-tation’ (published over twenty years ago in Rediscovering the forgotten Vienna Circle) Karl Müller concluded that Otto Neurath never explicitly developed such a theory and questioned Neurath’s claim that Isotype was a language, due to the weakness of evidence for this. In implicit agreement with Müller’s analysis, this essay will draw on Neurath’s correspondence and his ‘visual autobiography’ to show that he deliberately did not develop a theory of picture language, or even fully articulate a method, on the principle that it was too early in the history of visual education to make such definite statements. He also felt that such theorizing would restrict possible, future applications of Isotype.

There are some contradictions in the way Otto Neurath discussed Isotype, as perhaps there were in other areas of his work; Thomas Uebel has described him succinctly as ‘a very contrapuntal writer’.1 It seems almost to have been a principle of Neurath’s to be self-contradictory (or at least equivocal). In his 1942 essay ‘International planning for freedom’ he quoted Conrad Meyer: ‘I am not a wittily constructed work of fiction; I am a human being and full of contradiction.’ 2 Neurath’s habit of undermining certainty causes some difficulties of interpretation. He made statements claiming that Isotype was a kind of language, which should be in widespread use, yet he also admitted that it could never be a real language and he wanted to keep close control of how it was produced.

Neurath’s book of 1936, International picture language, firmly established a claim of linguistic status for Isotype. The use of this phrase is partly

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 31–57.

32 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

explained by Neurath having written the book in C. K. Ogden’s Basic English, which has a vocabulary of only 850 words to choose from. Neverthe-less, Neurath stated in his introductory note that the rules he would explain in the book are ‘in harmony with a complete system for an international picture language’. This is not something that he and his collaborators ever tried to develop, despite the claim for a system being made in the name Isotype itself—an acronym which stands for International System of Typographic Picture Education. In her account of how she invented this name, Marie Neurath confessed that it was not an ‘entirely satisfactory solution’.3

The name Isotype replaced ‘Vienna Method of Pictorial Statistics’ (Wiener Methode der Bildstatistik ) around the time that International picture language was being written, soon after Neurath and a group of close colleagues from the Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum in Wien had settled in the Netherlands. In correspondence at that time, Rudolf Carnap asked Neurath:

What does ‘isotyp’ [sic] mean? Representation by means of a similar picture? For a logician it rouses the association: ‘of the same logical type’. Wouldn’t it be possible to find another word? 4

Carnap referred here to an interpretation based on the Greek words ‘isos’ (the same) and ‘typos’ (type, symbol). Neurath replied:

Isotype—the name for our picture language; we are glad we have it. Reidemeister [later Marie Neurath] developed it systematically: I-nternational S-ystem O-f Ty-pographic P-icture E-ducation. And it otherwise means: using the same types, which we in fact do. I hope it does not cause any great confusion among logicians.5

Neurath’s last comment here—perhaps a little sarcastic in tone—indicates that he did not perceive Isotype as occupying the ‘icy slopes of logic’; instead he welcomed the name as a kind of brand to effectively identify work produced at the International Foundation for Visual Education in the Hague. After leaving Vienna and losing the municipal subsidy given to the Gesell-schafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum, it was necessary to establish practice on a commercial basis. The Dutch Foundation struggled financially and, after two years in the Netherlands, Neurath wrote:

33The Linguistic Status of Isotype

But we can barely exist any longer, and don’t know how things will go on, in spite of the positive attitude of important people towards our work, in spite of ‘success’ now again in educational circles. Just like our unified science has success—but it doesn’t bring us one penny. 6

Neurath may have been content to portray Isotype as a kind of ‘system’ and ‘language’ in order to enhance its appeal to potential clients during this difficult period.

Nevertheless, after the analytical debates about the use of language in the Vienna Circle, Neurath was naturally wary of using the term ‘language’ for referring to Isotype. He asked Carnap for advice on the matter during the writing of International picture language:

I am treating the work of our Institute theoretically and call it ‘International picture language’[.] [I] indicate rules which we use and also show how one ‘stresses’ something—that corresponds to stylistic rules of [letter]spacing [in gothic type] and underlining, etc. Now I would like to know how one should differentiate between the term ‘script’ and ‘language’. In ethnology many speak of ‘picture languages’, others of ‘picture script’. One speaks of Chinese script, although actually a language is meant whose translation into the spoken word is debatable. I would prefer using a terminology which is consistent with yours. Please make some remarks.7

Neurath probably sought consistency with Carnap’s book Logische Syntax der Sprache, which had been published not long before this request.8 Carnap replied:

I use the term ‘language’ in the broadest sense. I have hardly used ‘script’ or ‘script language’. I would possibly use these terms in such a way that ‘script’ or ‘script language’ designate a special variety of language, namely the written variety. A system of rules for the use of pictures (to express facts) is then a special type of language. Hence it seems to me that one can use the term ‘picture-script’ as well as the term ‘picture language’.9

Neurath took this as a kind of approval for calling Isotype a language: ‘I will use the term picture language as you have indicated’, he told Carnap. Yet he

34 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

was hesitant about taking this step, explaining that he had previously used only the term ‘picture script’ [Bilderschrift]. Indeed, in his longest and most detailed account of the Vienna Method—Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule (1933)—he seems quite deliberately to have used this term and avoided ‘picture language’ [Bildersprache]. To Carnap, he continued:

… it is naturally something else if there is a picture language with its own syntax, or a picture language without its own syntax. Translatable word for

Fig. 1

War and increase of population in Austria.

Exhibition chart made at the Gesellschafts-

und Wirtschaftsmuseum in Wien, c.1928

(T3d). A horizontal axis is used to draw

attention to a surplus in births or deaths.

Although this axis does not strictly cor-

respond to ground level, this association is

created by the birth symbols stacking above

it, while death symbols descend below it.

Fig. 2

Births and deaths in Germany in a year, from

International picture language, 1936 (it is an

English-language version of a chart

published in Die bunte Welt, 1929). Here

the axis has been given a vertical orienta-

tion, reflecting the adoption of a general rule

to arrange pictograms in horizontal rows.

Neurath made a naturalistic argument for

this: ‘The horizontal row corresponds to the

customary position of the objects. People,

animals, and cars move horizontally over the

earth’s surface. It would be strange to arrange

people one on top of the other.’ 10

35The Linguistic Status of Isotype

word, so to speak. The German script-language itself is different from the German speech-language. Above all in ‘style’, which is also language.11

Neurath pointed out in International picture language that Isotype could not translate verbal language ‘word for word’; but it did have some basic syntacti-cal rules, which were established during the Vienna period. The basic rule is that pictogram units should not be increased in size to indicate an increase in quantity, but should instead be repeated in greater numbers, at the same size. After initial years of experiment, it was also resolved to line them up in hori-zontal (not vertical) rows, with time running on the vertical axis. Arranged this way, Neurath likened the pictograms to letters composed in a printed line.12

Some examples were prepared around 1936 to show how statements such as ‘boy walking through doorway’ should be conveyed through Isotype, with counter-examples (figs 3 & 4). These make clear that Isotype has no com-ponents that are directly equivalent to words in many cases; but it would be difficult to interpret rules which dictate that these statements should be conveyed in precisely the approved configurations given here. Perhaps this

Fig. 3 & Fig. 4

Examples of ’not Isotype’ and Isotype

depictions of some simple operations.

c.1936 (T1413 & 1414)

36 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

was the point—that there should always be flexibility to allow for economi-cal (and creative) graphic renditions. (More examples of this kind appeared in Basic by Isotype, the book that was prepared alongside International picture language.)

Almost a decade after writing International picture language, Neurath continued to refer loosely to Isotype as a ‘visual language’ in a book titled ‘Visual education’, which he wrote towards the end of his life. He seemed to recognize the debatability of his usage, however:

Fig. 5 & Fig. 6

Pages from

Basic by Isotype

(London:

Kegan Paul, Trench,

Trubner & Co., 1937)

37The Linguistic Status of Isotype

If one shows realistic pictures instead of using impressive sentences or expres-sions, one uses a language which is a rather vague one, but vagueness in itself is no objection as long as ambiguity is avoided.13

Contemporary with this, in his ‘visual autobiography’ titled From hieroglyphics to Isotype, Neurath clarified that Isotype was not a language but a ‘language-like technique’:

There are many reasons why Isotype cannot be developed as a ‘complete language’ without destroying its force and simplicity. Our daily language, even in primitive societies, is to some extent richer than our Isotype representations can be, and one needs words added to the pictures.14

Around the same time he wrote to a colleague in England:

I object to all attempts to look at Isotype as a a quasi-language in full dress. It is just my point to maintain, that Isotype is adapted to impressive presenta-tion of relatively simple correlations. A full scheme of Hieroglyphics should frighten me.15

Neurath had admitted this in other words already in International picture language, calling Isotype a ‘helping language’ (in later writings he called it an ‘auxiliary language’).

While International picture language remains the best written account of Isotype, it should not be interpreted as a set of definitive statements that wholly encapsulate what was an activity of collaborative, graphic design. Taking that book as a summa ignores the rich and varied history of Isotype between 1924 and 1971, and encourages an appraisal of Isotype in purely conceptual terms. Neurath’s epistemological (and economic) writings enrich an analysis of Isotype, without doubt; but he certainly never considered it as a philosophical exercise. He often commented to colleagues and clients that Isotype could not be fully explained but only demonstrated in action.

The makers of Isotype clearly did not want to construct a whole language; Isotype was instead an approach to design for education, with some linguistic aspirations. Its few basic rules provided a certain systematic aspect. Neurath hesitantly referred to ‘Isotype vocabulary and the Isotype grammar, if one is allowed to use these terms in such a context’.16 Some rough parallels with

38 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

language can be drawn: for instance, in the way that pictograms could be combined to create the equivalent of compound nouns. Also, by linguistic analogy, a certain significance was attached to changes in form or colour; they were not changed arbitrarily.

To some extent Isotype was defined by what it did not do—what was left out. There is a similarity here to the way in which Neurath simply left out specific words from his vocabulary when writing, in order to avoid certain complications. Isotype generally never shows things in perspective, for exam-ple, because Neurath thought that such naturalism detracted from the power of the simplified imagery.

In From hieroglyphics to Isotype Neurath stated that the Isotype team attempted to achieve a ‘visual consistency’ lacking in some previous efforts in visual communication. Yet, on the same page (103), he claimed that ‘I think we were the first to evolve a theoretical framework of visual- ization’. This sounds suspiciously like the very thing which he criticized other people for doing, although it is perhaps a reasonable description of the broad rules formulated for Isotype. Such a phrase, added to claims for Isotype to be an ‘international system’ and a ‘picture language’, may encourage interpretation of it as having a utopian aspect. Karl Müller observed that Neurath thought ‘full symbolic languages’ were some-thing desirable but not practicable.17 There is no way of breaking down Isotype into definite components of meaning any more than verbal language could be, in Neurath’s view:

I cannot deny that many scientifically minded people do not like such a start full of vagueness; they would prefer—as I would prefer too, if I did not regard this wish as a utopian one—to start with exact initial definitions and atomic simple elements.18

Isotype was not any kind of ‘ideal language’, which is what Neurath described Carnap as having attempted to develop in his book Der logische Aufbau der Welt (1928).19 Neurath considered Carnap’s formulations as inapplicable to the social sciences (the principal province of Isotype) because they did not reflect the necessary mixture of ‘clean’ and ‘unclean’ ways of thinking. In his autobiography Carnap recalled that Neurath insisted on the materiality of language:

39The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Neurath emphasized from the beginning that language phenomena are events within the world, not something that refers to the world from outside. Spoken language consists of sound waves; written language consists of marks of ink on paper. Neurath emphasized these facts in order to reject the view that there is something ‘higher’, something mysterious, ‘spiritual’, in language, a view which was prominent in German philosophy. I agreed with him but pointed out that only the structural pattern, not the physical properties of the ink marks, were relevant for the function of language. Thus it is possible to construct a theory about language, namely the geometry of the written pattern.20

Here is a significant difference between the views of Carnap and Neurath: Carnap’s response, to dismiss the physical properties of graphic language as irrelevant, showed his vestigial attachment to the idealism of German philo-sophical tradition; Neurath had been occupied since the early 1920s with designing and producing graphic material and, for him, the particular form of ink marks on paper were not incidental—they were intrinsic to Isotype.

This difference between Carnap and Neurath emerged during the seminal ‘protocol sentence’ debate within the Vienna Circle. Neurath argued that ‘What is first given us is our historical ordinary language with a multitude of imprecise unanalysed terms [“Ballungen”].’ 21 In his view protocol statements were not intended as ‘elementary statements’—‘In this form they are even a protest against elementary statements.’ 22 As an example he gave the sentence ‘Otto observes an angry man’: this was imprecise because ‘angry man’ is not precisely defined (‘but “Otto” itself is in many respects an imprecise term’, he added). ‘We start by purifying this ordinary language of metaphysical components and thus arrive at the physicalist ordinary language. A list of for-bidden words can serve us well in doing this.’ 23 Such a ‘physicalist language’ is also served by using pictures instead of words: pictures make a direct, iconic connection to the physical world, not a symbolic one. Yet the Isotype pictograms representing ‘man’ or ‘woman’ are by nature imprecise—they are deliberately generic. In Neurath’s terms, they are also ‘Ballungen’, imprecise clusters of concepts.24 The graphic simplification in Isotype is instrumental, and does not correspond to a reduction of connotation. Isotype pictograms are generalized pictures due to their simplicity. Neurath commented: ‘The figures must not function as individuals, rather as symbols for a genus [Gattung].’ 25

Although Neurath recognized no direct descent of Isotype from either hieroglyphics or Chinese script, he found some analogies with these

40 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

historical ‘picture scripts’.26 He compared their advantages with those of alphabetic script:

A people with a conceptual script (like the Chinese, for instance) has difficulties in creating a freely mobile symbolism; on the other hand, it runs less easily into the danger of talking philosophical nonsense. … … letters as signs without conceptual meaning are, however, well suited for a strictly scientific symbolism.27

Care must be taken in mapping Neurath’s views about verbal language onto his work in picture language. There are some enticing similarities, but the shift from word to image is, in Isotype terms, a ‘transformation’ or meta-morphosis [Umwandlung] of linguistic mode, which entails more differences than similarities. However, to make a crude analogy, Isotype charts could

Fig. 7 & Fig. 8

Pages from the Isotype ‘picture dictionary’, with pictograms designed by Gerd Arntz

in collaboration with Otto Neurath. 1930–4. The solid silhouette version of ‘man’ with legs

together (top right of left sheet) was sometimes used to depict ‘person’ (both sexes).

41The Linguistic Status of Isotype

be seen as a kind of graphic protocol statement lacking the rigour of the verbal kind defined by the bracketed qualifications about who exactly made the observation and when. Although Isotype charts bear the signature of the Isotype Institute (and before that the Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum or the Mundanæum), the origin and editing of the information contained in them is rarely made explicit: sources of statistics are often only given when a book appendix allows space, for example.

Neurath was not interested in analytical systems that pretend to classify whole languages. As Herbert Feigl noted, Neurath was ‘skeptical if not out-right opposed to’ semantics as developed by Carnap.28 In ‘Foundations of the social sciences’ he stated:

I think that ‘semantics’, as evolved by Carnap and [Alfred] Tarski, will support many kinds of calculus analysis, but I feel uneasy when thinking of its application to empiricist arguments and the danger of slipping into ‘ontological’ ways of arguing.29

For the same reason Neurath had reservations about the theory of ‘semiotic’ (singular, not plural) expounded by the American philosopher Charles Morris in a long essay titled ‘Foundations of the theory of signs’ for the first volume of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Neurath was editor-in-chief of this encyclopedia, although he seems to have left the editing of Morris’s essay mainly to Carnap, who was assistant editor (along with Morris him-self). Neurath gave Morris’s essay the title ‘Semiotic’ in an initial contents list, having noted Morris’s previous use of the word, but Morris resisted it as a title ‘because the term is not known to many people’, and instead proposed ‘Theory of signs’. Neurath welcomed this as ‘a real name of a science’. Yet he considered Morris to have gone too far in terms of constructing a system of classification: he agreed with Morris that one should try to ‘systematize’ as far as possible, without pretending to make a complete or final system—this was essentially the approach in Isotype—but it seemed to him that in Morris’s study ‘the classification exceeds the clarity that can be attained in this area at the present time’. ‘I fear that too much terminology in an area that is so little developed does not have a clarifying effect.’ 30

It is perhaps significant that Neurath barely mentioned Morris or Semiotic[s] in his introduction to volume one of the Encyclopedia; he mentioned more favourably the linguistic discipline of Significs, which

42 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Fig. 9

A diagram by Charles Morris

titled ‘Semiosis and semiotic’. This

was included in a letter he sent to

Neurath, 3 February 1938. (VCA-m)

Fig. 10

Extract from Neurath’s reply to Morris, 14 February 1938, including his diagram based on Morris’s

concepts. Neurath’s version tends toward Isotype in being purely visual, with separate verbal

explanations. It also begins to resemble an atomic diagram. In the text below he appears to

introduce the term ‘design’, but this is an abbreviation of ‘designatum’, as used by Morris. (VCA-m)

43The Linguistic Status of Isotype

responded principally to the pragmatic aspect of language. 31 In his intro-duction Neurath offered an epigram that illuminates study of much of his work: ‘One can love exactness and nevertheless consciously tolerate a cer-tain amount of vagueness.’ He continued: ‘How can one combine such a critical and skeptical attitude with the unparalyzed driving power which is needed to attain success in social and private life?’ 32

Neurath was consistent in observing that visualization had strong limits—that it was capable of less complexity than verbal language. He discussed this matter with Patrick Meredith, a member of the advisory committee for the Isotype Institute in the UK. Meredith established a Visual Educa-tion Centre at University College, Exeter (in south-west England); he also became the first lecturer in visual education in Britain. He met several times with Neurath, and some of Neurath’s ideas are clearly recognizable in short essays written by Meredith in the early 1940s. He described the work of his ‘Visual Education Centre’ as ‘concerned with the bearing of three norma-tive disciplines on visual production, namely logic, semantics and statistical theory’.33 Neurath was doubtful about establishing visual education as some kind of academic discipline by pretending that it was more developed than it really was:

I think the Visual Education business is in the beginning. It seems to be rather dangerous to create terms for such a provisional activity. The statements one wants to make are poor and few only. After some research work you will perhaps need a few terms. My answer is: try to discover how visual education goes on at the moment, particularly in certain disciplines. Even a first rather vague information would mean a lot, since one does not know anything about the state of affairs. From such research you will reach certain results and making descriptive statements, perhaps, maybe, you will use some expressions frequently, which afterwards will be fixed by use and then become elements of the normal discussion, but I think it hardly desirable to start with such phraseological attempts before any clear results have been reached. You see from my articles how careful I avoid to use particular terms. [sic] I try to remain within the daily life language realm. I avoid even acknowledged expressions of modern psychology, knowing how many misunderstandings may grow up from that. Therefore I suggest to speak simply and frankly of the problem without anticipating any classification or hypothesis.34

44 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Neurath’s resistance to Meredith’s use of the phrase ‘visual logic’ led him to admit that ‘logic’ had been on his notorious list of ‘dangerous’ words since the Unity of Science congress of 1937, which, he conceded, put him in a difficult position: ‘In short, I myself do not know how to apply the term properly, and therefore—against my intentions, because we speak of Logi-cal Empiricism—I dropped the term altogether.’ 35 By contrast he seemed content to use the word ‘language’ in a rather loose way, possibly expanding its definition, without fear of creating confusion.

Meredith claimed that ‘visual language’ is ‘a richer and more powerful medium of expression than verbal language’—Neurath disagreed:

… you want to present our Isotype or Visual Education in general as some-thing ‘theoretically’ better evolved than something else in the field of verbal presentation. I cannot see that. But I think you have the desire to give the Visual Education business some ‘higher’ marks than it deserves. You see such over-statements may induce people to reply and then we shall be in a bad position, because we cannot show how fine Visual Education is in supporting theoreti-cal analysis—it is not.36

Neurath also objected to Meredith misrepresenting one of Neurath’s ideas by stating that ‘visual expression’ is ‘multi-dimensional’:37

you write, that Visual Education by means of its more dimensions is better adapted to the more dimensions of modern thinking. I said just the opposite. The visualization is based on three or two dimensions, that is sometimes an advantage from the viewpoint of impressiveness, compared with the writing appearance of one dimension. But, scientific reasoning needs an indefinite number of dimensions, this is just given by our writing, but not by visualization. The presentation is more impressive but is relatively poor, poorer than our language, and that is, I think one fair reason, why some people subconsciously and consciously are against visualization, I myself have this serious criticism.38

After Otto Neurath’s death Marie Neurath continued to warn Meredith about being too theoretical (he appears to have been constructing an analyti-cal framework called ‘semagraphics’):

45The Linguistic Status of Isotype

I will tell you why I cannot see how your approach could help me any further. I cannot see how you can show, by making your structure in the epistemic space, whether a lesson or a chart or a chapter is good or bad educationally. It is the same with your semagraphics as far as I understand it. It seems to me that you can find a place for any type of representation, whether good or bad or senseless. Why then the whole trouble? Don’t you want to find out what is good and what bad in visual education? Why not help to develop methods to find this out? This was what Otto tried to impress on you during the last long talk wasn’t it? 39

The Neuraths’ priority was creating graphic material, not primarily ana-lysing it. Their concern was a practical one—to design visual material that conveyed information clearly, and they were interested in research if it helped to show what was effective in practice. Indeed Neurath had approached the influential professor of psychology at the university of Vienna, Karl Bühler, about making some scientific studies with Isotype material.40 He was open to research on the assumptions behind Isotype, commenting to Meredith: ‘I would like to make experiments and research dealing with problems of “icons” and verbal expression. The borderline between word language and picture language is insufficiently analyzed.’

International system or proprietary technique?

In From hieroglyphics to Isotype Neurath reflected:

The history of hieroglyphics covers a long period, while the history of Isotype as yet covers barely two decades. During this short time it has become some-what stabilized and is now only changing like a language, which also alters and enriches its vocabulary, grammar and style. (104)

But, unlike most languages, it was intended for one-way communication. It was not a language offered for anyone to create statements for themselves. In terms of reading, Isotype should require little or no learning; Neurath hoped that looking at Isotype was not much different than looking at the real world. But creating statements with Isotype was complex and, in his view,

46 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

required a certain attitude—essentially that of Logical Empiricism. ‘Isotype is not just the application of symbols [pictograms] to something,’ he remarked to a colleague, ‘it implies a particular attitude, which needs careful treatment before becoming successful.’ 42 He explained to Patrick Meredith that ‘Isotype education is similar to empiricist education and is connected with a certain alteration of attitude, teacher and pupils.’ 43

Neurath gave more details about this ‘attitude’ to R.W. Moore (headmaster of a well-known private school in England named Harrow):

You see our educational tendency is to present problems in a simple way, not by transforming verbal generalizations again, but, as far as possible by presenting descriptive items, from which the reader may infer a generalization. Of course even that has not to be handled in a rigid way. We try to start from something you can understand as a plain man, without particular education. We think that one may present something of any prob-lem, one can discuss properly, in this way—but not the whole problem. A selection is unavoidable because visual representation is something coarse and primitive.44

He summarized this approach to another colleague: ‘The point is: in Isotype we avoid “analogies”, we try to present either concrete factual items or symbolic relations.’ 45

The application of Isotype to consistent design and production of graphic information is accurately reflected by Neurath’s description of it as a ‘language-like technique’. It could be argued that it was a proprietary technique, due to the fact that it was never fully systematized, or even fully articulated. Neurath suggested that there was a secret ingredient in Isotype already during the Vienna period:

For it is clear that the ‘Vienna Method’ is, unlike the usual graphic methods, not a machine into which one throws sequences of figures in order to get quantitative pictures. The ‘Vienna Method’ requires creative [gestaltende], educational work.46

Marie Neurath described the work of design in Isotype (‘transformation’) as requiring ‘educational tact’ [pädagogischen Takt].47

During the last years of his life Otto Neurath recognized that the Isotype method remained somewhat elusive:

47The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Up to now there is no Isotype curriculum in existence which would enable people to learn this new technique properly from the start. It is more or less routine work, based on a great many rules, the application of which depends upon a highly skilled judgement.48

But he did not accept others freely adapting Isotype principles. There was a right way to do it, in his view, which was partly covert: he insisted that any pro-spective Isotype ‘transformers’ should be trained only at the Isotype Institute. Neurath explained this to his son, Paul, who began to teach the visualization of statistics in the USA during the early 1940s:

We devoted many years to Visual Education. Sometimes we thought, perhaps one could make the subject teachable in a simple way, but after experience and research we discovered that only a team of highly skilled people are able to make transformations and to create charts and models composed of stand-ardized elements. Long training is needed, years.

He reiterated the point that he had made about the Vienna Method:

We discovered that one cannot make automatically Isotype charts, as one cannot make automatically musical compositions, or architecture or something else, in spite of the fact, that there are rules which regulate the conventions.49

When discussing the same issues with Meredith, Neurath added that the mat-ter ‘touches many principles of the transfer of abilities and skill’.50 He saw Isotype chart-making as a craft that could only be learned by apprenticeship.

Otto and Paul Neurath had a strong disagreement with each other about the propriety of Isotype—and their discussion of the matter is informative with regard to Isotype not being an easily teachable system. Otto Neurath criticized his son for pretending to teach a subject without sufficient experi-ence of it; his disapproval was partly linked with his dislike of the adap-tation made of Isotype in America by Neurath’s former colleague Rudolf Modley. Paul Neurath showed a page from Modley’s book How to use pictorial statistics (1937) to his students because Otto Neurath himself had not written a book on ‘how to make’ Isotype charts (International picture language is too full of equivocation to be such a book). His father explained to him the differences between conventional, schematic visualization and Isotype:

48 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Visualization by means of geometrical devices is a work, which skilled people can learn, but visualization by means of Isotype is something wholly different, because here the educational decision enters the field. To present something impressively, implies dropping something, making rough figures instead of exact figures, but not in a systematized way, but from case to case. A tech-nique of presentation very useful today may be not useful tomorrow … the mankind chart [fig. 11] very good as long as you get the three rows—fine. If alterations appear, perhaps the arrangement should be changed … And

Fig. 11

Chart ‘Völkergruppen der Erde’

(human groups of the earth) from

Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft (1930).

Estimated data for 1930; each whole

figure represents 100 million people.

This particular graphic solution for

showing relative population is not as

obvious as it may seem. An alternative

design could have featured generic

pictograms for ‘[hu]man’ placed in

rows on the particular areas of a world

map to which they belong. Instead, a

striking correlation emerges if human-

ity is grouped in three categories—

‘white’, ‘brown/black’ and ‘yellow’

people (as Neurath called them). So

the pictograms were designed (and

coloured) to convey directly these

racial distinctions, and simply lined

up in three rows to emphasize the

similarity in quantity between the

groups. Neurath commented that

most people believed wrongly that

there were roughly three or four times

as many ‘yellow’ people as ‘white’ in

the world; but looking at this chart,

he asserted, made it difficult to forget

that there were roughly the same

amount of each at that time.51

49The Linguistic Status of Isotype

that is something startling for many people. The substitution of bars by rows of puppets becomes boring and if you want to be exact you are destroying the effect of Isotype. To explain these finesses needs an intense analysis—even if one devotes only three hours to the presentation of the results.52

A balance of unity with variety was essential to Isotype, in Otto Neurath’s opinion, as he explained to Meredith:

we always fear that the vivid and imaginative element of Isotype could be too much pedantically framed and transformed into a kind of litany … The combination of a unified language with a multiplicity of striking expressions, that is the secret of the Isotype habit.53

Variety was important in making each chart as individual as possible within the limits of Isotype because memorability was central to its educational aims. During the period of the Vienna Circle’s linguistic debates, Neurath wrote with polemical overstatement: ‘In language nothing but order is essential, and that is already represented by a sequence of signs in Morse code.’ 54 It is clear, however, that while he may have considered order the only essential aspect of language, he did not consider it the only desirable feature. This applied to ‘picture language’ too:

Isotype ‘writing’ is like writing a novel in any language. It is not sufficient—as everybody realizes—to know the words and the grammar; one also has to know how to select combinations of words to produce a striking result.55

He developed this point in correspondence with a colleague:

I myself stress the point, that Isotype is mainly a technique of educational style and a highly complicated grammar. The elements are stable, but the wit is in the arrangement, like Shakespeare is in the arrangement not in the dictionary of our English language. Isotype is the name of this technique executed by a team of highly skilled people. … I should not speak of ‘perfection’. The Isotype stock will be enriched, never finished …

Here Neurath added two further important observations: that Isotype should be open ended—an accumulative, encyclopedic enterprise; and that it

50 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

was a collaborative process of design and craft, not a fully theorizable system. All the skills involved—from analysing data to sketching graphic configur-ations, to cutting out pictograms and sticking them down as part of the final artwork—were important and had their place.

But the fulcrum of Isotype work was ‘transformation’, and it was this creative design work which Neurath deemed difficult to teach. ‘It is hope-less, my dear, to explain Isotype to anybody’, he declared to a colleague, ‘it is important to get the possibility to show it.’ 57 Paul Neurath wrote to his father of the difficulty he had in justifying this approach to his students:

I use[d] to tell them, and this is a pretty verbatim quotation: As to the produc-tion of these types of [picture-statistical] graphs there are several opinions. The one held by the originator and main proponent of the method, and author of the books I have shown you, is that nobody can make satisfactory graphs of this type unless he has gone through several years of careful training in the outfit of the author. The method can not be learned from books, not from his own nor anybody else’s. He says so on the basis of about twenty years’ experience. Now I have my doubt in this opinion. [sic] And particularly do have doubt in general in the usefulness of any method, graphical or technical or sociological or any-thing, that can not be taught in other ways than by the originator in person, and that is therefore practically doomed to die with the author.58

This last observation proved to be rather prophetic. Isotype was inextricable from the economic, sociological and scientific preoccupations of Otto & Marie Neurath. When Otto Neurath died, Marie Neurath (as co-director of studies at the Isotype Institute) was able to carry on the work. Indeed, the role of the transformer had developed from Marie Neurath’s work in the Vienna Method, and, after it was renamed Isotype, she remained the only one filling this role. She seems to have found nobody to train as her successor, and con-sequently Isotype work stopped when she retired. Nobody has since taken it up in the same way.

If the Neuraths had been more open to free adaptation of their method, it would perhaps have spread more widely, but also more thinly, in a diluted form. It may be possible to trace the influence of Isotype in the incorporation of pictograms into international signage—although this is not the primary influence that Neurath would have wished for. When asked if he would grant permission for Isotype pictograms to be used by others, Neurath replied:

51The Linguistic Status of Isotype

we feel very strongly that the effect of our method depends not only on the charac-ters, but very largely on the way how they are used [sic], on the selection of represen-tations, on the simplifications, and many other measures. […] Therefore we cannot allow the use of the symbols if we have no influence on the entire layouts.59

Naturally, there was an aspect of protecting professional territory here, but it is perhaps this principle—that pictograms were not the whole point of Isotype—which prevented Marie Neurath from pursuing copyright procedures for Isotype pictograms when she was advised to do so after Otto Neurath’s death.

Otto Neurath’s dream of universal usage for Isotype and his simultaneous wish to have close control over it were, to a large extent, mutually preclusive. As with other modernist ideals (such as orthographic reform, for example), the individual proponents had no political power with which to enforce their proposals. There was some official sanction given to the Vienna Method in the USSR, where the Council of People’s Commissars issued a decree that ‘Dr Neurath’s method of graphic representation of statistics is to be applied in all schools, trade unions, public and cooperative organizations’. 60 It is not clear to what extent this was enforced; in any case, Neurath would not have approved of an inflexible order to apply the Vienna Method to all kinds of information.

Neurath was in the same position with Isotype as with Logical Empiricism, or more precisely with the use of physicalist, verbal language: he could not institute them (and indeed did not wish to) but could only lead by example. He may have occasionally overstated his claims in these matters, but Neurath was more aware than most people of the difficulties of instituting reforms on a broad basis. Nevertheless, should Isotype be considered a failure for not achieving the true status of an ‘international picture language’, as Peter Weibel suggested in his paper at the International Wittgenstein Symposium 2010? 61 Judging by effective projects such as the ‘Fighting Tuberculosis’ exhibition, seen all over America in the late 1930s, or the civic education programmes in West Africa of the 1950s [see Eric Kindel’s chapter in this volume], Isotype can be considered to have achieved significant practical success.

Should we expect Neurath’s pronouncements on the international valid-ity of Isotype to have been realized to a greater extent than his equally optimistic proposals for alternative forms of economy, or for a socialist order? Isotype was an early move away from ‘mechanical objectivity’ towards ‘trained judgment’ in scientific visualization, to use the terms suggested by Lorraine

52 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Daston and Peter Galison in their fascinating book Objectivity. Daston and Galison address the vexed issue of failure:

To contend that mechanical objectivity (or, for that matter, trained judgment) is a fraud and a delusion because it is never realized in purest form is a bit like making the same claim for equality or solidarity. These ethical values can change society without ever being perfectly fulfilled, and the same is true for epistemic virtues in science.62

Thanks to Robin Kinross and Elisabeth Nemeth.

53The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Notes

1 Thomas E. Uebel, Overcoming logical positivism from within: the emergence of Neurath’s naturalism in the Vienna Circle’s protocol sentence debate (Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi, 1992), 3.

2 ‘Ich bin kein ausgeklügelt Buch, Ich bin ein Mensch mit seinem Widerspruch’ (from Huttens letzte Tage) in Neurath, Empiricism and sociology, edited by Marie Neurath & Robert S. Cohen (Dordrecht/Boston: Reidel, 1973), 429.

3 Marie Neurath & Robin Kinross, The transformer: principles of making Isotype charts (London: Hyphen, 2009), 47.

4 Letter Carnap to Neurath, 12 June 1935 (translation by Marie Neurath; Vienna Circle Archive [VCA], Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, Neurath correspond-ence 227/8).

5 Letter Neurath to Carnap, 22 June 1935 (VCA). 6 Letter Neurath to Carnap, 30 April 1936 (VCA).7 Letter Neurath to Carnap, 13 December 1934 (VCA).8 Neurath recognized the importance of this book, and it made him conscious of

his historical place in the Vienna Circle debates. After reading a draft before publication, he remarked to Carnap: ‘I must now make a new place for myself in the world and I have a positive interest in my personal achievement being rather more precisely defined in your book.’ Letter of 8 March 1934 (English translation by the author; Vienna Circle Archive microfilm [VCA-m], Institut Wiener Kreis, University of Vienna). This also reflects Neurath’s preoccupation with making a living at this time; he even wondered about resuming an academic career. Indeed Carnap and Philip Frank made some effort to secure for him a professorship in Prague, but he was rejected on anti-semitic grounds.

9 Letter Carnap to Neurath, 19 December 1934 (VCA).10 Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule (1933) in Neurath’s Gesammelte

bildpädagogische Schriften, edited by Rudolf Haller & Robin Kinross (Vienna, Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1991), 287.

11 Letter Neurath to Carnap, 28 December 1934 (VCA-m).12 International picture language, 20 & 32. 13 ‘Visual education’, in Encyclopedia and utopia: the life and work of Otto Neurath (1882–

1945), edited by Elisabeth Nemeth & Friedrich Stadler (Dordrecht/Boston/ London: Kluwer, 1996), 330.

14 From hieroglyphics to Isotype: a visual autobiography (London: Hyphen Press, 2010), 104.15 Letter Neurath to R. W. Moore, 23 May 1944 (Otto & Marie Neurath Isotype

54

Collection; Department of Typography & Graphic Communication, University of Reading [henceforth IC] 1/10).

16 From hieroglyphics to Isotype, 102.17 Müller, ‘Neurath’s theory of pictorial-statistical representation’, in Rediscovering the

forgotten Vienna Circle, edited by T. E. Uebel (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1991), 232.18 ‘Universal jargon and terminology’ (1941) in Neurath, Philosophical papers 1913–

1946, edited by Marie Neurath & Robert S. Cohen (Dordrecht/Boston: Reidel, 1983), 229.

19 Neurath cited from Thomas E. Uebel’s translation in Overcoming logical positivism from within, 74.

20 Carnap, ‘Autobiography’ in The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, edited by P. A. Schilpp (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1963), 29.

21 ‘Protocol statements’ (1932/3), Philosophical papers, 91.22 ‘Pseudorationalism of falsification’ (1935), Philosophical papers, 128. Neurath

pointed out that Carnap’s view of protocol sentences differed from his own on this point.

23 ‘Protocol statements’, 91.24 A similar suggestion is made by Michelle Henning in ‘Living life in pictures:

Isotype as modernist cultural practice, New Formations (no. 70, Winter 2011): 41–59. I am grateful to her for letting me read it in draft.

25 Neurath [uncredited], ‘Form und Farbe der Mengenbilder des Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseums’, Das Bild (October 1929), 193.

26 Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule, 283; From hieroglyphics to Isotype, 103–4.

27 From two slightly variant translations of ‘Wege der wissenschaftlichen Weltauf-fassung’ (1930): the first paragraph is taken from Empiricism and sociology, 82; and the second from Philosophical papers, 46.

28 Feigl, ‘The Wiener Kreis in America’, in The Intellectual migration: Europe and America, 1930–1960, edited by Donald Fleming and Bernard Bailyn (Cambridge, Mass: Bellknap/Harvard University Press, 1969), 659.

29 ‘Foundations of the social sciences’, International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol. 2, no. 1, 48, n. 19.

30 Letters: Neurath to Morris, 5 January 1938; Morris to Neurath 30 January 1938; Neurath to Morris & Carnap, 14 February 1938. (English translation by the author; VCA-m.) For more on the relationship between Neurath and Morris, see George Reisch, ‘Disunity in the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science’, in Logical empiricism in North America, edited by Gary L. Hardcastle & Alan W.

55The Linguistic Status of Isotype

Richardson (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2003), 197–215.31 The omission of Semiotic[s] and the favouring of Significs was repeated in

Neurath’s essay ‘Universal jargon and terminology’.32 ‘Unified science as encyclopedic integration’, International Encyclopedia of Unified

Science, vol. 1, no. 1, 21.33 Patrick Meredith, ‘The Visual Education Centre, Exeter’, Nature (no. 3907,

16 September 1944): 355.34 Letter Neurath to Meredith, 15 May 1944 (IC 1/35). Neurath had made a simi-

lar point previously in print, warning of the dangers of the ‘hasty postulate’ of ‘complete definiteness’. (‘Ways of the scientific world-conception’, Philosophical papers, 45–6.) His scepticism was echoed fifty years later by the coiner of the phrase ‘the pictorial turn’, W. J. T. Mitchell, in Picture theory: essays on verbal and visual representation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994): ‘… settled answers of a systematic kind may be impossible. This may well be an introduction to a discipline (the general study of representations) that does not exist and never will.’ (7) Mitchell continues: ‘I am skeptical about the possibility both of transdiscipli-nary theory and of avoiding “bias” or achieving neutrality in the metalanguages of representation. Although I have great respect for the achievements of semiot-ics, and draw upon it frequently, I’m convinced that the best terms for describing representations, artistic or otherwise, are to be found in the immanent vernaculars of representational practices themselves.’ (14–15, n. 10)

35 Unsent letter from Neurath to Meredith, 22 January 1944 (IC 1/35). ‘Logic’ is a surprising addition to Neurath’s index verborum prohibitorum, which has been usefully reconstructed by George Reisch in ‘Economist, epistemologist … and censor? Otto Neurath’s index verborum prohibitorum’, Perspectives on Science (vol. 5, no. 3, 1997): 452–80.

36 Letter Neurath to Meredith, 15 May 1944 (IC 1/35). Neurath’s erratic use of commas in English has been corrected here.

37 Meredith, ‘Visual education in the war for health’, Health Education Journal (vol. 1, no. 3, July 1943): 124–9.

38 Unsent letter from Neurath to Meredith, 22 January 1944. Neurath made a similar point in both ‘Visual education’ (320) and From hieroglyphics to Isotype (109), imply-ing that his discussion with Meredith helped him to formulate his position.

39 Letter Marie Neurath to Meredith, 29 July 1946 (IC 1/35).40 Letter Neurath to Bühler, 5 September 1937 (VCA-m). Neurath also discussed fund-

ing with the Carnegie Foundation (New York) to publish a book based on tests made with Isotype material. (Letter Neurath to Charles Morris, 6 January 1937; VCA-m.)

56 The Linguistic Status of Isotype

41 Letter Neurath to Meredith, 10 June 1941 (IC 1/35).42 Letter Neurath to H.E. Kleinschmidt, 8 July 1945 (IC 1/46).43 Letter Neurath to Meredith, 20 July 1944 (IC 1/35).44 Letter Neurath to Moore, 27 December 1944 (IC 1/10). Moore had mentioned

reservations about Isotype in a lecture at the Royal Society, London.45 Letter Neurath to F. R. Cowell, 13 March 1944 (IC 1/8).46 ‘Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode’ (1931), Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften,

185.47 Marie Neurath, ‘Bildpädagogik’, Die Erziehung ( Jg. 7, H. 5, 1932): 315.48 From hieroglyphics to Isotype, 102.49 Letter Otto to Paul Neurath, 27 February 1944 (Nachlaß Otto & Marie Neurath,

Österreichische Nationalbibliothek [henceforth ÖNB]).50 Letter Neurath to Meredith, 24 October 1941 (IC 1/35). See also ‘Visual educa-

tion’, 319.51 ‘Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode’ (1931), Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften,

184.52 Letter Otto to Paul Neurath, 15 October 1945 (ÖNB).53 Letter Neurath to Meredith, 27 January 1941 (IC 1/35). 54 ‘Sociology in the framework of physicalism’ (1931), Philosophical papers, 62.55 From hieroglyphics to Isotype, 102.56 Undated letter Neurath to H.E. Kleinschmidt [1945] (IC 1/46).57 letter Neurath to H. E. Kleinschmidt, 8 July 1945 (IC 1/46). By contrast, Carnap

wrote of ‘transformation rules’, which he equated to ‘logical rules of deduction’, and he considered them ‘completely formulable in syntactical terms’. Logical syntax of language (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., 1937), 2.

58 Letter Paul to Otto Neurath, 21 December 1945 (ÖNB). (This was the day before Otto Neurath died, so he did not receive the letter.) The occasionally emotional content of this letter reveals that there were deeper, personal aspects to the disa-greement between father and son, which are beyond the scope of this paper.

59 Letter Neurath to Mr James (Calcium Chloride Association, Detroit), 26 November 1941 (IC 1/4).

60 ‘Museums of the future’, Survey graphic (no. 9, 1933): 479; see also ‘Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Sowjetunion’ (1932) and ‘Die pädagogische Welt-bedeutung der Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode’ (1933), Gesammelte bildpädago-gische Schriften, 207 & 241.

61 Weibel, ‘Bildsprache und wissenschaftliche Visualisierung’, ALWS Kirchberg, 10 August 2010. Weibel contended further that Neurath did not grasp the ‘digital

57The Linguistic Status of Isotype

revolution’—but the digital revolution occurred long after Neurath’s death. Should Johann Gutenberg be similarly criticized, despite the benefits that printing with movable type has brought us for more than half a millennium?

62 Objectivity (New York: Zone books, 2007), 377. Daston & Galison’s description of the expert with trained judgment corresponds precisely to the Isotype transformer: ‘The expert (unlike the sage) can be trained and (unlike the machine) is expected to learn—to read, to interpret, to draw salient, significant structures from the morass of uninteresting artifact and background.’ (328). There are some intriguing parallels between the historical, visual material examined by Daston & Galison and Neurath’s own selection in From hieroglyphics to Isotype.

Unless otherwise stated in captions, all images are taken from the Otto & Marie Neurath Isotype Collection; Department of Typography & Graphic Communication, University of Reading, UK. This essay stems from research carried out for the project ‘Isotype revisited’, funded by the Arts & Humanities Research Council and conducted at the Department of Typography & Graphic Communication, University of Reading, UK.

Scientific Attitude and Picture Language.Otto Neurath on Visualisation in Social Sciences*

Elisabeth Nemeth, Vienna

I have heard with great interest about the latest developments in relativity theory which can be traced to your conception that gravity as a function depends on the total distribution of mass and remains constant toward certain transform-ations (for example, rotation). It was this idea in your Mechanics which has never left me since my first reading, and has influenced my own intellectual development and by indirect paths even economics itself. It was your tendency to derive the meaning of particulars from the whole rather than the meaning of the whole from a summation of the particulars, which has been so important. It is in value theory in particular that these impulses have benefited me through indirect paths.1

These lines are taken from an undated letter from the front which Otto Neurath wrote to Ernst Mach, probably in 1915. Although serving as an officer in Galicia at the time, he was evidently resolved not to lose sight of his scientific career as an economist and, indeed, to advance it as far as possible. It was probably not long after writing this letter that he suggested to the War Ministry that a research post be set up and commissioned to document the experiences of the war economy for subsequent research work. The Ministry took up the proposal and put Neurath in charge of the post.2

In 1917 he obtained his habilitation in political economy at the Uni- versity of Heidelberg, thereby establishing himself as an expert on ‘state-run economic systems’, as the title of his habilitation lecture: economy in kind, war economy, planned economy. This specialisation was certainly in keeping with his work before the war, albeit with an emphasis due primarily to develop-ments during the war. Indeed prior to 1914 Neurath’s studies of the theory of war economy was only one facet of a complete scientific œuvre remark-

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 59–83.

60 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

able for its extraordinary breadth. It ranged from works on the sociology of religion in the Balkan states to banking and finance under the Monarchy, the impact of state interventions on pricing, and the history of optics, without forgetting philosophy. For Neurath, at the core of it all was nothing less than a new theoretical foundation of economics that would make it possible to bring together, in a fruitful way, the two main adversaries of the time: the histori-cal school of national economy, with its empirical orientation and its view of national economies as entities on the one hand, and the Austrian school with its mathematical methods and its emphasis on the individual appreciation of commodities as the basis of the value theory on the other.3 In his letter to Mach Neurath alludes to this highly ambitious project, a project on which he had already begun to elaborate around 1910 in a number of writings on the theory of social sciences and the value theory, and which he had also presented in his contributions to the debates on methods an values at the Social Policy Association.4

It will suffice, for our purposes, to sketch out Neurath’s project in a few broad outlines. Given that his economic theories were long considered absolutely abstruse and that, to this day, his terminology requires a degree of familiar-isation, it should be said that his economic approaches have proved more robust—to use a contemporary buzzword—than could ever have been thought. Since the 1990s they have been the subject of serious consideration in ecological economics; his contributions have also re-emerged in welfare and development economics and are now being discussed again in the context of Amartya Sen’s capability approach.5

In one of his most important essays on the value theory 6 Neurath advo-cated adopting ‘wealth’ as the subject matter of national economy, thus reviving a tradition that stretches from Aristotle to Adam Smith. Neurath believed that in spite of its venerable roots it was a tradition that had virtually disappeared from modern theory, to his mind quite wrongly.

In referring to wealth as the subject matter of national economy we are concurring with an ancient tradition. By wealth we mean the totality of pleasure and displeasure to be found in individuals and groups of individuals. The term pleasure, according to our usage, has the advantage of embracing both complex and primitive facts simultaneously.7

61Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

In Neurath’s view, the fact that economists have concentrated on the logic of exchange circumstances under market conditions, as represented in the unity of money, has all too narrowed the economic view. He felt that the price theory was often treated as if prices were an accurate representation of wealth. Admittedly, there are also ideological reasons for this constricted view: ‘The classical school of economics has examined one unique form of such systems of organisation, free competition, and it has praised it just like the mercantilists praised theirs.’8 But according to Neurath, the influence of an anachronistic science ideal was more important for such a restriction. And while such an ideal—the mechanistic—had long since been overcome in the natural sciences, it was very much alive and well in monetary and price theory. It re-emerges here as the ideal of the calculability of economic value with the aid of a single unit.

When Neurath defines wealth as the ‘totality of pleasure and displeasure to be found in individuals and groups of individuals’, it is not because he wishes to introduce a unit of measurement other than the monetary. Rather, he pro-poses a terminology that prevents us from looking for a unit in the first place that might serve as the basis for calculating the welfare of individuals or groups. Neurath justifies the terminological decision in favour of ‘pleasure’ with the fact that the term ‘in our usage embraces both complex and primitive facts to an equal degree’. The expression does not readily suggest that we search for an element that might serve as a unit of measurement for the whole. Accord-ingly, in Neurath’s wealth theory, ‘pleasure’ and ‘displeasure’ include elements as different as: the pleasure and displeasure afforded us by good/bad food; living conditions; clothing; good or bad working conditions; access to education or exclusion from it; but also the enjoyment to be gained from a professional or leisure activity; satisfaction through social recognition; access to culture such as theatre, music and museums; involvement in public life; etc. From 1917 Neurath refers to this constellation of different elements as the ‘life circumstance’, and it is with this conceptual understanding that his approach is now once again being discussed.9

As Neurath says, the approach aimed at conceiving of wealth as composed of fundamentally different types of elements is based on a decision. It consists in introducing ‘wealth as a comparable quantity, albeit one that is not measur-able’10. Even under this prerequisite the wealth of individuals and groups can be studied accurately, according to Neurath. True, we need to use more developed mathematical models than a calculus which captures a complex by reducing

62 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

its elements to a unit of measurement. According to Neurath, it is the modern methods of relational calculus that will enable economists to compare system-atically different constellations of dissimilar elements of wealth.

Neurath was aware that this comparative approach poses immense prob-lems of methodology. And he realised that the question of selecting the right methods for assessing these heterogeneous constellations was of the utmost methodological importance. So what were in his view, in 1911, suitable means for representing and systematically comparing such heterogeneous constel-lations: curves? formulæ? tables? In Neurath’s view neither curves nor formulæ are suitable for grasping the problems that are involved here. For Neurath, geometric representations are often detrimental to scientific analyses: because of them, one ‘all too easily transfers to the substrate characteristics that pertain to the geometric figures rather than to the substrate which they represent’. He added that geometric representation easily leads to ‘using simple curves and to neglect cases that might for instance require isolated dots for the represen-tation’.11 They were also an invitation ‘to formulate all problems in such a way that only two or at most three variables occur in each case’.12

Neurath was also of the view that efforts to express observed connections using formulæ can easily be misleading. Indeed, ‘formulæ are particularly apposite in cases where one approximately knows the nature of a connection, even if its details are unknown.’13 And in the area Neurath is concerned with, that is precisely not the case. He is therefore in favour of using the much older table form. Why?—Because tables allow us first of all to describe complexes that are still unknown to us. Even in cases where a great deal remains un-determined, they allow us to achieve clarity and

to monitor simultaneous changes of entire constellations. […] In investigations such as those practice demands, one is required to look into complexes that are entirely unknown to one and which one must first describe. The table form makes it possible to follow separately the variations of each individual combin-ation in a clearly structured way. […] Tabular representation allows random indeterminacy; gaps can be noted; etc. In such indeterminate cases geometric representation fails completely as one cannot very well draw an ‘indeterminate’ curve that may prove to be a series of isolated points. If one renders the theoretical representation and the concrete description in table form, one has the great advantage that one can carry out all the transitions from the most general to the most specific analyses in an analogue form.14

63Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

The two terms ‘describe’ and ‘variation’ are key concepts in Ernst Mach’s epistemology, and it is no coincidence that they should occur at precisely this point in Neurath. Let us remind ourselves of the letter to Ernst Mach men-tioned at the outset, a letter in which Neurath links his ideas in the field of economics with Mach’s The Science of Mechanics. At this point I would like to say a few words—very briefly—about Mach.15 In his Science of Mechanics—indeed in precisely the place to which Neurath alluded in his letter with his reference to the theory of relativity—Ernst Mach suspended, as it were, the classic formula of the law of inertia because he believed that the nature of the connection as formulated by the law had to be rethought. His famous studies of Newton’s terminology (in particular the way in which Newton intro-duced the concept of absolute space and absolute time) ultimately led Mach to propose a new formulation in which gravitation appears as a function of the entire mass distribution of the universe. In this critical reconstruction of key elements of Newtonian physics Mach himself saw only one example of something far more general. Something he did not tire of highlighting as an essential—perhaps even the essential—momentum of scientific progress: namely the dissolution of concepts which, to contemporary research, appear as established once and for all. Mach believed that it had to be shown time and time again that even the most firmly established concepts were merely auxiliary constructs that served to do nothing other than give a provisional account of relations extant between our experiences. And while such auxiliary constructs cannot be dispensed with—whether in our everyday lives or in science—we do tend to forget that we were the ones who introduced our concepts—as auxiliary constructs that help to give an account of the relations between our experiences. Lest we forget this, Mach demands that we should also keep dissolving the most firmly established concepts and formulæ (particularly those) so that we do not perceive them as something independ-ent of ourselves and allow them to become obstacles to our knowledge.

That is precisely the context in which Mach sees research into the history of science as an essential part of natural science itself. And it is also the context in which he explains what his theory of elements is about. No researcher, says Mach, can detach himself from historical developments; he always builds on findings already acquired, correcting them here and there, following them up elsewhere, and ‘also adding his own errors, often unnoticed, to those of his predecessors and contemporaries’.16 Such errors are due not least to the fact that ‘it was very much a matter of chance, of practical need, of earlier inves-

64 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

tigations, as to which elements emerged as the more important, which ones received the attention, and which ones remained unheeded’.17 We cannot undo the path, writes Mach, the attention of past researchers has taken in history, nor would it be desirable to do so. For even if we were to succeed in returning to ‘the entirely naive standpoint’, it would offer the advantage of uncondition-ality, but also its disadvantage: namely ‘the confusion resulting from the com-plication of the task and the impossibility of beginning an investigation’.18 The steps backwards into the past which Mach has in mind are of a different type. They should not lead us to a primitive standpoint, but to something which Mach calls ‘artificial naivety’. A resolution into Machian ‘elements’ is con-ceivable only from the starting point of a high level of scientific thinking:

So if today we appear to return to a primitive standpoint in order to conduct anew the research by better routes, it is an artificial naivety that does not surren-der the advantages gained over a long cultural journey, but on the contrary uses insights which presuppose a fairly high level of physical, physiological and psychological thinking. It is only on such a level that a resolution in ‘elements’ is conceivable. It is about a return to the starting points of research with the deeper and richer insight brought about precisely by the research that went before.19

It is my contention that, with his extremely broad definition of the wealth of individuals and groups, Neurath was seeking to adopt such a standpoint of ‘artificial naivety’ for the field of economics. By using different, non- mutually derivable elements as determinations of the phenomenon of wealth (and poverty), he introduced to economics an approach analo-gous to that of Mach in the fields of physics, physiology and psychol-ogy. Mach stressed the fact that—contrary to a common misconcep-tion—his theory of elements was not about finding some ultimate units which definitively could not be broken down any further. Rather, it was a matter of starting from complex findings and breaking them down into ‘elements that cannot currently be broken down any further’.20 The elements repeatedly listed by Mach by way of example—‘colours, tones, pres-sures, heat, odours, spaces, times, etc.’—clearly show that he meant largely to invalidate the traditional classifications for physical, physiological and psychological objects. It is not for nothing that most philosophers regarded Mach’s elements as nothing other than a mishmash from which they

65Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

turned away in disgust. Neurath did not fare much better with his wealth elements: they are just as confusingly heterogeneous as Mach’s elements.

It is important to see that, for Mach and Neurath, the willingness to adopt such an artificially naïve approach represents an essential moment in the scientific attitude. The value of that approach is not motivated morally (e. g. as a virtue of personal modesty), but epistemologically: the scientist needs such an approach if he (or she) is not to succumb to the seductive power of extant concepts.21

The key link with Neurath’s ‘Visual Education’ is precisely here. In a lengthy text written in the last few years of his life titled ‘Visual Education. Humanization versus Popularisation’ (published in 1995) Neurath differen-tiated what picture language was meant to achieve from what he referred to as the ‘popularisation’ of knowledge:

Generally speaking, on an average, books destined for children and the man in the street […] try to simplify the highest level of scientific formulation, presented in scientific books. Sometimes writers think that a translation of well-selected terms into popular terms is sufficient, whereas it is common knowledge that the insufficiency of these terms was the main reason for the introduction of scientific terms. This kind of translating from the complicated to the simple, from top to bottom, as it were, we shall call Popularisation of knowledge.22

Let us focus on what, from Neurath’s point of view, is problematic about popularisation. According to Neurath, the main reason for introducing scientific terms was that everyday language often proved inadequate when it came to formulating certain complex issues and their connections as precisely as scientists require. The popularisation that seeks to dumb down, as it were, the artificial language of science must therefore be misleading. So when Neurath speaks out against the top-down strategy of popular- isation in favour of a bottom-up strategy and refers to it as the ‘humanisation’ of knowledge, it would be a mistake to consider everyday language as such as the starting point (i. e. the ‘bottom’). The terms used in both scientific and everyday language mislead us towards the uncontrolled use of terms handed down to us. In both cases the strategy of choice—for both Neurath and Mach—is ‘artificial naivety’, which is deliberately aimed at perceiving our terms as sets of heterogeneous elements whose relations to one another we need to describe.

66 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

There are many people who become uneasy when confronted with a general term like ‘magnetism’ but who would not be irritated by a heading like ‘magnetic and magnets and iron’. Why should we not start with the pupil’s own realm and his own tools for expression and analysis? ‘Electricity’ is not a term to be used at a lower stage. By speaking of some piece of glass being ‘electric’ if it behaves in a certain way, and of such simple observation-statements, one avoids the misleading questions ‘what is electricity’, ‘what is gravity’, ‘what is life’? If we speak of living bodies when they behave in a certain way, we can go on to describe a virus, which is sometimes crystallised, sometimes propagating etc.23

Let us now turn to Neurath’s pictograms. They have been somewhat re- discovered and reappreciated in recent years.24 I would like to begin my thoughts on Neurath’s picture language with a passage which occurs several times in Neurath’s writings and which has often been cited in recent years. In my opinion it has been thoroughly misunderstood time and time again. According to Neurath, it is important for the ‘teaching-picture’ that it is created according to the following method: ‘At the first look you see the most important points, at the second, the less important points, at the third, the details, at the fourth, nothing more—if you see more, the teaching-picture is bad.’25

The misunderstanding about this passage, which I intend to repudiate in the following, consists in assuming that the criterion of a successful visuali-sation according to Neurath lies in the speed with which its content can be grasped. From that point of view one would have to deduce from Neurath’s remarks quoted above that the—perhaps unattainable—ideal case would be one where the visualised contents are grasped instantly, i. e. at a glance. The second and third glance would be nothing other than necessary evils, to be minimised of course; and in the case of a particularly successful visualisation they might not even be necessary. Frank Hartmann appears to be saying precisely that when, following the quotation, he explicitly writes: ‘A statement has to be recognisable at first glance.’26 And by way of example Hartmann cites a passer-by who also comes up in Neurath: he has little time and is able, en passant as it were, ‘to roughly take in the information in passing’.

This fictional passer-by is an important indication of where—I believe—the misunderstanding comes from. The pictograms used by Neurath began to take the world by storm in the 1930s, notably as symbols used for orientation purposes in public spaces and in our everyday world (operating instructions).

67Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

To this day we live with the ‘talking pictures’ designed for the most part by Gerd Arntz and to the dissemination of which Neurath contributed a great deal in his countless publications. (See picture 1 and picture 2.)

Picture 1. Picture 2.

So Neurath accurately recognised the role of these pictures in guidance systems for public spaces and assessed their future significance quite correctly. That includes presenting information so that it can be grasped as quickly as possible. However this function must not be confused with the method’s intended purpose, for which Marie Neurath, Otto’s third wife, invented the name Isotype (‘International System of Typographic Picture Education’). The name designates the main methodological principle through which the Vienna method differs from other visualisation methods. It does so by com-bining the two Greek words ‘isos’ (equal) and ‘typos’ (character). Differences in the size of quantities are to be represented by the juxtaposition of pictorial characters of the same shape and size—rather than by pictorial characters of dif-ferent sizes. The most famous example from the Vienna period features the long queues of the unemployed (see picture 3). Neurath further illustrated the point of the Vienna Method of Pictorial Statistics (the older name for the ISOTYPE method) by comparing it with examples of poor visualisation (see pictures 4 and 5 overleaf). Similarly analogous references to poor visualisation can also be found in today’s publications on the theory of visualisation (see picture 6).27

68 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

Picture 4.

Picture 5.

Picture 6.

Picture 3.

69Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

What is particularly interesting in our context is the way in which Neurath explained the main advantages of the methodological principle in Isotype.Here—in picture 7—Neurath shows us four different ways of visualising quantitative data: squares, circles, rectangles, and groups of figures. In all four cases sets are related to one another, specifically sets 1 and 2, and sets A and B, with A as a subset of 1, and B as a subset of 2. Neurath then strikingly demon-strates that the visualisation method used in each case determines how much the observer finds out about the size ratios. In the first case (the representation using squares) we can only determine the absolute size differences between A and B and between 1 and 2. The circles (example 2) already contain more information: with the help of the segments we can determine quantitatively the ratio of subsets A and B in relation to each of the total sets 1 and 2. Admittedly, the comparison between sets 1 and 2 (between the two circles) is limited to ascertaining an absolute difference in size. If we now consider the rectangles consisting of units (example 3), we can also work out for the first time the quantitative relation between set 1 and set 2. Finally the fourth case (groups of figures) is different from the others. Here it is not about the infor-mation on the set ratios being more abundant. The benefit is on another level, namely the memory level: we directly perceive which objects are involved and are therefore also better able to remember what objects were involved.

Picture 7.

70 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

So a key aspect is that Neurath’s visualisation method is not about re-presenting a statement in such a way that it can be perceived at a single glance. Indeed, Neurath constructs his charts in such a way that it is impos-sible to grasp what they have to say at one glance. That is probably also the reason why the Isotype method is virtually never used in today’s newspapers and why pie charts dominate instead. This phenomenon is not down to the fact that the Isotype method has been forgotten. The graphic artists of today’s Austrian Social and Economic Museum were specifically told by journal-ists that the Isotype method was too complicated for today’s readers.28 They would need too much time and too much attention to understand an Isotype graphic. It should be noted that Neurath was well aware that reading his pictograms required a degree of practice.—So what, then, is the advantage of the whole thing if it is not to provide people with information that can be grasped at a single glance?

Let us remind ourselves of Neurath’s project for a renewed economic theory. He was looking for a method that would be capable of describing the life circumstance of an individual or population as the embodiment of quite disparate elements. Neurath was already advocating that size ratios should not be calculated in figures but represented symbolically instead. In his extensive critique of Wundt’s Logik from 1910 he wrote:

Even Wundt, who after all does also consider exact logic and the parts of mathematics that do not deal with measurable quantities, does not indicate that the method of symbolic-exact representation and that of quantitative-exact representation do not have to coincide at all.29

Indeed, with the aid of symbols, it would be possible to compare heterogeneous entities precisely with one another without having to reduce their components to a uniform standard. Neurath made clear at the time what he had in mind by referring to the way in which pictures are compared.

One cannot compare two states by comparing them bit by bit, say first the constitution, then the climate etc.; each of them has to be comprehended as a whole. After all, neither can we compare pictures in this way, nor can we do this with respect to machines. The very idea of a calculus, however, consists of deriving a complex from the individual elements.30

71Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

Pictorial statistics provide a much clearer idea of what Neurath had in mind in this early text. For the comparisons that mattered to him to be carried out, the ‘pictures’ of the states that are to be compared have to be structured in a particular way. If we choose the first visualisation method (using squares), our judgements will have to be limited to form ‘A is larger than …’. To achieve greater precision, we would have to make a separate calculation. In this particular example that would be very easy to do (measure the sides of the squares, and calculate their surface areas and the difference between them). The calculation would end in a precise figure, namely the difference in sur-face area in mm². The precision is, of course, obtained using a method that replaces our visually guided comparative judgement. In more complicated cases the calculation would have to be made by an expert, aided perhaps by a computer.

By contrast the visualisation method which Neurath advocated is based on an approach in which the added precision is achieved in quite a different way, namely by comparing back and forth between two constellations of elements. The contrasted constellations trigger certain activities in the observer: ‘con-siderations’ in which she constructs the comparison herself. What is important to note here is that the pictorial representation conceived by Neurath can-not by any means replace the language of words. On the contrary. It is only in the case of the visualisation method he rejected (in the case of squares or of pictures of different size) that we can grasp what the comparison says directly, as it were, without language, at a glance: larger—smaller. By contrast the Isotype pictures are constructed discursively. We cannot grasp what they represent through immediate ‘intuition’ (using a philosophical expression of long tradition), but only by ‘going back and forth’ and gradually uncovering what the comparison is about. This is shown very nicely in the chart on the automobile industry. (Picture 8)

Here we see at first glance that many more cars are manufactured in North and South America than in Europe. In a next step—by adding up how many people work in each car industry—we see that eleven times more cars are man-ufactured per worker in America than in Europe. And in a third step we find out how this enormous difference comes about: behind the workers in America we can make out the conveyor belt. So again: without putting what we see into words, we will not grasp what is represented in the pictures. But we can and must find our own words for that—ideally in discussions and conversations about what is shown, such as those which, according to Neurath, were often to

72 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

be observed at the Social and Economic Museum. Neurath made many interesting observations about the educational implications of this experience and their significance in terms of democratic policy. But we cannot go into them here.

Here it is first and foremost a matter of understanding the Isotype method as an intellectual tool designed to make observers of the pictorial statistic charts perceive societies from a particular point of view: as collections of dif-ferent elements of individual pleasure and displeasure, of life opportunities and restrictions that can be unevenly distributed within a group of individu-als. The charts draw our attention to the fact that the distribution depends on factors that concern the whole of a population, a nation, a group, etc. However, the visualisation is structured in such a way that the individuals do not disappear within the whole to which they belong.31 On the contrary the observer has no option but to reconstruct a social whole, in each step of his comparison, as heterogeneous totalities of individual life circumstances. Through this means of visually guided judgement we experience the fact that what we see as the well-being of individuals and groups can vary sharply in scope and content depending on the point of view from which we consider them. And also that a great deal depends on the work and the imagination of those who seek to make societal facts visible. What those facts are will depend on which aspects of human life—and how many—they include in

Picture 8.

73Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

their observation, and what influencing factors they are seeking to address as a topic.32 In this process of visualisation of social facts it is by no means just social scientists, statisticians and graphic artists who are called upon. Observers, too, who are prepared to engage with the charts of pictorial statistics, so to speak as readers, will realise that deciphering the charts entails work and that the work involved frees up the imagination. If the charts are well made, they capture only a few aspects of a population’s life circumstance and represent them in several constellations. Good pictorial statistics, according to Neurath, are limited to correlating a clearly demarcated set of contents for the purposes of mutual comparison.33 And it is precisely because the Isotype representation

limits itself to representing only a few clearly defined data in correlation that it gives the observer something to think about. Here science does not emerge as the authoritative body that issues explanations and demands from non-scientists that they follow the explanations. The question of which causes are responsible for the differences between the compared constellations is suggested whenever an Isotype chart is considered. In many cases it can be regarded as the key point of the entire comparison and fully imposes itself on the observer. Of course it is strik-ing that, within the charts, the question of causal relationships is only rarely posited and answered explicitly – one of the examples in which this does happen is the conveyor belt at a car manufacturing plant (see picture 8). While in some charts the question of the causes does impose itself, it cannot be answered from the chart itself (e. g. the cycles of unemployment in picture 3). Some charts juxtapose size ratios where the question of a cause

Picture 9.

74 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

barely seems relevant (e. g. the case of housing density in cities, picture 9); in others a dependence between sizes becomes visible for which a causal inter-pretation seems irrefutable (e. g. the chart on ‘Home and factory weaving in England’, picture 10). The fact that the representation using pictorial statistics usually leaves unanswered the way in which the dependency between the represented sizes is to be interpreted is anything but a coincidence or an omission. Rather, Neurath is following an agenda inspired once again by Ernst Mach: Mach believed that the concept of cause was an anthropomor-phism that ought best to be eliminated from science altogether. Likewise the notion of the unity of science is one which Neurath borrowed directly from Mach. As Neurath wrote in 1945: ‘The educational background for Visual Education is that of Unified Science. The Unity of Science Movement is really concerned with a common terminology and with replacing e. g. a ‘cause-effect’ terminology by a ‘grow-out-of ’ terminology’.34 It is perhaps worth mentioning that a line could be reconstructed here, leading from Ernst Mach to Neurath to today’s widespread theories of ‘emergence’.

Sometimes though, as in the chart on ‘infant mortality in Vienna’ (picture 11), our attention is actually drawn to a whole range of factors that has an impact on the level, composition and distribution of well-being within a population. But even in this case it is not about naming an individual cause for

Picture 10.

75Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

the distributions and the way in which they change. We are dealing here with a comparison in two dimensions: between the periods 1901 to 1905 and 1925 to 1929, and also between two municipal districts of Vienna. Each of the four pictures shows 20 babies, with several of them obscured by small coffins. They symbolise the children who died before reaching their first birthday. We see at first glance that, overall, the number of small coffins in the 1920s is dramatically smaller than at the beginning of the century: infant mortal-ity fell by more than half in 20 years—a remarkable success story. We can imagine how the visitors at the Social and Economic Museum might have paused for thought and then wondered: what brought about this dramatic improve-ment? Hygiene measures, medicine, better nutrition? So while the picture raises the questions of the factors involved, it does not answer them. It focuses the attention on the second dimension of the comparison: the differences between the ‘more affluent’ and the ‘poorer’ districts of Vienna. Expressed in absolute figures, the drop in child mortality is the same in both districts: in both districts there are two small coffins fewer than in the years 1901–1905.

Of course for the wealthier 7th district that means a reduction of two thirds; for the poorer 16th district a reduction of only half. In the 1920s child mor-tality in the working-class district of Ottakring was still twice as high as in the middle-class district of Josefstadt. So how is it that both districts were able to benefit to such varying degrees from the overall improvement? The picture gives at least an indication of the answer to that question: the apart-ment in which the babies of the 7th district are shown is one third bigger

Picture 11.

76 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

and considerably brighter than the one in the 16th district. This refers to the serious housing problem that existed in Vienna between the two World Wars, and the enormous building activity undertaken by the Municipality of Vienna in the 1920s. And yet this pointer can hardly be misunderstood as a mono-causal explanation. It draws attention to the ‘institutions and measures’ that can be taken and are indeed taken. Here again we can well imagine the visi-tors of the Social and Economic Museum wondering and saying to themselves: the larger, airier apartments are one thing—but isn’t medical care just as impor-tant? Or setting up nurseries? Maternal health care? and so on and so forth.

In a genuinely scientific museum it could never be a matter, from Neurath’s point of view, of proclaiming certain answers as the only right answers. He devoted a lifetime to combating ‘pseudorationalism’, which elevates science to the pedestal of a quasi-religious body. Entirely in the tradition of Ernst Mach, Neurath regarded it as the task of science to describe relations between phenomena. And like Mach he was of the opinion that our view of the connections is often obscured by our own traditional concepts. For Mach, science was not just an instrument of enlightenment, but also an ‘enlighten-ing’ activity par excellence. As mentioned earlier, for Mach scientific progress is based on nothing other than the ability and the willingness of research-ers to keep seeing through their previous concepts and theories as auxiliary structures.35 What for Mach as a natural scientist was the progressive value of science in general had a direct political significance for the sociologist and economist Neurath. For Neurath, introducing a scientific approach in the Machian sense to social theory meant developing an approach that highlights connections that would otherwise remain unnoticed as long as there is talk of the ‘nation’, the ‘people’ or the ‘class’ as a whole. It very much takes these entities into account, but considers them as a group of individuals whose life circumstances are characterised by a set of elements whose distribu-tion depends on political, economic, cultural … measures and institutions. The project of making this artificially naive, scientific approach accessible to as many people as possible using visual education meant nothing other than an attempt to create the social preconditions for a discourse in which the issue of the political shaping of the social order in a rational way figures as a topic.

In one of his last writings Neurath once again emphasised the political dimension of this project. He wrote that visual education was not aimed first and foremost at imparting knowledge, but at passing on a ‘scientific

77Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

attitude’, adding that such an attitude was essential to the further develop-ment of democratic societies.

Education is not only the handing on of knowledge, it is also concerned with the ability to analyze observations and to find out something and contemplate all the matter under discussion from all sides. […] The transfer of looking at more than one possibility, to be prepared to alter statements, is the principle of the scientific attitude. The social pattern, which permits more than one opinion etc. is the ‘democratic pattern’. Part of education deals with the evolution of one’s own judgment, of a ‘scientific attitude’, a quality not restricted to scholars only; there are laymen who have it, and there are scientists who do not have it.36

Notes

* This article is a revised version of ‘Wissenschaftliche Haltung und Bildersprache. Otto Neurath zur Visualisierung in den Sozialwissenschaften.’ Tabellen, Kurven, Piktogramme. Techniken der Visualisierung in den Sozialwissenschaften. Vol. 1–2 of Mitteilungen des Instituts fuer Wissenschaft und Kunst: 31–42. The text was translated by Stephen Grynwasser and Naomi Osorio-Kupferblum.

1 An undated letter (probably from 1915) from Otto Neurath to Ernst Mach, Engl.transl. in Blackmore et al. (eds.) 2001, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 117–118.

2 On this and on Neurath’s biography see: Neurath 1973, Paul Neurath 1994, Cartwright, Cat, Fleck, Uebel 1996, Stadler 2001, Uebel 2005b, Cat 2010.

3 Uebel 2004 gives an excellent, comprehensive analysis of Neurath’s economic thought.

4 Neurath (1909) 2004, 292–296. See also Uebel 2004 and 2007.5 See also various examples: Martinez-Alier 1987, O’Neill 1993, 1998, 1999, 2007,

Nemeth and Heinrich (eds.) 1999, Uebel 2004, 2005a, 2007b, Lessmann 2007a and 2007b, Nemeth, Schmitz, Uebel (eds.) 2007.

6 Neurath 1911, reprinted in Neurath 1998, 470–518. Unfortunately this version of the article contains several errors. I therefore decided to use the original text from 1911. All the following quotations from Neurath 1911 were translated by Stephen Grynwasser and Naomi Osorio–Kupferblum.

7 Neurath 1911, 53.8 Neurath (1910) 2004, 272. 9 Contemporary poverty research speaks of the ‘multi–dimensionality’ of poverty

78 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

and wealth (cf. Lessmann 2007a and b), and ecological economics of the ‘incom-mensurability of values’ (cf. Uebel 2005a, 319 f.).

10 In italics in the original. Neurath 1911, p. 80.11 Neurath 1911, 78.12 Neurath 1911, 79.13 Neurath 1911, 80.14 Neurath 1911, 80.15 I have expounded and substantiated what follows in greater detail in Nemeth

2007.16 Mach (1905, 1926) 1991, 14, All the following quotations from Mach (1905, 1926)

1991 were translated by Stephen Grynwasser and Naomi Osorio-Kupferblum.17 Mach (1905, 1926) 1991, 14.18 Mach (1905, 1926) 1991, 14.19 Mach (1905, 1926) 1991, 16–17.20 Mach (1905, 1926) 1991, 8.21 Incidentally, there is an affinity here to Bachelard, Foucault and also Bourdieu.22 Neurath (1945) 1996, 257.23 Neurath (1945) 1996, 257.24 Twyman 1975 and 1985, Kinross 1981, 1984, Stadler (ed.) 1982, Mueller 1991,

Nemeth and Stadler (eds.) 1996, Leonard 2001, Stadler 2002, Hartmann and Bauer 2002, Moravian Gallery 2002, Behnke et al. 2004, Hartmann 2005, Blau 2006, Mertens 2007, Kraeutler 2008, Vossoughian 2008, Neurath Marie and Kinross 2009, Burke 2009, 2010a, Nemeth forthcoming. I want to draw special attention to the edition of a manuscript of the late Neurath which has not been published until 2010: From hieroglyphics to Isotype (see Neurath 2010) and to the excellent introduction by C. Burke (Burke 2010b). The volume includes the numerous illustrations intended by Neurath to accompany his text, and is completed by an extensive appendix showing examples from the rich variety of graphic material that he collected.

25 Neurath (1936) 1980, 23.26 Hartmann 2002, 49.27 The example in the figure is taken from Tufte 2001, 69, who by the way makes no

mention whatsoever of Neurath in his other books on the visualisation theory.28 In a personal discussion following a lecture at the Austrian Museum for Social and

Economic Affairs.29 Neurath (1910) 2004, 277.30 Neurath (1910) 2004, 280.31 For the relationship between holism and individualism in Neurath’s thoughts on

79Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

economics and how it impacts the Isotype method, see Nemeth 2003 and 2006.32 We should refer here to the strong affinity between Neurath’s project and Martha

Nussbaum’s works in the 1990s. See in particular Nussbaum and Sen, eds., 1993. Thoughts on this affinity can also be found in Nemeth 2003 and 2006.

33 That is the point in Neurath’s repeated insistence that a picture should not contain more information than can be grasped in three glances. See the quotation in note 24.

34 Neurath (1945) 1996, 259.35 See: Uebel 2000, 93–95.36 Neurath (1945) 1996, 260.

Literature

Behnke, Christoph, D. Stoller, A. Schlosser and U. Wuggenig, eds. 2004. Atlas. Spaces in subjunctive. Lüneburg: Verlag für Wissenschaft und zeitgenössische Kunst.

Blackmore, John, ed. 2001. Ernst Mach’s Vienna 1895–1930 or Phenomenalism as Philo-sophy of Science, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 218. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Blau, Eve. 2006. ‘Isotype and Architecture in Red Vienna. The Modern Projects of Otto Neurath and Josef Frank.’ Austrian Studies 14: 227–259.

Burke, Christopher. 2009. ‘Isotype. Representing social facts pictorially.’ Information Design Journal 17/3: 210–221.

Burke, Christopher. 2010a. ‘Back to basics: Otto Neurath and Isotype.’ Cambridge Literary Review 1/3: 221–235.

Burke, Christopher. 2010b. Introduction to Neurath 2010: vii–xvi. Cartwright, Nancy, Jordi Cat, Lola Fleck and Thomas E. Uebel. 1996. Otto Neurath:

Philosophy between Science and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCat, Jordi. 2010. ‘Otto Neurath.’ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.

stanford.edu/entries/neurath/Hartmann, Frank and Erwin K. Bauer. 2002. Bildersprache, Otto Neurath, Visualisie-

rungen. Wien: Wiener Universitätsverlag.Hartmann, Frank. 2005. ‘Humanization of Knowledge through the Eye.’, in Making

Things Public – Atmospheres of Democracy, edited by Bruno Latour and Peter Weibel, 698–707. Karlsruhe, Germany: MIT Press and ZKM.

Kinross, Robin. 1981. ‘On the influence of Isotype.’ Information Design Journal 2/21: 122–130.

80 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

Kinross, Robin. 1984. ‘The work of Otto Neurath in visual communication.’ Fundamentum Scientiæ 5/2: 185–99.

Kraeutler, Hadwig. 2008. Otto Neurath. Museum and Exhibition Work. Spaces (Designed) for Communication. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.

Leonard, Robert J. 2001. ‘“Seeing Is Believing” Otto Neurath, Graphic Art, and Social Order.’ History of Political Economy. Special Supplement. 31: 452–47.

Lessmann, Ortrud. 2007a. Konzeption und Erfassung von Armut. Vergleich des Lebenslage-Ansatzes mit Sens ‘Capability’-Ansatz. Berlin: Duncker und Humblot.

Lessmann, Ortrud. 2007b. ‘A Similar Line of Thought in Neurath and Sen: Inter- personal Comparability.’ In Nemeth, Schmitz, Uebel, eds., 115–130.

Mach, Ernst. (1905) 1991. Erkenntnis und Irrtum. Skizzen zur Psychologie der Forschung. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

Martinez-Alier, Joan. 1987. Ecological Economics. Energy, Environment and Society. London: Blackwell.

Mertens, Ferdinand. 2007. ‘Een Wereld – Verbeteraar’, in Den Haag. De Haagse Balling-schap van Otto Neurath. The Hague: Gemeente Den Haag.

Moravian Gallery in Brno. 2002. - a vývoj moderních globálnch znaku, - and the development of modern global signs, Edition Designrevue Cz. Prague: Alba Studio.

Mueller, Karl H. 1991. ‘Neurath’s Theory of Pictorial-Statistical Representation.’ In Thomas E. Uebel, ed., 223–254.

Nemeth, Elisabeth and Friedrich Stadler, eds. 1996. Encyclopedia and Utopia. The Life and Work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945), Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 4/96. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Nemeth, Elisabeth and Richard Heinrich, eds. 1999. Otto Neurath: Rationalität, Planung, Vielfalt. Wiener Reihe 9. Wien-Berlin: Oldenbourg/Akademie.

Nemeth, Elisabeth, Stefan W. Schmitz and Thomas E. Uebel, eds. 2007. Otto Neurath’s Economics in Context. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 13/07. Springer.

Nemeth, Elisabeth. 2003. ‘Gesellschaftliche Tatbestände sichtbar machen. Otto Neurath über den Gegenstand der Wirtschaftswissenschaft und seine Visuali-sierung.’ In Philosophie an der Schwelle des 21. Jahrhunderts, edited by Ewa Czerwinska–Schupp, 181–207. Frankfurt a. M.: Lang.

Nemeth, Elisabeth. 2006. ‘Socially Enlightened Science. Neurath on Social Science and Visual Education.’ In Thèmes de Philosophie Analytique, ed. by Mélika Ouelbani, 83–112. Tunis.

Nemeth, Elisabeth 2007. ‘“Freeing up One’s Point of View”. Neurath’s Machian Heritage Compared with Schumpeter’s.’ In Nemeth, Schmitz, Uebel, eds., 13–36.

81Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

Nemeth, Elisabeth. Forthcoming. ‘Visualising relations in society and economics. Otto Neurath’s Isotype-method against the background of his economic thought.’ In Pointure du Symbole, edited by Jean-Yves Beziau. Paris: editions Petra.

Neurath, Marie and Robin Kinross. 2009. The transformer. Principles of making Isotype charts. London: Hyphen Press.

Neurath, Otto. (1909) 2004. ‘Diskussionsbeitrag ueber die Produktivitaet des Geldes’, translated as ‘Remarks on the Productivity of Money.’ In Neurath 2004, 292–296.

Neurath, Otto. (1910) 2004. ‘Zur Theorie der Sozialwissenschaften’, translated as ‘On the Theory of Social Science.’ In Neurath 2004, 265–291.

Neurath, Otto (1911) 1998. ‘Nationalökonomie und Wertlehre, eine systematische Untersuchung.’ Zeitschrift für Volkswirtschaft, Sozialpolitik und Verwaltung 20: 52–114. Reprinted in Neurath 1998, 470–518.

Neurath, Otto. (1936) 1980: International picture language/Internationale Bildersprache. A facsimile reprint of the [1936] English edition with a German translation by Marie Neurath, published by the Department of Typography & Graphic Communication at the University of Reading.

Neurath, Otto (1945a) 1973. ‘From Vienna Method to Isotype.’ In Neurath 1973, 214–284.

Neurath, Otto (1945b) 1996. ‘Visual Education. Humanisation versus Popularisation’ edited by Juha Manninen. In E. Nemeth and F. Stadler, eds. 1996, 245–335.

Neurath, Otto. 1973: Empiricism and Sociology, edited by Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen, Dordrecht: Reidel.

Neurath, Otto. 1981: Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische Schriften (= Gesammelte Schriften 1 and 2), edited by Rudolf Haller and Heiner Rutte. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

Neurath, Otto. 1991: Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften (= Gesammelte Schriften 3), edited by Rudolf Haller and Robert Kinross. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

Neurath, Otto. 1998. Gesammelte ökonomische, soziologische und sozialpolitische Schriften (= Gesammelte Schriften 4 and 5), edited by Rudolf Haller and Ulf Höfer. Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

Neurath, Otto. 2004. Economic Writings. Selecions 1904–1945, ed. by Thomas E. Uebel and Robert S. Cohen. Vienna Circle Collection 23. Dordrecht: Kluwer

Neurath, Otto. 2010. From hieroglyphics to Isotype. A visual autobiography, ed. by Matthew Eve and Christopher Burke. London: Hyphen Press

Neurath, Paul and Elisabeth Nemeth, eds. 1994. Otto Neurath oder Die Einheit von Wissenschaft und Gesellschaft. Vienna/Cologne/Weimar: Böhlau

82 Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

Neurath, Paul. 1994. ‘Otto Neurath (1882–1945). Leben und Werk.’ In: Paul Neurath and Elisabeth Nemeth, eds., 13–96.

Nussbaum, Martha and Amartya Sen, eds. 1993. The Quality of Life. A Study prepared for the World Institute for Development Economics Research (WIDER) of the United Nations University. Oxford: Clarendon.

O’Neill, John. 1993. Ecology, Policy and Politics: Human Well-Being and the Natural World. London: Routledge.

O’Neill, John. 1998. The Market. Ethics, Knowledge and Politics. London/New York 1998.O’Neill, John. 1999. ‘Socialism, Ecology and Austrian Economics.’ In Nemeth,

Heinrich, eds., 123–145.O’Neill, John. 2007. ‘Pluralism and Economic Institutions.’ In Nemeth, Schmitz,

Uebel, eds., 77–100.Stadler, Friedrich, ed. 1982. Arbeiterbildung in der Zwischenkriegszeit. Otto Neurath, Gerd

Arntz. Ausstellungskatalog mit Forschungsteil. Vienna/Munich: Löcker.Stadler, Friedrich. 2001. Studies on the Vienna Circle. Vienna/New York: Springer.Stadler, Friedrich. 2002. ‘Schriftsprache und Bildsprache nach Otto Neurath –

Popularisierung oder Humanisierung der Wissenschaft?’ In: Wissenschaft, Politik und Öffentlichkeit von der Wiener Moderne bis zur Gegenwart, edited by Mitchell Ash and Christian Stifter, 267–303, Vienna.

Tufte, Edward. 2001. The Visual Display of Quantitative Information. Cheshire: Graphics Press.

Twyman, Michael. 1975. ‘The significance of Isotype.’ http://www.isotyperevisited.org/1975/01/the-significance-of-isotype.html

Twyman, Michael. 1985. ‘Using Pictorial Language: A Discussion of the Dimensions of the Problem.’ In Designing Usable Texts, edited by Thomas Duffy and Robert Walker. Orlando: Academic Press.

Uebel, Thomas E. 2000. Vernunftkritik und Wissenschaft. Otto Neurath und der erste Wiener Kreis im Diskurs der Moderne. Publications of the Vienna Circle Institute 9. Vienna/New York: Springer.

Uebel, Thomas E. 2004. ‘Neurath’s Economics in Critical Context.’ In Otto Neurath 2004, 1–108.

Uebel, Thomas E. 2005a. ‘Incommensurability, Ecology, and Planning. Neurath in the Socialist Calculation Debate, 1919–1928.’ History of Political Economy 37/2: 309–342.

Uebel, Thomas E. 2005b. ‘Otto Neurath. Leben und Werk.’ In Internationale Biblio-graphie zur österreichischen Philosophie. Bearbeitet von T. Binder, R. Fabian, U. Höfer, J. Valent, 7–51. Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.

83Scientific Attitude and Picture Language

Uebel, Thomas E. 2007. ‘Otto Neurath as an Austrian Economist: Behind the Scenes of the Early Socialist Calculation Debate.’ In Nemeth, Schmitz, Uebel, eds., 37–60.

Uebel, Thomas E., ed. 1991. Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Amsterdam: Kluwer.

Vossoughian, Nader. 2008. Otto Neurath. The Language of the Global Polis. Rotterdam: NAi publishers.

Picture Credits

Picture 6 shows page 69 of Edward R. Tufte’s The Visual Display of Quantitative Infor-mation (Cheshire: Graphics Press). His two examples of confusing statistics are taken from R. Satet, Les Graphiques (Paris 1932, p. 12) and the Los Angeles Times (August 5, 1979, p. 3).

Picture 7, the chart on Visualisation Methods, is taken from the 1980 bilingual fac-simile reprint: Otto Neurath: International picture language/Internationale Bildersprache [1936]. Edited by Robin Kinross. Reading: University of Reading, Department of Typography & Graphic Communication 1980.

All other images are taken from: Otto Neurath: Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften (Gesammelte Schriften Band 3), eds. Rudolf Haller and Robin Kinross, Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky 1991.

‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’ Otto Neurath’s Pictorial Statistics

in Historical Context1

Sybilla Nikolow, Bielefeld

In keeping with his principle that ‘metaphysical terms divide, scientific terms unite’ Otto Neurath (1882–1945) wrote in 1931 in the German teacher’s journal Die Volksschule:

Finally it should be noted that the picture education, especially the pictorial statistics, are of international importance. Words carry more emotional elements than set pictures, which can be observed by people of different countries, different parties without any protest; Words divide, pictures unite.2

For the primary aim to communicate empirical based observations Neurath believed his method of pictorial statistics to be a useful tool to transmit rational information across barriers of class, culture and education most effectively.

In figure 1 overleaf one sees Otto Neurath, two years before his untimely death in 1945, in front of a statistical chart on the occasion of an exhibition at the London cinema screening of the documentary The World of Plenty. The film was produced by British director Paul Rotha in cooperation with Neurath.3 In this film animated statistical charts were extensively used to explain the complex cycle of food production and subsequent distribution by the nutritionist Boyd Orr. In addition to that Neurath’s method was used as a voice-over in the film to help ordinary people to understand the figures behind the statistics. Like in other image-guided displays the pictures here were indeed capable of uniting the spectators, but not of speaking for them-selves. Neurath’s method, however, had a discursive element. His statistical

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 85–98.

86 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

charts were meant to encourage a discussion on the information displayed.Following Neurath’s famous slogan ‘words divide, pictures unite’ I will start

with a brief comment on the labelling of his pictorial statistics as language. Yet the main part of my paper will focus on two overlapping historical as-pects of his pictorial work in Red Vienna, rooting in his philosophical and educational intentions. To sum up my argument I will use the example of the peoples of the world in his chart collection Society and Economy published in 1930 to show in greater detail how Neurath’s philosophical and pictorial work went hand in hand.

Labelling his system as an International Picture Language as he did in his booklet from 19364, when he changed the name of his technique from Vienna Method of Pictorial Statistics into International System of TYpographic Picture Education (short Isotype), did not mean that Neurath claimed a general superiority of his system over natural languages.5 Moreover, he did not want his image-guided displays to communicate through visual tools alone. Isotype was developed as an educational aid and instrument for

Fig. 1

Otto Neurath in November 1943,

The Otto and Marie Neurath Isotype Collection (reprinted by permission of the

Department of Typography & Graphic Communication, University of Reading)

87‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

teachers to train the spectators to comprehend complex information. It was by no means intented that the spectators would design their own charts. Neurath was aware of the fact, that images are polysemous and need to be comple-mented by other media to become comprehensible. The design of the charts was a very complex task, because it required a particular expertise.

Isotype was developed closely along the writing system. The pictorial charts include words and numbers as in headings and legends to give precise information about the displayed subject. The symbols themselves were ar-ranged in lines and columns like in writing and charts. Neurath’s pictorial statistics required a structured observation. Isotype was supposed to facili-tate a strong empiricist view on the social order. It was primarily intended to appear in various educational contexts, like reading newspapers, school lessons, lecture halls or films as well in exhibitions. At least the first contact with this kind of visual material was monitored by trained teachers, who assisted the audience in absorbing complex information. In books and news-papers the pictorial statistics were explained by the corresponding text. In other situations a voice guided the acquisition of facts.

Seen from the production side one must say that charts were intended to make social reality comprehensible by generating social facts, which were mostly—but not exclusively—based on quantitative information. Neurath’s aim was to give access to expert information and to base public dis- courses on visual arguments. Isotype was an auxiliary device to observe the social order in a pertinent way. Neurath intended the pictures to unite the audience because the encoding of their visual arguments was supposed to work—generally speaking—regardless of the viewer’s background.

Flying over the Earth with Bird-like Empiricist Eyes

As a social engineer Neurath transcended the confusing variety and complex-ity of the social world. He did not let himself become confused by the chaos of individual impressions, but rather developed a way of observing patterns of social order and behaviour that could signify relevant global changes in time and space. His perspective was bird-like, with the exception that he flew from the North and West to the South and East. Likewise he developed the following thought experiment in explaining how one should view the expan-sion of worldwide capitalism in 1928:

88 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

If one could only fly over the Earth and show everybody, Chinese gardeners live side by side in old fashion. Next to them a capitalist germ cell which puts its feelers out into the country! See the factory chimney smoking! Ships come and go. And in the North, nomads and tribes of hunters who don’t know anything of a capitalist order even though they sell furs to entrepreneurs. A sharpened eye would be able to grasp this. All of this can be grasped and represented in pictures!6

The charts show what his sharp empiricist eyes have seen, especially how dif-ferent elements constitute a social phenomena or how persons, objects and things are linked together, which he claimed to be the only legitimate objects of research in the social sciences published in the Vienna Circle manifesto in 1929 as well in his Empirische Soziologie in 1931 and in his writings in picture education.7

Neuraths occupation with pictorial statistics is closely connected to his philosophical work. Thomas Uebel commented that his method contributed to building the foundations of the Scientific World-Conception, but not mere-ly in a one-way direction.8 Simon Shaffer underlined his argument that during the 20th century the public had a tremendous impact on what was regarded science by referring to the Viennese Museum of Society and Economy as institution that served as an instrument for the Vienna Circle in general and for Neurath in particular to transmit the right image of science to the public, thus fighting metaphysical tendencies as well as irrational and religious belief.9 Neurath’s method was intended to fix information in the mode of protocol statements, that is, to register all variations of a phenomenon in time and space. It became the public trademark of a non-disguised application of the scientific attitude to reality. Elisabeth Nemeth has convincingly shown how Neurath in his early foundation of social science was looking for a way to compare heterogeneous entities in a precise way without reducing the subject to one single denotation and how to use the example to compare two pictures to explain his method.10

Neurath’s philosophical work and political activities went hand in hand with his occupation with the pictorial statistics (in figure 2, statistical pub-lications among his books and editions are set in bold italics). Neurath de-signed the Viennese method in line with his Scientific Conception of the World, which he was advocating as a left-winger of the Vienna Circle and the Unity of Science Movement.11 I agree with Peter Galison and Robert

89‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

Leonard, who consider Neurath’s preoccupation with pictorial statistics as the visual pendant of his philosophical program to renew philosophy on an empirical and rational basis.12 The defined rules of his method, like the simplicity, uniformity and meaningful distinctions of his symbols as well as his syntax, only allow him to display visual arguments that meet the limit-ed standards of protocol sentences. Neurath’s pictorial statistics display a social order in which phenomena were strictly specified through temporal and local functions. As Neurath said, one would not be able to design picto-rial statistics according to the Viennese method for meaningless, all-up or religious statements and beliefs.13

Otto Neurath in Red Vienna

1920 Secretary General of the Research Institute for

Gemeinwirtschaft

1922 Secretary General of the Austrian Union of

Settlements and Allotment Gardens

1922 Gildensozialismus, Klassenkampf und

Vollsozialisierung

1924 Foundation of the Museum for Settlement and

Town Planning in Vienna

1925 Foundation of the Museum of Society and Economy

in Vienna

1928 Foundation of the Vienna Circle

1928 Lebensgestaltung und Klassenkampf,

Die Gewerkschaften1929 Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung (with Hahn

and Carnap), Die Bunte Weltfrom 1929 Schriften zur Wissenschaftlichen

Weltauffassung 1–11 (1929–1937)

1930 Gesellschaft und Wirtschaftfrom 1930 Erkenntnis 1–8 (1930–1938)

1931 Empirische Soziologie

from 1931 Foundation of Museums in Moscow, London,

Amsterdam, New York

1932 Technik und Menschheit1933 Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule1933 Einheitswissenschaft und Psychologie

Fig. 2

Historical chart

of Neurath’s

publications

and activities.

90 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

A Museum of the Future

The institution that allowed Neurath to develop his method was the Vien-nese Museum of Society and Economy (fig. 3). This institution and Neurath’s Viennese Method of Pictorial Statistics were specific outcomes of Red Vienna’s housing and settlement movement of the early 1920s (see also figure 2). As general secretary of the Austrian Union of Settlements and Allotment Gardens, Neurath organized an extensive education program, in-cluding lectures and courses for settlers as well as very popular public exhibi-tions on housing, town planning and building techniques.14 From 1923 on he arranged for the teaching activities of the Union to take place under the roof of the Settlement and Town Planning Museum. It held exhibitions but also func-tioned as a centre of practical advice for settlers. In 1924 Neurath approached the municipality of Vienna with the idea of expanding this institution and re-naming it Museum of Society and Economy in order to be able to organize even larger exhibitions on much broader social and economic issues.

It opened officially in January 1925. Besides a section on Settlement and Town Planning, which was inherited from the earlier institution, it had two new departments: ‘Arbeit und Organisation’ [Labour and Organiza-

Fig. 3

Advertisement of the Museum of Society and Economy,

The Otto and Marie Neurath Isotype Collection (reprinted by permission of the

Department of Typography & Graphic Communication, University of Reading)

91‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

tion] and ‘Lebenslage und Kultur’ [Life Circumstances and Culture].15 In contrast to the traditional museums of his time, which exhibited numerous unique artefacts and curiosities, Neurath’s museum concept was different and more challenging. It was neither a place where objects were collected for their peculiarity nor a building with exhibition rooms. It was a workshop for the production of didactic material. This material was displayed in a spot, where people had to pass it by on their way to the administrative of-fices. Since each current permanent exhibition located in the foyer of the New City Hall, people had to pass it by on their way to the administrative offices, thus allowing them to become acquainted with the displayed ma-terial in way that was not as intimidating as a museum might have been. Satellite exhibitions were displayed on the outskirts of Vienna.

He conceptualised his institution as a ‘museum of the future’. It should be organized, he claimed in his article in Survey Graphic in 1933, around the presumed interests of the citizen seeking explanations for social and other important issues of the day.16

In his workshop he strived to manufacture charts for exhibitions as one might manufacture cars or books in series of identical copies:

To speak of the museum of the future is like speaking of the automobile of the future. Automobiles are manufactured in series and not produced one by one in a smithy. The idea that every museum ought to contain unique exhibits has come to us from the past. […] It was the same at one time with books: some famous manuscript entered into a collection, a unique treasure; but today, there are ten thousand reproductions of the same manuscript. In the future, muse-ums will be manufactured, exactly as books are today.17

For Neurath museums of the future were to be able to manufacture their exhibitions anywhere and publish copies of their artefacts for any media, in-stead of displaying unique objects. His model of production for the Viennese method was the modular assembly system.

Representing the World Population via Pictorial Statistics

Looking at one particular example, allows one to better understand how Neurath’s principles were incorporated into his pictorial statistics in collabo-

92 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

ration with his colleagues at the Viennese Museum of Society and Economy. Figure 4 is part of the global collection ‘Society and Economy’ including 100 coloured charts showing the distribution of populations, natural resources, economic products as well as social, political and cultural aspects of life in time and space.18

The result of Neurath’s bird-like flight over the Earth results for instance in a snapshot of the peoples of the world in 1930: showing three main groups, represented in white, yellow and dark colours. One basic figure of a man of the same size, body shape and gender is used because Neurath believed that all humans belong to the same kind. The signs were under-stood as signatures of objects and phenomena that should be represented. Following his basic principle that nothing seems to be more dangerous than a symbol that tells the observer more than the designer wants to express19, he disapproved of too much detailed realism in the expression, polysemous display or meaningless graphical information. He thus clearly disassociated his visual method from art, where the focus was on individualistic expres-sion. In Neurath’s pictorial statistics all its graphical characteristics were supposed to be exclusively of informational value.20

In order to take into account the human diversity, he clustered groups of people together by colouring their skin and focusing on hats. The upper row shows the Europeans and their emigrated descendents in white. The second depicts the American Indians in red, Africans in black, and Oriental and Indian people in brown. The lower row, finally, represents the Chinese, Mongols, Japanese and Asians in yellow. In his choice of colours he followed the general tradition in representing human diversity, but avoided the sup-posedly clear race classifications of his time. He used the more neutral term of ‘population groups’, largely defined in social anthropology.

The figures were structured in series, designating a certain number of people being part of one group on a scale of 100 million people. Neurath’s chart not only portrayed statistics in the picture, but also gave the observer a visual argument regarding the equilibrium between the political and eco-nomic leading world of the West and the North (upper row), the colonial world of the South (mean row) and the rising powers of the East (lower row). The pictures were part of Neurath’s colonial political education on the oc-casion of the International Socialist Workers’ Congress 1928 in Brussels. In the corresponding article Neurath referred to the globalization of capital and the resulting problems for the international working class.21 In showing

93‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

Fig. 4 Peoples of the World from Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft (1930), Plate 96

94 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

that the world population splits in three groups of almost same size, among them the Chinese who were fewer than expected, he intended to rationalize political discourse by restricting himself to pure observational facts. The big task—as he said in his article—was to persuade the workers from the West (especially in Germany and Austria, who had no first-hand experience with colonialism) that the cattle breeders from the East were neither a danger nor strangers, but came from the same social class, and that workers around the globe should make a united front against the exploitation of worldwide capitalism.

As early as 1926 Neurath had recognized how crucial his visual vocabu-lary was for the depiction of the international working class by graphical means:

It is difficult to describe workers from different countries in different ways. It is a striking feature of our age that clothing becomes more similar, so that, by a mere glance, it is difficult to distinguish a German from a French or an English worker. The same is the case with the entire population. It is not wise to reach back to the old ideas of past eras and to describe, for example, the Americans as wearing a grey cylinder, a goatee or other strange things, or the Germans as wearing a pointed cap. Modern people are not aware of these differences!22

Neurath was aware of the fact that for semiotic reasons stereotyping and standardization of his pictures were necessary to make communication across borders possible. The search for cultural independent symbols was obviously not trivial and perpetuating stereotypes. In fact, the representation of the peoples of the world for a pictogram representing human mankind in 1930 was the result of a much longer process and not his final solution at all.23

‘We could not photograph social objects even if we tried.’

The example also demonstrates how Neurath mediated between a more nat-uralistic representation, such as used in physical anthropology to represent humans by using photographs, and a more abstract pure schematic depiction through words, numbers or graphs that only experts could decipher. With his pictorial statistics Neurath wanted to achieve the same effect that was already

95‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

common practice in, for instance, biology and physics, namely the production of pictures with a camera to which objectivity, authenticity and realism were attributed. In his paper on the museum of the future he justified his method in the following way:

To come to the point, an abstract formula is educationally as useless as is a naturalistic reproduction. What we need is a schematic representation that can be immediately understood. We could not photograph social objects even if we tried. They can be demonstrated only through symbols. It is because this is not an easy task that it has so long remained unfulfilled.24

For epistemological as well as educational reasons, Neurath viewed the exist-ing graphical methods for visualizing statistics as unsuitable. He repeatedly argued that in most of the cases curves and diagrams would misrepresent exactness with regard to social facts that had not been empirically proven.25

Neither were mere abstract representations the solution due to their incom-prehensibility for the layman. Especially in Neurath’s own field of expertise, the social sciences, in which the principles of the Vienna Circle were even less accepted, he introduced his pictorial method as prescription to produce facts that were based on observational statements and to make clear-cut statements on heterogeneous entities like populations.26

Neurath’s plan to democratize the global order through the use of Isotype in the communication of anything anywhere failed in its pretentious totality. Like contemporary pictorial systems, they work where people of different cultures need orientation in space, for instance, at the airport or in a refugee camp. Other useful applications are the labelling of consumer goods and instruction manuals. These examples demonstrate how for well-defined purposes image-guided displays can bridge cultural differences and complement the Babylonian confusion caused by everyone speaking his/her own natural language. If we study Neurath’s case in its historical context we see how innovations in pictorial systems were deeply connected with ideas to modernize science and society.

96 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

Notes

1 I want to thank Elisabeth Nemeth for inviting me to the Workshop at the Wittgenstein Symposium 2010 in Kirchberg. Preliminary results of this paper were presented at the departmental seminar in the Max Planck Institute for History of Science in Berlin (Dept. III) in November 2009 and at the Panel on ‘Creating a World Population: The Global Transfer of Population-Control Tech-nologies in the Twentieth Century’ of the Historikertag in Berlin in October 2010. I thank the participants of both meetings for helpful comments. For access, help in evaluating and permission to reproduce archival material from the Otto and Marie Neurath collection of the Isotype Institute at the Department of Typog-raphy & Graphic Communication, the University of Reading I am indebted to Chris Burke and Eric Kindel. For their help with the translation I thank Birgit Kolboske and Marc Weingart.

2 Otto Neurath, ‘Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode’, Die Volksschule 27 (1931): 569 (reprinted in Otto Neurath. Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften, edited by Rudolf Haller and Robin Kinross (Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1991: 180), my translation.

3 Eric Knight and Paul Rotha, World of Plenty. The Book of the Film (London: Nicholson & Watson, 1945), Tim Boon, ‘Agreement and Disagreement in the Making of World of Plenty’, in Nutrition in Britain. Science, Scientists and Politics in the Twentieth Century, edited by David F. Smith (London/New York: Routledge, 1997), 166–189.

4 Otto Neurath, International Picture Language (London: Keagan Paul, 1936), trans-lated by Marie Neurath and reprinted in Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 355–398).

5 Otto Neurath, International Picture Language (as in note 4), 373.6 Otto Neurath, ‘Kolonialpolitische Aufklärung durch Bildstatistik’, Arbeit und Wirt-

schaft, 1928, 15: 677 (reprinted in Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 130), my translation.

7 [Hans Hahn, Otto Neurath and Rudolf Carnap], Wissenschaftliche Weltauffas-sung. Der Wiener Kreis (Wien: Arthur Wolf, 1929), reprinted in: Otto Neurath. Wis-senschaftliche Weltauffassung. Sozialismus und Logischer Empirismus, edited by Rainer Hegselmann (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1979: 81-101, English translation in Otto Neurath. Empiricism and Sociology, edited by Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen (Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1973: 301–318), Otto Neurath, Empirische Soziologie. Der wissenschaftliche Gehalt der Geschichte und Nationalökonomie (1931, reprinted in: Otto Neurath. Gesammelte philosophische und methodol-

97‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

ogische Schriften, edited by Rudolf Haller and Heiner Rutte (Wien: Hölder-Pichler- Tempsky, 1980, Vol. 1: 423–527, English translation in Neurath 1973, Empiricism and Sociology: 319–421), Otto Neurath, Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule (Wien/Leipzig: Verlag für Jugend und Volk, 1933), reprinted in Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 265–336.

8 Thomas Uebel, ‘Arbeit am “Unterbau” der Wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung’, Grazer Philosophische Studien 41 (1991): 235-243.

9 Simon Schaffer, ‘What is Science’, in: Science in the Twentieth Century, edited by John Krige and Dominique Pestre (Amsterdam, 1997: 33).

10 Elisabeth Nemeth, ‘Gesellschaftliche Tatbestände sichtbar machen. Otto Neurath über den Gegenstand der Wirtschaftswissenschaften und seine Visualisierung’, in: Philosophie an der Schwelle zum 21. Jahrhundert, ed. by Ewa Czerwinska-Schupp (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang 2003: 181–208), Elisabeth Nemeth, ‘Visualising Relations in Society and Economics. Otto Neuraths Isotype-method Against the Background of his Economic Thought’, in: Pointure du symbole, edited by Jean-Yves Beziau (Paris: editions Petra, 2011: forthcoming).

11 For a more detailed account see Sybilla Nikolow, ‘Aufklärung durch und mit Beobachtungstatsachen. Otto Neuraths Bildstatistik als Vehikel zur Verbreitung der wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung des Wiener Kreises’, in: Wissenschaft und Öffentlichkeit als Ressourcen füreinander. Studien zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte im 20. Jahr-hundert, edited by Sybilla Nikolow and Arne Schirrmacher (Frankfurt am Main: Campus, 2007: 245–272).

12 Peter Galison, ‘Aufbau/Bauhaus. Logical Positivism and Architectural Modern-ism’, Critical Inquiry 16 (1990): 709–752. Robert J. Leonard, ‘ “Seeing is Believ-ing”. Otto Neurath, Graphic Art, and Social Order’, History of Political Economy 31 (2000) (Special Issue: Economists and Art. Historically Considered): 452–478.

13 Neurath 1936, International Picture Language (Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 373).

14 Nader Vossoughian, The Language of the Global Polis (Rotterdam: NAi Publishers, 2008): 54–58.

15 Otto Neurath, ‘Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum in Wien’, Österreichische Ge-meinde-Zeitung 2 (1925), 2: 1–12, (Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 1–17, Eng-lish translation of this article in: Neurath 1973, Empiricism and Sociology: 214–218).

16 See for Neurath’s concept from a contemporary museological view: Hadwig Kraeutler, Otto Neurath. Museum and Exhibition Work (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2008).

17 Otto Neurath, ‘Museums of the Future’, Survey Graphic 22 (1933), 9: 458

98 ‘Words Divide, Pictures Unite.’

(reprinted in Neurath 1973, Empiricism and Sociology: 218–223).18 Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft. Bildstatistisches Elementarwerk. Das Gesellschafts- und Wirt-

schaftsmuseum in Wien zeigt in 100 farbigen Bildtafeln Produktionsformen, Gesellschafts- ordnungen, Kulturstufen, Lebenshaltungen. (Leipzig: Bibliographisches Institut, 1930). For a more detailed description of this collection see Sybilla Nikolow, ‘Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft. An Encyclopedia in Otto Neurath’s Pictorial Statistics from 1930’ in: European Modernism and the Information Society. Informing the Present, Understand-ing the Past, edited by W. Boyd Rayward (London: Ashgate Publishing, 2008): 257–278.

19 Otto Neurath, ‘Schwarzweißgraphik’, (1926, reprinted in: Neurath 1991, Bild-pädagogische Schriften: 55). Presumably based on Ludwig Wittgenstein’s bonmot ‘Wovon man nicht sprechen kann, darüber muss man schweigen.’

20 Neurath 1933, Bildstatistik, see Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 279–284).21 Neurath 1928, Aufklärung (Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 126–132.22 Otto Neurath, “Statistische Hieroglyphen”, (1926, reprinted in Neurath 1991,

Bildpädagogische Schriften: 43), my translation.23 For a detailed discussion of the graphical representation of the population groups

see Sybilla Nikolow, ‘Gestaltete Bilder und visuelle Argumente. Die “Völker der Erde” in Otto Neuraths Bildstatistik und “Isotype” ’, in: Bild und Gestalt. Wie formen Medienpraktiken das Wissen in Medizin und Humanwissenschaften?, edited by Frank Stahnisch and Heijko Bauer (Hamburg: LIT Verlag, 2007): 229–243.

24 Neurath 1933, Museums of the Future: 462.25 Neurath 1926, Hieroglyphen (Neurath 1991, Bildpädagogische Schriften: 44), Marie

Reidemeister, “Die Kunst der statistischen Darstellung“ Kulturwille. Monatsblätter für Kultur- und Arbeiterschaft, 4 (1927), 9: 194–5.

26 It was Paul Rotha who understood Neurath’s visual arguments displayed in his charts as clear-cut statements that he used in his documentaries. Paul Rotha, ‘Films and Other Visual Techniques in Education, 1946’, in: Rotha on the Film. A Selection of Writings about the Cinema (London: Faber and Faber, 1953): 89.—For Rotha’s documentaries see also Tim Boon, Films of Fact. A History of Science in Documentary Films and Television (London: Wallflower Press, 2008).

Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Sophie Hochhäusl, Ithaca, NY

Introduction

Architects are trained to distinguish between two kinds of maps: representa-tional ones and those that serve as heuristic devices. While representational maps are usually drawn to make observations more accessible to a larger audi-ence, the map as an architectural tool, serves as a device for design thinking. By means of drawing space it makes relationships visible that could not have been conceived without drawing. When deploying such maps, architects pay close attention to the particularities of space, because insight can only be gained when non-spatial observations are put in relationship to a certain terrain. Its synergy generates new content, meaning, knowledge and possible design solutions.

Austrian philosopher and economist Otto Neurath (1882 – 1945) was famous for his engagement with representational maps. He revolutionized the discipline of chart making by finding a way to create picture statistics and quantitative maps that were accessible to a larger public. In this paper however, I will argue that Otto Neurath’s map City Planning served not only as one of the first well-accessible socio-political maps of a city, but that it was in effect also a heuristic device.

Originally crafted in color, City Planning (fig. 1, overleaf) was edited to appear in red, black and white, accompanying Neurath’s text ‘Visual Representations of Architectural Problems’, in Architectural Record in July 1937.1 The text and the 1937 map were a direct reaction to a similar and in effect more extensive mapping operation pursued by CIAM IV (Congrès Internationaux d’Architecture Moderne, International Congresses of Modern Architecture) in 1933. Nonetheless it was Neurath who first illustrated the socio-political map for urbanism according to graphic rules and with a

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 99–136.

100 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

graphic vocabulary that possessed a consistent logic and even syntax. In addition, I will explore to which degree Neurath perceived of the city as an agglomeration of social facts and in how far his socio-political map contri-buted in planning the city on such basis.

In order to create this map, three main fields of expertise came into play. First, Neurath’s specific views on urbanism were different from those of most architects’. A second necessary expertise to Neurath’s undertaking was the ability to graphically craft abstracted data—the transformation, which was invented at Neurath’s ‘Museum of Society and Economy’ (Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum). Thirdly, in search of ‘humanizing’ knowledge, Neurath hoped that by making information graphically available, he would enable all people to ‘participate in a common culture’, eliminating ‘the canyon between educated and uneducated people.’ 2

CIAM however, was a catalyst for creating the 1937 map as well, in that it triggered Neurath’s further research in illustrating the city. When in 1937 his map finally appeared, it marked the culmination of Neurath’s search for simplicity in the context of a spatial discussion. The map was however also the last to ever accompany one of Neurath’s texts on architecture and urbanism and it ended Neurath’s public theorizing of the city, which had lasted for two decades with the exception of the Bilston experiment.3

Fig. 1

City Planning,

Basis to the 1937 Map, 1937,

source: Otto and Marie Neurath

Isotype Collection,

Department of Typography &

Graphic Communication, University

of Reading, UK, 5/18 2047.

101Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Rem Koolhaas’s AMO (research unit of OMA, Office for Metropolitan Architecture) is the most prominent architectural think tank promoting the use of the map as tool as well as representational device in a contemporary context. Through their heavy publication activities and their particular architectural wit, AMO has fostered an interest in mapping that is now found in architecture schools all around the world. Although Koolhaas never cited Neurath, some aspects of AMO’s maps are strikingly similar to the ones produced by the Museum of Society and Economy. So when I first decided to assess socio-political mapping and its application to architecture it was precisely to understand this missing piece: how did socio-political mapping in architecture first emerge, which connotations did it possess, which goals did it initially pursue, did Neurath have an influence on the contemporary debate on mapping and if so, how?

Otto Neurath’s Urbanist ConvictionsThe Austrian Settlement and Allotment Garden Association

The first and most fundamental component to the 1937 map City Planning was Otto Neurath’s distinct perception of urbanism. To Neurath the Modern city was an economic organism. But unlike many of the Modern figures in architec-ture that either rationalized city building by economic means, or subordinated the production of city planning to the economy of the industrialized world, Neurath perceived economic strategies as a means to substantiate a lively ur-banism. Neurath’s conviction that life in a city could largely benefit from the forces that shaped it, was based on his knowledge of economic relationships.

When Neurath collected images of harbors, grain silos and factories in 1925 for instance, he did not necessarily admire them for their machine æsthetics, as modern architects did at the time.4 For Neurath, ports, ware-houses and elevated railway tracks represented the global industry, in which he believed lie the foundations for a socially improved Modern city. 5

What does the city of the future look like? Above all, it is shaped by the modern, large scale industries of global trade. The city of the future is characterized by harbors, railway stations, silos, warehouses, factories, sweeping platforms of elevated traines, and ironworks. […] But how will the residential dwellings be distributed? 6

102 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Hence, to Neurath the city was an agglomerate of economic relationships and such institutions, and housing maintained a crucial position amongst them. Furthermore, they had to be connected via transportation routes, which he also saw as interwoven with sociological and anthropological components. Cities were spaces where cultural exchange took place, where people met in plazas and in coffee houses, where they demonstrated and went to school, where they were hospitalized, enjoyed a walk in a park, or swam in a pub-lic pool.7 When looking at urban fabric, Neurath saw it as a unity between architecture and organization.8 And he realized this unified vision between architecture and organization when he became the secretary of the ‘Austrian Settlement and Allotment Garden Association’ (Österreichischer Verein für Siedlungs- und Kleingartenwesen).

During the years of WWI ‘wild settlements’ had emerged on the outskirts of Vienna, when people in search of food and shelter had started to cultivate small gardens and build provisional barracks. The Austrian Settlement and Allotment Garden Association finally came into existence in the early 1920s to unite the 230 dispersed settlement clubs. Neurath’s great achievement was to mend it into an efficient operation while still maintaining the settler’s principle of self-help.

Due to his knowledge in economies and organization, Neurath put a system in place that allowed the large building enterprise the settlement movement had become to be governed by three core agendas: economical, political, and educational ones. In particular these agendas were all shaped around the concepts of ‘communal economy’ (Gemeinwirtschaft) and com- munity (Gemeinschaft).9 This meant that the settlers where still involved in building their own houses, even when architects designed them, and that each settler kept ‘a piece’ of all communal facilities. In addition, educational material was provided within the association to inform and publicize the achievements of the settlers. Often this included extensive exhibitions and magazines.

In comparison to other housing typologies, later pursued in ‘Red Vienna’, the settlement movement perceived of itself not necessarily as a strictly urban form of living. Houses were rarely higher than two stories—as the chief architect of the Association’s Siedlungsamt, Adolf Loos had proclaimed—and they always maintained a close connection to their gardens, where they tilled vegetables. Often houses even had small stables or barns.

It was with the settlement movement that the unity of organization and urban strategies came to full bloom. For Neurath economical and political enterprises truly were as important as the objects—the urban elements—they

103Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

created. And the hidden organization that lived behind all elements of a city was also what had to be drawn out and explored in Neurath’s 1937 map, and what would take his urban project to a next step.

In terms of housing, Neurath always favored settlements over multi-storey dwellings, but over time his receptiveness to other urban conceptions grew. He started to recognize that settlements could not be employed everywhere, since they were not as dense as the communal projects the city of Vienna started to realize. He also underlined that Gemeinschaft, thus formally articu-lated differently than in the settlements, was also generated in the munici-pal dwellings. He wrote: ‘In the public dwellings of Vienna’s municipality emerges a new common life. The common courtyard serves the play of chil-dren, on summer evenings young and old possibly even dance to the sound of the loudspeaker.’ 10 He also noted that the diverse proposals for common living, worked out by many different architects in Vienna encouraged benefi-cial pluralism.11 This notion of pluralism in urban planning was connected with his philosophical perception of coherentism and logical empiricism. Coherentism advanced the idea that truth was a compound of entire systems, but could also be ascribed to its individual propositions. However, scientific

Fig. 2 Shadow looming over new Settler Houses, 1925—1932,

source: N-15, N-Files, Otto and Marie Neurath Isotype Collection,

Department of Typography, University of Reading, Reading, UK.

104 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

opinions differed on the question of whether coherentism allowed many possible systems of truth or only a single one. Neurath believed that whatever decision one made ‘lay in the ‘path of life’ chosen by the decision maker.’12

Therefore, a city had to encourage various models to solve problems, so a collective decision could be made by many people on the basis of what they found appropriate for their ways of life and their needs. This attitude fore-shadowed Neurath’s notion of the purposes of picture statistics. By showing various statistics (aspects of reality) chart by chart, they encouraged their viewer to draw his or her own conclusion.

Otto Neurath’s Graphic Convictions The Search for Simplicity

Since Neurath perceived of the Modern city as an economic organism, he had to find a way to illustrate the ‘invisible forces’ that governed it. To facilitate this comprehension, which could potentially transgress borders and social status, he strove for a universal language: the language of picture statistics.13

In fact, for exhibitions of the settlers a visual chart collection of their achievements was established. In 1925 a permanent Museum emerged from this, soon called ‘Museum of Society and Economy’ (Gesellschafts- und Wirt-schaftsmuseum). This Museum became the home of picture statistics, where the graphic depiction of data was tested and refined.

Most crucial to creating quantitative charts was the role of the transformer —the statistical and graphic personnel that translated data into the quan-titative map. Charts at the Museum were not only created according to æsthetic judgment and graphic knowledge, but were also mathematically precise although they were rounded off.

The graphic history of the 1937 map, City Planning, was threefold, since the map consisted of pictograms, patterns made of symbols and spatial parameters.

I.S.O.TY.P.E. (International System of TYpographic Picture Education) symbols usually showed quantities by the repetition of a singular symbol, rather than by scaling in size. While in the 1920s quantitative charts were mainly characterized by arrays of symbols, which actually represented quantities, a main shift occurred in the early 1930s when symbols started to be paired. Until then ‘factory’ and ‘shoe’ for example, were represented as two

105Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Figs. 3, 4, 5 Main Symbols, ‘Various ISOTYPE Symbols’, ‘Various ISOTYPE Patterns’,

‘Second Version of a Section of the same (1937) Map’, ca. 1937,

source: ‘Visual Representation of Architectural Problems’, Otto Neurath,

Architectural Record, 1937, 57–58.

Fig. 6 ‘Baumwollwirtschaft Chart 44’, ca. 1929–1930, source: Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft.

106 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

separate symbols, had two separate meanings and usually indicated a quantity of shoes or factories when multiplied. By the early 1930s however, symbols started to appear in pairs, and the merge of shoe and factory indicated, ‘shoe factory’. This fundamentally added to the nature of ISOTYPE.

While the history of pictograms is well documented in Neurath’s writing, the graphic history of the hatches, the second entity employed in the 1937 map, is less clear. From an architectural stand point, they represented a break-through because they bridged the symbol to the plan. They allowed the sym-bol not only to signify quantities within space, but to actually become space when multiplied. They efficiently represented the fabric of rural and urban space to the ‘uneducated eye’. Color solids, and technical hatches composed of horizontal, vertical and inclined lines, were employed in other architectural maps at the time, but they were never nearly as comprehensive as Neurath’s ‘wallpapers’, as he liked to call them.

Neurath employed his quantitative maps to depict information in an unbiased way, as done with geographical maps,13 and his aim was for them to contain a catalogue of universal signs as neutrally as in geographical maps, yet he seldom worked with the actual spatialties of a city. For one, the implica-tions of actual spatialties of the city and their illustration required a degree of technical or architectural craftsmanship that was too complex for the ‘ordi-

Fig. 7

Paired Symbols,

‘Picture 17’

source:

Otto Neurath, International Picture

Language, Kegan Paul, Trench,

Trubner & Co, London, 1936, 51.

107Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

nary man’ to decipher. In order to illustrate simple facts Neurath decided to dismiss actual geographical charts and decided to work with cartograms.

In the appendix of Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft Neurath argued that ‘the cartographic depiction of the atlas was adjusted to match the picture statistics.’15 They were intentionally ‘not geographical maps, but only cartograms’.16 Further-more, the Museums’ town plans rarely contained more than one geographical layer, which was also usually highly abstracted. Neurath insisted that quantitative information was to be kept completely separate, once a map reached a more detailed level of abstraction. According to Neurath, town plans should only ‘explain the character of a district, but not its exact location or disposition.’17

This shows that it was not until the 1937 map that Neurath thought in depth about how to map socio-political factors onto space. Before then, these two layers were consciously kept apart. Pairing layers stood at the end of a long process. Although the segregation of space from statistical information might have fostered better understanding of the chart, it also testifies to Neurath’s underestimation of space’s dispositions and its resulting complexities.

Since the cartograms consciously followed the laws of the pictogram, they never inherited the properties of a real diagram. Besides Neurath’s notion of pluralism the concept of the social silhouette is crucial for investigating Neurath’s resistance to spatial praticularities, which are essentially design

Fig. 8

‘Bodem’, Gound,

source:

Gerd Arntz Archive,

Gemeentemuseum, The Hague,

Netherlands, Folder 8.

108 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

strategies.18 The social silhouette promotes that certain aspects of life ought to be only depicted in single charts, so that they do not lead the reader to false conclusions. In The International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (1944) he states:

Various nations have different mortality rates; one cannot say that where the mortality rate is higher, we may also expect a lower standard of public health. It may be that in one nation the percentage of old people is extraordinarily high and, therefore, the national mortality rate may also be very high, even if in all age groups the mortality rates were lower than in other nations. The silhouette of mortality rates would tell us what the situation is.19

This is precisely why Neurath wanted to illustrate every single category by itself. Only in their collectivity would the charts create a social silhouette that would show a more holistic picture of social interconnectivities. In contrast to architects, Neurath, the philosopher, could perceive the city as the cognitive construct of manifold social relations that it was. He was freed from the bur-den of having to coerce it with the specificity that a design task demands.

But it is also for this reason, that Neurath’s maps were representational tools, but rarely heuristic instruments. Because only in mapping various spa-tial aspects within one realm design solutions can be derived.

With the 1937 map Neurath did not mean to arrive at design conclu-sions, but he did start to map multiple apects in one city plan. In addition, he achieved what he had always wanted and what no architect had accomplished before him: to illustrate socio-economic forces within the city with the same objectivity as the geographical map.

Fig. 9

‘New York, Chart 71’,

ca. 1929–1930,

source: Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft.

109Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Otto Neurath’s Pedagogical ConvictionsFrom Picture Statistics to Picture Education

Neurath’s ultimate goal always was to enable everyone to ‘participate in a com-mon culture’ and he fought to eliminate ‘the canyon between educated and un-educated people.’20 In this search of ‘humanizing’ knowledge therefore, graphic education had to be scientifically and pedagogically probed in relation to the intended audience. The vehicle for this refinement became the Museum21—it was where new tools were invented and tested.22 And they travelled from there, as exhibitions, catalogs and matrices, to museums and into classrooms.

While the invention of new media for ISOTYPE did not change the lan-guage of picture statistics much, they were additional instruments through which this language could be articulated. Concretely, this meant a shift from exhibiting solely quantitative maps on paper, toward providing a set of items that could be used to inform the broad public, ranging from magnetic boards to short films and the Museum itself.23 The alteration from using solely charts towards a wide variety of media was also reflected in a change of name: the word Bildstatistik (picture statistics) was replaced by Bildpädagogik (picture pedagogy) better known as Picture Education. Picture Education was also written as P. E. to form i.s.o.ty.P.E. abbreviation.24

Between 1925 and 1932 the ‘Museum of Society and Economy’ started an extensive collection of their own commissioned photographs.25 As a result of the Museum’s collaboration with Vienna’s ‘Professional Support Bureau and the Viennese Chamber of Labor’ employees at the Museum studied the life of the worker and labor environments meticulously. But staff of the Museum did not only go out to picture work environments, prospective wage earner were also invited into the Museum to gain an overview of various job possibilities.26 Progressive sequences—lantern slide shows—of work scenes were also depicted which created a narrative on the duties of the hairdresser, the locksmith, the optician, the tailor, the carpenter, the blacksmith and the factory worker.27 These small narratives were headed by a title and a credit slide as well as a ‘lead image.’

The most interesting results however were possibly achieved during the Museum’s work with students. By the end of the 1920s, picture education became a part of the Viennese school reform. Initiated by the social-democratic government of Red Vienna, the school reform tried to weed out antiquated teaching methods that were considered debris of the monarchy.

110 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

The Vienna method was from then on probed in various school types, but mostly in Hauptschulen (middle schools: 10–15 year olds), elementary schools (6–10 year olds) and kindergartens (3–6 year olds). While different teaching materials were used to engage various age groups, drafting of picture statistics was taught at all levels. Surprisingly, this led to the understanding that picture statistics were often more easily appropriated and correctly employed by younger students.

When confronted with drawing the statistical chart, ‘How many children stayed at home on the weekend and how many went outside?’ Neurath remarked that teens were inclined to solve these problems in an all too detailed and naturalistic way, if the instructor did not specifically request symbolic depiction.28 He attested on the drawings:

Fig. 10

Media, Relief Chart and Models at

Neues Rathaus, Vienna, 1925–1932,

source: N-1750 N-Files.

Fig. 11

Children Building Arntz Symbol, Vienna, 1925–1932,

source: N-979, N-Files.

111Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

In an all-girls’ class, for instance, one will find series: of (drawn) girl-(figures), whose little dresses feature all kinds of details. Braids and such animate the composition. The girls, who stay at home, look outside the window, whose drapes are affectionately drawn out. The lead images give reason for picturesque activity. All too easily they lose the character of statistic free symbolism.29

The technique of drawing picture statistics, however, proved apt for children in elementary schools. Research in child psychology had shown that during the years of elementary school and earlier, children were very capable of inventing symbols and designing them in an abstract way.30 Neurath attested to this in Bildstatistik und Schule:

In one […] case a child indicated the ‘Sunday in the open-air’ with the tree symbol adjacent to a mushroom symbol, omitting [the symbol] of children walking outside. Asked why he chose the tree and the mushroom, he answered absolutely in terms of best picture education: the tree alone could indicate a park in Vienna; with the mushroom it becomes clear that it is a forest.31

In general, children quickly grasped the method of drawing quantitative rather than geographical maps. However, ISOTYPE was still not for every-body. Neurath knew and actually intended this. It was not taught in gymna-siums, secondary schools or at universities, it was kept from institutions that drew on the upper class. First and foremost, ISOTYPE was provided to those

Fig. 12

Sunday in the open-air,

approximately 6 years old, Vienna,

1925–1932, source: N-546, N-Files.

112 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

who needed it most, a non-specialist audience. And in this instance, the apparent simplicity of the Vienna Method was unique; because it empowered the weak, it gave the ones who could not read the chance to participate, and it considered the adult just like the child and those with any kind of disadvan-tage or disability.32

When the school material started to travel, so did the Museum’s exhibi-tions. And it was for this reason that some rather famous architects took notice of Neurath and invited him to be the first non-architect member to advise them on how to create a didactic map of the city.

Nobody knew what they were getting themselves into, until after they boarded a steam ship that carried them toward Athens and the most defining congress of architecture and urbanism of the 20th century: CIAM 1933.

CIAM as Catalyst for the 1937 MapNeurath and ‘The Functional City’

CIAM IV, titled ‘The Functional City’, took place on the cruise ship SS Partis II en route from Marseilles to Athens between July 29 and August 12, 1933.

With the goal to map 32 cities in terms of housing, working and leisure zones as well as routes of transportation, the CIAM architects were drawn to Neurath’s expertise on cartograms and they hoped he would help them to enhance their visual language for illustrating the city. Neurath on the other hand was attracted to CIAM as a platform, because it presented an oppor-tunity to launch an interdisciplinary professional language on a large scale. In addition, Neurath was in close contact with the architects Josef Frank and Magarete Schütte-Lihotzky, who both belonged to the CIAM’s left wing. Therefore the original CIAM declaration, drafted by one of CIAM’s left wing members, resonated with Neurath’s understanding of urbanism. It stated:

The idea of modern architecture includes the link between the phenomenon of architecture and that of the general economic system. Town planning is the organization of the functions of collective life; the redistribution of land, the indispensable preliminary basis for any town planning, must include the just division between the owners and the community of the unearned increment resulting from works of joint interest.33

113Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

With CIAM IV however, its left wing became less influential. The election of the Dutch architect and city planner Cornelis Van Eestern

as CIAM’s chairman in 1930 was crucial to CIAM politics, because he symbol-ized the neutral compromise between the opposing (Swiss)-German and (Swiss)-French camps. While the (Swiss)-French camp headed by Le Corbusier thought of architecture more along the lines of Fordist production and æsthetics, the (Swiss)-German camp, including Hannes Mayer and Hans Schmidt, perceived the architectural tasks at hand in purely functionalist terms. Some of the left wing camp certainly also dismissed capitalist modes of architectural pro- duction. Van Eesteren’s mild nature and his will to mediate between different actors contributed to his aptness as chairman.

A further quality that prepared Van Eesteren for the preparations of CIAM IV was his double role as architect and urban planner. In 1929 we was called to serve in the Urban Development Section of Amsterdam’s Public Works Department where he started to work on an extension plan for the city. For this purpose he drew out maps generating a comprehensive design strategy. Since Van Eesteren had completed three model maps for the city of Amsterdam, it was sensible to use their logic and organization as the basis for maps of ‘The Functional City.’ 34

The first map in 1:10,000 sought to show existing conditions in a city, recording industrial and housing zones, as well recreational areas. The second map, drawn at the same scale, analyzed transportation networks, and the third, at 1:50,000, captured ‘the city in its regional setting, including areas of public and private open space, and additional information on all four [Corbusian] functions of dwelling, work, recreation and transportation.’ 35

Van Eesteren created the model maps and 72 symbols that would help clarify the given information. At a preparatory meeting in Berlin, during which the Berlin Building Exposition took place, a contribution of the ‘Museum of Society and Economy’ received special attention from the CIAM members due to its comprehensive designs. It was then that Sigfried Giedion suggested collaborating with non-architect specialists for CIAM IV, namely Otto Neurath.36 Although preliminary meetings between Neurath and Van Eesteren had taken place before 1933, Giedion notified Neurath to join the congress on the Patris at last minute.

Van Eesteren had done his best to develop a comprehensive graphic system in preparation of the congress. He was, however, unable to unite his 72 symbols in a coherent way and mixed conventional architectural drawing

114 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Fig. 13

‘CIAM Model Map I’,

Cornelis Van Eesteren,

CIAM, 1931,

source: gta Archive,

CIAM Archive, ETH Zurich.

Fig. 14

CIAM Delegates on Board of the Patris, 1933,

source: gta archive, CIAM Archive, ETH Zurich.

Fig. 15

Le Corbusier on Board of the Patris,

Background, Three CIAM Model Maps, 1933,

source: gta archive, CIAM Archive, ETH Zurich.

115Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

methods with symbols. Therefore Van Eesteren hoped that Neurath’s speech would clarify certain graphic hurdles. This was especially important since the beginning of a publication of CIAM’s maps was anticipated as soon as the CIAM delegates would return from the Congress. Neurath’s speech was held in Athens on August 4, where the maps were exhibited at the Athens’ Polytechnic University.

The Patris left Marseilles on July 29, 1933. The first three days on board were dedicated to discussions and analyses of the delegations’ maps. Le Corbusier held an introductory speech, addressing the question of how the maps could achieve at concrete conclusions.

The next day, Cornelis Van Eesteren addressed the relationship of effective illustrations of urban analyses and their translation into design proposals in his speech ‘Methoden des funktionellen Städtebaus (Methods of Functional City Planning)’.37 He explained how data had been extracted and to which urban proposals these analyzes led. He accompanied his lecture with the extension plan for the city of Amsterdam as an example. On the collection of data, he said:

In the extension plan, one only has to take into consideration the entities that require an advantageous position in relation to the entire body of the city. These are the objects that appear insular in every city: hospitals, mental institu-tions, cemeteries, crematories, etc.38

Fig. 16

Sigfried Giedion and

Otto Neurath, 1933,

source: gta archive, CIAM

Archive, ETH Zurich.

116 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

But he also stated:

On the basis of technical details, like railways and shore connections, solutions were found and extensive reports were drafted. For the expected population a prognosis was made and a minimum as well as a maximum were determined, for both cases the plan should propose housing possibilities.39

His speech was followed by Neurath’s ‘L’urbanisme et le lotissement du sol en representation optique d´après la méthod viennoise’ (Town Planning and Lot Division in terms of Optical Representation Following the Viennese Method ).40 Neurath’s answer to mapping densities in a city was still what he had always pledged: they should not be mapped into the drawing, but they should be shown in a separate supporting chart. Presenting the image ‘Men Living on a Unit of Space in Town’, he reiterated:

If one wants to show the density of inhabitants in the large cities of the world using our method, they would be characterized by monuments, for example, Paris by the Eiffel Tower and Notre Dame, London by the bridge over the

Fig. 17

Cornelis Van Eesteren,

In the Background his Symbols, 1933,

source: gta archive, CIAM Archive, ETH Zurich.

117Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Thames, etc. The population density will be represented by black or colored figures. At first glance, one will notice that while in Anglo-Saxon cities, for example, there are fewer inhabitants per 100 square meters than in the cities of Central Europe. I do not enter into considerations of whether dwelling in one- or two- floor buildings determines this situation.41

This solution was of course disappointing to the architects, because it did not allow for density to have a spatial implication. Neurath also insisted that actual maps did not even have to be drawn up at all and that cartograms served the cause of mapping the city even better than maps with spatial precision.

It is not always necessary to show these graphics on geographical maps; it often suffices to use geographical diagrams. The diagram facilitates observation. I think that we could better represent many facts studied at this congress through similar diagrams [to the ones I’ve shown] rather than through plans or geographical maps.42

To some, this statement must have felt disconcerting, since they had spent days and weeks in preparation of their precise city maps.

At last Neurath showed plans on the city development in Damascus, produced for the Atlas Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft in 1930, to illustrate the topic of the Congress more closely. These maps were however lacking any kind of paired information like combinations of spatial implications and symbols, or implied socio-political and demographic data.

But Neurath’s speech, despite its lack of new insight, was of course accurate in its criticism of the CIAM maps. It identified their shortcomings by calling out their lack of a uniform system of symbols. Furthermore, it pointed out that they were not apt for the public at large. To remedy this, Neurath suggested the usage of wallpaper cut outs and symbols on paper, which schools had been able to order through the Museum.

Although Neurath’s speech was disappointing, he was elected to serve on various committees and a collaboration between CIAM and the Museum in Vienna was planned before returning to Marseille. On August 12, upon arrival in Marseille, a first meeting of the publication commission, consisting of Van Eesteren, Sigfried Giedion, László Moholy-Nagy and Otto Neurath took place. Earlier the English delegation had questioned the ‘scientific

118 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

legitimacy’ of CIAM’s resolutions, which also affected this first meeting.For Neurath illustrating CIAM’s resolutions was a chance to spread his

international language of signs widely. Therefore he wanted to rework some of the Congress’ material. Giedion’s idea, however, was that only the Con-gress material should be used, so that the Congress could proceed faster. This caused a dispute between Neurath and the architects.

Neurath, on one hand, advised that the resolution should be shown in simple statements with newly produced fragments of plans illustrating the resolution’s singular focal points.43 Moholy insisted that CIAM’s maps were ‘impressive’ and best displayed the resolution’s origin as well as its process. In conclusion, the commission decided that a small publication should contain the resolution with ‘images and explanations’ and that the larger publication required ‘in depth reassessment with perfect optical representations’.44

In the near aftermath of the congress, Neurath was eager to get to work. Van Eesteren, however, wrote a letter to Moholy-Nagy confessing that he was really happy Moholy had ‘so actively participated in the congress’, in particular

Fig. 18 Left Hand: Charts of Damascus, ca. 1929–1930, source: Technika Chronika, gta archive, CIAM Archive, ETH Zurich.

119Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

in a conversation with Neurath, because otherwise they ‘would have certainly fallen victim to his rather limited system’.45

An upheaval occurred in November of 1933, when Neurath was noti-fied late of the second get-together in Paris. He issued a short letter to Le Corbusier’s CIRPAC (Comité international pour la résolution des problèmes de l’architecture contemporaine ) voicing his discontent.46 When he did not hear back from CIRPAC for three weeks, he finally decided to confide in Van Eesteren: ‘Please tell me how all of this should be understood in your opinion. If promi-nent members of your CIRPAC do not attach importance to the collaboration with us, I would prefer to withdraw my institute, but not without maintaining a personal friendly memory of you and your kind way of conduct with us.’ 47

Nobody replied to Neurath until five months later. During this time Van Eesteren was serverly sick. When he finally wrote back in May of the following year, he stressed, however, that as soon as Neurath made concrete suggestions on the basis of the plan of Amsterdam, he would still present these results to CIRPAC.48 A meeting between Van Eesteren and Neurath followed this letter.

During the months of Van Eesteren’s sickness, Neurath had his own problems. In the winter of 1933/34, he left Vienna for a visit at the ‘Isostat’ in Moscow. In February, the Austrian Civil War broke out. Representatives of the Viennese social democratic government and those affiliated with it were imprisoned. When the police came to search Neurath’s office at the ‘Museum of Society and Economy’, Marie Reidemeister warned Neurath not to come back to Vienna and they arranged to meet in Prague, from where they immigrated to Holland and finally settled in The Hague.

Van Eesteren was honest in giving Neurath a second try in 1934. In a letter to Giedion, issued a couple of days after his meeting with Neurath in Amster-dam in May, he wrote that he was still of the opinion that ‘something must grow’ from the collaboration between the congress and Neurath.49 Concretely, he thought of the exhibition ‘The Functional City’ that he planned to show in Amsterdam where the next CIRPAC meeting would take place. He still hoped that Neurath could advance his symbols for city planning.

In preparation for an exhibition titled ‘The Functional City’ which was held in Amsterdam in 1935, Neurath’s interest and Van Eesteren’s enthusiasm for the collaboration rekindled. They met frequently between October 1934 and February 1935. Neurath tried to work on the symbols and maps, inden-tifying some of the major spatial problems. ‘One should possibly combine

120 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

density of population, number of apartments, floor heights etc. [by means of symbols]’ Neurath wrote.50

The final death blow to the collaboration came with a presentation Neurath gave for the architecture collective ‘de 8’ which included Van Eesteren. The meeting did not draw much attention and many architects left displeased with Neurath’s speech.51 Neurath on his part, was highly disappointed that Van Eesteren did not show up. He wrote a last letter stating that he was very sorry about his absence, because Van Eesteren ‘was always so mediating.’ 52 He concluded: ‘Everything can be solved given some consideration, but neither is it only a graphic task nor is it solely that of an architect; it requires an inter-mediary … TRANSFORMATION … But this is an old song I have already whistled and jingled to you in different variations.’53 ‘The Functional City’ exhibition in Amsterdam opened in July of 1935. Neurath was never credited anywhere, although some charts were modeled after his suggestions.

Why did this collaboration between Neurath and CIAM fail so catastrophic-ally? For one, Enrico Chapel has very precisely assessed the complication of Neurath targeting a different audience than CIAM. He stressed that from the beginning, Neurath and the CIAM architects aimed at diverse target groups and they also ‘expected totally different reactions.’ 54 Chapel continues:

Neurath invented his system within the framework of a global visual communi-cation programme, with a view to ‘humanize’ knowledge for the greater benefit of the general public; the architects sought to internationalize an established body of knowledge; their principal targets were the decision-makers in the field of urban production.55

This is certainly relevant, since Le Corbusier for example conceived of the purposes of CIAM IV transnationally. This ‘meant working closely with large interests with the capital to implement his overarching vision of social and architectural transformation’ as Mumford has argued in his CIAM Discourse on Urbansim.56 But in general the architects wanted to pride themselves with their technical expertise and with the fact that they had found the means of representation that were specific to their discipline. Again, Enrico Chapel has put it precisely in saying:

In the first place, one should not underestimate the difficulty of applying a pictorial method that was not designed with town planning in mind […]

121Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

This system, which visualized social phenomena and economic data, failed to account for a whole range of dimensional and more generally spatial param-eters, which are nonetheless indispensable to any study carried out prior to the intervention of urban space.57

Kees Somer supports Chapel’s assessment in stating that the CIAM archi-tects saw their maps ‘as practical instruments’ and ‘their attention remained focused, on the reality of urban planning, which they had investigated with an immediately operational purpose: the improvement of the planning and design of the environment in which people live.’ 58 These observations are crucial because they precisely describe the difference between the map as an architectural heuristic device and the map as representational medium: and this is the divide that could not be overcome by Neurath and the architects in the framework of CIAM IV.

The 1937 Map—City PlanningFrom City Planning to Architectural Record

In 1937, two years after the end of his failed collaboration with CIAM, Neurath published his first socio-political map of a town, originally titled City Planning. The title is more charged than one might assume at first glance, as it suggests a concern with actual ‘planning’ rather than just a sober analysis, which would have been the typical mode of operation for Neurath.

The great breakthrough of the 1937 map was the overlap of spatial parameters with hatches and pictograms. This overlap was certainly miss-ing in the map of Damascus that Neurath had presented on the Patris, and it was also missing in all his quantitative charts of the world. While the ISOTYPE symbols presented altered concise syntax, the 1937 map also effectively clarified how to successfully employ ‘wallpapers’ and how to abstract spatial implications. In fact, the 1937 map was one of the first that mapped space with precision, which eventually enabled it to show first traits of the map as architectural tool.

Admittedly, when comparing Neurath’s map to Van Eesteren’s model map I of Amsterdam, Neurath’s approach in mapping the city still looks relatively abstract. But given a closer reading it becomes apparent that Neurath actually managed to supersede Van Eesteren’s approach in creating an insightful tool.

122 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Among CIAM’s three model maps, model map I of Amsterdam lends itself best to a comparative study, because it depicts existing conditions in a city and accounts for housing, work and leisure zones in a manner closest to the content of Neurath’s map.

Fig. 19

The 1937 Map, 1937,

source:

Architectural Record,

July, 1937, 56.

Fig. 20 ‘CIAM Model Map I’ and 1937 The Hague Map Comparison

123Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

In a first and most obvious instance Neurath’s hatches are more developed than Van Eesteren’s. ISOTYPE hatches could be inverted due to their simplicity and indicate two different, but clearly speled out things in one map. Van Eesteren’s hatches on the other hand employed a multitude of different manners of hatching, so that his charts became impossible to read without an index.

The indication of density was not successfully addressed by either map. Van Eesteren used numbers to indicate additional social factors in the plan, but they did not provide a general understanding of the relationship between statistics and space. Neurath, on the other hand, did not even try to address this issue, since he stayed true to his principle that quantitative information should be kept separate from the map. ‘Architects who are always closely connected with making floor plans and maps mostly intend to show social facts on maps, but in a great many cases we have to give preference to other methods of representation’, he criticized in Architectural Record.59 In his text Neurath reiterated this by showing density charts of different cities, something he had already demonstrated on the Patris by the example of Damascus.

On a second level, the comprehensiveness of Neurath’s symbols was also greatly improved, since a way was found to differentiate various types of buildings by simple means. Houses, factories, and big halls like railway stations could be distinguished by the basic shape of their symbols. Whether a space was located outdoors or indoors was indicated by black and white back-grounds.60 In addition, Neurath gave his symbols a background so they could be read as a symbol only. He also showed them in elevation, which made them clearly more abstract and identifiable as a symbol.

Van Eesteren’s symbols on the other hand, are ‘driving’ or ‘floating’ in all kinds of directions, which makes the plan very literal. In addition this makes it difficult to understand what the symbols imply: is this a real ship or is this an area for ships?

And thirdly, there was the issue of spatial abstraction, which had always been Neurath’s weak point. When analyzing Neurath’s map the discrepancy in scale is unsettling. The map seems to depict an urban environment and it indicates urban institutions (hospital, factory) yet the size of the city seems too small, too trimmed, to be an actual city.

Unfortunately Neurath did not often discuss maps individually, in fact there is no hint in the literature that the 1937 map derived from a real city. The general assumption has always been that it is a generic representation.

124 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

This is logical, since Neurath argued for years that rules in city planning were best illustrated by means of showing small generic parts or cut-outs. Yet, how does one illustrate a generic city or invent a city from scratch? This would seem to be a fairly complicated task for someone who had no such specific training.

What counters the generic theory is that Neurath usually drew from actually found social and economic facts. So why would he make an excep-tion with the city? Why would he not treat the city as a spatial social fact? In addition, the 1937 map clearly seemed to be ‘Neurath’s attempt at [contrasting] the language of “The Functional City” ’ and that would suggest working with an actual city.61 After all, CIAM specifically set out to map more than thirty actual cities in the world. But as for being the illustration of a real city, the 1937 map was too out of proportion, and as generic it was too specific.

It seems that to some extent both theories are applicable: The 1937 map is indeed generic, but there is reason to believe that the generic cut-out was drawn on the basis of a significant city. It was a city meaningful to Neurath, a city that made sense in contrast to Van Eesteren’s Amsterdam, namely The Hague, Neurath’s new city, the city where he continued his legacy.

It seems that in the end Neurath realized that spatial givens were important to take into consideration, even when depicting the city. However, he kept this realization a secret, because it was most important to emphasize that such

Fig. 21 The Hague 1930 and 1937 Map Comparison

125Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

infrastructure could exist with slight differences in every city in the world. In order for the map to be a valid response to CIAM it needed to be a

place that possibly incorporated all aspects of ‘The Functional City’; housing, workplaces, recreational areas and various transportation networks. Obvi-ously, such a place was hard to find in only a small cut-out of a city. Therefore modifications had to be made: spatial transformations.

The charts above, first depicting an actual plan of The Hague and lastly depicting the 1937 map, suggest that the trained statistical transformers were able to transform the particularities of space. They seem to suggest that from the actual city, a good transformer would move on to draw out a larger city block and scale it down. Then the transformer might morph a river into a sidewalk and some housing blocks into a river. The transformer might also copy an airfield from the far south of the city and insert it straight up north into the fictional city, where it fit best alongside a major transportation route. Then, he might also do the same with a lake from the outskirts of the city. Finally, the transformer could start drawing out actual greenery in the city. He might also invent some greenery and reshape some housing blocks and move them to where they fit best. And if he is a gifted transformer, he will eventually arrive at a generic city.

The combination of spatial implications and socio-political factors alone was one big step, but to actually work on the basis of a real city while at the

Fig. 22 Transformation, all figures drawn on the basis of the 1930 plan of The Hague,

2010, source: Sophie Hochhäusl.

126 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

same time making such spatial transformations signifies one step towards the operative. Van Eesteren was never able to improve his symbol dictionary despite his dedication. Neurath alone did make a step forward: he started to develop his first and last map of a city and moved toward city planning.

But let me be clear: Neurath never did one thing: he never combined quantitative and spatial maps. That would have been a too suggestive move, inviting seductive design conclusions and singular decisions. So when the question was posed in the beginning if Neurath perceived of the city as an agglomeration of social facts, then the answer is yes, he did. He believed that these social institutions in a city could and had to be mapped in the city, that in fact they needed to be drawn out so that people could come to an understanding of their built environment. But still, he never thought of the maps, as means of making precise design decisions.

Nonetheless he illustrated in the generic map of The Hague a city how he envisioned it: as small town by the water, fifty percent greenery, fifty per-cent urban fabric, possibly reminiscent of the Viennese settlement movement. But Neurath also stressed the city’s important institutions: working areas and leisure zones, hospitals, kindergartens and playgrounds as well as facto-ries. And they were integrated in housing zones, in great contrast to how the CIAM architects had envisioned the city during CIAM IV. More than only creating an altered illustration of the city, Neurath also represented a piece of the city as he projected it.

Neurath referenced the CIRPAC in this text only once, in a footnote. He stated that ISOTYPE standardization could be compared ‘with various attempts at architectural representation, e.g. with the stimulating proposals of the CIRPAC made by Van Eesteren.’ 62 It is unclear if that mention was really meant as a tribute to the ‘stimulating proposals’, or if it was meant to parallel his own work to that of CIAM, mention of it, he might have felt, was long overdue.

127Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Postscript

In an interview conducted for this research on Neurath, Rem Koolhaas con-firmed that he was familiar with the work of Arntz and Neurath and that he had been influenced by it. On occasion AMO’s maps even seem to have much in common with Neurath’s maps, although AMO’s certainly uses both, operative maps as a means of design, and those that communicate precise statements about the world.

‘But doesn’t a liquid, completely globalized world, also require more liquid maps?’ I asked Koolhaas during the interview, ‘ones that apply a fundamentally different logic, than the ones from the 1920s and 30s.’

‘How would you imagine that?’ he asked me. ‘Are they in real time, are they alive?’ And then he answered:

The promises of the digital are short-lived. In many cases before the promise can establish itself, the decadence of it already prevails, or the commercial pre-vails, or the trivial prevails. It has been an incredibly difficult domain in which to retain precision and to retain integrity. In certain cases exactly against this fluidity and against this immediate abuse of every idea, that the Internet […]

Fig. 23 World of IKEA, Image courtesy of AMO.

128 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

seems to suggest, [we create maps that are] at least momentary freeze frames of particular conditions.63

‘I think we [make maps] … as interpreters at a moment of great political and ideological confusion’ Rem Koolhaas said at the end of the interview. ‘To some extent we adopt a language, not so much ironically, as a statement that there once was clarity, but the clarity is currently gone.’

Sometimes I wonder what Neurath and Van Eesteren would say if they saw that today ‘their maps’ have finally been altered for making precise state-ments, while at the same time being effective design tools. I think they would be very satisfied. Only Otto Neurath might ask Rem Koolhaas, about his ultimate purpose.

129Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Notes

1 Otto Neurath, ‘Visual Representation of Architectural Problems’, Architectural Record, July 1937: p. 56–61.

2 Otto Neurath, ‘Visual Education: A new Language’, Survey Graphic (1937): 25. ‘When will the Middle Ages be at an end? As soon as all men can participate in a common culture and the canyon between educated and uneducated people has disappeared.’

3 Sybilla Nikolow, ‘Planning, Democratization and Popularization with ISOTYPE, ca. 1945. A Study of Otto Neurath’s Pictorial Statistics on the Example of Bilston, England’, Induction and Deduction in the Sciences, Vienna Circle Yearbook 11 edited by Elisabeth Nemeth and Friedrich Stadler (Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2003), 299–329.

4 These are all photographs of other photographs or publications that Otto Neurath collected in the N_Files. These are N_421, N_425, N_430. ISOTYPE Archive, Department of Typography, University of Reading, Reading, UK.

5 Otto Neurath, ‘Städtebau und Proletariat’, Der Kampf, (1923): 240.6 Otto Neurath, ‘Städtebau’, 240. ‘Wie wird die kommende Stadt aussehen? Vor

allem arbeitet an ihr die moderne, großorganisierte Industrie, der weltumspan-nende Handel. Hafenanlagen, Bahnhöfe, Silos, Lagerhäuser, Fabriken, kühn geschwungene Hochbahnen, Eisenkonstruktionen kennzeichnen die kommende Stadt, Wolkenkratzer recken sich stolz empor, an bestimmten Stellen durch be-stimmte Zwecke bedingt, einem Gesamtbild unter Umständen durchaus harmo-nisch eingefügt. Wie aber werden die Wohnungen verteilt sein?’

7 Otto Neurath, ‘Städtebau’, 240. ‘Es geht darum, nicht nur die Industrie- und Wohn-bauten richtig zu verteilen, Wohnungen mit den Verkehrswegen richtig zu verknüp-fen, es geht auch darum, das so Geschaffene architektonisch harmonisch zusammen-zuführen, die Stadt als eine einzige architektonische Einheit anzusehen!’

8 Otto Neurath, ‘Städtebau’, 240. ‘Was für Architekturideen leben nun in den

130 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Architekten und Organisatoren, was für Architekturideen werden von den breiten Massen aufgesogen?’

9 For a detailed discussion on the notions of Gemeinwirtschaft and Gemeinschaft see Nader Vossoughian’s chapter ‘Community’, in Nader Vossoughian, Otto Neurath: The Language of the Global Polis (Rotterdam: NAi, Punlishers 2008)

10 Otto Neurath, ‘Kommunaler Wohnbau in Wien?’, Die Form (1931), 52. ‘In den Volkswohnungsbauten der Gemeinde Wien beginnt ein neues Gemeinschafts- leben. Der gemeinsame Hof dient dem Spiel der Kinder, an Sommerabenden tanzt Groß und Klein wohl gar nach den Klängen eines Lautsprechers.’

11 Otto Neurath, ‘Kommunaler Wohnbau’, 52. ‘Die Neubauten zeigen die ver-schiedensten Formen, wie sie eben entstehen, wenn in toleranter Weise die breiten Scharen der freischaffenden Architekten sich betätigen können … .’

12 Andreas Faludi. ‘Otto Neurath and Planning Theory’, in Encyclopedia and Utopia, The Life and Work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945), edited by Elisabeth Nemeth and Friedrich Stadler (Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996), 208.

13 Otto Neurath, ‘Die pädagogische Weltbedeutung der Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode’, Die Quelle, (1933): 209. ‘Die internationale Bedeutung dieser Methode beruht unter anderem darauf, dass wie die Erfahrung zeigt, die gleichen Bilder-tafeln in verschiedenen Ländern verwendet werden können. Die Bilder sind ge-eigneter als Worte, eine Menschheitskultur vorbereiten zu helfen. Worte trennen – Bilder verbinden.’

14 Otto Neurath, ‘Autobiography’, 100. ‘When controversial problems are presented in print, people expect some kind of bias from the outset, in a way which they would not expect from looking at geographical maps. Isotype is bound to be as neutral as maps and to provide material for free discussion from any point of view. Isotype symbols have fewer positive or negative associations than the printed or written words of a language. You cannot write in a neutral way without being boring, but you can present a neutral picture which is nevertheless attractive.’

15 Otto Neurath, ‘Grundsätzliches zur Kartographie’: Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft, Bild-statistisches Elementarwerk, (Leipzig: Bibliographisches Institut A. G., 1930): 102.

16 Otto Neurath, ‘Grundsätzliches’, 102. ‘In diesem Bildstatistischen Elementarwerk gibt es keine geographischen Karten, sondern ausschließlich Kartogramme, um Eintragungen vorzunehmen oder bestimmte Tatsachen zu veranschaulichen.’

17 Otto Neurath, ‘Grundsätzliches’, 102. ‘Auch die Stadtpläne sollen nur den Char-akter der Stadtteile, die Verschiebungen der Lage kennzeichnen, nicht aber genaue Lokalisierungen ermöglichen. Die kartographische Darstellung des Atlas wurde

131Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

ausschließlich der Bildstatistik angepasst.’18 Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap, Charles Morris, eds., International Encyclopedia of

Unified Science, Foundations of the Unity of Science, Volumes I-II of the Encyclopedia (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1944)

19 Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap, Charles Morris, eds., International Encyclopedia, 33.20 Otto Neurath, ‘Visual Education’, 25. 21 Whenever I have capitalized the word ‘Museum’ it means that I am referring to the

‘Museum of Society and Economy’.22 Otto Neurath, ‘Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaft im Lehrbild’, Österreichische

Gemeindezeitung, May 1, 1927, 44. ‘Man muss nun darangehen, festzustellen, welche Lösungsweisen uns zur Verfügung stehen, es muss der Bereich der Dar-stellungsarten abgegrenzt werden. Leuchttafeln, Magnetkarten, Zeichenfilme, die alle bedürfen methodischer Pflege. Man muss allmählich feststellen, was man so darstellen kann, was nicht; welche Vorteile das ruhende statistische Bild vor all dem hat. Die Wirkung von statistischen Bildern, die abwechselnd aufleuchten, ist noch allzuwenig untersucht.’

23 Nader Vossoughian has described this notion in detail. Nader Vossoughian, Otto Neurath: The Language of the Global Polis, (Rotterdam: NAi Publishers, 2008), 79.

24 Otto Neurath, ‘Bildhafte Pädagogik im Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmuseum in Wien’, Museumskunde, Neue Folge III (1931): 125–9. Neurath used the term Bild-statistik all throughout the 1920s and well into the 1930s. Although pedagogy had always been an element of Neurath’s aspirations, it became the most important goal in the early 1930s when Picture Education replaced Picture Statistics for the first time in an article’s headline in ‘Bildhafte Pädagogik’. For the change in artice headlines see Robin Kinross, index to Band 3 Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften, by Otto Neurath, edited by Rudolf Haller and Robin Kinross (Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1991) v–vi.

25 Otto Neurath, ‘Bildhafte Pädagogik’, 128. ‘Das Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsmu-seum beschränkt sich nicht auf Bildstatistik, es hat in seinen Werkstätten mit seinen Mitarbeitern noch eine Reihe musealer Hilfsmittel geschaffen, wie neuartige Karten in ungewöhnlichen, pädagogisch wirksamen Ausschnitten (Projektionen), technische Bildtafeln, insbesondere zur Rationalisierung großzügige Holzmodelle für seine Abteilung Wohnung und Städtebau, auf durchsichtigem Material Grundrisse übere-inanderliegender Stockwerke, Magnettafeln zur Eintragung wechselnder Mengen; auch die Photographie wird zur Charakterisierung viel herangezogen.’

26 See Note to Illustration 2.24 and 2.25 in N. Vossoughian, Global Polis, 77.27 Images are at the Otto and Marie Neurath Isotype Collection, University of Reading,

132 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

Department of Typography.28 Otto Neurath, Bildstatistik nach Wiener Methode in der Schule, (Vienna and Leipzig:

Deutscher Verlag für Jugend und Volk, 1933), 39. ‘Bilder der 10–14jährigen zeigen deutlich, wie die Aufgabe immer naturalistischer gelöst wird, wenn man nicht aus-drücklich die symbolische Darstellung verlangt.’

29 Otto Neurath, Bildstatistik in der Schule, 39–40. ‘In einer Mädchenklasse z. B. sieht man Reihen von Mädchen, deren Kleidchen allerlei Details aufweisen. Zöpfe und anderes belebt die Situation. Die Mädchen, welche daheim bleiben, blicken etwa zum Fenster hinaus, dessen Gardinen liebevoll ausgemalt werden. Die Führungs-bilder geben Anlass zu malerischer Betätigung. Allzuleicht verlieren sie den Charakter statistikfreier Symbolik.’

30 Otto Neurath, Bildstatistik in der Schule, 36. ‘Während auf den unteren Stufen die Kinder, wie dies den Erfahrungen der Kinderpsychologie entspricht, sehr geeignet sind, Symbole zu erfinden und vereinfacht zu entwerfen, drängt sich auf höherer Stufe, insbesondere knapp vor der Pubertät, der Naturalismus vor, welcher die mannigfaltige, reiche Darstellung bevorzugt.’

31 Otto Neurath, Bildstatistik in der Schule, 39–40. ‘Mit 6- und 7jährigen wird Bild- statistik anfangs am besten in der Weise betrieben, dass man Beispiele wählt, in denen ein Zeichen einen Gegenstand darstellt … Es wird z. B. die Frage auf-geworfen: Wie viele Kinder waren am letzten Sonntag daheim, wie viele im Freien. […] Die Erfindung von Zeichen ist auf dieser Stufe sehr aufschlussreich; […] In einem anderen Fall hat ein Kind den “Sonntag im Freien” mit einem Baumsymbol, verbunden mit einem Pilzsymbol gekennzeichnet, unter Weglassung der Kinder, welche ins Freie wandern. Gefragt, weshalb es den Baum und den Pilz gewählt habe, antwortete es durchaus im Sinne bester Bildpädagogik: Der Baum alleine könnte einen Park in Wien bedeuten, durch den Pilz wird klar, dass es ein Wald sein soll.’

32 Otto Neurath, ‘Visual education’, 28. ‘This visual method has special uses in teach-ing public health lessons, child care, safety, and so on, adults and to children, and in teaching retarded or handicapped children. The International Foundation for Visual Education is working along these lines in many countries.’

33 Kenneth Framton, ‘Introduction’, in Eric Mumford, The CIAM discourse on Urbanism, 1928–1960 (Cambridge and Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2000), xi.

34 For a detailed description of how the three CIAM model maps came into being see Kees Somer, The Functional City: The CIAM and Cornelis van Eesteren, 1928–1960 (Rotterdam: NAi Publishers, 2007), and Eric Mumford, CIAM.

35 Eric Mumford, CIAM, 62–63.

133Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

36 Sigfried Giedion, ‘Letter to Cornelis Van Eesteren, 21. 12. 1931’, CIAM Archiv, 42-K-1931, Eidgenössische Technische Hochschule, Zürich, Switzerland. ‘Vielleicht ist die erste Karte mit den Verkehrszeichen, die sich oft ähnlich sehen, nicht ganz leicht lesbar. Die zweite Karte jedoch ist beim ersten Anblick klar. Vielleicht sollten wir in Zukunft mit Spezialisten von Zahlenzeichen und Statistiken zusammenarbeiten. Wir wollen den Direktor des Wiener Gesellschaftsmuseum, Dr. Neurath, nach Zürich kommen lassen, da er meines Wissens über die grösste Erfahrung auf diesem Gebiete verfügt (erinnerst du dich an die Wandtafeln der österreichischen Abteilung der Berliner Bauausstellung?)’

37 Cornelis Van Eesteren, ‘Methoden des Funktionellen Städtebaus’, Technika Chronika, (1933): 1150. ‘Über die Methoden städtebauliche Erscheinungen zu fassen, über die Erscheinung an sich und über Wege welche zum städtebaulichen Entwurf der Stadt der Zukunft führen, werde ich jetzt sprechen.’

38 Cornelis Van Eesteren, ‘Funktioneller Städtebau’, 1152. ‘Im Generalplan hat man nun die Lage der grossen Einheiten anzudenken welche eine gute Situation im Bezug auf den ganzen Stadtkörper verlangen. Es sind dies Objekte, die in jeder Stadt vereinzelt vorkommen wie: Krankenhäuser, Irrenhäuser, Friedhöfe, Krema-torien u. s. w.’

39 Cornelis Van Eesteren, ‘Funktioneller Städtebau’, 1152. ‘Ausführliche demogra-phische Studien wurden gemacht. Über Technische Einzelfragen, wie Eisenbahn, Uferverbindung, kam man zur Lösung und wurden ausführliche Berichte auf-gestellt. Für die zu erwartende Bevölkerungszahl wurde eine Prognose aufgestellt und ein minimum und ein maximum festgestellt, für welche beiden Annahmen der Plan Wohnmöglichkeit bieten soll.’

40 Neurath’s speech was printed in Technika Chronika which is available at the gta archive at the ETH, Zurich.

41 Otto Neurath, ‘L’Urbanisme’, 1153. ‘Si l’on veut montrer la densité d’habitation dans les grandes villes mondiales d’apres notre méthode, celles-ci seront caracter-isées par des médaillons, p. e. Paris par la tour Eiffel et Notre Dame, Londres par le pont sur la Tamise, etc. La densité d’habitation sera représentée par des figurines noires ou colorées. A première vue on constatera alors que dans les villes anglo-saxonnes p. e. il y a par 100 m2, moins d’habitants que dans les villes d’Europe Centrale. Je n’entrerai pas dans des considérations pour savoir si le fait de l’habitation sur un seul ou sur deux étages détermine cette circonstance.’

42 Otto Neurath, ‘L’Urbanisme’, 1153–4. ‘Il n’est pas toujours nécessaire de pre-senter ces graphiques sur des cartes géographiques; il suffit souvent d’employer des schémas géographiques … Le schéme facilite l’observation. Je pense que nous

134 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

pourrions mieux représenter une quantité de faits étudiés à ce Congrès par des schémas semblables, plutôt que par des plans et des cartes géographiques.’

43 Marie Reidemeister, ‘Protocoll of the Publication comissions’ meeting 12. 8. 33., Attachment Otto Neurath Letter to Sigfried Giedion, 19. 8. 1933’, 1–2, CIAM Archiv, 42-K-1933, Eidgenössische Technische Hochschule, Zürich, Switzerland. ‘aussprache ueber die veraenderung der bisherigen karten. M sehr dafür, weil ein-drucksam und werdeprozess steigend. N sehr dagegen, weil vollkommenstes gezeigt werden soll einfache relationen der resolution an vereinfachten ausschnitten besser demonstrierbar. Zusammenarbeit zuerich, amsterdam, wien mit M., G., vE vermit-teln, man einigt sich darauf, dass entwicklung der arbeit gezeigt wird mit beispielen aus karten, und zwar faelle groesster mannigfaltigkeit und faelle, die zu besonderer kritik anlass geben, um eventuell die notwendigkeit der mundaneumsarbeit zu ent-wickeln. M und vE betonen, dass das chaotische der stadt gezeigt werden soll.’

44 M. Reidemeister, ‘Protocoll’, 2. ‘Die grosse publikation nach gruendlicher durch-arbeitung mit vollkommener optischer darstellung.’

45 Cornelis Van Eesteren ‘Letter to Lazlo Moholy-Nagy, 4. 9. 1933’, Vienna Circle Archive, 232, Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, The Netherlands. ‘Ich bin wirk-lich sehr froh darueber dass du den congress mitgemacht hast, nicht nur weil du einen schoenen congres-film gemacht hast und den schoenen fotos die wir noch zu sehen bekommen werden, aber vor allem weil du an der congres-arbeit so activ teil genommen hast. Von neuem hat es sich bewiesen, dass an unserem congres auch uns nahestehende nicht-architekten teilnehmen muessen. Besonders ist mir in erinnerung geblieben wie activ du an der besprechung mit Neurath teilgenommen hast—worin du immer das menschliche und psychologisch richtig wirkende in der diskussion nach vornen gebracht hast, sonst waeren wir sicher zu viel dem etwas begrenzten system Neurath’s zum opfer gefallen. Du wirst bemerkt haben, dass ich waehrend den ganzen verhandlungen versuchte deine und Neurath’s ideen fruchtbar aufeinander einwirken zu lassen, da ich davon fuer die publikation dieser congres-arbeit viel erwarte. Ich hoffe auf deine weitere schoepferische mitarbeit an der congressarbeit. Es wird noch viel noetig sein um mittel und wege zu finden um die wuensche zu verwirklichen.’

46 Otto Neurath, ‘Letter to C.I.R.P.A.C., 24. 11. 1933’, CIAM Archiv, 42-K-1933, Eidgenössische Technische Hochschule, Zürich, Switzerland.

47 Otto Neurath, ‘Letter to Cornelis van Eesteren 5. 12. 1933’, Vienna Circle Archive, 232, Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, The Netherlands. ‘Bitte sagen Sie mir wie das alles Ihrer Meinung nach zu verstehen ist. Wenn prominente Mitglieder Ihres CIRPAC auf die Zusammenarbeit mit uns keinen Wert legen, würde ich es

135Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

vorziehen, mit meinem Institut auszuscheiden, nicht ohne Ihnen und Ihrer liebeswürdigen Art des Verkehrs mit uns eine persönliche freundliche Erinnerung zu bewahren.

48 Cornelis Van Eesteren, ‘Letter to Otto Neurath, 2. 5. 1934’, Vienna Circle Archive, 232, Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, The Netherlands.

49 Cornelis Van Eesteren, ‘Letter to Sigfried Giedion 10. 5. 1934’, Vienna Circle Archive, inv. nr. 232, Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, The Netherlands. ‘Neurath. […] Ausgangspunkt ist immer noch, dass aus der zusammenarbeit zwischen kongres – und neurath etwas wachsen muss, sei es dass ... neurath so vollständig ist, dass wir damit erreichen (wovon ich noch nicht ueberzeugt bin) was wir vorhaben – oder dass wir daraus etwas neues wächst. Neurath hat die absicht nach london zu gehen und ich würde es begrüssen, wenn in diesem sinne mit ihm umgesprungen würde. Ich halte es für wichtig zu versuchen, dass wir mit ihm zu etwas kommen, du weißt aus barcelona wie kritisch ich seinen damaligen vorschlägen gegenüber stand, aber perönlich mit ihm zu etwas zu kommen, halte ich für möglich.’

50 Otto Neurath, ‘Letter to Vornelis Van Eesteren 21. 11. 1934’, Vienna Circle Archive, 232, Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, The Netherlands. ‘Wir haben die Zeichensache nun wieder um einiges gefördert. Die Schwierigkeit beruht darauf für eine bestimmte Art der Darstellung die Zeichen festzulegen, als damit Zeichen zu bekommen, die auch für andere Plandarstellungen verwendbar sind. Man soll womöglich Bevölkerungsdichte, Wohnungsanzahl, Stockwerkshöhe usw. kom-binieren können und sowohl für jede Kombination zu Zweien, als auch zu mehr ein brauchbares Bild bekommen, das optisch orientiert.’

51 Kees Somer, Cornelis van Eesteren, 179.52 Otto Neurath, ‘Letter to Cornelis Van Eesteren 20. 2. 1935’, Vienna Circle Archive,

232, Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, The Netherlands. ‘Es war mir sehr leid, dass Sie nicht kamen. Sie sind immer so sänftigend. So vertrat ich mit freundlicher Unerbitterlichkeit das Prinzip, man müsse alles, was der Darstellung für eine etwas breitere Oeffentlichkeit dient, so gut pädagogisch bearbeiten, als es möglich ist. Die zögernde Zustimmung und geringe Bereitschaft BILDPÄDAGOGIK als eine Spe-zialität anzuerkennen ist mir vertraut.’

53 Otto Neurath, ‘Letter to Cornelis Van Eesteren 20. 2. 1935’, Vienna Circle Archive, 232, Noord-Hollands Archief, Haarlem, The Netherlands. ‘Es lässt sich bei eini-ger Überlegung alles wirksam lösen aber das ist n i ch t nur e ine g raph i s che Au fg abe , so wenig es nur e ine Arch i t ek t enau fg abe i s t , es bedarf der Dazwischenschaltung der TRANSFORMATION , das ist der bildpädago-gischen Analyse und Richtung-gebung. Die Bemerkung, dass der Architekt nicht so

136 Otto Neurath: Mapping the City as a Social Fact?

viel Zeit für solche Sachen haben könne, beantworte ich mit dem Hinweis darauf: er solle auch die Zeit nicht auf so was verwenden, sondern das eben hiefür aus-gebildeten Spezialisten über-lassen. Das ist aber das alte Lied, das ich Ihnen in verschiedenen Variationen schon vorgepfiffen habe und vorgeklimpert habe.’

54 Enrico Chapel, ‘Otto Neurath and the CIAM – The International Pictorial Language as a Notational System for Town Planning’, in Encyclopedia and Utopia, The Life and Work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945), edited by Elisabeth Nemeth and Friedrich Stadler (Dordrecht, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996), ‘Town Planning’, 175.

55 Enrico Chapel, ‘Town Planning’, 175.56 Eric Mumford, CIAM, 20. ‘But avoiding revolution, of course meant working

closely with large interests with the capital to implement his overarching vision of social and architectural transformation. Such interests transcended national borders, and he was prepared to welcome capitalist internationalism in the service of social rationalization and reform along Taylorist lines.’

57 Enrico Chapel, ‘Town Planning’, 173.58 Kees Somer, Cornelis van Eesteren, 179.59 Otto Neurath, ‘Architectural Problems’, 58. ‘Architects who are always closely

connected with making floor plans and maps mostly intend to show social facts on maps; but in a great many cases we have to give preference to other methods of representation. We must avoid accumulating maps showing social data; it is more instructive to combine maps and pictographs. This leads us to a use of a symbol dictionary which contains symbols applicable to both maps and pictographs. This is the basis of visualization more widely applied.’

60 Otto Neurath, ‘Architectural Problems’, 59. ‘The symbol, representing stations, factories, kindergartens, and other buildings are in black with a white design in the middle.’

61 Nader Vossoughian indicated that the 1937 map was Neurath’s way of illustrating the functional city in his subtitle to 4.4., N. Vossoughian, Global Polis, I however, think Neurath solutions really wanted to contrast the Functional city.

62 Footnote to Otto Neurath, ‘Architectural Problems’, 57. ‘See examples in Otto Neurath, Basic by Isotype, Kegan Paul, London, 1937, We can couple ISOTYPE standardization with various attempts at architectural representation, e. g. with the stimulating proposals of the CIRPAC made by Van Eesteren.’

63 Interview with Rem Koolhaas, April 13, 2010, see Appendix B, Sophie Hochhäusl, ‘Otto Neurath – The Other Modern: Proposing a Socio-Political Map for

Urbansim’, (MA Thesis, Cornell University, 2010).

Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond: On Otto Neurath’s Isotype Contributions

to Visual Communication and

Museum Learning

Hadwig Kraeutler, Vienna

In the interwar years of the 20th century, the philosopher, sociologist, and economist Otto Neurath (Vienna 1882–Oxford 1945) gained international recognition for his (r)evolutionary approaches to employing museums and exhibitions as instruments of enlightenment and empowerment. Neurath, convinced that in what he called the ‘Era of the Eye’ visual means would provide powerful and egalitarian modes of communication, wrote in 1925:

[M]odern man is conditioned by the cinema and a wealth of illustrations. He gets much of his knowledge during leisure hours in the most pleasing way through his eyes. If one wants to spread knowledge, one should use means simi-lar to modern advertisements.1

Neurath founded and directed the Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftmuseum (GWM, Social and Economic Museum, 1925–1934), part of the new structures to help carry through the socialist politics of the Red Vienna. Neurath’s key innovation in this context was the Vienna Method/Isotype,2 a method to systematically think about and prepare predominantly visually structured informational settings, for which he introduced the expression ‘visual language’. Isotype-work—in its full visionary scope—would mean carefully designed, ‘orchestrated’ settings for communication (museum, exhibition, film, book, wall-chart, etc.) using ‘collages’ of graphic, pictorial and other representations (text, image, object, media) in international cooperation for visual education.

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 137–174.

138 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

In Vienna, and later in the Netherlands (The Hague, 1934–1940) and in England (1940–1945; Oxford, Isotype Institute from 1942) Neurath worked with a (changing) interdisciplinary team of experts—a fact he always under-lined. Among others, there were well-known figures such as Gerd Arntz (1900–1988), the GWM’s graphic designer, and Josef Frank (1885–1967), the museum’s architect. From 1925 onwards, Marie Neurath (1898–1986) worked in the GWM-team. She became the principle ‘transformer’ (trustee of the public, audience advocate), a decisive position in the Isotype team, and she was also instrumental in the preparation of Rondom Rembrandt (Around Rembrandt, 1938).3

For quite obvious reasons—one being Neurath’s forced departures, but also the ephemeral quality of, and lack of archival structures for museo-graphic materials—evidence of the museum and exhibition work is scarce. Still, the concepts and circumstances behind Rondom Rembrandt are reliably documented. Important primary materials of this art-sociological visualisa-tion are held at the Isotype Collection of the University of Reading.4

In the last decades there has been considerable interest in Isotype, with dis-cussions mostly concerning questions of graphic communication and design.5 The concepts, and broader implications of Isotype, as exemplarily evidenced in museum and exhibition work,6 had remained outside the focus. Pictograms, employed all over the world, indeed are the easy to reproduce and success-ful ‘trade-mark’ of Neurath’s. An exploration of Isotype work restricted to the graphic and diagrammatic applications and not exploring the museum and exhibition work, however, does not offer comprehensive treatment of Neurath’s socially relevant ‘tools for thinking’.

More recently, the diverse ‘turns’ (pictorial, spatial, medial), as well as globally apparent pressures and problems (issues of economy and ecology, rise of nationalism and fundamentalism, lack of education and literacy) and new opportunities (availability of internet technology and visual media) have pointed at the relevance of, and (help to) re-establish interest in Neurath’s work with the visual and visual communication.

Today ‘the museum’ is discussed as part of the social institutions which (together) are systems of order that perpetuate, preserve, and legitimise codes and practices (material and immaterial) of a collectivity. Even in economically oriented debates, the arts and culture today are seen as most important, as social glue—giving the foundations for everything else in society. In this,

139Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

[T]he function of the museum […] is to provide us with a central arena of sociability, […] the agora, the common place.7

Museum and exhibition work constitutes culturally created and culturally vested methods which involve power-linked narratives.8 Their active and passive uses are learnt in performative acts. The very moment of actually experiencing the (predominantly visually structured) museum/exhibition presentations is defined by the meeting of the (mix of; often incompatible) ‘narratives’ developed in the (institutionalised, anonymised) cultures, and the preconditions brought in by the individual (learner/user).9

In this context, Neurath’s Isotype museum and exhibition work, with coordinated thematic programming, and based on close attention to what was happening in the actual visits, excelled in several still (r)evolutionary and relevant features: Exhibitions were shaped so as to open access for the popula-tion at large and provide ‘a common language’. Isotype proposals were geared at traditionally underserved museum audiences, at empowering and engaging them actively in practical politics—in a truly democratic effort breaking up the usual museum hierarchies. Work was carried out in a team (including scientists, technicians, designers, educators), the processes were monitored in order to produce meaningful offerings, useful tools, as well as integrated procedures of self-reflexivity (of the institution). This overall attitude was embodied in the key position, the transformer, responsible for choosing relevant information, and an appropriate and attractive visual language.

Neurath was not interested in merely ritual and affirmative use of social institutions, such as museums and exhibitions. The Isotype enterprise involved not only targeted use of subject expertise, newest technologies and structures, but also new and egalitarian concepts. This was connected to Neurath’s democratic quest to ‘develop and employ a conception of knowledge as an instrument of emancipation’,10 and was meant to treat problems bewilderingly apparent in the turbulent first half of the twentieth century. Neurath’s pro-gressive museum work—serving the entire society—just as his philosophy, was inextricably linked to pedagogical theory, to the social sciences, and politi-cal thought. Neither these larger topics, nor the prevailing conditions of that historical time and era, among others the decisive practical politics in the Red Vienna, are treated here.11

First in this essay, I briefly explore Neurath’s notions of visual educa-tion, visual language, and learning, and introduce Isotype, authoritatively

140 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

described in Neurath’s Bildpädagogische Schriften and in the précis exposition International Picture Language (1936).12 Next, using the art-related exhibition Rondom Rembrandt as a practical example of ‘picturing social facts’,13 and with a focus on audience orientation and audience development—central museo-logical concerns—I enlarge on the Isotype approach. Here, applications of Isotype strategies in the preparation of pictorial statistics and pictorial charts are examined in more detail. As Rondom Rembrandt proposed new aims for museum work, and new practices for discussing art topics, part of this essay also touches on basic issues concerned with art museum work. With this, in a second strand, I implicitly argue that today’s ‘museum’—a specific conceptual framework, a shaped social tool, and designed interface (i. e. pictured social fact), which at the same time also functions as a shaper of social facts—is still being challenged by Neurath’s Isotype work.

More than Meets the Eye: Otto Neurath’s Concern with ‘Visual Language’

and ‘Visual Argumentation’

Neurath often referred to the overriding importance of the visual in the tools used for the communication processes he sought to provoke. His advice is proverbial: ‘A picture says more than a thousand words’, ‘What can be shown with the help of a picture should not be said by words’, or ‘words divide, pictures unite’.14 Neurath emphasised that scientists using the most advanced techniques for discussing work-results were doing so in optical representations, with photographs to render visible sound waves, astronomical phenomena, the spectres and structures of crystals, to trace the behaviour of ants, of children. Such factual visual rendering of a specific given situation was what Neurath called ‘optical protocols’. Also three-dimensional models, with possibilities of change, enlargement, re-assembling, for example the globes employed in astron-omy or geography, formed part of what Neurath called ‘pictorial education’.15

Propagating the use of visual education and visual aids, and pointing at their potential, Neurath stated:

School has to take note of omnipresence of pictures, if the effect of the street is not to become overruling. […] The schools like all old organisations are rooted in the past—pictures are for those without education.16

141Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Neurath’s and his team’s work of the 1920s was meant for the ‘uneducated masses’, for those without academic skills, such as reading and writing, and no time and/or energy left after a long day’s work hours. According to Neurath, the diagnosis was clear: Factual information should preferably be conveyed visually, informative pictures (using pictograms/symbols as the basic element) and models should be part of a comprehensive and universally applicable Isotype approach.

However, what Neurath ultimately aimed at with the use of the visual was not the quick and ‘effortless’ transfer of information—although a key moment—most important was its potential for procuring egalitarian learning opportunities. As Neurath expained in the 1940s, education should not only concern the delivery of knowledge. He wrote:

The social pattern which permits more than one opinion etc. is the ‘democratic pattern’. The transfer of the scientific attitude is not mainly concerned with knowledge but also with the creation of certain habits, sincerity of research and integrity of arguing. That implies not only thinking of how to pass exami-nations but also of deliberating on various possibilities of arguments, in short, how to become ‘meditative’ on certain subjects.17

This kind of learning entailed: To analyse observations, develop a concept by taking into account many diverse aspects and integrating diverging viewpoints, to look at human interdependencies. Neurath aimed at an open approach/attitude, respecting a democratic principle, which lies in the potential to modify and to negotiate. He also wanted to secure that prejudices should not gain the upper hand, and excluded any claims for absolute truth. He held visual means to be especially well suited for this endeavour, more democratic, open for diverse readings, not dependent on book learning.

Visual education leads to internationalisation much more than word educa-tion. One can use the same visual arguments connected with explanatory words in various languages, even with various remarks on the same visual material. Visual education is related to the extension of intellectual democracy within single communities and within mankind, it is an element of international social planning and engineering.18

Neurath explained that it was the social settings, as experienced in the GWM’s exhibitions, the active use of factual information offered, the language

142 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

developed in the comparisons, and the exchange of views, which were deci-sive for the transfer of such an attitude. The practical museum and exhibition work—covering a period of roughly twenty-five years—was crucial for the development of Isotype, its scope and variety.19

In order to clearly link the ‘what, why, who and how’, audience orientation had already become a key factor in the GWM’s work in Vienna. For this, the transformer was introduced—the expert ‘knowing exactly what potential visual resources there are to solve any given problem of presentation […] of trans-lating the scientific specialist’s intentions into visual reality.’ 20

The transformer guided the GWM-team to make sure that the latest educational and scientific findings were acted upon, that the visualisations would be attractive, ‘speak’ to, and convey the exhibition content, engage the users, and make them use the information.21 The exhibition develop-ment processes were monitored, and the results were evaluated and dis-cussed to improve future work (Figs. 1 and 2). This Isotype-methodology provided for the self-reflective attitude necessary to deliver effective and ‘visually enticing’ environments. These concerns were shared with the users.

As a didactic and pedagogic approach, Isotype would not only require the close observation of the visually organised messages, but entail active analysis of the ‘optical protocols’ by the learners, the use of the arguments devel-oped in discussions, and sometimes practical application of their own Isotypes (charts, displays made by the learners).22 In the charts, both message and possible interpretability were basically formulated. However, formulated so as to make the user integrate them into existing concepts. Aesthetic experience,

Fig. 1 Photograph of mock up exhibition situation, c. 1938,

I.C. N 2003, Isotype Collection, University of Reading.

143Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

activities of direct observation (apprehension, contemplation), and a situation of discourse developed from that, should not be circumvented.

Neurath’s Bildpädagogische Schriften do not contain a systematic explo-ration of the concepts visual, visuality, visual education, communication, or visual argumentation. These terms generally relate to complex competencies such as decoding, consuming and creating visual messages, ranging from very conventionalised everyday uses (e.g. traffic signs) to the visual media as indi-vidualistic and artistic categories conveyed in complex structures of visual/image-arrangements (e.g. painting, image, picture, stage set, film, exhibition, collage; using tone, colour, composition to create a story, atmosphere, emo-tion).23 Although it is well known that the visual is not as clear and clean as a word-/text-based language, several characteristics of ‘language’ are found: communicative potential, parts and arrangement-structures, Saussurean langue/parole contexts, diachronic and synchronic aspects, etc. Neurath often described the Isotype museum work (aims, methodology) in the context of visual education (Bildpädagogik). Also in International Picture Language—The first rules of Isotype (1936) museums and exhibitions are treated prominently, especially in the part ‘Grouping Pictures With Other Things’ (pp. 65–73).24 Museums and exhibitions figured as constitutive elements in the plans for the Mundaneum, an international support-network for integrated visual educa-tion started in nucleus version in the early 1930s, and were repeatedly referred to in Neurath’s manuscripts of the 1940s, ‘Visual Education’, and ‘Visual Autobiography’.25

In addition to the ‘auxiliary’ verbal languages (as BASIC)26, Neurath saw ‘Isotype as a visual language’ which had to perform a different task, that of

Fig. 2 Chart showing ‘contradicting directions‘ in exhibition design: direction of reading vs.

direction of walking, c. 1938, I.C. N 1992, Isotype Collection, University of Reading.

144 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

‘conveying visual arguments and visual information […] to reach […] the masses spread over the surface of the earth’.27

The full use of the rules of the ISOTYPE system will make a complete change in our ways of teaching. [He saw it as a] guide to deeper knowledge and to science, without the danger which is so frequent in education by words: that of taking note only of details and seeing nothing of the general view. If the general view is given by teaching pictures, it will be kept in mind.28

In 1942, in a letter to Julian Huxley (1887–1975) Neurath again put forward these utopian ideas. He wrote:

Visual Education can be made much more “neutral” than education by means of words. For international purposes therefore, Visual Education is a proper tool. […] Experience taught us, that […] People usually enter exhibitions, look at charts, less hesitantly than they would read periodicals of a different “faith”. Another point: You may look at pictures without particular efforts.29

These plans with a global scope did not develop further. Otto Neurath died in December 1945.

When discussing Neurath’s use of the concept ‘pictorial/visual language’, several basic assumptions cannot be overlooked: Neurath repeated time and again that the ‘pictorial/visual language’ was not a (normal) language, was not to be understood without supplementing words from a natural language:

What we have to do with here, however, is a picture language, which is not able to give the story by itself, but only with the help of a normal language.30

This refers to the text-elements (necessary to clarify the potential factual statements of the pictogram-arrangements) providing the momentum for the visually observable ‘arguments’ to be performed in language interpretations—the diverse actualisations by the users (verbal comments, deductions).

The ISOTYPE picture language is not a sign-for-sign parallel of a word lan-guage. It is a language, which may be put into words in different ways. The units of the picture language have different senses (HK: meaning) when they are in different positions.31

145Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

It is not possible to give a word for every part of such a picture or a statement for every group of parts.32

Propagating Isotype as a visual language for supporting an argument (in a lecture, school teaching, notice boards, shop windows, newspaper illustra-tions, brochures, slide-presentations, etc.) Neurath implied using all media available for visually presenting information (photographs, films, books, posters, exhibitions, museums, etc.), referring to all in sum as the ‘orchestrated’ tools for visual information and communication, and explained:

Some of the visual devices have mainly to serve as entertainment, advertisement or propaganda. Others have systematically to bring over some habits and attitudes from one group of the population to another—mainly from the older to the younger generation—in a rather argumentative way. This kind of transfer may be called “visual education”.33

Pointing at a fundamental phenomenological orientation of visual education, Neurath underlined that visual education enforces a more human approach than education through writing, as it deals with things that are within every-one’s grasp:

[It] is neutral and satisfies the feeling of having knowledge in common, which in turn implies having a medium in common, international, neutral, etc.34

Symbols are not very dependent upon any fashion. Therefore they are not only international but also as it were, “inter-tempera”.35

For international purposes, a stringent system of conventions would be needed for creating a common atmosphere for people with different languages, occupations, and outlooks, as ideas had to be communicated and transferred over time, space, and cultures.36

This work of Neurath’s had already begun at the GWM in Vienna. Besides the transformer methodology, the Isotype-approach offered a range of visual materials characterised by the pictorial statistics, the Isotype Exhibi-tion Technique for ‘visual argumentation’37, and a set of ‘Rules to keep in Mind’ concerning the structural organisation of exhibitions (with chapters, redundancy). The principles and procedural rules of Isotype-designs were

146 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

routinely documented and systematically developed to render best-suited visual statements. Thus, established best practice influenced the production of the next task at hand, producing a complex pictorial language in a semiotic approach,38 which allowed for both continuity and flexibility.

The practical organisation and didactic support needed to spread this encompassing Isotype approach is echoed in the composition of the kits for the GWM’s travelling exhibitions. These consisted of a series of charts with pictorial statistics (produced in a modular system), a manual with instruc-tions for how to place and mount them (arrangement and overall structure, intended viewing position, organisation of information), and the support materials, such as booklets and slides for working with visitor-groups.

In short, everything [was] geared towards quick orientation and easy retention of information.39

The ‘Isotype Exhibition Technique’ pointed out ‘rules’ for the visualisations, and for relating to the interests of the users more generally (among others): express in words only what cannot be visualized, avoid monotony, aim to satisfy varied interests, avoid overcrowding, unify charts and models, emphasize experiences of daily life. Neurath’s basic ‘rule’ in this context reads:

A picture made according to the Vienna method shows at first glance the most important aspects of the subject; obvious differences must be at once distin-guishable. At the second glance, it should be possible to see the more important details; and at the third glance, whatever details there may be. A picture that has still further information […] is from the point of view of the Vienna school, to be rejected as pedagogically unsuitable.40

The charts (pictorial elements, captions) had to be as clear in their ‘visual statements’ that these ‘three steps’ were sufficient to allow for various proc-esses of observing, decoding, and recombining specific visually conveyed ‘information’. Pictograms and images used were without renderings in per-spective, without hues or special reference to the optical of colours. But col-our coding, and the ‘tactile’ qualities of lines and outlines were purposefully employed.

For Otto Neurath ‘reading’ a well-prepared Isotype chart was as easy as counting, grouping, and measuring—but had to be learned:

147Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

[r]eading a picture is like making observations with the eye in everyday experience: what we may say about a language picture is very like what we may say about other things seen by the eye. For example: the man has two legs; the picture-sign has two legs; but the word-sign ‘man’ has not two legs.41

The chart ‘Development of Amsterdam’ and the title page from the Rondom Rembrandt exhibition (cf. figs. 3, 4), and a New Year’s greeting card (fig. 5) pro-vide good examples for different Isotype applications and the visual language.

Fig. 3

Two charts: the

development of

the University

of Leiden and

of the population

of Amsterdam,

spread (pp. 2 & 3

from the booklet

Rondom Rembrandt),

(1938), I.C. 3/2,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

Fig. 4

Rondom Rembrandt,

title page for the

exhibition booklet,

leporello-dummy

(assembled between

1938 and 1946?),

I.C. 2029, Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

148 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

The ‘Development of Amsterdam’, basically a ‘classical’ pictorial chart, uses symbols (pictograms), a guiding image 42 (evoking a context necessary for the intended interpretation—here the coat of arms of Amsterdam), very little text (establishing that each of the man symbols represents ten thousand inhabitants), and is organised in vertical (time) and horizontal (amounts) axis/coordinate.

The title page of the exhibition-booklet (fig. 4) shows a different combi-nation of text (two words) and five pictograms: the characteristic signature-like ‘R’ (used for Rembrandt, and for his artwork), the silhouettes of a man with palette and paintbrush (painter), of a man with backpack (migrant), two silhouettes a ‘Dutch’ house (home, living) and a sailing-ship (commerce); the last two also used in the New Year’s greeting card (evoking other interpretations).

Also the New Year’s Greeting, ‘ISOTYPE 1940’ (fig. 5) combined symbols, ‘like words’, with text elements (the heading; three words for the location: ‘The Hague Holland’; and the sentence: ‘The International Foundation for Visual Education wishes you a Happy New Year’). The visual arguments are rendered in the customary clear-cut imagery of Isotype, without painterly quality in the visual elements or composition. These symbols, partly also used in other interpretational contexts, e.g. in the Rondom Rembrandt charts, help to formulate other statements here. Most conspicuously the ‘logo’ of Isotype (the ‘figure holding a chart’) is repeated five times. For this specific purpose ‘put’ in ‘boat’-shapes ‘going’ in different directions, it holds up charts with symbols representing Isotype work, i. e. evoking the range of subjects treated by the International Foundation for Visual Education. There ‘are’: a worker

Fig. 5

Isotype –

New Year‘s greeting of 1940,

I.C. MS 1091 5/18 T 300,

Isotype Collection,

The University of Reading.

149Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

(stone-mason, inspired by an Egyptian hieroglyph); elements of pictorial statistics; a sailing-ship (commerce); a locomotive (traffic); an elephant (evoca-tive of Neurath’s ‘pictorial signature’); an outline map of, and two symbols for ‘living’ in the Netherlands (silhouettes representative of a ‘Dutch’ house and of a windmill).

This incomplete and rough description—not mentioning e. g. colour, proportions or composition—clearly demonstrates how cumbersome a (necessarily not exhaustive) ‘translation’ of the visual message into words is, whereas the image is ‘open-ended’, and in its totality instantly given to the viewing capacity of the observer. Neurath often discussed these ques-tions and propagated Isotype—visual education—as one possibility among others:

Frequently it is very hard to say in words what is clear straight away to the eye. It is unnecessary to say in words what we are able to make clear by pictures. […] Education has to put the two together, and a system of education has to see which language is best for which purposes.43

Isotype charts employed communicative elements from the linguistic and the pictorial, the text and image repertoires,44 and delivered a controlled, inter-medial configuration for synoptic observing—rather than merely picture- or word-based, and/or temporally consecutive information. The potential for diverse interpretational approaches and the informative content developed was decided by the connections elicited from the users, not based on (previously internalised) knowledge of a subject or disciplinary systematic. This meant that conclusions about the meanings of the information presented were largely left to the viewers, as they actively had to study the information and seek relationships—a natural activity for scientists which was to be evoked also from the newly initiated users—confident, curious, and positive in a ‘club atmosphere’. Thus an Isotype exhibition was a dynamic, and process-oriented tool for argumentation where the verbalizations were delivering different ‘meditations’ and not finite conclusions.

The aim was not to deliver a product in legible signs, but to engage the users to actively ‘read’ (observe and combine) the visually conveyed facts, to argue a case from the information delivered, sensitive for and respectful of other viewpoints. The aim was to foster enfranchisement and empowerment, a tolerant and meditative ‘attitude’.

150 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

In Rondom Rembrandt, for example, the user was not told what was ‘to be seen’ in the works of Rembrandt, or about the complex research system and terminology used by art historians. Rather the exhibition provided opportuni-ties to relate to the works of the ‘legendary’ Rembrandt on everyday terms. This enabled the user to establish confidence, to take the time, look, see, learn vocabulary, find out about possible categorisations and concepts, compare, meditate, and talk about the experience. Neurath coined a specific term for such a sense-based and egalitarian approach. He called it ‘humanising’, as opposed to a paternalistic ‘popularising’.45 The exhibition Rondom Rembrandt provides an exceptional and ‘condensed’ example for how this Isotype-approach was applied for treating art-related matter.

The Art-Related Exhibition Rondom Rembrandt

Rondom Rembrandt produced in Holland in 1938, was revolutionary in several aspects. Focussed on audience orientation, addressing hitherto underserved audiences, it proposed new approaches for engaging with art: There were new topics, a new type of venue, and a new funding scheme.46 Taken together and taken seriously, these had/have the potential to challenge established tradi-tions of art history and conventional museum work. Neurath circumscribed the underlying socially/educationally founded rift like this:

There are people who are interested in Rembrandt’s paintings, drawings, etchings etc. [… They] may enter a museum or buy a book […]. There are others, who heard of Rembrandt, are interested in the famous man, like some of his pictures, but do not know how to come into closer contact with him.47

Rondom Rembrandt was meant for those ‘others who [had] heard of Rembrandt’. As Neurath wrote:

In The Hague, Rotterdam, and Amsterdam we set up exhibitions in depart-ment stores. They were visited by thousands of people who ordinarily would not have gone to a museum.48

These unusual locations underlined the effort to provide egalitarian opportuni-ties for seeing pictures (art works) and for thinking and talking about them as

151Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

something other than ‘holy relics’. It made the act of ‘going to exhibitions’ easy and part of everyday concerns, a possible ‘cultural habit’ for the man and the woman ‘in the street’. In the same vein, the key visuals used in Rondom Rembrandt pointed at practical measures relating to the visitors’ life-circum-stances (production and consumption of goods, transport processes, commod-ity-features of specific historical times, Rembrandt’s family and influence in society). This overall theme is beautifully ‘enacted’49 in the title page to the accompanying exhibition booklet (fig. 4). The synchronic method and Isotype methodology as had been applied to practical subject matter in the GWM’s previous work (health, housing, social and economic development) was used to conceptualise Rembrandt’s life and time. In argumentative and visual lan-guage-like technique of presentation it made ‘the hero approachable’.50

Neurath did not try to directly change the classical art museums, but made use of museum displays. Rembrandt’s works, as would have been known to everyone in 1938 in Holland, were on show in the Rijksmuseum in Amster-dam and the Mauritshuis in The Hague, while the exhibition was held at the ‘Bijenkorf ’. 51 Thus the originals in the traditional museum collections seem to have provided the specialised disciplinary context.

Rondom Rembrandt was mainly organised with pictorial charts and made extensive use of photographic reproductions (of artworks).52

As a whole it showed how an interest in the arts and an understanding of a certain historical period could be developed by combining a well-arranged, language-like technique of presentation.53

Not presupposing specialist knowledge or vocabulary, Rondom Rembrandt did not primarily refer to customary categories of art appreciation, such as painterly achievements or æsthetic qualities in Rembrandt’s works. In a social historical perspective it embedded the artist, his work and innovations in the changing circumstances—economic, technical, and social—of his time (figs. 6, 7, and 8).

The ‘language-like’ Isotype features included: a coherent system for exhi-bition layout, design of individual elements (charts with pictorial statistics), arrangements of photographs (reproductions of paintings) and maps, colour-coding, interactive games. Pictograms (quantities) were used for: Rembrandt’s works, (artistic) genres, pupils/artists, students, goods, or commerce. In some occurrences (arranged in rows/groupings of amount pictures) these ‘asked’ for

152 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Fig. 6

‘Rembrandt and his family’,

(chart from the exhibition

Rondom Rembrandt using

photographs),

(1938), I.C. T 1698,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

Fig. 7 ‘Rembrandt and his family’ and ‘Apprentices and painters influenced by Rembrandt’,

spread (pp. 8 & 9 from the booklet Rondom Rembrandt), (1938),

I.C. 3/2 -15, Isotype Collection, University of Reading.

153Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

counting, e. g. number and placements of (Rembrandt’s works in museums), economies (Rembrandt’s, art-market, general), population (of Amsterdam, Leiden), or students (which showed ‘at one glance’ how distant Rembrandt’s time was; cf. fig. 3). Lead images established a clear visual connection—for example the Dutch interiors (reproductions of paintings by other artists) to the respective social backgrounds of commissions for Rubens vs. Rembrandt (fig. 18).

Some practices of the specific discipline art history were also employed for the Rondom Rembrandt-presentations. These concerned observational skills (comparing, rating) and aimed at establishing a concept of chronology and stylistic development for Rembrandt’s oeuvre.

Fig. 9

‘300 Years University of Leiden‘

(Detail). Chart from the booklet,

I.C. 3/2., Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

Fig. 8

‘What was paid

for a painting by

Rembrandt‘,

chart for the exhibition

Rondom Rembrandt,

leporello-dummy

(assembled

between

1938 and 1946?),

I.C. T 1703,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

154 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Fig. 11

‘Changes in Rembrandt’s

techniques‘

(page from the

booklet Rondom Rembrandt),

(1938 ),

I.C. 3/2, Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

Fig. 10

‘Rembrandt in his painted

selfportraits’

(chart from the exhibition Rondom

Rembrandt using photographs),

(1938 ),

I.C. T 1687, Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

155Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Referring to these charts (collage of photographic reproductions with ‘sequenced’ self-portraits of Rembrandt’s, fig. 10; his renderings of hands and faces, fig. 11) which helped to discern changes in Rembrandt’s style in the course of the different periods of his career, and to the colour coding (fig. 12), Neurath wrote:

This […] taught many things, you see immediately alterations in his gesture, in his personality […] how his brush is changing, from the first paintings to the last. We subdivided his life line, and gave each of these subdivisions a particular colour, from the young man’s green to the old man’s brown. These colours lead the visitor through the exhibition, the reader through the booklet.54

Neurath explained how this was attempted by showing ‘the brushwork’ in photographs of enlarged details of Rembrandt’s works (fig. 11), or with other synoptic collage-arrangements (fig. 13), and gave a reason, why:

[Also] the layman who now learns what research means […] likes that, assumed, that this knowledge does not ask for long hours of studies.55

The colour coding kept aware of fundamentally important background infor-mation (historical time and changing surroundings) without producing ‘visual noise’.

If we had not done this, we should have had to label all his etchings and paintings with their dates, thus burdening the visitor with more detail than he could absorb.56

Describing how the background of Rembrandt’s time was visualised in this exhibition, Neurath wrote:

What was his time, a visitor may ask? Where? […] You may show a picture of Leyden, which presents the town as an industrial one. An ISOTYPE brings a short history of the textile production in Leyden, the maximum period is identical with the Rembrandt period. You may present old colour prints, or paintings of old Amsterdam, and of Rembrandts Amsterdam—very nice and impressive town views.57

156 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Neurath first related to the interests and capacities of the envisaged users (which questions might arise? what subject-knowledge should be expected?) and in a second step suggested (appropriate) means of visualisations to choose from (a blend of Isotype and conventional images).

Organisational schemes of certain charts were specific to the Rondom Rem-brandt exhibitions, and some charts, although treating the same topic differed in the versions for the exhibition and the booklet respectively. Examples are:

Fig. 12

‘Rembrandt’s paintings in the

Netherlands‘

(page 11 from the booklet

Rondom Rembrandt),

(1938 ),

I.C. 3/2, Isotype Collection, Univer-

sity of Reading.

Fig. 13

‘Apprentices and painters

influenced by Rembrandt’,

version with paintings

indicating the

contemporary background

(chart from the exhibition Rondom

Rembrandt using photographs),

(1938 ),

I.C. T 1699 from 3.2-14.

157Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Fig. 14

‘Rembrandt’s Selfportraits‘

(page 7 from the booklet

Rondom Rembrandt),

(1938 ), I.C. 3/2,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

Rembrandt’s chronologically arranged self-portraits (figs. 10, 14), a chart relating to his time and contemporaries (figs. 15, 16), a map indicating the distribution of his works (figs. 12, 17), or the charts comparing art activities and markets of Rembrandt and Rubens (figs. 18, 19).

Fig. 15 ‘Contemporaries and important events of Rembrandt’s times‘ (exhibition chart

from Rondom Rembrandt with photographs of portraits, paintings of buildings,

commerce, whaling, etc.), (1938 ), I.C. 3/2, University of Reading.

158 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Fig. 16

‘Contemporaries and

important events

of Rembrandt’s time’,

chart from the booklet

(with signatures;

pictograms for

commerce, whaling, etc.),

I.C. 3/2 –42,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

Fig. 17

Rembrandt’s Paintings

in the Netherlands

(chart from the exhibition

Rondom Rembrandt

using photographs),

(1938),

I.C. T1708,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

159Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

The ‘visual weight’ of the pictograms rendered the extent of the artists’ thematic specialisations, and the text established the percentage-relation to their complete œuvres. Specific symbols (not difficult verbal terms) were used for the artistic genres (portrait, landscape, religious and mythological paint-ings). In the exhibition version, the additional lead images (showing a likely historic placement of the artworks) served as clues for the artists’ respective markets. In the booklet, this information is not visually conveyed.

In addition to the observational tasks, and as a special attraction, simple games (‘question and answer’ machines, devices for self-testing) were devel-oped for the Rondom Rembrandt-exhibitions (cf. fig. 20). These provoked curi-osity and engaged the users (physically as well as mentally) who were asked questions concerning the exhibition and would find out if their answer was right or wrong.

Fig. 18

Chart from

Rondom Rembrandt

exhibition, comparing

Rembrandt‘s and

Rubens‘ subjects

of paintings,

using photographs

to show the

various destinations

(1938),

I.C. T 1696,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

160 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Fig. 19

Chart from

Rondom Rembrandt

booklet, comparing

Rembrandt‘s and

Rubens‘ subjects

of paintings,

using pictograms

(1938),

I.C. 2034,

Isotype Collection,

University of Reading.

Fig. 20 Photograph of mock-up exhibition situation, c. 1938,

I.C. 5/15 (detail, T 1814), Isotype Collection, University of Reading.

161Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Neurath underlined the importance of such concrete, practical provisions for interactivity and involvement, and pointed out that these had already been introduced by the GWM in Vienna. He also reported that the Rembrandt-exhibition in department stores was ‘visited by ten thousands of people, who have been very interested in this new type of exhibitions and this new type of booklet’ and pointed at the deliberate combination of individual events, particular pictures, and analyses in detail, with environmental material, in the two different, but corresponding versions.58

In the booklet—with considerably more text—charts and photographs (some in symbol variants, as technically required with regard to viewing-size, reprographic-quality, cost of printed matter) and corresponding text were especially carefully matched. Marie Neurath described this as a new way of ‘bring(ing) text and pictures intimately together’.59 After the successful Rondom Rembrandt-project, a series of ‘Around [other well known artists]’ was envisaged, using this ‘pictures and text’ approach.

The intentions behind such Isotype-enterprises can be summarised as follows: to make an art topic easily accessible—physically, intellectually, and emotionally. This concerned the use of unusual venues, as well as the demo-cratic ‘visual language’ and the flexible and impressive visualisations of concepts. The text of the exhibition booklet ends as folllows:

By [i. e. with the help of] only this booklet and the Isotype pictures one does not get to know Rembrandt: but maybe through his works. May this small collection be inspiring to visit the museums and to better get to know the Dutch Golden Age which also was the century of its greatest artist.60

This conveys two especially pertinent points, namely as Neurath writes, with the booklet and the Isytype exhibition ‘one does not get to know Rembrandt: but maybe through his works’, and that the pedagogical task set out for the Isotype work was to engage, kindle interest, and inspire to go further.

Obviously (more than 70 years later), it is not possible to ascertain what Rondom Rembrandt ‘meant’ for the users. It possibly enabled the untrained lay-users to understand and use new terms, to work out categories of art appreciation, provided time for conversations, and with this helped them develop competencies for experiencing art. One effect seems clear: Rondom Rembrandt’s presenting and networking these themes and diverse contextu-alisations in a dynamic and uncommon production structure/environment

162 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

(as offered in the department stores), vastly enlarged the potential for learn-ing and ‘meaning’. It touched new ground and provided an example of integrated and sustainable audience-orientation, a component necessary for (responsible) public presentations in museums and exhibitions.

The quality and success of the Rondom Rembrandt exhibitions had not gone totally unnoticed. In 1946, Paul Rotha,61 the influential British film-maker, had been invited as a speaker to the British Museums Association’s Annual Confer-ence. In his discussion of visual communication techniques, Rotha reported on ‘the well-known work of the Isotype Institute’. He specifically pointed at its efforts in creating a ‘picture language’ and ‘orchestra of instruments for visual education’, and as an outstanding example mentioned Rondom Rembrandt.62

Still, there seem to be no other contemporary reactions or direct influence of this project in its own time. We have to keep in mind, however, that often Neurath’s work did not fit his contemporaries, as he was ‘not afraid of taking up untimely issues’.63 Rondom Rembrandt took place shortly before the Second World War, an extremely difficult epoch for European societies, and the ven-ues, the department stores, put it (at least mentally) far from peer review or a disciplinary art historical or museological context.64

More recently, picture historian Astrit Schmidt-Burkhardt introduced a reproduction of a Rondom Rembrandt chart (fig 7; the Rembrandt family-chart) to discuss Gerd Arntz’s graphic style. Although earlier in the book she had referred to Neurath’s ‘Wiener Methode’ (Isotype), the connections were not made clear, and the underlying notions (exhibition purpose, user-context, language-like visualisations, team work) were not pointed out in relation to the Rembrandt-chart.65

What is seen in an image (artwork, diagrammatic chart, etc.) does not only depend on the competencies brought to the encounter but also on the socially developed and embedded instruments.66 This has to do with competencies in ‘languages’ or ‘language dependent’ communication systems (traditions), with trespassing customary disciplinary boundaries, and with attitudes. Neurath proposed a forum of research that draws upon the expertise and methods of several of the relevant disciplines—art history, perceptual psychology, anthro-pology—without presuming any one of these to be a complete explanatory model, but with the understanding that each must retain the rigour of its methods and yet be open to other approaches.

The most concrete revolutionary quality of Neurath’s museum work was its decisive and stringent perspective of the ‘future user’, its ‘constructivist’ and

163Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

collage-like work-method, corresponding to his basic concept of ‘orchestration’. In this work of ‘humanising’ specialist/expert work, to make it approachable and understandable for the average user (the broad masses without academic training), special importance was given to visual communication.

Museum Work and Visual Argumentation

In the Western world, systematic learning and the transfer of information are (not only seemingly) coupled to spatially and visually structured concepts (departments, sections, scripts, segments and strata) and ‘pictured as social facts’ in specific spaces (school, library, museum, laboratory, university). The breakdown of such conceptions (representative and constitutive), and the realisation of the fact that these are mental and communal (constructions/restrictions) and undergoing constant shift, is pushed by the new technologies offering new conversations, and characterised by the qualities and the ‘fluid-ity’ of the virtual and immaterial. Such traditions and conceptions are also challenged by taking seriously Neurath’s historic, but still provoking, ‘orches-trated’ enterprises.

The transinstitutional and cross-media aspects of visual culture, where museums and exhibitions figure prominently, make the museum a pre-eminent site for contested views of identity, power, and control. We are used to think about viewing images and media as a process of socialization in specific culture settings: who gets to produce images? Who gets to consume them, who can do both?

Within this complex, the art museum has traditionally played an impor-tant role in the transferral of art practices, and according to Pierre Bourdieu (1930–2002) has functioned as a legitimizing central higher authority. There, in the museum, which takes out of the original context of production and use, neutralises and re-loads with other qualities, the æsthetic disposition is produced and reproduced.67 As such, the art museum has also functioned as a socially distinguishing authority, as a ‘marker’ between pertaining and being locked out—heightening the social status of its patrons. Also more recent art-sociological research implies that the relationship between demographic background and consumption of art has not changed since that recorded by Bourdieu. The majority of the population lacks imperative empowerment and access to the ‘performed’ code. The museum is reserved for the affluent

164 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

and better educated. What is happening there is ‘shared’ within a specific segment of society—those capable of specialised (not necessarily academic) discourse, implying connoisseurship and rituals, with clear links to economic power and art markets. These ‘distinguishing’ differences can be internalised to a degree that they seem ‘natural’. However, they have to do with education, acquired competencies, and habits.68

Contrary to ‘pure’ art history concerned with intra-disciplinary refinement (discussions of iconology or iconography), a sociologically oriented art-science/art-studies (visual culture studies) not only takes into account the history of pro-duction, but the history of reception as well as that of the media for perception.69

In this context, Rondom Rembrandt can justly be seen as an important historical example. The traditions sustaining ‘distinction’ and perpetuating inequality as identified by Bourdieu’s work, were certainly worked against by Rondom Rembrandt, with it’s clear orientation at lay-audiences, in not art-related sur-roundings, and by introducing everyday common concerns, topics and questions, also echoed in the French sociologists’ research. Bourdieu identi-fied similar clues as had been devised by Isotype-methodology, as pertinent and successful categories for establishing possible recognition formations for non-specialised audiences.70 Rondom Rembrandt proposed and carried through a previously unknown sociological structural approach and introduced novel observational categories, and with this, broadened the social base for meaning.

Research into the conditions or the results of museum/exhibition use had barely started in Neurath’s times. Also in this respect the GWM work must be seen as an early and exceptional example.71 Innumerable surveys and evalu-ations of museum visiting and learning have been undertaken since.72 These have delivered relatively stable pictures of audiences and visiting patterns, and confirm many of the less formally secured observations of an earlier date—as made by Neurath.

Nowadays research concerned with learning and communication in museums, based on constructivist epistemology emphasizes the dynamic and complex relationships between learning and social contextualisations.73 It also clarified that the learner’s own perception of learning and of her/his individual situation in this process constitutes an influential component of learning, and underlines the importance of incorporating appropriate ‘conceptual frameworks’, as well as of providing assistance for the users to ‘make sense’, and applying principles of interpretation and learning, to museum displays.74

165Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Neurath did not narrowly focus on the visual within the boundary of traditional humanistic scholarship, or ‘high culture.’ His concept surpassed what has been divided into ‘high’ or ‘fine’ art and ‘low’. He related to informa-tional design, museums and exhibitions, books, films, architectural concerns, and employed the most diverse media and strategies in his Isotype work, using the visual for (visual) communication. Today, the visual is often studied in such a less bounded fashion, as the new paradigm of ‘visual culture’ represents a holistic and encompassing approach to the visible world. As expressed in his ‘visual autobiography’ and often underlined by Neurath—also by the con-glomerate materials and strategies he referred to—the worthiness of visual material or practice, as an object of study, depends not on its inherent art-qualities, but on its place within the context of the whole of visual cultures. Neurath encouraged looking at matter under scrutiny from many sides and considering all implications, as a meditative mood and democratic ‘scientific’ attitude should imbue all of society.

Contemporary museum discourse is characterised by (verbalized) ethical notions and concepts such as inclusivity and democracy, by interdisciplinary, multifocal, co-operational and international structures. This again evokes Neurath, who pointed at social contingencies, renounced all foundationalist conceptions, and definitely related sustainable advancement of societies to a general sharing in democratic and egalitarian structures, and to an increase in

Fig. 21 The pictogram ‘R’ as developed for Rondom Rembrandt to denote both Rembrandt,

and his works (Isotype Collection, University of Reading) and a random collage of

Rembrandt signatures. (H. Kraeutler 2010).

166 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

the quality of the lives of the many. Neurath aimed for an inclusive democracy and underlined that provisions for learning, communication and exchange were necessary. He saw museums/exhibitions, predominantly visually organ-ised, as constituting powerful tools with great potential for playing an active role in this painstaking process of general advancement.75

For museums and exhibitions the main question is: How to start a comprehen-sive scheme and then to reach the detail, what’s the argument and not what does the director want to present. Single objects on view should be linked by illuminating schemes.76

Indeed, museums, through their educational power can be important engines for social change. By some museum workers, education has been addressed as ‘the essence of museums’ and as ‘the most potent weapon at our disposal’.77

In practice, however, realisations are often confined to a pragmatic attitude, aiming at peer review levels, and frictionless implementation within the limits of the already accepted.

More than half a century after Neurath’s critical work, the newer findings confirm his methodological approach, the importance of the visual, and, most importantly, that it is the fundamental aspects, touching on the structures and characteristics of the traditional museum, which need to be rethought and changed, in order to provide for more relevant institutions, for a ‘museum for the future user’ engaged in the important business of ‘picturing social facts’.

167Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Notes

1 Neurath 1973: 214 (Neurath 1925).2 After 1934, the initial name Vienna Method of Pictorial Statistics was given up in

favour of the acronym ISOTYPE – International System of TYpographic Picture Education.

3 Marie Neurath (née Reidemeister; later Otto Neurath’s third wife); Cf. Robin Kinross, ‘The work of the transformer’ in Neurath and Kinross 2009: 77–96.

4 The material from the Isotype Collection is referenced here as: I.C. followed by the archival reference number (e. g. I.C. 3.2/42).

5 Cf.: Hartmann and Bauer (eds., 2002), Nikolow and Schirrmacher (eds., 2007), Vossoughian (2008). Online at: http://www.hyphenpress.co.uk/journal/2008/05/12 isotype_recent_publications.

6 Cf. This article is a revised version of a paper given at the workshop ‘Picturing social facts. On Neurath’s visual language. Gesellschaftliche Tatsachen darstellen. Zu Neuraths Bildersprache’ in the framework of the 33rd International Wittgen-stein Symposium in Kirchberg, Austria, August 8, 2010. An extensive treatment of this aspect of Neurath’s Isotype work is found in Kraeutler 2008.

7 Gopnik 2007: 3.8 Cf. Marrinan 1992.9 Cf. Roberts 1997.10 Cf. Cartwright and Uebel, ‘Philosophy in the Earthly Plane’ in Nemeth and

Stadler 1996: 39–52, 43 (italics as in the original).11 For a contextualisation of Otto Neurath, the philosopher, sociologist, political

economist, historian, and information on his life and work, see Stadler 2001. 12 Neurath 1991 and Neurath 1936.13 Cf. the topic of the Neurath-workshop at the Wittgenstein Symposium 2010 (see

note 7).14 Neurath 1991: 190, 242, 346. 15 Neurath 1991: 180.16 Neurath 1936: 21.17 Neurath 1996: 259–260.18 Neurath 1996: 331. 19 Neurath: ‘The Isotype-method was developed as the result of practical exhibition

work’ (Neurath 1991: 417).20 Neurath 1973: 219.21 Neurath 1991: 255.

168 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

22 Neurath 1991: 265–336.23 The term ‘visual literacy’ is used to mean experience with the workings of visual

media coupled with a heightened conscious awareness of these workings. Four consequences are commonly said to flow from visual literacy: comprehension of visual media, transfer of cognitive skills from the interpretation of visual media to other tasks, awareness of visual manipulation, and æsthetic appreciation (cf. Raney 1997: 15).

24 Neurath 1936.25 The latter was published as: Otto Neurath. From hieroglyphics to Isotype – A visual auto-

biography, edited by Matthew Eve and Christopher Burke, London: Hyphen Press, December 2010.

26 Neurath was concerned with Basic English, Esperanto, Interglossa (Neurath 1996: 335); Basic English is a restricted language, limited to 850 English terms, cf.: Neurath 1936 (reprint 1980: 6).

27 Neurath 1996: 335.28 Neurath 1996: 24–26.29 Cf. Otto Neurath’s letter to Julian Huxley, of December 1942 (I.C. MS 1091, File

1/35).30 Neurath 1936: 16.31 Neurath 1936: 18.32 Neurath 1936: 19.33 Neurath 1996: 291.34 Neurath 1996: 333.35 Neurath 1996: 334.36 Neurath 1996: 332.37 Neurath 1936: 65–73; 1991: 275, 594–595; Marie Neurath 1974: 130; Cf. the

teaching strategies identified in Raney (1971). The clear case for visualisation, visual literacy, and visualisation skills as core skills and essential to thinking has often been argued (Kress and Van Leeuwen 1996; Pink 2006; Sturken and Cartwright 2001).

38 Cf. Marie Neurath, ‘Wiener Methode and Isotype: my apprenticeship with Otto Neurath’ in Neurath and Kinross 2009: 9–76; 55.

39 Neurath 1991: 197 (italics as in the original).40 Neurath 1973: 223 (1925). An abbreviated version of this is used as the intro-

ductory paragraph to the chapter ‘The Chief Points of the ISOTYPE System’ (Neurath 1936: 27).

41 Neurath 1936: 20.

169Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

42 Neurath and Kinross 2009: 20.43 Neurath 1936: 26–27.44 Both information modes are basically differently structured, employ different sets of

elements and rules—disjunctive symbolic orders/structures—and imply activating respective modes of recognition, use, combination (cf. Krämer 2009: 157–159).

45 Neurath, ‘Visual Education. Humanisation versus Popularisation’ in Neurath 1996 (1945).

46 Cf. Marie Neurath in Neurath and Kinross 2010: 57. 47 Cf. Neurath, ‘Around Rembrandt’ (I.C. 3.2/42). This typescript was written in

English, i.e. not Neurath’s mother tongue. No changes in vocabulary, spelling or punctuation were made in the transcripts used here.

48 Neurath I.C. 3.2/42.49 Cf. the caption used for this image in Neurath and Kinross 2009: 57.50 Neurath I.C. 3.2/42 (italics as in the original).51 Rondom Rembrandt was sponsored by the Dutch department store De Bijenkorf

(on the occasion of Queen Wilhelmina’s 40 years’ jubilee) for simultaneous show-ing in the sales venues of three of its branches, 1–15 September 1938. The main outlet is situated just across the ‘Gracht’ (canal) from the Rijksmuseum.

52 Cf. Laurie 1932. 53 Neurath, I.C. 3.2/42.54 Neurath I.C. 3.2/42; Cf. footnote 30.55 Neurath I.C. 3.2/42.56 Neurath I.C. 3.2/42.57 Neurath I.C. 3.2/42 (capital letters as in the original).58 Neurath I.C. 3.2/42.59 Marie Neurath in Marie Neurath and Robin Kinross 2009: 59.60 Cf. (my translation): ‘Door boeken en Isotype-afbeeldingen alleen echter leert men

Rembrandt niet kennen: men moet zijn werken zelf gaan zien. Moge deze kleine verzameling een opwekking zijn tot het bezoeken van musea en tot het beter leren kennen van Holands Gouden Eeuw, die ook de eeuw was van zijn grootste kunste-naar’ in: International Foundation for Visual Education (Stichting for Beeldpaeda-gogie), Uitgegeven ter gelegenheid van de tentoonstlling ‘Rondom Rembrandt’ in de Bijenkorf, Amsterdam–Den Haag–Rotterdam, n. d.: 12.

61 Paul Rotha (1907–1984) produced experimental film with Isotypes from 1941 onwards, e. g. ‘World of Plenty’, ‘Land of Promise’, ‘Total War in Britain’ (cf. Neurath 1991: 644). This cooperation brought a continuation of experimental work with ‘diagrammatische Filme’ (diagrammatical films) started as early as 1927

170 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

in Vienna. The talk for the MA was about ‘The film and other visual techniques in education’ (Rotha 1946: 141–145).

62 Rotha 1946: 141–142.63 Kinross 1994: 72.64 Enquiries regarding possible material evidence or documentation of the exhibi-

tions had been directed to the Bijenkorf Archives (Amsterdam City Archives), the Rijksbureau voor Kunsthistorische Documentatie (The Hague), and the Rijks-museum (Amsterdam). These pointed out that Rembrandt-exhibitions had been organised by the Rijksmuseum in Amsterdam in 1935 (centenary) and in 1938 (letter from Rijksmuseum, Amsterdam, NL, of November 30, 1990). The Rijks-museum’s library has a copy of the Rondom Rembrandt exhibition-booklet.

65 Cf. Schmidt-Burkhardt 2005: 32–34.66 Kastner 2009: 106.67 Bourdieu 2001: 461.68 Bourdieu 1994.69 Bourdieu and Darbel 2006: 74.70 Cf. Bourdieu 1974, 2006.71 Marie Neurath in Neurath and Kinross 2009: 58.72 See the overview in Kirchberg 2005.73 Cf.: Falk and Dierking 2000, Hein 1998, Hooper-Greenhill 2007.74 Cf.: Black 2005, Hein 1998, Hooper-Greenhill 2007, Roberts 1998.75 Kraeutler 2008.76 Neurath 1996: 312.77 Fleming 2008: 7.

171Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Literature

Alpers, Svetlana. Rembrandt’s enterprise. The studio and the market. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988.

Alperson, Philip (editor). The Philosophy of the Visual Arts. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992.

Anderson, Gail (editor). Reinventing the Museum. Historical and Contemporary Perspectives on the Paradigm Shift. Lanham, New York, Toronto, Oxford: Altamira Press, 2004.

Bal, Mieke and Norman Bryson. ‘Semiotics and Art History’ in The Art Bulletin, Vol. 73, No. 2, June 1991, 174–298.

Black, Graham. The Engaging Museum. Developing Museums for Visitor Involvement. London and New York: Routledge, 2005.

Bourdieu, Pierre. Distinction. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1994.Bourdieu, Pierre and Alain Darbel. L’Amour de l’art: Les musées d’art européens et leur

public. Paris: Edition Minuit, 1966. English translation: The Love of Art. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991.

Cartwright, Nancy and Jordi Cat, Lola Fleck, Thomas E. Uebel (editors). Otto Neurath: Philosophy between science and politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

Falk, John H. and Lynne D. Dierking. Learning from Museums: Visitor Experiences and the Making of Meaning. Walnut Creek, Lanham, New York and Oxford: Altamira Press, 2000.

Fleming, David. ‘The International Slavery Museum’ in International Council of Museums (editor), ICOM-News, Paris, 1/2008: 7.

Genoways, Hugh H. (editor). Museum Philosophy for the Twenty-first Century. Lanham, New York, Oxford: Altamira Press 2006.

Gopnik, Adam. ‘The Mindful Museum’ in American Association of Museums (editor), Museum News, Nov./Dec. 2007, 37–41: 3.

Hartmann, Frank and Erwin Bauer (editors). Bildersprache. Otto Neurath – Visualisierungen. Vienna: WUV-Facultas Universitätsverlag, 2002.

Hein, George E.. Learning in the Museum. London and New York: Routledge, 1998.Hooper-Greenhill, Eilean. Museums and Education, purpose, pedagogy, performance.

London and New York: Routledge, 2007.Kastner, Jens. Die ästhetische Disposition. Eine Einführung in die Kunsttheorie Pierre

Bourdieus. Vienna: Turia + Kant, 2009.Kinross, Robin. ‘Blind Eyes, Innuendo and the Politics of Design.’ Visible Language

(28) 1 (1994): 68–78, Providence: Rhodes Island School of Design.

172 Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

Kirchberg, Volker. Gesellschaftliche Funktionen von Museen. Makro-, meso- und mikro-soziologische Perspektiven. Berliner Schriften zur Museumskunde, Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaft, 2005.

Krämer, Sybille. ‘ “Schriftbildlichkeit” oder: Über eine (fast) vergessene Dimension der Schrift’ in Bild – Schrift – Zahl, edited by Sybille Krämer and Horst Bredekamp, 157–176 (Second edition). Munich: Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 2009.

Kraeutler, Hadwig. Otto Neurath. Museum and Exhibition Work—Spaces (Designed) for Communication. Frankfurt, Berlin, Bern, Bruxelles, New York, Oxford, Vienna: Peter Lang Internationaler Verlag der Wissenschaften, 2008.

Kress, Gunther and Theo van Leeuwen. Reading images: The grammar of visual design. London: Routledge, 1996.

Laurie, Arthur Pilans. The brush-work of Rembrandt and his school: illustrated by photo-micrographs. London: Oxford University Press, 1932.

Marrinan, Micheal J.. ‘Cultural Institutions and the Topography of Art History’ in Philip Alperson (editor) 1992: 521–529.

Neurath, Marie and Robin Kinross (editors). The transformer, principles of making Isotype charts. London: Hyphen Press, 2009.

Neurath, Marie. ‘Isotype’, in Instructional Science, 3 (1974): 127–150, Amsterdam: Elsevier Scientific Publishing Company.

Neurath, Otto. International Picture Language. London: Kegan Paul, 1936 (Facsimile Reprint, Department of Typography and Graphic Communication, University of Reading, editor, 1980).

Neurath, Otto. Empiricism and Sociology. With a Selection of Biographical and Autobio-graphical Sketches. Edited by Marie Neurath and Robert S. Cohen, Vienna Circle Collection (Vol. 1), Dordrecht/NL and Boston/USA: Kluwer/Reidel, 1973.

Neurath, Otto. Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften, Volume 3. Rudolf Haller and Robin Kinross (editors), Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1991.

Neurath, Otto. ‘Visual Education—Humanisation versus Popularisation’ (edited by Juha Manninen) in Elisabeth Nemeth and Friedrich Stadler (editors), Encyclopedia and Utopia. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996: 245–335.

Nikolow, Sybilla and Alf Schirrmacher (editors), Wissenschaft und Öffentlichkeit als Ressource füreinander. Studien zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte im 20. Jahrhundert. Frankfurt/M.: Campus, 2007.

Pink, Sarah. The Future of Visual Anthropology: Engaging the Senses. London: Routledge, 2006.

Raney, Karen. Visual Literacy. Issues and debates, Report on the research project ‘Framing visual and verba Experience’, a collaboration between Middlesex University and the Arts Council of

173Rondom Rembrandt and Beyond

England, published by School of Education Middlesex University, London, 1997.Roberts, Lisa C.. From Knowledge to Narrative, Educators and the Changing Museum.

Washington, D. C: Smithsonian Institution Press, 1997.Rotha, Paul. ‘The film and other visual techniques’ in Museums Association (editor),

The Museums Journal, vol. 1946 / 8, London: 141–145.Sandell, Richard (editor). Museums, Society, Inequality. London and New York:

Routledge, 2002.Schmidt-Burkhardt, Astrit. Stammbäume der Kunst. Zur Genealogie der Avantgarde.

Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 2004.Stadler, Friedrich. The Vienna Circle—Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence

of Logical Empiricism. Vienna-New York: Springer, 2001.Sturken, Marita and Lisa Cartwright. Practices of Looking: An introduction to Visual

Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.Vossoughian, Nader. Otto Neurath. The Language of the Global Polis. Rotterdam: NAi

Publishers, 2008.

Permission for reproduction of photographic and other documentary materials used for this article is gratefully acknowledged. The full credit reference is: Otto and Marie Neurath Isotype Collection, Department of Typography & Graphic Communication, University of Reading, UK.(http://www.reading.ac.uk/typography/)

Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

Eric Kindel, Reading

The potential of Isotype for communicating to diverse, international audiences is generally attributed to the simplified imagery it employed to produce compelling and easily understood visual explanations. While it frequently supported and was supported by verbal language, Isotype’s ‘picture language’ circumvented linguistic complexities and the obstacles to communication they created.1 The emphasis placed on the international application of Isotype is embedded in its name and in the title of Otto Neurath’s International picture language, the book that describes Isotype most fully.2 But how effective was Isotype when deployed beyond the modernised West where it was mainly used? An answer does not come readily to hand since very few opportunities arose to test it in the developing, non-Western world during more than four decades of Isotype activity. One opportunity, however, did arise through work in British colonial West Africa. Between 1952 and 1958 commissions were undertaken in Sierra Leone, Nigeria and the Gold Coast (Ghana), countries then moving towards independence (figure 1). Those in Nigeria, for its Western Regional Government, were the most substantial and provide some evidence of how Isotype fared at the further reaches of the international sphere its inventors hoped it might serve.

Before the Isotype Institute’s contact with Nigeria, its director Marie Neurath had never visited Africa; nor had her late husband Otto. But Africa was, in key respects, fundamental to Isotype. It was there that knowledge about economy, governance, health, agriculture and much else was urgently needed; and there that conditions of sub-literacy or illiteracy were thought at once most suitable and most challenging for visual education. Such conditions offered the

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 175–193.

176 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

possibility of testing the claim that visual education in general and Isotype in particular—conceived and, by 1940, deployed only in Europe and North America—could function effectively beyond the West.3

Despite the lack of opportunities early on to test Isotype so far afield, a substantial meeting with Africa did draw near in 1943 that hints at how it might have been used in this context. That year Otto Neurath and the Isotype Institute became involved in plans for a travelling exhibition about Africa, initiated by the British Colonial Office (figure 2). A proposal for the exhibition, titled ‘Human life in Africa’, was written by Neurath; it was informed by the view that Africa should not be placed in ethnographic isolation but instead seen as having much in common with Britain. Human knowledge in both places was essentially comparable if not always devel-oped to the same extent. This view is seemingly reinforced by the propos-al’s display strategies that make no concession to differences among those attending the exhibition, whether in Britain or in Africa. A meeting with the Africans should therefore take place on (more or less) equal terms through communication techniques able to reach a variety of audiences. As Neurath insisted, ‘the cosmopolitan pure human approach should prevail.’ 4

By the early 1950s, and after Otto Neurath’s death, Africa was finally met when Marie Neurath and the Isotype Institute became involved in publish-ing initiatives there. These were being pursued by the London-based book packaging company Adprint; it, in turn, had been encouraged by the British Colonial Office, which ‘wanted parts of West Africa … linked by magazines and books’.5 The work would be handled through a new Adprint subsidiary, Buffalo Books. The Isotype Institute had already contributed to numerous Adprint publications since the early 1940s and Buffalo Books was an

Fig. 1

West Africa

(political),

early 1950s.

177Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

extension of this relationship.6 The first project was a prospective colour magazine named Forward, developed in consultation with several West African governments (figure 3). A trial number was produced in English and vernacular languages, and incorporated articles, illustrations and comic strips by West African writers and artists; Isotype contributions included illustrated diagrams. Despite its encouraging blend of content, Forward made it no further than its trial number, issued in the Gold Coast. But other, related initiatives were already well underway, now with the government of the Western Region of Nigeria.7

Fig. 2

Otto Neurath, sketch,

added to a letter to Paul Rotha,

24 May 1943 (detail); IC 1/44.

Fig. 3

Forward magazine, no. 1, probably 1954,

front cover and spread with Isotype illustrated diagram, 325 × 250 mm (cover);

distributed in the Gold Coast (Ghana).

178 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

The 1950s were a unique period in Nigerian history. Over the course of the decade the country made increasing gains in self-determination until, in 1960, it achieved full independence from Britain. Much of Nigeria’s growing independence during the 1950s was exercised regionally, and of its several regions the governance of the Western Region was by some distance the most politically and socially progressive. In 1953, the British Government convened one of a series of conferences intended to strengthen Nigeria’s constitutional footing in the period leading up to its anticipated independence. One of the Western Region’s delegates was Obafemi Awolowo who, as Minister of Local Government and leader of the ruling Action Group party, shaped the region’s political programme (figure 4). While in London he was introduced to Isotype and the possibilities it held for communicating his government’s programme of reform to the Western Region’s people.8

In her memoir ‘What I remember’, Marie Neurath recalls her first contact with Awolowo:

One day Awolowo … was expected. Foges came to me with a short text by him and said: ‘I would like to make clear to these people that they need visual methods in their country; read through this text quickly and make drawings for its main theses; not that [Awolowo] wishes to illustrate it; he should just see how pictures would help him.’ So I read quickly, plucked out a few points, and made some pencil sketches on slips of paper. I was there when Awolowo arrived in his Yoruba robes, together with his private secretary. After a while

Fig. 4

Portrait of Obafemi

Awolowo, around 1950.

179Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

my sketches were given to him; he looked at them quietly and began to talk with his secretary; ‘how could we best use them?’ 9

The sketches shown to Awolowo included simple visualizations of federal structures, indirect and direct elections, political hierarchies, and constituency make-up (figure 5).10 His response must have offered cause for optimism, as shortly she afterwards wrote ‘It is a pleasure to see how quickly these highly intelligent representatives grasp the roughest of my sketches, and how the method seems to appeal to them’.11 Awolowo’s ‘grasp’ suggests that he quickly understood Isotype and the possibilities it held for the Western Region.

Some months after her meeting with Awolowo, the Western Regional Government invited Marie Neurath to Nigeria to develop a programme of public information. Her title would be ‘Visual Aids Expert’ and she would be based in the regional capital Ibadan. A first trip would take place from June to September 1954, with a second planned for the following year. Both trips would take her away from London and the Isotype Institute for lengthy periods. That she accepted such arrangements as necessary (though she declined a first proposal of a single 6-month stay) indicates her understanding of the importance of local immersion.12 While this was no doubt a practical arrangement, giving her direct and on-going contact with ministers and civil servants in the Western Region, it also enabled her to experience conditions on the ground. She could observe how, where and by whom visual aids were used—if at all—before resolving on how Isotype work might be best designed and integrated into the local scene.

Fig. 5

Marie Neurath,

sketch,

probably 1953,

126 × 203 mm.

180 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

Fig. 6

Education for all

in the Western Region, front cover,

Ibadan: Western Regional Government,

1955, 204 × 163 mm.

Fig. 7

Education for all in the Western Region, pages 2–3.

181Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

Among the first items on Marie Neurath’s itinerary after arriving in Ibadan were visits to primary schools. The visits headlined in regional news-papers and the accompanying articles describe what she saw of education both in the capital and in nearby villages.13 She encountered a range of visual aids made by pupils that dealt with topics such as water supply, imports and exports, geography, health, agriculture and basic maths; and she was impressed by their efforts. Another experience had even more direct consequences:

Already in London I had been given a ‘white paper’ on education to read … . From this I had designed a large summary chart; it went straight into the wastepaper basket after I had walked through the streets of Ibadan; why should these people have to struggle with my chart? I made a booklet of 16 pages out of it; problems, tasks, solutions were shown step by step. This format was retained for all the other subjects.14

The booklet to which Marie Neurath refers, Education for all in the Western Region, was the first in a series that would explain the government’s plans for social reform and betterment in simple and direct terms (figure 6). Booklets were commissioned by ministers in connection with their port-folios and became known as ‘White Paper’ booklets.15 For each booklet, effort was initially directed towards identifying and detailing themes. Designs then evolved through a series of mock-ups with visualizations and texts that depicted and narrated existing circumstances in the Western Region and how reforms and new initiatives would lead to improvements in the lives of all. The aim was to explain rather than instruct. Work was mainly done in the Ministry of Education where Marie Neurath was given an office. Throughout the process ministers and civil servants played an important collaborative role in shaping content, reviewing design work in progress and resolving details of a specialist nature.

The results can be seen in the printed booklets. In the first spread of pages in Education for all, for example, a blend of local content with Isotype technique plays out in a scene whose function is to introduce the benefits of education (figure 7). Pictograms are integral to the scene but among them are figures whose profiles are naturalistic and whose clothing is in the Yoruba style.16 The figures assume postures typical of village living: a child sits on the ground, a woman with a child strapped to her back kneels over a cooking pot, a chicken pecks the ground. The houses as depicted are made of mud, straw

182 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

and timber, or cement block and corrugated iron. These locally identifiable elements are then brought together using a familiar Isotype strategy: com-parison. Parallel village scenes each include a box that frames a child’s devel-opment with and without education; alternative outcomes and the material benefits of education are made plain. Text is precisely keyed to the graphic arrangement and reinforces the pictorial narrative.

In a second example, Better farming for better living in the Western Region, the visual argument again begins with local elements: crops and agricultural processes indigenous to the Western Region (figure 8). These are shown on subsequent pages in scenes and contexts that are at once familiar to farm-ers (the booklet’s intended audience) and newly configured to illustrate how cooperation and partnership with the government would bring about change (figure 9). Graphic sequences present farmers and officials facing problems and finding solutions; comparisons show improvements in methods and productivity. Throughout, text is structured in parallel to graphic mat-ter, further explaining scenes or clarifying issues. As in all of the booklets, the English is plain and clear. This was no doubt done to accommodate audiences of mixed reading abilities, but also in anticipation of the text’s translation into the vernacular Yoruba, in which specialist terms might not be available.17

By the end of her first visit, Marie Neurath had completed work on several booklets and agreed their design and accompanying texts with government officials. When she returned to the Western Region in late February 1955 for a second three-month stay, proof copies of several book-lets were in hand (figure 10); these she was eager to try out on their intended users.18 She again visited schools where, at one school, Education for all was handed out to several classes. The pupils reacted to it with enthusiasm and curiosity. Notes taken by their teachers record the pupils’ understanding of graphic comparison, before-and-after scenarios and relative advantage or improvement. The notes describe classroom scenes in which teachers led the looking and reading, but where pupils also gathered around and pointed to the booklet’s pictures. These interactions sometimes led to more detailed teaching demonstrations or to complementary activities.19 Better farming for better living, on the other hand, was tested out on farmers, though exactly where and how these encounters played out is not clear. Marie Neurath did venture into a forest one day to a nearby village where she gave the booklet to a family, to study their reactions. They were intrigued and asked to keep

183Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

Fig. 8 Better farming for better living in the Western Region, pages 2–3,

Ibadan: Western Regional Government, 1955, 204 × 163 mm (single page).

Fig. 9 Better farming for better living in the Western Region, pages 14–15.

184 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

it. Reflecting on her experiences, she concluded that in general the booklets functioned best when they were looked at collectively (as in schools), then taken home and absorbed there.20

Other work completed around the time of Marie Neurath’s second trip to the Western Region included a series of ‘poster-leaflets’ on health topics, designed for use in surgery waiting rooms (figure 11). These had been conceived the previous August while Marie Neurath was in Benin City to learn more about health care provision. There she visited a leprosarium, a hospital, several first aid stations and a surgery. Seeing the surgery’s waiting room ‘crammed full’ of patients returning again and again with the same complaints, she suggested producing educational pictures with which medical assistants could explain to patients, while they waited, the nature of their con-dition and how it could be prevented. ‘They would then perhaps grasp what they were doing wrong and how they should do it better.’ 21 She consulted the resident doctor (Ogunlesi) about which health care themes he considered most pressing and with him decided to address four: food, water, leprosy and tuberculosis. Poster-leaflets in a 2-fold format were then produced in Eng-lish and Yoruba. Unfolded, they could be displayed on a wall; folded, they could be taken away and studied at home. The poster-leaflets again combine locally familiar figures and scenes with graphic configurations typical to Isotype.

Fig. 10

Better farming for better living in the Western Region,

Health for all in the Western Region, Paying for progress in the Western Region, front covers,

Ibadan: Western Regional Government, all 1955, 204 × 163 mm.

185Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

In places, generalised pictograms work side-by-side with specific ones; in one instance (‘Leprosy’) ‘Nigerian man’ examines ‘Isotype man’ to assess his condition (figure 12).

Among the projects completed by the Isotype Institute in the Western Region, those associated with election processes should also be mentioned. The work involved the design and production of posters and booklets for regional elections. The booklets gave instructions on how to register for the election, and how and where to vote; the posters variously identified registration and polling stations, and illustrated the voting process.22 A poster was also made to

Fig. 11

Poster-leaflet,

‘Leprosy’,

380 × 506 mm

(unfolded).

Fig. 12

Poster-leaflet, ‘Leprosy’, (detail).

186 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

explain the Western Region’s structure of government; it is unusual in that it is the only design among all the Nigeria work that relies wholly on generalised pictograms. Overall, the programme of information on voting was considered a success, as attested by a government minister who informed Marie Neurath that voter turn-out in the Western Region had been double that in the Eastern Region. He was convinced that Isotype deserved the credit.23

Apart from the work so far described, Marie Neurath undertook another initiative during her second visit: the establishment of a Visual Aids Office in Ibadan. A memorandum was drawn up detailing how a team of local work-ers would be recruited and trained.24 The team would include a teacher, who would act as the transformer, an artist, and a technical assistant. Training the team would be in the hands of Marie Neurath. Crucial to the new office, as she saw it, was the need to test work on the local population. It is clear that she harboured some doubts about the effectiveness of Isotype work in the Western Region up to that time: after remarking ‘Our visual material should be understandable to the literate, and easily explained to the illiterate’, she admitted that ‘How far it fulfils these claims has still to be tested.’ To find out, she suggested setting up a permanent exhibition site where designs could be shown and public’s reactions noted. She also recommended conducting tests in locations where she herself had done so, including at schools in villages and towns, in hospital waiting rooms, among village farmers and in adult education classes.

Considerable efforts were made by Marie Neurath to find candidates for the Visual Aids Office. The tone and phrasing of the memorandum, however, suggest that she was not entirely optimistic about the prospects:

In the course of training, a number of such pamphlets [i. e. like those already made by Isotype] should be produced by the Nigerian trainees under the supervision and guidance of members of the Isotype Institute. The rate of such production will obviously be handicapped; unsatisfactory work will have to be repeated; unsuitable trainees will have to be replaced.

But the initiative never got that far, as no suitable candidates were found. Whether for this reason or for other political or financial ones, the government gave only qualified support to the plan, and by the end of Marie Neurath’s second stay the possibility of establishing a local office and training scheme had been given up on. Efforts continued in London where

187Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

a promising candidate was identified. Surviving documents record the heavy programme of training he embarked on; it involved intensive exposures to cultural products including films, exhibitions and books, and instruction to develop his critical and artistic faculties. But for reasons that are not clear, this initiative also faltered and came to an end.25

These, then, were the main projects completed in the Western Region by Marie Neurath and the Isotype Institute, as part of the Buffalo Books part-nership.26 In retrospect, the Isotype Institute’s engagement there was brief but significant. The Nigerians were undoubtedly enthusiastic about this new and colourful visual method, and the Isotype Institute produced work of a high standard. After 1957, however, the projects fell away. It may be that the programme of public information had simply fulfilled its brief, culminating in the 1957 regional elections. Thereafter and in the run-up to Nigerian inde-pendence (1960), one might surmise that more immediate political concerns occupied the attention of the Western Regional Government at the expense of projects like those it commissioned from Isotype.

In her memoir, Marie Neurath offers little by way of summary. She remarks only that

it was good that we were able to have this experience. Otto had said that we were creating the method not, finally, for the Viennese, but rather for the Africans, and so it proved. That we had to alter the symbols for man, woman, house and so on in the process, was within the scope of the rule that the symbols should ‘speak’, that is, be immediately understandable. The interna-tional character was maintained in the basic approach.27

This approach, of course, was Isotype’s underlying techniques of graphic explanation whose effectiveness had been demonstrated through long appli-cation. But Marie Neurath also points out what may at first seem paradoxical in Isotype: that to enhance its international effectiveness, it had to take on a more local flavour, its existing elements (pictograms and other visualizations) requiring variations that were identifiably of the place. This international character was based not on inflexible universality but on negotiated accom-modation: the familiar had to be adopted if Isotype was to be usable.28

If one returns to Otto Neurath’s International picture language, one sees that his notion of Isotype is similar to Marie Neurath’s summary statement. It is of an approach intelligible to all, but one that was flexible, that could

188 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

produce specific meanings, and where necessary could be supplemented or updated. What is missing though is the extent to which international differ-ences needed to be afforded, as Marie Neurath later discovered through her contact with Nigerian audiences. And this suggests something else that goes unacknowledged in International picture language: that if Isotype was to indeed function internationally, it needed to be taken places and created there. The envisioned demands of the Nigeria work surely compelled Marie Neurath to experience the place and meet the people—the subject experts. When read-ing her recollections, one realises how much of it is devoted not to the work itself but to descriptions of a country that was very different from any she had previously encountered. Flora and fauna fascinated her, as did people and places, and her many encounters with Nigerians young and old were clearly experiences she wished to preserve. They show her getting to know the place, knowledge that was surely crucial to getting the work right.

Finally, the Isotype Institute’s work in the Western Region of Nigeria dem-onstrates the challenges of operating internationally. The several instances of Isotype’s export to distant places—geographically or culturally—show that spreading it so far afield could be difficult, whether in the Soviet Union, North America or Africa. The right conditions of commission, application and dissemination were essential before it became usable in these places; and thereafter its long-term success was hardly assured. Especially problematic were local offices for making work based on Isotype principles; where they could be established and suitable locals recruited (neither of which happened in Nigeria), considerable time and effort were needed to secure good work-ing practices. But would the work go on being done correctly? And how long could an office continue when financial resources became scarce or the politi-cal situation unstable? These mundane contingencies also make up Isotype’s international character or, at the very least, are a consequence of it. They contain the risks of spreading it internationally while highlighting how much was in fact achieved under the circumstances.

189Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

Notes

1 For a fuller exploration of the putative language aspects of Isotype, see Christopher Burke’s essay ‘The Linguistic Status of Isotype’ in this volume, 31–58.

2 Isotype = International System Of TYpographic Picture Education. The name/acronym was devised by Marie Reidemeister (later Neurath) around 1935. Otto Neurath, International picture language (London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co., 1936).

3 For related remarks by Otto Neurath at about this time, see his text ‘Visual education’, in Encyclopedia and utopia: the life and work of Otto Neurath (1882–1945), edited by Elisabeth Nemeth and Friedrich Stadler (Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer, 1996), especially 264, 292, 333–4.

4 ‘Human life in Africa’, first draft, July 1943, Otto and Marie Neurath Isotype Collection, University of Reading (hereinafter ‘IC’) 1/44. Neurath’s proposals were produced for Rotha Films, with which the Isotype Institute was to collaborate. Although the proposal and associated planning documents refer to an undifferenti-ated Africa, there are indications that the Colonial Office was directing ‘Human life in Africa’ towards Britain’s West African colonies. Plans for the exhibition were eventually abandoned. Neurath continued to pursue the idea, however, through correspondence and exchanges with Sir Hanns Vischer of the International African Institute in London (see IC 1/6 and 1/11). Arrangements were made for Neurath to meet African students at the institute to discuss Isotype and visual education; it is not clear if this meeting ever took place, following Vischer’s unexpected death. I am grateful to Christopher Burke for drawing my attention to these documents.

5 Wolfgang Foges, Weiner Library (London), item no. 1361/29–85, material relat-ing to Aldus books, including a summary of his firms’ output dictated by Foges, 1983; cited in David Lambert, ‘Wolfgang Foges and the new illustrated book in Britain: Adprint, Rathbone Books, and Aldus Books’, Modern typography in Britain: graphic design, politics, and society (London: Hyphen Press, 2009), 113–28. Foges was Adprint’s managing director; the ‘parts of West Africa’ presumably refers to Britain’s colonial territories.

6 Buffalo Books was set up to undertake projects in the developing world and was a partnership of expertise between Adprint, the Isotype Institute and the print-ers Purnell & Sons (which owned Adprint); ‘Reaching the people’, draft text for a Buffalo Books capabilities booklet, c. 1956, IC 3.2/178 (typescript). The Weiner Library material (cited above) also contains notes about Buffalo Books, though

190 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

these are faulty in places, as suggested by Wolfgang Foges, who recorded them some 30 years after the events described and without supporting documents. Although Foges was also the managing director of Buffalo Books, day-to-day operations were in the hands of Frame Smith.

7 ‘[Forward] was well received by the public, and editions in several local languages were issued by the Gold Coast Vernacular Literature Bureau. The experiment proved, however, that under the conditions of marketing and distribution obtain-ing at the time, the regular issue of such a periodical, however well suited to its pur-pose, was not at the moment an economic possibility.’ ‘Reaching the people’, cited above. Related initiatives in the Western Region of Nigeria were likely connected with Forward; evidence comes from a colour supplement (printed proof) depicting government structures and activities in the Western Region, together with notes and rough drawings, all of which remain among the Forward working materials. The notes outline plans to visualise a series of development issues in the maga-zine, issues that would comprise much of the Nigeria work subsequently (discussed below). IC 3.2/165.

8 That Marie Neurath met Awolowo in 1953 (August) in London cannot be fully confirmed by documents in the Isotype Collection. Their meeting at that time is surmised by Awolowo’s presence at the constitutional conference in July and August; and by Marie Neurath’s report soon after of a first meeting with an unnamed Nigerian minister; see Obafemi Awolowo, Awo: the autobiography of Chief Obafemi Awolowo (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), 180; and Marie Neurath, letter to Waldemar Kaempffert, 23 September 1953, IC 1/47. As leader of Action Group, Awolowo was, in effect, the Western Region’s prime minister; in October 1954 he was formally named Premier.

9 ‘What I remember’, unpublished typescript, 94–5, IC, unaccessioned. This text was written in 1980 in German, and translated into English in 1982 by Robin Kinross. It bears some relationship to a shorter text written by Marie Neurath in 1986 which focuses on her visual education work; the latter has now been published as ‘Wiener Methode and Isotype: my apprenticeship and partner-ship with Otto Neurath’ in Marie Neurath and Robin Kinross, The transformer: principles of making Isotype charts (London: Hyphen Press, 2009); the account of the Nigeria work in the latter is considerably briefer than in ‘What I remember’.

10 IC 3.2/165. The sketches are grouped together with a minority report issued by Action Group for the 1953 conference. This is probably the text handed to Marie Neurath by Foges; it covers issues similar to those she sketched.

11 Marie Neurath, letter to Waldemar Kaempffert, 23 September 1953, IC 1/47.

191Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

12 This in keeping with earlier Isotype projects, in the Soviet Union and to a lesser extent in the United States, both of which involved Marie Neurath and others in lengthy stays abroad while work was planned and (in the Soviet Union) made locally.

13 Southern Nigerian Defender (22 July 1954; lead story), Nigerian Tribune (22 July 1954), and Daily Times (24 July 1954); the articles excerpt or reproduce in full a text apparently supplied by the government’s press office. IC 3.2/169 (newspaper cuttings and typescript).

14 ‘What I remember’, 95–6, cited above.15 Marie Neurath recorded how the commissioning happened: ‘I had a discussion

about my work in the house of Awolowo, the prime minister; I first had to design a booklet about schools—general education was just being introduced—together with the minister of Education, Awokoya. During the discussions, the minister of agriculture, Akinloye, said that he wanted to have a book too. The minister of health, Ighodaro, soon introduced himself as well; Chief Akran gave me access every time I needed any help; I probably spoke with him most when I was prepar-ing the more general booklet, “Paying for progress”.’ ‘What I remember’, 95, cited above.

16 It is notable that new pictograms were devised for the peoples of the Western Region despite the availability of existing pictograms of Africans. The latter, used in a succession of Isotype charts representing the world’s human groups and incor-porating highly generalized physical features, clothing and headwear, were clearly not relevant to the specificity of the Nigeria work. See, for example, Gesellschaft und Wirtschaft (Leipzig: Bibliographisches Institut, 1930), plate 96.

17 Here, and throughout the work for the Western Region, graphic arrangements were designed with sufficient space to allow for English texts to be substituted with Yoruba. One might regard this feature—present in nearly all Isotype work (whether it was made use of or not)—as a specifically international one that accommodated language variations.

18 For most of the Nigeria projects, design work was done in the Western Region, while print-ready artwork was completed later in London. In this respect, work arrangements were similar to those adopted in the late 1930s, when design work done by Otto Neurath and Marie Reidemeister in the offices of the National Tuberculosis Association in New York was subsequently made print-ready at the International Foundation for Visual Education in The Hague.

19 ‘What I remember’, 98, cited above. The notes made by teachers, written on small sheets of paper, were given to Marie Neurath afterwards; IC 3.2/171.

192 Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

20 ‘What I remember’, 98, cited above. It appears that Marie Neurath was not present when Better farming for better living was tested on farmers.

21 ‘What I remember’, 97, cited above. A precedent for this idea can be found in remarks made by Otto Neurath some years before: ‘Sometimes one has to give health instruction or information on agriculture or on citizenship, without having time for preparatory teaching. To influence sub-literates posters and picture sheets combined with the minimum of words may be used with advantage.’ Otto Neurath, ‘Visual education’, 264, cited above.

22 It appears that a first booklet, Voting in the Western Region of Nigeria (1955), was produced in preparation for regional elections in 1956, and a second booklet, Registration and voting in the Western Region of Nigeria (1956), for regional elections in 1957. There is no record of how the booklets were distributed; the posters were apparently used on-site at registration and polling stations.

23 ‘What I remember’, 98, cited above; the minister was Rotimi Williams, then Minister of Local Government.

24 ‘Memorandum on training for visual education’, typescript, IC 3.2/171. Quotes that follow are from this source.

25 IC 3.2/172; the candidate was J. Isi Afiari.26 There were a number of other, mostly minor, projects undertaken in the

Western Region that are not discussed here, as well as several publica-tions produced for the Gold Coast (Ghana) and Sierra Leone. Through-out all the work in West Africa, it is broadly accurate to attribute design elements to the Isotype Institute, and production (project management, international liaising and logistics) to Buffalo Books, and Frame Smith in particular.

27 ‘What I remember’, 99, cited above.28 Marie Neurath articulated this most fully in ‘Isotype’, Instructional science, vol. 3,

no. 2 (July 1974): 147: ‘Becoming citizens of the world we gradually recognised that our symbolism was often international for western man only. More than before I recognised this when I had to work out ways of informing the Nigerian people about health, education, agriculture, voting etc., in visual terms. Man, woman, house, plants, markets, trees … all had to be drawn in a different way to be understandable in that country. Also the approach, the speed of informa-tion, the colour scheme, the ways to catch the attention—all had to be different.’ Similar remarks occur in her article ‘The origin and theory of Isotype’, Year book of education (1960): 117, where, in reference to the Nigeria work she states: ‘Every chart has to represent a familiar visual background—adherence to the method

193Reaching the People: Isotype Beyond the West

cannot go so far as imposing an alien background on those unable to share one’s experience of it.’ These latter remarks occur in a section titled ‘The universality of Isotype’, though it is notable that here Marie Neurath refrains from describing Isotype as ‘universal’, preferring ‘international’ instead; she only goes so far as to describe Isotype as ‘an elaboration of the child’s approach which is more or less universal … .’ However, in her article ‘Otto Neurath and Isotype’, Graphic Design, 42 (June 1971): 19, she writes: ‘The method and the approach are, I think, more universal than the symbols are. I had to discover this when I worked for Africans for some time. I had to make things clear to them, and I could not force our “international symbols” on them. … When things are equal all over the world the symbols can be the same.’

All images except figures 1 and 4 are taken from material in the Otto and Marie Neurath Isotype Collection, University of Reading. This essay is part of ‘Isotype revisited’, a research project conducted in the Depart-ment of Typography & Graphic Communication, University of Reading, and funded by the Arts & Humanities Research Council (UK).

From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

Karl H. Müller & Armin Reautschnig, Vienna

The starting and the reference point for this article lies in Otto Neurath’s Isotype (International System of Typographic Pictorial Education) which was developed as an international picture language from the late 1920s onwards up to Neurath’s untimely death in 1945. Even eighty years after its rapid con-struction phase, Isotype remains a huge source for inspirations and a reference point for promoting visualization in a most comprehensive way, albeit within the restrictions and constraints of the technological settings of the 1920s or 1930s.1

In the subsequent article, three major issues will be addressed. The first part provides an assessment of the relative importance of visualization in con-temporary science and society and gives a preliminary answer to the question whether visualization should still be considered as an important scientific or societal topic. The second issue deals with rapid changes in information and communication technologies and a general drift towards a digital information and knowledge base. Within these great transformations the question will be answered whether Neurath’s mode of Isotype-production should be adapted or accommodated to today’s scientific or societal environments. Finally, the third topic deals with a relatively new visual medium which can be classified as visual data analysis (VDA). VDA is a new visual way for analyzing complex micro data sets in the social sciences within a comparative framework.

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 195–214.

196 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

1A New Kind of Visual Science

The first major issue for this article lies in a preliminary assessment of the contemporary relevance of visualization in science on the one hand and in society on the other hand.

Turning to the first part of the question it is interesting to note for historical reasons that Otto Neurath’s Isotype was viewed by his friends and colleagues from the Vienna Circle or from the Unified Science-movement as an interesting and stimulating way of communication which however was situated outside the domains of scientific analysis proper. Within science, visualizations in the form of Isotype-diagrams were mostly seen as illustrations without any cognitive surplus value.2

Several decades later the assessment of a marginal impact of visualization within the scientific domain has changed dramatically. Again for historical reasons it is intriguing to see that one of Otto Neurath’s fiercest opponents in economic, societal or planning arenas, namely Friedrich August von Hayek, would have become his strongest ally in the field of visualization within scientific fields. In 1967, Friedrich August von Hayek wrote a rather neglected article entitled ‘The Theory of Complex Phenomena’ (Hayek, 1967) which was published several years later as a small booklet in German ‘Die Theorie komplexer Phänomene’ (Hayek, 1972, reprinted 1996). In this article, Hayek developed a typology of complex phenomena and processes which he clearly differentiated from their simple counterparts. Table 1 lists the results of Hayek’s distinctions between simple and complex phenomena or processes across several dimensions. It turns out that Hayek’s differentiations are almost iden-tical to a more recent dualistic conceptualization of a phase transition from Science I, the science of theoretical physics and of relative simplicity to Science II, the science of the life sciences and of relative complexity3. Both Hayek’s typology of simple and complex phenomena and the Science I-Science II-typology focus on patterns, pattern recognition and pattern formation as the core-elements of analysis. But a shift from laws to patterns, almost by necessity, implies that the role of visualization must have increased significantly.

According to Table 1 complexity science alias Science II proves to be pattern-based, and stands in a striking contrast to the law-based paradigm for simple phenomena and processes under Science I.

197From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

Table 1 Friedrich August von Hayek’s Main Distinctions between

Simple (Science I) and Complex Phenomena (Science II)

Dimensions Simple Phenomena (Science I) Complex Phenomena (Science II)

Degree of Complexity

Low High

Measure of Complexity

Small number of Variables

Large number of Variables

Bonds between Variables

Causal RelationsDegree of

Complexity

Specification Schema

Laws Patterns

Mode of Analysis

Covering Law-Model

Pattern-Recognition and Pattern Formation

Forecasting Law-based Pattern-based

Leading Science Theoretical PhysicsEvolutionary Biology and

Complexity Sciences

As a consequence, it can be stated for the science domain in general that

the importance of patterns and, thus, of visualizations has increased dramati-cally over the last decades and, in all probability, will continue to do so in the future. Visualization in science has moved from the cognitive margins and from a mere by-product of algorithmic analysis to the core mode of scientific investigations.

The growing importance of patterns and visualizations within the increas-ingly dominant life sciences and the sciences of complexity is accompanied by another series of shifts and phase transition that separate today’s social science work environments and practices from Neurath’s office and Isotype-environments in the 1930s or the early 1940s. Within the sciences in general and the social sciences in particular three major changes or phase transitions occurred during these decades simultaneously in the domains of epistemic cultures4, laboratories5 and research infrastructures. In all three instances a profound shift occurred towards digital or cyber-contexts, manifesting them-selves in digital or cyber-epistemic cultures, in digital or cyber-labs and in digital or cyber-research infrastructures.6

198 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

For the subsequent discussion it becomes of utmost importance that the daily routines of social scientists are more and more embedded in a digital or cyber-environment which, of course, has strong repercussions for traditional or analogue communication tools like Isotype as well.

2Visual Media and Visual Settings

Turning to the second part of the initial question, viz. the contemporary societal relevance of visualization, a few concepts need to be introduced, namely the notions of visual media and of visual settings. The concept of a medium will be used in a rather specific manner far from the current social science or humanities frameworks7 and it follows closely to a proposal by Douglas R. Hofstadter (1997) who defined a medium in the following way:

A medium is a vehicle for patterns, a propagator of distortions, a transmitter of disturbances. […] A linguistic medium is a carrier of messages. (Hofstadter 1997: 181)

Hofstadter goes on to introduce the notion of linguistic media by specifying that

a linguistic medium is definable as: a language restricted by a set of constraints that are not so tight as to preclude the expression of arbitrary meanings (Hofstadter 1997: 182)

Thus, different languages can be seen as instances for a linguistic medium. One can easily see that in Hofstadter’s understanding a medium, linguistic or otherwise, is very closely linked to notions like rule systems, production systems, grammars or programs.

In this spirit, a visual medium can be described as a visual configuration ‘restricted by a set of constraints that are not so tight as to preclude’ the forma-tion or the recognition of arbitrary visual patterns. Thus, the notion of pattern formation and pattern recognition stands at the core of visual media. Addition-ally, rule or production systems, broadly conceived, for pattern formation or for pattern recognition can be understood as specific instances of visual media.

199From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

Table 2 The New Multiplicity of Visual Media, Settings and Utilization Contexts

Societal Systems/ Networks

Visual Media and Utilization Contexts

Visual Settings

Education

Visual Education and Visual Learning in Primary, Second-

ary and Tertiary Education

Schools and Institutions of Higher Education

Science

Complex Visual Analysis, Visual Data-Mining and Exploratory

Visual Analysis, Visual Languages for

Animal-Man Communication, etc.

Digital Science Labs

Economy Visual Occupational Learning Work-Places

Information and Communication

Visual Modules in Newspapers, Journals, Books, etc; Visual

Components in User-Surfaces of Information

and Communication Technologies

(ICT)

Private Households; Public Spaces, etc.

Arts and Culture Visual Artistic MediaMuseums, Exhibitions,

Art Galleries, Public Installations, Cyber-Settings, etc.

Life Worlds Visual Communication (Various Sign Languages, etc.)

Private and Public Spaces

International Communication

Visual Information Systems, Visual Language Learning, etc.

Public Spaces; Large-Scale Organizations, Traffic Networks, etc.

Settings, finally, can be defined as spatio-temporal domains in which media

can be utilized. From a functional point of view, these settings can be split into major societal systems like education, science and technology, culture and so on. From a holistic viewpoint, settings can be attributed to forms of life or to any spatio-temporal specification like households, work-places, public spaces, etc. Otto Neurath’s Isotype can be seen, thus, as a visual medium which has been very successfully applied to different settings like education, culture or science. Moreover, Isotype has been created as a weak rule system with a small number of explicit rules and a large number of implicit routines.

Turning more specifically to contemporary visual media, the most important point to be emphasized lies in the rapid proliferation of a large wave of new visual media which are supported by digital information and communication

200 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

technologies. Digital visual media have programs as their underlying units and their general output lies in visual patterns. Table 2 presents an overview of the startling number of new visual media. Moreover, from Table 2 it becomes clear that these broad scope of new visual digital media offers strong support for the claim that the 21st century will become the century of the digital or, alternatively, of the cyber-eye, following the 20th century as the century of the eye (Otto Neurath).

3The Limits of Isotype in the Cyber-Age

In view of the shift to patterns, complexity science and to digital or cyber-research environments on the one hand and a new wave of digital visual media and settings across society on the other hand it is worthwhile to con-template the question whether Isotype as a homogeneous picture language should be adapted or accommodated to the new digital environments across science and society. Probably not unexpectedly, the answer is clearly negative. Basically, three groups of reasons can be given why Isotype cannot and should not be revitalized within the current cyber-contexts.

The first group of reasons against a digital version of Isotype is linked to the overwhelming proliferation of new visual digital media across very different functional settings and with highly heterogeneous user-groups. It is not only difficult to imagine that a single visual medium like Isotype can be meaningfully applied across all these different settings and user-groups, it turns out to be impossible that a single visual medium is capable to fill out all new visual niches. Turning to the science domain alone one is con-fronted with a very large number of different visual media and with widely differing utilization contexts which make it outright impossible to develop a single visual medium to account for all these different utilizations. Thus, Isotype would need to be developed as a family of different visual media, unified sufficiently by family resemblances in design principles across these different media.

While the first set of arguments against a digital Isotype still allows the building of an Isotype family of visual media, the second group of reasons excludes the possibility of such a digital Isotype-family altogether. The second set of reasons has to do with Isotype as a symbol-based visualization instru-

201From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

ment or as a picture language. Neurath was fully aware that Isotype was not a complete language when compared to a linguistic medium. In his visual autobiography Otto Neurath himself remarked that

there are many reasons why Isotype cannot be developed as a ‘complete lan-guage’ without destroying its force and simplicity. Our daily language, even in primitive societies, is to some extent richer than our Isotype representations can be. (Neurath 2010:104)

Nevertheless, a symbol library lies in the core of Isotype and constitutes its differentia specifica. But from Table 2 it becomes rather obvious that many of the new visual media and settings produce only abstract patterns and do not or, in most instances, cannot rely on symbolic arrangements. In fact, the concluding sections of this article will introduce a visual medium for the social sciences under the name of visual data analysis (VDA). Most of the data-transformations in VDA would be impossible if one were to rely on the symbol library simply because many of the usual data dimensions or variables like trust in institutions, life-satisfaction, political attitudes, policy issues, etc. cannot be symbolized in an adequate manner.8 Accordingly, one is faced with the following dilemma: Removing or downsizing the impor-tance of the link to the Isotype-library of symbols would change Isotype to something fundamentally different which no longer can be regarded as an accommodation or an adaption, but as a clear break with the Isotype-past. Keeping the link to the Isotype-library of symbols excludes Isotype for most of the current visual media and settings.

The third group of reasons against a digital version of Isotype comes from the limitations and restrictions of the new digital visual media themselves. The high aesthetic surplus value of Isotype-pictures was achieved through an artistic transformation of objects to self-speaking or self-explanatory symbols. This transformation process required time and the final product was very care-fully produced as a single and unique piece. The contemporary online-settings for visual media operate with hundreds and more users, distributed globally, who expect instant visual results. Additionally, computer screens and print-ers make it almost impossible to achieve this aesthetic Isotype-surplus due to inherent limitations in screen or printing resolutions which become particularly evident when using large numbers of small symbols. Finally, Isotype was based on a closed technology where observers were confronted with a pre-given set

202 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

of visual stimuli, carefully prepared and crafted by the Isotype-team. In sharp contrast, contemporary visual media are essentially grounded in open technolo-gies where users are expected to create the visual outputs most suitable for them in a relatively short amount of time of a few seconds only.

Thus, in the brave new cyber-worlds Isotype remains a vital reference point for visualization goals or for a comprehensive listing of potential comparative advantages of visualizations due to two decades of intensive interactions with numerous observers and users. But Isotype would be lost in transformation from its original mode of analogue manufacturing to the current digital production environments.

4A Basic Outline of Visual Data Analysis (VDA)

and Its Four Main Contexts in the Social Sciences

Subsequently, a new visual medium will be introduced which has been designed for the social sciences and which belongs to the new components in a digital social science lab. This new visual medium allows and supports a visual online-analysis of societal changes, observed or simulated, in a comparative framework. This new visual medium which has been established under the name of visual data analysis (VDA)9 is based on survey or panel data from a varying number of countries. The primary goal of VDA lies in a visual analysis of patterns which are produced by suitable VDA-programs. Over the last years a new VDA-program has been produced which runs under the name of WISDOMIZE and which is currently available online in its version 2.0.10

VDA is one of the new media and settings where the Isotype restrictions become very obvious. Usually, the variables in the micro data sets use con-cepts which fall beyond the reach of the Isotype-library. Instances like, for example, life satisfaction, trust in institutions, work flexibility, or values do not have counterparts in the Isotype symbol library. Additionally, the European context for VDA requires a large compilation of different countries on a single screen which makes it almost impossible to use any type of symbols because the available space for a larger quantity of symbols is much too small.

Visual data analysis can be undertaken within four different data contexts which can be specified with the help of two independent dimensions. The first dimension is time and can be divided into single points in time or into multiple

203From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

time points. The second dimension can be described as the unit of analysis and can be divided into single units or into multiple units. Units can refer to regions, populations or to both regions and populations. Figure 1 exhibits the four main data contexts for VDA.With the help of Figure 1 the four different data contexts can be described in a more detailed manner.

• Thefirstcontextisfocusedonasingleunituforasinglepointintimet.Inorder to become comparative one needs at least a small number of dimen-sions or variables which are to be compared within this single case-context.

• Theseconddatacontextisstillrestrictedtoasingleunit,butusesatleast

two points of observation ti (i = 1, 2, … T). Thus, the second context is the most elementary instance for a comparative study of changes.

• Thethirddatacontextusesatleasttwodifferentunitsuj( j=1,2,…,U),but is restricted to a single point in time t. The third context may be seen as the paradigmatic case for comparative analysis.

• Finally,thefourthdatacontextcomprisesatleasttwounitsandtwopointsof observation. The fourth context becomes the most complex one for comparative analyses with ti x uj data sets.

Fig. 1

Four Main Data Contexts for the

Visual Data Analysis (VDA)

204 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

These four data contexts can be used for various forms of pattern recogni-tions. In principle one can distinguish between two main types or groups of patterns which exhibit important attributes of a data set. These two main groups can be divided into elementary patterns like extreme values, variances ort deviations from the main value and into complex patterns like similarities, coherences or distances.

5Patterns and Prototypes within the Visual Data Analysis

With respect to the two groups of patterns for the different data contexts each group contains a small number of specific patterns. In sum, one can differen-tiate currently between three elementary or simple patterns and four complex patterns which, in combination, constitute the field of visual data analysis. However, each of these elementary or complex patterns is able to address specific questions and to provide an open and observer-dependent amount of visual answers.

With respect to the group of elementary patterns one can list the following three main instances:

• Extreme values: Patterns for a quick recognition of extreme values and out-liers in a given data-set. In this area a number of variables or variable groups as well as of units can be selected and the extreme values of this data set become visualized.

• Deviations from an average or a reference value: Patterns for a rapid insight into

higher and lower than average concentrations or, alternatively, into lower and higher formations for a given reference value. Once again, a number of variables or variable groups as well as of units have to be chosen by the user and an average or reference value has to be specified.

• Variance : Patters for a fast identification of the statistical spread in a given data set. These visualizations are mainly, but not exclusively based on scat-ter plots which have become the main field of visual analysis for variance features.

205From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

The group of complex visual data analyses comprises at present time four different patterns:

• Similarities: Patterns for a quick detection of grades of similarities or dis-similarities between sub-populations in a data set. In this instance n dimen-sions or variables must be selected and at least two sub-populations n(si ) for each unit must be specified.

• Coherence: Patterns for a rapid cognition of interrelations between several data groups. Here one has to select at least two dimensions, but preferably two data groups with n and o dimensions which can be visually analyzed for their visual positive or negative correlations.

• Clustering: Patterns for a fast identification of groups or types in a data set. In this case, one needs n dimensions and u different units in order to find groups or clusters in a given data set. Usually one is capable of selecting two, three or more visual clusters within a given n x u dataset.

Fig. 2 Six Visual Fields of Analysis for Data Context I (Single Point in Time, Single Unit)

206 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

• Distances: Patterns used for the quick detection of multidimensional dis-tances across relatively large sets of dimensions. Here one needs d different domains within a given data set where each domain contains preferably a constant number of dimensions.

The gallery of patterns in Figure 2 exhibits six cases of visual data analysis within the first data context, namely for a single time point and a single unit. The data come from the European Social Survey (ESS) which can be con-sidered as the European best practice for comparative data production.11

Aside from data contexts and elementary or complex patterns one can distinguish between different visual prototypes which visualize a given data set in a specific manner so that it can provide visual answers for specific research questions. From Figure 2 one can see that visual prototypes can be classified with labels like an extreme value-prototype, a deviation-prototype (deviations from a mean or a reference value) or as the data-square or data rectangle-prototype. In general, each prototype can be used for one or more elementary or complex patterns and each elementary or complex pattern comprises one or more visual prototypes.

Table 3 lists the three basic components for VDA, namely data contexts, patterns and prototypes.

Table 3 Basic Components of Visual Data Analysis

Data:Elementary and

Complex Data Contexts

Patterns: Elementary and

Complex Patterns

Prototypes: Elementary and Complex

Pattern Generators

Single Unit,Single Point in Time

Exteme Values Deviations from Mean or

Reference Value

A Small Set of Pattern Generators for One or More

Elementary or Complex Patterns

Single Unit,Multiple Points in Time Variances

Multiple Units,Single Point in Time

SimilaritiesCoherence

Multiple Units, Multiple Points in Time

Clustering Distances

207From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

6Complex Visual Data Analysis of European Data

In this section two examples for a complex visual data analysis will be provided and analyzed in some detail. The data come, once again, from the European Social Survey (ESS) and the pattern to be studied visually has been labeled as coherence-analysis. With respect to the data, two different domains have been selected, namely trust in five different institutions, namely the national parliament, the legal system, police, politicians and political parties. The

Fig. 3 Visual Coherence-Analyses in Four Data Contexts

208 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

second domain falls under the heading of social capital, including happiness, life satisfaction, health and four specific dimensions for social capital. Figure 3 provides an overview of visual coherence analyses within the four different data contexts where the third and the fourth data context fall under the head-ing of complex visual data analysis.

As can be easily seen from Figure 3, these patterns provide visual answers to different research questions with respect to underlying coherences between the domain of trust in institutions on the one hand and social capital, broadly understood, on the other hand.

• The first data context provides answers for the coherence between twodata groups within a single unit, in this case Austria. Here a competent observer is able to find out whether one can identify a coherent pattern between the two data groups within a single country, in this case in Aus-tria. Obviously, for Austria the coherence between trust in institutions and social capital is weak at best.

• Theseconddatacontextgivesvisualcluesondynamiccoherencesandonanswering the question whether two groups of dimensions exhibit a coher-ent or incoherent dynamic pattern. Clearly from Figure 3 one can see that in the Austrian case no dynamic coherence can be identified and both data groups show a very different dynamical pattern.

• The thirddatacontext looks for coherencesat theEuropean level forasingle point in time. Here one can observe a weak coherence between these two domains across Europe. Countries which are strong in trust in institu-tions turn out to be strong in social capital as well, although one can find several exceptions to this general pattern.

• Finally,thefourthdatacontextprovidesvisualanswersfordynamiccoher-ences at the European level. Generally, one can see that no dynamic coher-ences can be identified because in many instances positive changes in one domain are accompanied by negative changes in the other domain and vice versa.

Finally, Figure 4 exhibits a gallery of visual patterns for assessing multi-dimensional socio-economic distances in Austria (data contexts I & II) and in

209From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

Europe (data contexts III and IV). The data set comes, once again, from the European Social Survey. This time, seven domains, namely migration policies (1), asylum-policies (2), media utilization (3), participation and citizenship (4), trust in institutions (5), social capital (6), and working conditions (7) have been selected and seven independent dimensions have been selected for each of these domains. Finally, for each of the 7 dimensions x 7 domains the color-ing was undertaken in a distribution-dependent way. Take trust in parliament as one of the 49 dimensions used in Figure 4, then the countries which fall

Fig. 4 Visual Distance-Analyses in Four Data Contexts

210 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

under the upper third of the distribution were colored in blue, countries in the middle third with ocher and countries in the lower third with red. In this way, each of the 7 domains x 7 dimensions in each regional unit was colored either in blue, ocher or red. Consequently, countries with predominantly blue (red) colors are positioned in the upper (lower) third of the European distribution in most of the 49 dimensions. Multidimensional socio-economic distances across Europe can be identified visually by finding countries or regions with mostly blue colors on the one hand and mostly red colors on the other hand. For the third data context in Figure 4 one can see, for example, that Denmark and Poland are the countries with the biggest socio-economic differences across the 7 x 7 dimensions. More specifically, the four data context offer visual clues for the following set of research questions.

• Withinthefirstdatacontextanobservergetsvisualpatternswithrespectto socio-economic distances between several domains in a single country, namely in Austria. Here a competent researcher is able to find out visu-ally which of the ESS-domains differ most within Austria. As it turns out, the fifth domain (trust in institutions) and the seventh domain (working conditions) exhibit the biggest differences within Austria.

• Theseconddatacontextoffersvisualcluesonthedynamicsof thesesevendomains and, thus, on the socio-economic distances with respect to the changes in these seven domains. The second data context in Figure 4 shows for example that the second and the sixth domain exhibit the big-gest differences within Austria.

• Thethirddatacontextlooksforsocio-economicdistancesacrossEuropein a highly multi-dimensional context. Observing the third data context more closely one will recognize, for example, that Scandinavia shows very big socio-economic differences to Eastern or South-Western Europe.

• Finally,thefourthdatacontextoffersvisualpatternsfordynamicdistancesat the European level. This time it remains a task for the reader or observer to identify socio-economic distances with respect to the changes in the seven domains.

With Figures 3 and 4 the preliminary overview on a new visual medium for visual data analysis in the social sciences has come to an end. It should be emphasized that VDA offers a quick detection of characteristic features especially in large-scale European or global data sets. Moreover, VDA can be

211From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

combined with traditional statistical analyses or with qualitative data analyses. In this way, visual methods like VDA close the ensemble of social science methods to a closed triad.

7Towards Worlds of Visual Media and Visual Settings

Otto Neurath as a fervent optimist with respect to new technologies would find himself today in local and global contexts which are characterized by a strik-ing discrepancy between an enormous proliferation of new visual media and the absence of high quality visual designs especially suited for these different settings. In all probability, Neurath would explore these different visual media and settings and would produce innovative visual solutions which would be situated well beyond the classical Isotype-approach.

Isotype as a unified symbol language and as a visual medium across dif-ferent settings in science or society is definitely dead within today’s cyber-environments. But several of the general design principles still live on and it would be a fascinating second-order task to see whether today’s worlds of visual media adhere to these general standards and principles on the one hand and are able to fulfill the comparative advantages inherent in visualization. In this sense, Neurath’s Isotype remains a vital and critical reference point for the current visual cyber-environments as they have been developed so far and for the visual media and settings still to come.

Notes

1 On Neurath’s Isotype, see Neurath, 1991, 2010 or Müller, 1991a,b.2 On this point see especially Müller, 1991b.3 On the distinction between Science I and Science II, see Hollingsworth/Müller,

2008 or Müller/Toš, 2011. For a wider discussion of this distinction, see Boyer, 2008, Mayntz, 2008, Nowotny, 2008 or Sornette, 2008.

4 On the notion of epistemic cultures see especially Knorr-Cetina, 1999.5 Laboratories in a very general way can be seen as the spatio-temporal settings

in which epistemic cultures manifest themselves. See especially Latour/Woolgar, 1979 or Knorr-Cetina, 1984.

212 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

6 Otto Neurath would have been a keen observer of this process because already in the early 1940s he proposed a so-called Gelehrtenbehavioristik which was character-ized by him in the following way, taking sociology as reference point: ‘Sociologists deal, among other things, with tools and tales, with the language of magic, theology, jurisprudence, economics, and pedagogics; but also with the language used by the sociologists themselves, with their statements and their habits, i. e. with the behav-ioristics of sociologists […] We have fine questionnaires as far as preliterate tribes are concerned but hardly any when we try to ask sociologists how they themselves behave in arguing and writing. Since sociological predictions are directly connected with actions which create what has been predicted, the difficulty is very understandable. More than in other sciences, taboos and old folklore come into the picture when human actions are under consideration.’ (Neurath 1970: 42 p.)

7 For a contemporary summary, see Bentele/Brosius/Jarren, 2003, Faßler/Halbach, 1998, Grau, 2007, Grau/Keil, 2005, Hickethier, 2003, Leschke, 2003, Liebrand/Schneider/Bohnenkamp/Frahm, 2005, Ludes, 2003, Lüsebrink, 2003, Lüsebrink or Rusch, 2002.

8 As an Isotype-transformer one is usually faced with the following dilemma. Even for seemingly empirically observable dimensions in social science data sets like political attitudes or social capital one can either invent new symbols which, how-ever, are no longer self-explanatory and have to be described for observers sepa-rately or one abandons the search for appropriate symbols altogether and loses, thus, the power of visual arrangements. In general, even moderately theoretical terms are not only difficult, but outright impossible to visualize in a self-evident manner. (For a detailed discussion, see Müller, 1991a)

9 On visual data analysis (VDA) see, for example, Müller/Reautschnig, 2010.10 For a deeper understanding, visit the wisdom homepage under www.wisdom.at

and look under the category of visualization in order to proceed to WISDOMIZE 2.0.

11 On the European Social Survey (ESS), see, for example, Jowell et al. (2007) or Toš/Müller et al., 2009.

Literature

Bentele, G., Brosius, H.B., Jarren, O. (2003) (eds.), Öffentliche Kommunikation. Handbuch Kommunikations- und Medienwissenschaft. Wiesbaden: Westdeutscher Verlag.

Boyer, R. (2008), ‘The Quest for Theoretical Foundations of Socio-Economics:

213From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

Epistemology, Methodology or Ontology?’, in: ‘Discussion Forum: On Rogers Hollingsworth and Karl H. Müller “Transforming Socio-Economics with a New Epistemology” ’, in: Socio-Economic Review 6, 733–746.

Breckner, R. (2008), ‘Bildwelten – Soziale Welten. Zur Interpretation von Bildern und Fotografien’, in: Online-Beitrag zu Workshop & Workshow vom 23./24. 11. 2007, www.univie.ac.at/visuellesoziologie.

Eco, U. (2002), Einführung in die Semiotik, neunte Auflage. München: UTB.Faßler, M., Halbach, W.R. (1998) (eds.), Geschichte der Medien. München: Fink.Grau, O. (2007) (ed.), MediaArtHistories. Cambridge: MIT-Press.Grau, O., Keil, A. (2005) (eds.), Mediale Emotionen. Zur Lenkung von Gefühlen durch Bild

und Sound. Frankfurt: Fischer.Hayek, F:A.v. (1967), Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics. London: Routledge &

Kegan Paul, 22–42.Hayek, F.A.v. (1972), Die Theorie komplexer Phänomene. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul

Siebeck).Hayek, F: A. v. (1996), ‘Die Theorie komplexer Phänomene’, in ders.: Die Anmaßung von

Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 281–306.Hickethier K. (2003), Einführung in die Medienwissenschaft. Stuttgart: Metzler.Hofstadter, D. R. (1997), Le Ton Beau de Marot. In Praise of the Music of Language. New

York: Basic Books.Hollingsworth, J. R., Müller, K. H. (2008), ‘Transforming Socio-Economics with a

New Epistemology’, in: Socio-Economic Review 3 (6), 395–426Jowell, R., Roberts, C., Fitzgerald, R., Gillian, E. (2007) (eds.), Measuring Attitudes Cross-

Nationally: Lessons from the European Social Survey. London: Sage Publications.Knorr-Cetina, K. (1984), Die Fabrikation von Erkenntnis. Zur Anthropologie der Natur-

wissenschaft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Knorr-Cetina, K. (1999), Epistemic Cultures. How the Sciences Make Knowledge.

Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press.Latour, B., Woolgar, S. (1979), Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts.

Beverly Hills: Sage Publications.Leschke, R. (2003), Einführung in die Medientheorie. München: Fink.Liebrand, C., Schneider, I., Bohnenkamp, B., Frahm, L. (2005) (eds.), Einführung in die

Medienkulturwissenschaft. Münster: LIT.Ludes, P. (2003), Einführung in die Medienwissenschaft – Entwicklungen und Theorien, second

edition. Berlin: Schmidt 2003.Lüsebrink, H.-J. (2004), Französische Kultur- und Medienwissenschaft. Eine Einführung.

Tübingen: Narr.

214 From Otto Neurath’s Isotype to Multiple Worlds of Visual Media

Mayntz, R. (2008), ‘Networks and Self-Organization: Dissecting the Model of “Com-plex Networks”’, in: ‘Discussion Forum: On Rogers Hollingsworth and Karl H. Müller “Transforming Socio-Economics with a New Epistemology” ’, in: Socio-Economic Review 6, 750–754.

Müller, K. H. (1991a), Symbole – Statistik – Computer – Design. Otto Neuraths Bildpädagogik im Computerzeitalter. Wien:Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky

Müller, K. H. (1991b), ‘Neurath’s Theory of Pictorial-Statistical Representation’, in: Thomas Uebel (Hrsg.), Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle. Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath and the Vienna Circle. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 223–251.

Müller, K. H., Reautschnig, A. (2010), ‘Die visuelle Datenanalyse (VDA) in der vergleichenden sozialwissenschaftlichen Forschung’, in: T. Hug, A. Kriwak (eds.), Visuelle Kompetenz. Beiträge des interfakultären Forums Innsbruck Media Studies. Innsbruck: Innsbruck University Press, 236–250.

Neurath, O. (1970), ‘Foundations of the Social Sciences’, in: Neurath, O., Carnap, R., Morris, C. (eds.), Foundations of the Unity of Science. Toward an International Encyclopedia of Unified Sciences, Vol. 2. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

Neurath, O. (1991), Gesammelte bildpädagogische Schriften. Wien: Hölder Pichler Tempsky.

Neurath, O. (2010), From Hieroglyphics to Isotype. A Visual Autobiography. London: Hyphen Press.

Nowotny, H. (2008), ‘Bargaining, Not Borrowing: On Problem Choice and Problem Space’, in: ‘Discussion Forum: On Rogers Hollingsworth and Karl H. Müller “Transforming Socio-Economics with a New Epistemology” ’, in: Socio-Economic Review 6, 754–759.

Sornette, D. (2008), ‘Interdisciplinarity in Socio-Economics, Mathematical Analysis and the Predictability of Complex Systems’, in: ‘Discussion Forum: On Rogers Hollingsworth and Karl H. Müller “Transforming Socio-Economics with a New Epistemology” ’, in: Socio-Economic Review 6, 759–770.

Rusch, G. (2002) (ed.), Einführung in die Medienwissenschaft. Wiesbaden: Westdeutscher Verlag.

Toš, N. Müller, K. H. et al. (2009), Three Roads to Comparative Research: Analytical, Visual, Morphological. Wien: edition echoraum.

Out of the Wild

Bart Lootsma, Innsbruck

Out of the Wild is a research project by the chair for architectural theory of the University of Innsbruck. In the beginning, students and staff from the Platform History, Theory and Criticism of the Academy of Fine Arts in Vienna were involved as well and played a crucial role in its setup. Out of the Wild tries to find continuities in architectural thinking that came out of the Viennese Settlers’ movement after the First World War. It tries to figure out if and how these ideas spread and were developed further and if they have a potential for architecture and urbanism today and in the near future. The project centres around three Austrian-born architects and theoreticians: Otto Neurath (1882–1945), Friedrich Kiesler (1890–1965) and Christopher Alexander (born 1936) but also investigates personalities, ideas, projects, events and movements in their vicinity. An important tool in this research is a website, www.outofthewild.eu, which allows us to visualize both direct synchronous relationships between people and events as well as relation-ships and developments in time. The idea and structure for this website were developed by architecture students and staff of the Academy of Fine Arts in Vienna and the University of Innsbruck. Michæl Hofstädter from Ovos web design programmed it. The website consists of a database, a customized Content Management System (CMS) and a web interface, which not only allows to store and present events and contents in a range of different formats, but also to visualize the relationships between these different contents/events in history and between each other. This enables a new and more complex view of these relationships.

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 215–226.

216 Out of the Wild

The project is called Out of the Wild as an inversion of the title of the 1996 non-fiction book by Jon Krakauer and the Sean Penn movie that was based on it from 2007, in which the young American Chris McCandless, probably influenced by the great Romantic American trad-ition of Henri David Thoreau and Jack London, leaves civilization behind to survive on his own in nature. At the end of the book, after having tried in vain to return to civilization and shortly before he dies from eating poisoned plants and starvation, the main protagonist writes down as a last entry in his diary that ‘Happiness is only real when shared’ (Krakauer 2007). This sentence seems almost an echo of Otto Neurath’s dictum that ‘The sum of world happiness is too small. It must be made bigger.’ (Neurath, as quoted by Vossoughian, in a lecture at the University of Innsbruck, 2008) Out of the Wild seeks a way to turn a tradition or urbanism that is based on liberal individualism, as it became heavily promoted from the nineteen seventies on, into forms of urbanism that seek synergies and also try to address shared needs and desires, without returning to classical collectivist examples.

Surveys

Scientific methods in architecture and urbanism became increasingly impor-tant in Europe after the First World War. They ranged from empirical æsthetics to functional analyses. Taylorism and Fordism left their traces from France to Russia, as Jean-Louis Cohen has demonstrated in Scenes of the World to Come (Cohen 1995). Of course, statistics have played an important role in Western Europe and its colonies for centuries. As Ian Hacking remarks, ‘Every state, happy or unhappy, was statistical in its own way. […] Vision-aries, accountants and generals have planned censuses in many times and places.’ (Hacking 1990, 16) However, with the explosive growth from cities to metropolises at the end of the nineteenth century, the survey became increasingly important for urbanism and soon became a crucial role in the planning and design process all over Europe. Therefore, it is no surprise that all key urban projects that were developed in the aftermath of the First World War were largely driven by statistics. These statistics tied projects, which were often presented as visionary and from the nineteen fifties on dismissed as ‘utopian’ to the everyday reality of the city. Le Corbusier, for example, presented his ‘Contemporary City for Three Million Inhabitants’ from 1922

217Out of the Wild

in his Œuvre Complete (Le Corbusier 1964) accompanied by quantitative comparisons to other cities and four facsimile images of his sketchbook that were largely filled with statistical calculations. It was a city for three million inhabitants because Paris had 3.000.000 inhabitants in 1922. The program for Le Corbusiers ‘Contemporary City’ was distilled from extrapolations of the actual program of the city of Paris. In Großstadtarchitektur (Hilberseimer 1927) Ludwig Hilberseimer criticised Le Corbusiers ‘Contem-porary City’ for not giving an adequate answer to the given numbers and continued in one breath with his proposal for a ‘High Rise City’ from 1924, that was developed as a remedy to cope with the increasing congestion in the centre of the city of Berlin.

Setting up a new department for city development in the nineteen twenties, advised by architect Cornelis van Eesteren, the social democratic aldermen of the city of Amsterdam decided for a scientific approach from the beginning. First, in 1928, Th. K. van Lohuizen, an urban planner specialized in surveys was hired and only after that the architect Cornelis van Eesteren. With their surveys they were able to prove that the inner city of Amsterdam could largely survive in the state they found it. After that, from 1929 on, they developed the AUP, the famous general extension plan of Amsterdam, which was realized with minor adaptations until the year 2000.

What these projects had in common was that, in the first place, they all sought remedies for the congestion of the cities centres, which was due to their explosive growth; and second, that these solutions departed from the assumption that it would be possible—among many other things—to realize large-scale infrastructural and industrially produced building projects by mobilizing large scale municipal, state or industrial investments. The way this capital could be mobilized and the internal organization of these projects differed from case to case, depending on the ideological view of the architects and politicians involved. The Saint Simonist Le Corbusier had the industrial elite dominating the centre; the socialist Hilberseimer sought to delimit the alienation of work by proposing neighbourhood units, in which dwelling was placed immediately on top of industry; and Van Eesteren and Van Lohuizen, working for the social democratic city council, distributed all functions as equally over the Amsterdam as they could.

Otto Neurath, as the ‘architect’ of the Viennese Settlement Movement, shared some essential characteristics with his notorious colleagues, in particular his belief in scientific methods and statistics. However, radically

218 Out of the Wild

different from them, statistics were not the immediate, unquestionable basis to produce a program for experts to produce an urban project but rather an educational tool for the masses, to help them shape their own individual lives and to understand what they voted for. Also, different from most of his colleagues at the time, Neurath departed from issues that played in the peri-phery of the city of Vienna – the centre having been organized before the First World War with the Ringstrasse and the large infrastructural works planned by Otto Wagner. Also, initially, Neurath had a very different take on the industrialization of the housing production, as he did not immediately depart from large, abstract quantities of housing and other functions needed, but from the smallest possible, concrete unit: the individual hut built by the settlers themselves. This was related to his belief to be able to continue after the collapse of the economical system during the war with an economy in kind, in which there was no money involved. Different from his colleagues in the rest of Europe, he sought therefore for a ‘Converse Taylor System’. Different from most of his colleagues, Neurath did not propose to tear cities down or create artificial land to form a tabula rasa to build upon but worked with the situation he found, which he tried to improve in small steps, almost as in his famous metaphor in which the body of knowledge is compared to a boat that must be repaired at sea:

We are like sailors who on the open sea must reconstruct their ship but are never able to start afresh from the bottom. Where a beam is taken away a new one must at once be put there, and for this the rest of the ship is used as support. In this way, by using the old beams and driftwood the ship can be shaped entirely anew, but only by gradual reconstruction. (Neurath, in: ‘Anti-Spengler’ [1921] 1981, 184)

Whereas most modernist approaches to urbanism have increasingly become criticized from the nineteen fifties on just because of their abstract approach that tried to build cities from scratch, Neurath’s contribution to urbanism, notwithstanding a revival over the last couple of years, has almost been forgotten. There are many reasons for this. Soon in the nineteen twenties, ‘Red Vienna’ also chose more collective approaches, because large-scale collective projects proved more efficient in solving the housing problem. After 1934 many people involved left Austria to live in exile. As the project Out of the Wild wants to show, this did not stop the theoretical impulse the ideas of

219Out of the Wild

Otto Neurath and the Viennese Settlers Movement had given architectural and urban thinking in the work of notable other Austrian-born architects and theoreticians, such as Friedrich Kiesler and Christopher Alexander, to be developed further. Today, this tradition might have more potential than more established modernist approaches in architecture and urbanism.

Shantytowns

Today, we are confronted with new tasks and challenges for architecture and urbanism. The need for more sustainable lifestyles presents some of those. The way we analyze and calculate the ecological footprint of a house today reminds one of the way Otto Neurath unravelled the ‘Rootstock of a Settlement House’ (Vossoughian 2008, 56). Other tasks and challenges arise as consequences of the postcolonial era. Globalization does not just consist of increasing flows of people, data, money and goods all over the world. It also means that we cannot blend out the increasing percentage of settlements in the world that consist of shantytowns any longer. They are part—and with over fifty per cent of the world population living in them a large, an ever-increasing part it most certainly is—of the context of architecture. The way shantytowns are built, hut after hut by the people themselves, bears striking similarities to the situation in Vienna after the First World War. Therefore it is unavoidable that architecture and urbanism will have to rethink their roles in the world, putting themselves in the service of the people who live there. Large-scale modernist housing programmes, like they were still successful in Hong Kong and Singapore in the nineteen fifties and sixties, are not possible any more today because of the immense investments needed. Looking at the increas-ing amount of quasi temporary camps in our cities—the refugee centres, the homeless sleeping in tents in Paris and in the United States, the Roma in Italian cities, the victims of earthquakes in Italy and Turkey, the victims of Katrina in New Orleans; or looking at the explosive increase of informal set-tlements in Turkey and in the former Yugoslavian countries, etc., etc.—this context inevitably comes closer and closer. Retroactive legalisation of illegal and informal extensions of cities, as largely financed by institutions like the World Bank and the European Union, is an unavoidable task. It is however only the first step in the direction of another form of mental amnesty that will allow us to start working on these shantytowns in proactive ways.

220 Out of the Wild

Otto Neurath

More than any other historical example, Otto Neurath and the Viennese Settlement Movement from the period immediately after the First World War might help us to find new perspectives for dealing with this situation. In 1919, Vienna was in a desperate state and hundreds of thousands of families, both from outside the city and from the city itself, sought refuge around allotment gardens and in the periphery to avoid starvation by growing their own food.

For many observers of the city, these Zigeunersiedler or ‘gypsy settlers’ were the ideal citizen-planners in that they relied on know-how and instinct, utilizing everything around them, from urban refuse to trees and captured prey, in order to assure their survival. They illustrated the power of community as an agent of urban reform, and as a force that had the potential for improving life in the metropolis more broadly. (Vossoughian 2008, 17)

The governing Social Democratic Party accepted and supported this movement reluctantly, but still almost from the beginning, as it knew it could not afford any collective infrastructure and wanted to build upon the self-supporting energy of the settlers. For Neurath, who had been work-ing on theories related to the socialization of economy in Vienna after becoming general secretary of the Research Institute for Gemeinwirtschaft in 1919, this was an ideal opportunity to put his ideas into practice. As a key player in the Austrian Settlement and Allotment Garden Association, the Public Utility Settlement and Building Material Corporation (GESIBA), the Settlement and the Housing and Construction Guild of Austria, Neurath looked for a ‘Converse Taylor System’, in which he tried to combine ‘bottom up’ and ‘top down’ strategies borrowed from industry (Vossoughian 2008, 29). In the diagram of the ‘Rootstock of a Settlement House’, Neurath dissected a settler’s house in all its components and traced them back through different forms of production to their origins in the reigns of minerals, plants and animals. A diagram in similar style unravelled the organization of an industrial company, in which many did standardized work on raw materials to produce products, from which only a small part of the company profited financially. As long as Neurath could, he maintained an economy in kind, in which peo-ple paid for their houses by performing collective duties, for example build-ing the houses, the roads and other necessary infrastructure. Architects like

221Out of the Wild

Adolf Loos, Josef Frank, Margarethe Schütte-Lihotzky and many others were also involved in this ambitious and successful undertaking and developed new housing typologies and building systems that unskilled workers could deal with. Information and communication, in the form of newspapers and exhibitions were important aspects of Neurath’s approach and became even more crucial to him after he left the Settlers Movement. From 1928 on, together with the artist and graphic designer Gerd Arntz he developed Isotype, a sign language that allowed communicating statistical data about the city—and later on about the world—in a simple and striking way, in order to make the citizens understand the complex organisation of their city.

Friedrich Kiesler

The Settlers Movement and Otto Neurath were deeply anchored and well known in the Viennese society in the nineteen twenties. Many young Austrian architects and thinkers more or less grew up with the movement and the ideas that belonged to it and tried to give them a place in their own work—even if they might also develop in other directions. One of them is Friedrich Kiesler, who might be an important link between the early theoreticians of the Settle-ment Movement and more contemporary thinkers.

Kiesler claims that he worked with Adolf Loos to assist on the Settlement Movement in 1920. This has never been confirmed and is unlikely, as Loos became Director of the Siedlungsamt only in 1921. Still, this claim shows that Kiesler was well aware of the Settlement Movement and keen on being associated with it. Kiesler left for New York to settle there already in 1926. According to an entry in the diary of his wife Stefi Kiesler at the Kiesler Foundation in Vienna, Kiesler met Otto Neurath there in 1933. A copy of Neurath’s book Modern Man in the Making from 1939 can be found in Kiesler’s private library in the Kiesler Foundation in Vienna. Although Kiesler has been associated with artistic movements from De Stijl to Surrealism, the esoteric and irrational overtones of which seem difficult to relate to the strict positivism of the Vienna Circle, the participatory aspects of the Settlement Movement or Loos’ craftsman-inspired traditionalism, there is also a continuous more down-to-earth and strangely pragmatic tendency present in his work, notably in his theoretical writings. With his writings on Correalism and Biotechnique, Kiesler showed himself a strong defender of

222 Out of the Wild

multidisciplinary, scientific design approaches to avoid building design would ‘continue to exist as a series of disparate, overspecialized, and unevenly distributed products’ (Kiesler [1939] 1996, 92–120).Under the title ‘Magic Architecture’—a title that might be confusing in this context—over the years he produced a series of texts and manuscripts for books that try to root architecture and urbanism in the everyday. Taking a distance from mystical inspirations, according to Kielser ‘Magic Architecture’ was to be distinguished from ‘Dream Architecture’, he wrote already in 1936 ‘it is not an expression of escape into religious solitude (resignation)’. For Kiesler, Magic Architecture is the expression of the creativeness of man, but not in isolation. Instead,

[i]t is the emphasis on participation. […] Magic architecture is not dream architecture, like that of temples or castles; it is the architecture of everyday, every-night reality. Magic architecture is a tool of realistic life. […] Magic architecture is a generator. It can operate on any scale. Any cell of habitation is a nucleus for a power house of joyful living. Neither wealth of cash, nor that of building material, nor social power are needed to accomplishing the most with the least. […] Magic architecture is of course, unthinkable without its socio-logical roots in a society of free will and sacrifice. (Kiesler 1996, 34)

In the nineteen fifties, Kiesler tried to turn the original short essay into a book, which never came beyond the stage of manuscript. In this manu-script, which finds itself in the archives of the Kiesler Foundation in Vienna, he tried to root architecture in the landscape and as an evolution of animal nests. The manuscript, which is richly illustrated with clippings from popular scientific magazines like National Geographic, shows many exam-ples of anonymous architecture, preceding Bernard Rudofsky’s—also a native Austrian—Architecture Without Architects, which was published in 1964 on the occasion of an exhibition under the same title in the Museum of Modern Art in New York (Rudofsky 1964). In the manuscript of a book he started work-ing on in the nineteen fifties but which was left unfinished, Kiesler returned to the themes of ‘Magic Architecture’. In this manuscript he struggled notably with the question where the animal function of shelter stops and architecture begins, but still tried to distinguish it from the Dream Archi-tecture. Crucial is however that Architecture (written with a capital A) is not implemented from above but comes out of the everyday. Or, as Kiesler

223Out of the Wild

formulates it in the unpublished manuscript that is equally titled ‘Magic Architecture’, a book he was working on in the nineteen fifties but was never published, as it finds itself in the Kiesler Foundation in Vienna: ‘Architecture must wait.’ The manuscript can not only be read as an attempt to continue the lessons from the Settlement Movement and the gradual improvements architects like Loos, Frank and Schütte-Lihotzky tried to make on the huts they found, but also somehow as an attempt to reconcile the collective architectural values as they were realized on a large scale in Europe in the nineteen fifties with American urbanism, which always departs from the individual house.

Christopher Alexander

Intuitively, we can immediately understand the work of Christopher Alexander as a continuation of certain aspects of the Settlement Movement, particularly if we think of the participatory tendencies, and of the analytical and philosophical work of Otto Neurath, if we think of Alexanders A Pattern Language as an encyclopædia consisting of architectural protocol sentences. In the tradition of the great architectural encyclopædias of the nineteenth century, like those of Eugène Emmanuel Viollet-le-Duc, it is also a handbook, a manual with which one can build his or her own house, neighbourhood or city. Also Alexander’s fascination for diagrams recalls that of Neurath. Already in ‘Notes on the Synthesis of Form’, with which he took his PhD in Architecture from Harvard in 1964, Alexander dissected the design process by means of tree diagrams that recall Neurath’s ‘Rootstock of a Settlement House’. In the appendix ‘A Worked Example’, Alexander demonstrated the functioning of his interpretation of the design process by means of an Indian village, in other words by means of an example from vernacular architecture (Alexander, 1964). Alexander’s patterns in A pattern Language, 1.166 numbered examples of architectural situations from the large scale of a region to the small scale of ornaments and building components like bricks, read as an even more ambitious dissection of a larger whole. Intriguing is that Alexander already reserves the idea that some of the patterns might be updated in the course of time, depending on the number of asterisks that are placed behind them in the header:

224 Out of the Wild

You see then that the patterns are very much alive and evolving. In Fact, if you like, each pattern may be looked upon as a hypothesis like one of the hypothe-ses of science. In this sense, each pattern represents our current best guess as to what arrangement of the physical environment will work to solve the problem presented. The empirical questions centre on the problem—does it occur and is it felt in the way we have described it?—and the solution—does the arrange-ment we propose in fact resolve the problem? And the asterisks represent our degree of faith in these hypotheses. But of course, no matter what the asterisks say, the patterns are still hypotheses, all 253 of them—and are therefore all tentative, all free to evolve under the impact of new experience and observation. (Alexander et al. 1977, XV).

As such, Alexander’s thinking reminds us not just of Kiesler’s evolutionary concept of Magic Architecture, it also recalls Neurath’s ship metaphor once again. Still, even though Alexander was born in Vienna in 1936 and raised in England, where he studied Mathematics and Architecture at Cambridge University, he and Neurath never met and one will not be able to trace immedi- ate references to either Neurath or the Settlement Movement in Alexander’s work. References to other Viennese logical positivists, such as Ludwig Wittgenstein (Alexander 1964), do appear, just as to Friedrich Kiesler, notably to the ‘Chart of Need-Evolution in Technology’ that is related to Kiesler’s theory of Correalism (Chermayeff and Alexander 1963). Alexander invested a great deal of his energy and ideas in building with unprivileged groups, such as in his Mexicali Project from 1975 in Baja California and the Previ project in Peru from 1976.

Conclusion

The way ideas and traditions travel in history is, particularly in a globalized world, not necessarily a linear process. They travel through literature and persons and often arrive at their final address only through a detour. They are taken up and congested, bend to different peoples’ needs, only to be taken up and reworked again, only hoping to find themselves back as improved components in a new, more or less plausible whole. Out of the Wild might enable us to figure out how certain ideas as they were developed in the Viennese Settlement Movement travelled in time from one protago-

225Out of the Wild

nist to another, maybe not always directly but maybe even through other Austrian-born protagonists that we hardly mentioned or did not even mention in this article yet: Josef Frank, Herbert Bayer, Karl Popper, Paul Feyerabend, Ludwig Wittgenstein and many others. The plausibility of the hypothesis that a continuity of thinking from Neurath to Alexander exists is high, because the migration of thoughts is traceable through the connections of the Austrians in exile. For now, the website www.outofthewild.eu is the only medium that allows us to map these complex relationships.

What we did discover until now, apart from the immediate relationships discussed above, is that the correspondences between Neurath, Kiesler and Alexander mainly revolve around themes that deal with conceptions of organization, wholeness, endlessness, participation and happiness. Different kinds of diagrams are important communicational tools in both analysis and design. All three are important predecessors and pioneers in the development of computer software, parametric design and the Internet. If we would be able to prove these continuities, would it be possible, maybe with the help of new computer technology, to once again transform the ideas of the Viennese Settlement movement into methods that have a better chance of success? Maybe that is too much to ask. But even if we will not be able to solve that problem, we might at least open doors to a different sensibility in think-ing about architecture. Because apart from the quest for more sustainable, worthy living conditions for the largest part of the population, the question how architecture, Magic Architecture, as a more intelligent form or organisation develops out of the everyday reality of the built environment, remains the key question of what architecture is or could be—and thereby it might attract the attention of the profession.

226 Out of the Wild

References

Alexander, Christopher. 1964. Notes on the Synthesis of Form (Cambridge, Mass./ London: Harvard University Press).

Alexander, Christopher, Sara Ishihama, Murray Sylvester, with Max Jacobson, Ingrid Fishdahl-King, Shlomo Angel. 1977. A Pattern Language: Towns, Buildings, Constructions (New York: Oxford University Press).

Chermayeff, Serge, Christopher Alexander. 1963. Community and Privacy (New York: Doubleday & Company, Inc., Garden City.)

Cohen, Jean-Louis. 1995. Scenes of the World to Come, European Architecture and the Ameri-can Challenge (Paris/Montreal: Flammarion/CCA).

Hacking, Ian. 1990. The Taming of Chance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Hilberseimer, Ludwig. 1927. Großstadtarchitektur (Stuttgart: Hoffmann). Kiesler, Friedrich. 1996. ‘Magic Architecture’ in Frederick J. Kiesler, Selected Writings

(Ostfildern: Hatje). Kiesler, Friedrich. [1949] 1997. ‘Manifeste du Corréalisme’. Originally in L’Architecture

d’Aujourd’hui 2, 2. 6. 1949, 80–105. Facsimile in: Dieter Bogner, Friedrich Kiesler, Inside the Endless House (Wien: Böhlau).

Kiesler, Friedrich. ‘Magic Architecture’, unpublished manuscript, written in the 1950s (Archives of the Kiesler Foundation, Vienna).

Krakauer, Jon. 1996. Into the Wild (New York: Villard).Le Corbusier. 1964. Oeuvre Complète. Volume 1, 1910–29 (Zürich: Les Editions

d’Architecture/Artémis). Neurath, Otto. ‘Anti-Spengler’ [1921] 1981, in Otto Neurath. Gesammelte Philosophische

und methodologische Schriften, vol 1, edited by Rudolph Haller und Heiner Rutte, (Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky) 139–196.

Rudofsky, Bernard. 1964. Architecture without Architects (New York: MOMA, Doubleday & Company, Inc., Garden City).

Vossoughian, Nader. 2008. Otto Neurath, The Language of the Global Polis (Rotterdam: NAi Publishers).

Vossoughian, Nader. 2008. ‘Otto Neurath, The language of the Global Polis’. Lecture, Univ. of Innsbruck, 20-05-2008, Podcast at www.architekturtheorie.eu, http://www.architekturtheorie.eu/?lang=DE&archive_id=175 or in iTunesU.

On the Theory and History of Diagrams∂

Zur Theorie und Geschichte der Diagramme

Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

Steffen Bogen, Konstanz

Vorüberlegungen

Mein Text folgt einer einfachen Versuchsanordnung: Gegeben sind drei Beispiele, die in unterschiedlicher Hinsicht als Diagramme klassifiziert wer-den können. Im Vergleich der Beispiele sollen nicht nur augenscheinliche Differenzen systematisiert, sondern auch Gemeinsamkeiten aufgezeigt werden. Die so definierte Qualität des Diagrammatischen sollte sich auch in anderen Zusammenhängen wiederfinden lassen, etwa auch dort, wo man eher von Bildern als von Diagrammen sprechen würde. Wenn ich als Kunsthistoriker solche allgemeinen, im Kern philosophischen Thesen entwickle, bleibt die Argumentation doch durch meine Herkunft geprägt. Ich versuche starke Beispiele zu wählen, die ein entscheidendes Reflexionspotential für eine Theorie des Diagrammatischen bereithalten.1

Bevor ich zu meinen Hauptbeispielen komme, möchte ich das Feld des Diagrammatischen mit drei einleitenden Beispielen abstecken. In gewisser Hinsicht bilden sie Pendants zu den später analysierten Diagrammen. Allzu gewagten Verallgemeinerungen sollen sie als Korrektiv entgegensteuern. Vor allem aber sollen sie zeigen, wie unterschiedlich die Kategorie des Diagram-matischen ausfallen kann, und wie schwierig es folglich ist, einen übergreifen-den Begriff zu entwickeln. Als erstes Beispiel verweise ich auf die logischen Diagramme, die Leonhard Euler 1773 in seinen Briefen an eine deutsche Prinzessin entworfen hat (Abb. 1). Sie erlauben es, einige konditionale Propositionen des Typs „wenn A dann B“ mit Hilfe von Flächenrelati-onen darzustellen.2 Eine ganz andere Gruppe von Diagrammen stellen Kräfte- oder Bewegungsdiagramme dar, wie sie bereits im Bereich der antiken Mechanik und Optik gezeichnet wurden. Wiederum wähle ich ein Beispiel als

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 229–248.

230 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

erste Orientierung aus: eine Zeichnung aus einem mechanischen Traktat von Leonardo da Vinci (Abb. 2).3 Die Figur am linken Rand des Blattes hat das, bereits von antiken Mathematikern als Diagramm formulierte, Hebelgesetz zum Thema: Die am Rad aufgehängten Gewichte halten sich die Waage, wenn das Verhältnis ihrer Gewichte dem Verhältnis ihres Abstands zur Achse des Rades entspricht. Schließlich muss die Definition auch besser verständ-lich machen, worauf der Begriff des Diagramms heute vor allem angewendet wird: auf Diagramme, die statistisch erhobene Daten veranschaulichen, zum Beispiel in Form von Kurvendiagrammen (Abb. 3).4 Das abgebildete Beispiel stammt aus der Pionierzeit solcher Diagramme und ist William Playfairs Statistical Breviary von 1801 entnommen. Thema sind die Importe und Exporte Englands im 18. Jahrhundert, respektive ihre schwankende, und doch relativ parallele Entwicklung.

Abb. 1

Leonhard Euler

Logische Diagramme aus:

Lettres à une Princesse

d’Allemagne sur divers sujets

de physique et de philosophie,

Frankfurt u. Leipzig, 1774

Abb. 2

Leonardo da Vinci

Diagramm zum Hebelgesetz

1493

231Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

Die zusammengestellte Trias von Diagrammen weist große Unterschiede in Form und Funktion auf. Die entscheidende Frage lautet daher: Gibt es überhaupt eine essentielle Gemeinsamkeit zwischen den Beispielen? Um eine positive Antwort geben zu können, sollte man bei den diagrammati-schen Operationen ansetzen. Damit sind Handlungen der Produktion und Rezeption gemeint, in denen das Herstellen und Auswerten der graphischen Form das Nachdenken über ein bestimmtes Thema unterstützen kann, sei es die Beziehung von Begriffen, konkreten Dingen oder Daten. Die materiell-graphische Seite entsteht in der Bearbeitung einer glatten, statischen Fläche, auf welcher mit einem beweglichen Instrument Spuren hinterlassen werden. Auch andere Verfahren der Einschreibung sind möglich, aber das ist der prototypische Fall: Diagramme sind ihrem Wesen nach flächig und graphisch. Farbe und Kolorierung sind sekundär, was nicht bedeutet, dass sie, wenn sie eingesetzt werden, irrelevant sind.

Wichtig ist der komplementäre Faktor der Rezeption: die gesetzten Spuren müssen als etwas wahrgenommen werden, was sich nach bestimmten Regeln hervorbringen, verändern und in der Vorstellung in Beziehung setzen lässt. Erst dann wird aus der graphischen Einschreibung eine diagrammatische Operation. Man muss relevante Eigenschaften der Spuren auswählen und zueinander in Beziehung setzen. Man kann zum Beispiel auf topologische Nachbarschaften von Flächen oder den Schnittpunkt von Linien achten. Man kann Linien mit einer Bewegungsrichtung ausstatten und Positionen gedanklich verschieben und aufeinander abbilden usw. Wichtig ist, dass dabei verschiedene Eigenschaften ein und derselben Spur in ein Verhältnis

Abb. 3

William Playfair

Kurvendiagramm

zu den Exporten

und Importen

Englands im

18. Jahrhundert

aus: The commercial

and political atlas and

Statistical breviary,

London,1786

232 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

zu verschiedenen anderen Spuren gesetzt werden können. Dabei können Be-ziehungen entdeckt werden, die bei der Setzung noch gar nicht bedacht wor-den sind. Im materiellen Kontinuum der graphischen Fläche sind sie jedoch festgehalten. Das macht das Diagramm zu einem Experiment des Denkens: Im Auswerten kann man darüber nachdenken, welche Relationen notwendig aus den Regeln der Setzung folgen, selbst wenn man beim Einschreiben noch gar nicht alle Beziehungen überschaut hatte.

Die Erkenntniskraft der diagrammatischen Operation entfaltet sich im Wechselspiel zwischen „außen“ und „innen“: „Außen“ steht für die Materia-lität des Papiers, und die Spuren, die dort mit Hilfe eines Werkzeugs hinter-lassen worden sind. „Innen“ steht für die Kompetenz, die Spuren gezielt und regelgerecht setzen und in verschiedenen Relationen wahrnehmen zu können, aber auch für die Fähigkeit, diese sensorischen und motorischen Aktivitäten in der Vorstellung kontrolliert antizipieren zu können. „Innen“ und „außen“ stehen damit nicht für abgegrenzte Orte wie „mein Körper“ vs. „meine Umwelt“, sondern für Richtungen des Übergangs zwischen Potentiellem und Aktuellem: In der Bewegung von innen nach außen werden aus vorgestell-ten Bewegungen und Regeln Spuren auf dem Papier. In der umgekehrten Bewegung von außen nach innen werden aus diesen Spuren wiederum Wahrnehmungen und Vorstellungen.

Nun wird man einwenden, dass dies für jeden graphischen Akt gilt, auch für das Schreiben oder freie Zeichnen und Kritzeln, und daher nicht für eine diagrammatische Operation allein charakteristisch sein kann. Man be-achte freilich, dass das, was diagrammatisch ist, auch nach der bisherigen Definition, nicht ausschließlich durch die graphische Einschreibung erzeugt wird, sondern sich erst im Akt der Rezeption entfaltet. So wäre es auch verkehrt, Schreiben und freies Zeichnen kategorisch von der diagrammatischen Einschreibung trennen zu wollen. Sinnvoller ist es, nach diagrammatischen Anteilen im Schreiben und Zeichnen zu fragen.

Über die phänomenologische Definition hinausgehend, gilt es ein seman-tisches und pragmatisches Potential des Diagrammatischen zu klären. Es ent-steht dadurch, dass das regelgeleitete, graphische Wechselspiel von innen und außen in Analogie zu Referenzhandlungen gesetzt wird. Bei aller Unterschied-lichkeit der Beispiele scheint mir das zentrale Thema einer diagrammatischen Operation die Unterscheidung zwischen dem, was in einer bestimmten Situati-on durch die Vorstellung noch frei bestimmt werden kann, und dem, was durch die (angenommene) Übereinstimmung von Vorstellungen mit den Regeln der

233Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

materiellen Wirklichkeit bereits festgelegt ist. In Eulers Kreisen geht es zum Beispiel um die Frage, ob man sich Cs vorstellen darf, die A sind, und Cs die nicht A sind, wenn man festgelegt hat, dass manche As B sind und alle Bs C (Beispiel: manche Logiker (= A) haben Läuse (= B). Alle, die Läuse haben, kratzen sich am Kopf (C). Kann es dann Leute geben, die sich am Kopf kratzen und Logiker sind, und Leute, die sich am Kopf kratzen und keine Logiker sind?) Im Hebelgesetz geht es um die Frage, durch welche frei gewählten Abstände und Gewichtsverhältnisse man ein Gleichgewicht der Kräfte herstellen kann. Playfairs Diagramme wollen klären, was sich aus den erhobenen Daten für die Zukunft schließen lässt: ist zum Beispiel die Vorstel-lung begründet, dass Import und Export stets gleichmäßig schwanken?

Die Stärke der diagrammatischen Operation besteht darin, dass die Unterscheidung zwischen dem, was nach den Regeln der Einschreibung bereits festgelegt ist, und dem, was sich noch frei bestimmen lässt, nicht einfach voraussetzungslos behauptet wird, sondern pragmatisch, im Um-gang mit dem Papier, wie in einem kleinen Experiment getestet werden kann. Hierbei sind die entscheidenden Faktoren ja bereits beisammen: Das Außen der hinterlassenen Spuren und das Innen der Kompetenz, Spuren mit Bezug auf übergeordnete Regeln setzen, wahrnehmen und auswer-ten zu können. Die schwierigsten Probleme der Welt, so die Hoffnung der Diagrammatiker, lassen sich auf diesen Raum minimaler Bewegungen und Spuren herunter brechen. Dort lässt sich testen, was sich noch frei bestim-men lässt, wenn andere Vorstellungen bereits nach bestimmten Regeln zu Papier gebracht worden sind. Dabei baut sich ein ikonisches Verhältnis auf zwischen dem, was wir uns innerhalb und mit der graphischen Setzung vorstellen können, und dem, was in einer Referenzsituation denkbar und möglich wäre. Ist es möglich, Feuer zu finden, das kalt ist? Ist es möglich ein Rad so zu drehen, dass sich ein anderes Rad dadurch in die gleiche Richtung dreht? Ist es wirtschaftlich sinnvoll, die Einnahmen unabhän-gig von den Ausgaben zu steigern? Die Freiheit, die das Diagramm in der Rezeption lässt, wird zum Indikator für den Spielraum, den eine Kultur in der Welt auszuschöpfen versucht. Das ist der Kerngedanke, der in den folgenden drei Beispielen entwickelt werden soll. Mit der Frage nach dem Diagrammatischen, das die Beispiele gemeinsam haben, sollen also zugleich ihre Differenzen deutlich werden.

234 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

Problemata Mechanica

Ich beginne bei einer Figur, die im 3. Jahrhundert vor Christus entstanden ist und zu den Grundfiguren der antiken Mechanik gehört (Abb. 4). Sie ist Teil der pseudo-aristotelischen Problemata Mechanica.5 Am Anfang dieses Textes stehen Ausführungen zur Bewegung von Rädern, aus denen im Verlauf der Argumentation das Hebelgesetz hergeleitet wird. Das Diagramm lässt sich leicht nach den Angaben des Textes zeichnen. Zur diagrammatischen Operation gehört aber auch eine entsprechende Übung der Vorstellungskraft. So fordern die einleitenden Ausführungen den Leser auf, die einfache und gleichsam leere Figur in der Vorstellung zu verändern. Er soll sich die Drehung eines einzelnen Rades vorstellen, und dann zu einer Kette von Rädern über-gehen. Dabei soll er verstehen, dass sich angrenzende Räder stets in unter-schiedliche Richtungen bewegen.

Analysieren wir zunächst den graphischen Akt genauer: Beim Zeichnen eines Kreises wird der Impuls zu einer Drehbewegung in die Tat umgesetzt. Die Spur verbindet sich mit geometrischen und dynamischen Idealvorstel-lungen. Entscheidend ist, dass die Form unabhängig von ihrer wirklichen Produktionsrichtung mit einer frei gewählten Drehrichtung wahrgenommen werden kann. Diese vorgestellte Drehung kann der ursprünglichen Zeichen-richtung auch entgegengesetzt sein. Die diagrammatische Operation wird somit vor allem von innen, durch kontrollierte Vorstellungen bestimmt: Wir

Abb. 4

Aristoteles (Umkreis),

Diagramm

zur Bewegung

angrenzender Räder

aus:

Problemata Mechanica

London, 1963

235Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

lassen Kreise nach Belieben rotieren und stellen uns dabei vor, Räder in be-liebige Richtungen drehen zu können.

Der Lehrsatz nimmt dann allerdings auf eine Erfahrung Bezug, die auf-gezwungen sein soll und nicht mehr frei bestimmt werden kann: Ist die Bewegungsrichtung eines Rades frei gewählt, dreht sich ein angrenzendes Rad auf eine bestimmte Weise mit. Man denke etwa an zwei ineinander greifende Zahnräder. Die Drehrich-tung des zweiten Rades kann nicht frei und unabhängig vom ersten Rad bestimmt werden. Der Mechaniker soll lernen, seine Vorstellungskraft entsprechend einzuschränken.

Der Text leitet diesen Satz aus einer Reihe von diagrammatischen Operati-onen her. Ich verdeutliche dies, indem ich die imaginäre Transformation des Diagramms durch sukzessiv hinzuge-fügte Pfeile veranschauliche (Abb. 5). In der Abbildung sind die zusammen-gestellten Formen des Diagramms als Phasen einer gedanklichen Transfor-mation der graphischen Form zu ver-stehen, die mit t0, t1, t2 usw. bezeichnet sind. In t1 wird zunächst eine beliebige Drehrichtung eines Rades angenom-men. Diese Drehbewegung wird dann gedanklich in zwei Teile geteilt (t2). Es entsteht die Form eines Rades, dessen gegenüberliegende Seiten „sich in verschiedene Richtungen drehen“ (eine Formulierung, die ich dem Text der Problemata Mechanica entnehme). Verschiebt man diese Drehbewegung an die Kontaktstellen Γ und Δ, lassen sie sich auch auf die benachbarten Räder übertragen (t3). An dieser Stelle

Abb. 5

Transformation des aristotelischen

Diagramms zur Bewegung angrenzender

Räder, Hervorhebungen vom Verfasser

t0

t1

t2

t3

t4

t5

t6

236 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

kommt eine entscheidende, durch eine gesetzte Spur erzwungene Beobachtung ins Spiel. Der rote Pfeil bei Γ (t4) lässt sich auch der angrenzenden Kontaktstelle Β zuordnen. Er bleibt in diesem doppelten Bezug dennoch die Wahrnehmung ein und derselben Spur. Geht man von dieser Identität aus, lässt sich die Bewe-gung von Β nicht mehr unabhängig von Γ wählen.

Aus dieser Beobachtung kann nun in wenigen Schritten das Prinzip der umgekehrten Drehrichtung hergeleitet werden: Α bewegt sich nach der ein-geführten Regel (die besagt, dass sich gegenüberliegende Seiten eines Rades in entgegengesetzte Richtungen drehen) umgekehrt zu Β, entsprechend be-wegt sich Ζ umgekehrt zu Ε (t5). Fasst man diese Richtungen zusammen, steht das postulierte Prinzip auf dem Papier. Angrenzende Räder bewegen sich in entgegengesetzte Richtungen (t6). Der Aha-Effekt ergibt sich daraus, dass das Ergebnis nicht als vollkommen willkürliche Vorstellung gezeichnet wurde, sondern durch die Wahrnehmung bereits materialisierter Vorstellungen und die Anwendung elementarer Regeln bedingt ist.

Fassen wir diese Analyse mit Blick auf eine Theorie des Diagramma-tischen zusammen. In der Einschreibung der Spur und deren gedankli-cher Transformation wird die graphische Fläche zunächst von innen her bestimmt. Es werden Vorstellungen nach bestimmten Regeln in die Tat um-gesetzt. In der Wahrnehmung einer gesetzten Spur kann die graphische Fläche dann zum Stellvertreter einer Außenwelt werden, die uns den Vorstellungen entsprechende Erfahrungen aufzwingt, die von außen nach innen führen. So stehen die Pfeile im aristotelischen Diagramm der Drehrichtungen einmal für Bewegungen, die willkürlich ausgeführt sind und einmal für Bewegungen, die in Erfahrung gebracht und sozusagen „erlitten“ sind. Dieser essentielle Gegensatz wird in der diagrammatische Operation zu einer reflektierbaren Größe: In Beziehung zu Γ steht der rote Pfeil für ein willkürlich in Drehung versetztes Rad, d. h. für eine Bewegung, die unabhängig vom materiellen Kontext ist und von den eigenen Wünschen und Vorstellungen abhängt. In Beziehung zu Β hingegen steht der Pfeil für eine Drehung, die vom materi-ellen Zusammenhang der Räder abhängig ist, so dass die Bewegung eines Rades unter Umständen auch mit katastrophaler Plötzlichkeit falsche Vorstel-lungen durchkreuzen kann.

Das Geheimnis der diagrammatischen Operation zeichnet sich hier beson-ders deutlich ab. Es besteht darin, dass sich auf der einen Seite alles als Form verstehen lässt, die man aus einem freien Bewegungsimpuls heraus mit Bezug auf übergeordnete Regeln in die graphische Fläche einschreiben kann. Auf

237Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

der anderen Seite lässt sich aber auch alles als Form verstehen, die dort gemäß einer bestimmten Regel gesetzt ist, ohne dass die Vorstellung die dauerhaft festgehaltene Einschreibung auslöschen könnte. Die Leichtigkeit, mit der sich beide Aspekte ineinander verwandeln lassen, hilft Fälle zu kontrollieren, in denen das Verhältnis von Regeln, Vorstellungen und unveränderlichen Bedin-gungen der Wirklichkeit verwickelter ist.

Zu beachten ist, dass der Text der aristotelischen Lehrschrift keine einzige Bewegungsrichtung genau bestimmt. Die Pfeile, die ich in der Präsentation hinzugefügt habe, stehen für Vorstellungen, die genauso gut exakt umgekehrt hätten ausfallen können, solange der systematische Wechsel der Richtungen gewahrt geblieben wäre. Mit dem überraschend leeren Diagramm wird die Regel erklärt. Der Fall, auf den sie angewandt werden kann, bleibt dort, wo es unwesentlich ist, unbestimmt und abstrakt. Die Leere der graphischen Form verweist auch darauf, dass der Mechaniker von einem Überschuss seiner Vor-stellungen gegenüber der materiell determinierten Wirklichkeit ausgeht. Hat er bestimmte Regeln durchschaut, kann er die konkreten Fälle in seinem Sinn anordnen und bestimmen. Diese Beobachtung wird in der Unterscheidung der Hauptbeispiele an Bedeutung gewinnen.

mundus – annus – homo

Damit komme ich zum zweiten Beispiel, welches sich als Früh- oder Vorform eines logischen Begriffsdiagramms verstehen lässt. In der Analyse dieses Beispiels soll auch eine im Vergleich zur mechanischen Lehrfigur andere Verwendung der diagrammatischen Grundoperation deutlich werden. Das Diagramm geht ebenfalls auf Aristoteles und seinen Kreis zurück. Thema ist die aristotelische Elementenlehre, die vier Grundelemente und vier Grund-eigenschaften postuliert. Ich zeige ein farblich ausgestaltetes Beispiel aus einer karolingischen Handschrift des 9. Jahrhunderts (Abb. 6).6

Wiederum ist es grundlegend, den Akt der Einschreibung von zwei Sei-ten her zu denken: als etwas, was faktisch auf das Papier gesetzt worden ist, und als etwas, was sich als Potential der Setzung nach bestimmten Regeln vorstel-len und dabei auch in Beziehung zu anderen Setzungen bringen lässt. Mit Bezug auf Schriftzüge lässt sich das auch einfach als Zusammenhang von Schreiben und Lesen begreifen. Nehmen wir einen konkreten Begriff wie calidus als Beispiel. Fasst man calidus als Schriftzug auf, steht dieser unverrückbar

238 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

an bestimmten Stellen auf dem Papier, nämlich an zwei verschiedenen Stellen rechts oben im Kreis. Wer den Begriff calidus lesen kann, hat die Fähigkeit, die graphische Spur in einer zukunftsoffenen Menge von Fällen an beliebiger Stelle als Anwendung der Schreibregel für dieses Wort wiedererkennen und von anderen Wörtern unterscheiden zu können.

Die konkrete Lektüre bleibt damit offen und anschlussfähig. Gibt es wei-tere Regeln, die nicht nur für den einzelnen Schriftzug, sondern auch für

Abb. 6

Diagramm zur

aristotelischen

Elementenlehre aus

einer karolingischen

Sammelhandschrift

München, Bayerische

Staatsbibliothek,

clm 16128, fol 16r.

239Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

seine Beziehung zu anderen Wörtern und Kreissegmenten gelten? Wir können tatsächlich erkennen, dass die zwei Schreibungen von calidus in einem blassgelb markierten Kreissegment zusammengefasst sind. Auch die anderen Eigenschaftsbegriffe (humidus, frigidus und sicca [für siccus]) sind jeweils zwei-mal geschrieben und durch ein Kreissegment verbunden, so dass sie in dieser Hinsicht als Einheit erscheinen. Die identischen Adjektive lassen sich jedoch auch getrennt auf verschiedene Kreise beziehen, die um die vier Elemen-te geschlagen sind. Das erste, weiter links und oben im Kreis geschriebene calidus ist zum Beispiel dem türkis-blauen Kreis um IGNIS zugeordnet, das benachbarte calidus einem kleinen dunkelblauen Kreissegment um AER. Dieses Segment ist verkürzt ausgeführt, kann jedoch im Analogieschluss gedanklich weiter gezogen werden.

Welche Referenzhandlungen spielen hierbei eine Rolle? Die Suche nach Regeln, die in der Form des Diagramms verkörpert sind, gleicht nach Aristoteles der Erkenntnis von Prinzipien, die nach seiner Elementenlehre in der ganzen körperlichen Welt gelten. (Auf einer ersten Ebene entspricht das Diagramm damit den Regeln, nach denen die aristotelische Elementenlehre aufgebaut und verstanden werden kann.) Wer die Welt, respektive die Natur-lehre, des Aristoteles lange genug studiert, kommt demnach zu dem Schluss, dass die ganze Vielfalt der Körper aus der unterschiedlichen Mischung von nur vier Elementen (Feuer, Luft, Wasser und Erde) entsteht. Jedes Element ist durch zwei von vier Grundeigenschaften charakterisiert. Eine Referenz-handlung für das Lesen von calidus im Kontext der Kreissegmente könnte also darin bestehen, einen konkreten Körper vor sich zu haben, an dem man die Eigenschaft warm feststellt und den man dann entweder mit dem Element Wasser oder Luft in Beziehung bringt. Die Lehre des Aristoteles be-zieht sich jedoch nicht auf einzelne Fälle, sondern auf alle möglichen Fälle: In der Fläche des Papiers soll man sich die gesamte körperliche Welt vorstellen, so wie sie die Lehre definiert. Dann kann man die Beziehungen auswerten, die sich daraus ergeben. In den Fokus der Aufmerksamkeit rückt damit nicht die Wahrheit der einzelnen Aussage (stimmt es wirklich, dass Luft stets warm ist?), sondern die relative Wahrheit der Aussagen untereinander. Zum Beispiel: Wie stützt die Definition der Luft als warm die konträre Definition der Erde als kalt?

An dieser Stelle lässt sich noch einmal möglichst präzise die Frage nach der Freiheit von Vorstellungen im Zeichnen des Diagramms stellen. Im Fall der mechanischen Räder wurden zwingende Regeln der Körperwelt angenommen,

240 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

die der Vorstellung dennoch Spielraum ließen: die Drehrichtung des ersten Rades ist frei vorstellbar, die Bewegung der verzahnten Räder jedoch nicht mehr. So blieben die Kreise auch leer, ohne Richtungspfeil. Nicht die Zeich-nung, sondern die Vorstellung konnte bestimmen, in welche Richtung sich das System im konkreten Fall drehen sollte. Die freie Setzung der ersten Richtung verwandelt sich in den Zwang, resultierende Richtungen abzuleiten.

Im Schema der aristotelischen Elementenlehre ist der Freiraum des Rezipienten auf andere Weise eingeschränkt. Im Grunde hat er allein die Wahl, einen Anfang für seine Lektüre und Betrachtung zu wählen. Die Schreibrichtung, die alle Begriffe bis auf den zentralen Titel auf das Zen-trum hin orientiert, signalisiert, dass man gleichberechtigt an jeder Stelle in das System einsteigen kann. Dann wird man begrifflich an die Hand genommen: Die verschiedenen Aussagen lassen sich auf verschiedenen Wegen erschließen – am Ende zählt jedoch das System und nicht der Weg. Nimmt man das Diagramm wörtlich, wird eine perfekte Kongruenz von innen und außen entworfen: Das Schema bezeichnet den Aufbau der mate-riellen Körperwelt ebenso wie den Aufbau des geistigen Unterscheidungs-vermögens des Gelehrten (der lange genug Aristoteles und seine Kommen-tatoren gelesen hat).

Gerade weil alles, was in das Diagramm geschrieben ist, keine weitere Bestimmung zulässt, fordert die Form dazu auf, zusätzliche Vorstellungen in das System einzuschreiben. Das Diagramm selbst ist Ergebnis einer solchen Operation, indem nicht nur das Thema der vier Elemente (mundus), sondern auch das Thema der vier Jahreszeiten (annus) und die auf Galen zurückgehende Lehre der vier Säfte und Temperamente (homo) in dieselbe Form geschrieben werden. Dem Feuer (IGNIS ) wird zum Beispiel der Sommer (aestas) und die gelbe Galle (colera) zugeordnet. Durch die gemeinsame Projektion wird die Kompatibilität der verschiedenen Lehren veranschaulicht: Die Einteilung des Jahres in vier Jahreszeiten, die Unterscheidung von vier Elementen und die Grundsätze der Humeralpathologie beruhen auf denselben logischen Operationen der Unterscheidung.

So ist die mittelalterliche Kultur der Diagramme, angefangen mit Isidor von Sevillas Schrift De natura rerum, über Jahrhunderte damit beschäftigt, die Figur nicht nur zu kopieren, sondern mit weiteren Begriffen, zum Teil auch mit figürlichen Symbolen anzureichern. Mit unerschöpflicher Energie werden neue Begriffe gesucht und Allegorien entworfen, die in das System passen. In der historischen Entwicklung des Denkens mag die Figur geholfen haben,

241Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

in verschiedenen Themen und Argumenten die iterative Anwendung grund-legender logischer Operationen erkennen zu können. Sie kann aber auch umgekehrt dazu beigetragen haben, die Beweiskraft einer logischen Operation mit der Wahrheit ihrer semantischen Spezifizierung zu verwech-seln. Die perfekte Symmetrie des Kreises und die farbliche Ausgestaltung der Figur scheinen die relative Wahrheit der Aussagen beständig in eine absolute Wahrheit transformieren zu wollen. Es gäbe dann tatsächlich nur diese eine zwingende Möglichkeit, die Welt in vier Elemente und vier Grundeigenschaf-ten aufzuteilen. Man sollte jedoch mit kontextunabhängigen Behauptungen vorsichtig sein. Es lassen sich nämlich auch Zusammenhänge denken, in der die Ausgestaltung eine ästhetische Reaktion auf das Bewusstsein gewesen ist, dass die Besetzung der logischen Struktur kontingent und nicht mit allen möglichen Erfahrungen deckungsgleich ist.7

Zwischenfazit

Nach den beiden ersten Hauptbeispielen können zwei Grundgedanken einer Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen zusammengefasst werden. Sie betreffen deren Genus und Spezifika.

1. In diagrammatischen Operationen wird die von Regeln geleitete Bezie-hung zwischen Handlungen und dabei aufgezwungenen Erfahrungen erkundet. Die graphischen Akte eignen sich dafür, weil sie eine ideale Kongruenz zwischen beiden Seiten herstellen: Alles, was sich an graphi-schen Spuren auf dem Papier nach bestimmten Regeln vorstellen lässt, lässt sich dort ohne Aufwand und Anstrengung dauerhaft realisieren. Aus der Vorstellung einer Spur, die nach bestimmten Regeln gesetzt wer-den soll, kann durch die Bewegung eines Instruments die Erfahrung einer Spur werden. Diese Spur kann in der Wahrnehmung dann wieder mit der Regel verbunden werden, der sie folgt. Die graphische Fläche ist eine Art Membran, die sowohl von innen, durch die wechselnde Aktivität von Vorstellungen, als auch von außen, durch eine Art beständige Passivität und Trägheit der materialisierten Spuren, bestimmt wird.

2. Ein wesentliches Spezifikum verschiedener Operationen betrifft die Frage, inwieweit eine Differenz zwischen den Bereichen Vorstellung und Erfahrung

242 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

produktiv gemacht wird: Geht es um Erkenntnis im klassischen Sinn, das heißt um Vorstellungen, die durch materielle Bedingungen erzwungen wer-den? Oder ist eher Planung und Kontrolle das Ziel: Ist die diagrammatische Operation ein Instrument, materielle Unbestimmtheiten durch Vorstellun-gen besser bestimmen zu können?

Pulsschreiber

Der zweite Teil der These wird bei der folgenden Analyse des dritten und letz-ten Beispiels noch stärker in den Mittelpunkt rücken. Der Aspekt der Planung ist hier gesteigert und mit einem Moment der Rückkopplung verbunden. Mein Hauptbeispiel ist dem 1880 erschienenen Buch Méthode graphique von Etienne-Jules Marey entnommen (Abb. 7).8 Anders als die bisherigen Beispiele steht die Abbildung nicht für die diagrammatische Operation selbst, sondern für eine Darstellung der Einschreibung. Zu sehen ist ein komplexer Apparat, dessen Nadel eine Linie in ein geschwärztes Papier ritzt. Der Ausschlag der Haut beim Pulsieren des Blutes verstärkt über einen mechanischen Hebel den Ausschlag der Nadel. Das gerußte Papier wird durch einen Motor angetrie-ben und bewegt sich möglichst gleichförmig unter der Nadel hindurch. Die Abbildung selbst, ein Holzstich, ist von Hand gefertigt und abgedruckt. Dem Stecher lag vielleicht ein technisch produziertes Pulsdiagramm zusammen mit einer Fotografie des medizinischen Apparats vor.

Die Linie des Pulsschreibers soll Auskunft über eine Veränderung der kör-perlichen Welt geben, in diesem Fall des Pulses. Ohne ein solches Verfahren bliebe der Puls eine vage Qualität, durch die Einschreibung wird er zu ei-ner quantitativ bestimmbaren Größe. Die Aufzeichnung eröffnet eine Matrix des Vergleichs: Verschiedene Pulsschläge lassen sich vergleichen, über weite Zeiträume hinweg, zwischen verschiedenen Menschen aber auch an ein und demselben Patienten in verschiedenen Situationen. Da die Einschreibung au-tomatisch erfolgt, müssen die Regeln, denen die Kurve folgt, im Moment der Aufzeichnung noch nicht bekannt sein. Erst in der Auswertung verschiedener Aufzeichnungen kann über das Verhältnis von regelhaftem Verlauf und indi-vidueller Ausprägung diskutiert werden. Die graphische Fixierung dient damit dem Ziel, Prinzipien des Pulses und seine Abhängigkeit von verschiedenen Pa-rametern überhaupt erst erkennen und verstehen zu können. Ohne Verfahren der Aufzeichnung wären sie womöglich unerkannt und unentdeckt geblieben.

243Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

Mit der Methode der Messung und Aufzeichnung vervielfachen sich die Möglichkeiten, medizinische Erkenntnisse zu gewinnen, Therapien zu entwickeln und deren Erfolg zu kontrollieren. Die Apparate der Einschrei-bung haben sich seit Mareys Schrift aus dem Jahr 1878 verfeinert (EKG), so dass Kurven und technische Aufzeichnungen immer stärker ins Zentrum der medizinischen Beobachtungen und Überlegungen gerückt sind: Welche Eigenschaften einer bestimmten Kurve sind relevant? Durch welche physio-logischen Abläufe lässt sich ihr Verlauf erklären? Welche Schwankungen sind unbedenklich, welche bedenklich? Die Beobachtung und Auswertung der Kurve unterstützt die Untersuchung des Körpers, erschließt unzugängliche Bereiche und kann die unmittelbare Untersuchung sogar ganz ersetzen.

Ohne die Details dieses Prozesses erhellen zu können, verdeutlicht Mareys Abbildung, wie die graphische Fläche der aufgezeichneten Kurve sich an die Stelle der pulsierenden Haut setzt und dabei viel stärker als die leben-dige Haut zu einer Membran zwischen innen und außen werden soll: Die Handwurzel, an der sich der Puls abzeichnet, steht für eine „Außenhaut“ des Patienten, der die Stärke und Frequenz des Pulses nur in einem sehr begrenz-ten Maß willentlich kontrollieren und den eigenen Wünschen und Vorstel-lungen unterwerfen kann. Erst das geschwärzte Papier, in welches die Kurve eingeschrieben wird, unterstützt die Verwandlung der Außenhaut in etwas, was dem Zugriff von innen zugänglich werden soll. Dazu bedarf es der Kom-petenzen eines Arztes. Die Fläche des Diagramms ist also – paradoxerweise – viel stärker als die Haut des Patienten eine „Innenhaut“, auf der sich abzeich-nen soll, was durch die medizinische Intervention vorgestellt und kontrolliert

Abb. 7

Étienne-Jules Marey

Darstellung eines Pulsschreibers

aus: La méthode graphique dans les sciences expérimentales

et principalement en physiologie et en médecine, Paris, 1878

244 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

werden kann. Das Ziel einer technischen Medizin ist es, den individuellen Verlauf der Kurve und ihre allgemeinen Regeln so beeinflussen zu können, als ob sie mit Hilfe einer freien Hand gezeichnet worden wäre. Zeichenmittel sind in diesem Fall nicht Stift und Papier, sondern wenn nötig Medikamente und operative Eingriffe, die auf den Körper im Apparat der Einschreibung Einfluss nehmen.

Das medizinische Kurvendiagramm ist das Beispiel, das vielleicht am deut-lichsten vom Eigenwert der wahrnehmbaren Form wegführt und stattdessen weite pragmatische Handlungsräume öffnet. Ein Kurvendiagramm wird in dem Bewusstsein gezeichnet, dass die materielle Welt und die Regeln, denen sie unterworfen ist, durch die Welt der Gedanken und Vorstellungen entscheidend mitbestimmt werden kann. Nicht nur dadurch, dass innerhalb vorgegebener Regeln und Prinzipien bestimmte Fälle geschaffen werden, die zu bestimmten Resultaten führen. Das ist die Welt der mechanischen Positions- und Funktions-diagramme. Ein Kurvendiagramm ist mit einem ungleich größeren Spielraum verbunden: In ihm kann über die Gesetze und Prinzipien selbst verhandelt wer-den. Was soll normiert, welche Zusammenhänge sollen gestiftet werden? Ab welchem Punkt soll man eingreifen? Welcher Fall gilt als normal, welcher als unbedenklich, welcher als therapiewürdig? Die Unterscheidung zwischen dem, was sich frei bestimmen lässt, und dem, was man eben als körperlich gegeben hinnehmen muss, wird zum Gegenstand einer Diskussion, die immer wieder auf Diagramme zurückgreifen muß, um nicht gegenstandslos zu werden.

Abb. 8

Deutsche Börse,

Frankfurt a. M.

Verlauf des DAX

am 15. April 2003

© Gruppe

Deutsche Börse

245Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

Ist es übertrieben, darin ein generelles Signum der Moderne zu erkennen? Diagrammatische Operationen steuern als Instrumente der Rückkopplung vielleicht alle wesentlichen Handlungsräume der modernen Welt. Im ökono-mischen Kontext unterhält man sich täglich, ja stündlich über den wünsch-baren, vorhersehbaren aber auch ungeplanten Lauf von Kurven. Das sei mit dem Bild eine Börsenkurve angedeutet (Abb. 8). Immer geht es darum, den wahrscheinlichen Verlauf der Kurve mit dem gewünschten abzugleichen und dann geeignete Parameter der Intervention zu finden. Diese lassen sich nur bedingt aus der Untersuchung der graphischen Form allein ableiten. Aber stets lässt sich der Einfluss von Interventionen, ihr Erfolg oder Misserfolg an der graphischen Form ablesen.

Fazit

Diagrammatische Aufzeichnungen folgen Regeln, die die Innenwelt unserer Vorstellungen und Wünschen mit einer Außenwelt körperlicher und materieller Prinzipien verbindet. Im graphischen Akt sind die Faktoren in idealer Wei-se aufeinander bezogen: Die Spur, die nach bestimmten Regeln als Teil der körperlichen Außenwelt auf das Papier gesetzt und dort nach dem Prinzip räumlicher Nachbarschaften festgehalten wird, und die Wahrnehmung der Spur als etwas, was sich aus der Innenwelt der Vorstellungen und Wünsche heraus nach bestimmten Regeln setzen, transformieren und in Verhältnis zu anderen Spuren bringen lässt.

Stets ist in den diagrammatischen Operationen nicht die Eliminierung eines Pols das Ziel: Der Umgang mit Diagrammen steht weder für eine rein geistige Erkenntnis, die eines materiellen Widerparts nicht bedürfte, noch ist das Diagramm ein technisches Artefakt, das funktioniert, egal ob wir es verstehen oder nicht. Diagrammatische Operationen bleiben – selbst wenn die Einschreibung mit einem technischen Apparat verbunden ist – von den Vorstellungen und dem Verständnis der Nutzer abhängig. Dabei werden die graphischen Handlungen und die Regeln, denen sie folgen, in Relation zu Referenzhandlungen gesetzt.

Zum einen können damit im klassischen Sinn des Begriffs „Erkenntnis“ Welten entworfen werden, in denen die graphische Handlung keinen Einfluss auf die Referenzhandlung haben soll, sondern deren feststehende Prinzipien und Regeln in der diagrammatischen Operation wiederholt und aufgedeckt

246 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

werden sollen. Im Diagramm lassen sich dann die logischen Konsequenzen aus der angenommenen Verkörperung von Vorstellungen und Regeln ziehen. Das mittelalterliche „mundus–annus–homo“-Diagramm ist ein Beispiel für diese Gattung, wobei freilich offen ist, was wirklich als Referenzhandlung gelten darf. Lange Zeit wurde das Diagramm so gelesen, als ob es die Analyse der körperlichen Welt selbst betreffen würde. Inzwischen ist das Diagramm historisiert und wird auf die Lektüre einer bestimmten Form von Naturleh-re als deren systematische Zusammenfassung bezogen. Das ausgestaltete Diagramm provoziert damit eine konstruktivistische Kritik: Reagiert die ästhe-tische Ordnung auf das Bewusstsein, dass wir eine derart perfekte Ordnung der Welt gar nicht vorfinden, hat sie gar die Funktion einer unbewussten Kom-pensation oder bewussten Manipulation anderer Rezipienten? Viele Bild- und Kulturwissenschaftler werden den Reiz der diagrammatischen Überlegungen darin erkennen, eine solche Bild- und Diagrammkritik schreiben zu können: Angeblich „ontologische Wahrheiten“ können als ästhetische Setzungen reflektiert und kritisiert werden.

Diagrammatische Operationen sprengen jedoch den klassischen Begriff von Erkenntnis: Nur in einem kleinen Bereich werden damit Welten model-liert, in der die graphischen Handlungen durch die Referenzhandlungen bereits vollkommen bestimmt sind. Viel häufiger ist die Erkenntnis eines Überschusses der Vorstellungen gegenüber der vorgefundenen Wirklichkeit, das Aufdecken eines Gestaltungsspielraums innerhalb der Welt das eigentliche Ziel der dia-grammatischen Praxis. Dieses Thema muss einer nur vermeintlich naiven Praxis dann nicht erst nachträglich durch einen kritischen Rezipienten ein-geimpft werden, vielmehr steht es von Anfang an in deren Zentrum: Mit der diagrammatischen Operation werden Pläne geschmiedet und die Referenz-handlungen so ausgerichtet, wie sie in der graphischen Handlung vorbereitet wurden. In der graphischen Einschreibung wird die Einpassung von Vorstel-lungen in materielle Vorgaben modelliert. Besonders in dieser Funktion sind Diagramme zu einem zentralen und mächtigen Instrument der Kulturent-wicklung geworden.

In der Moderne erscheint diese Funktion noch potenziert: Diagramma-tische Operationen sind zu einem zentralen Instrument der Steuerung und Rückkopplung körperlicher und kultureller Prozesse geworden. Ihr Gegen-stand sind zeitliche Prozesse, deren Verlauf durch die Einführung neuer Regeln radikal verändert werden kann. Erfolgt die Herstellung der Diagram-me in einer offenen und reflektierten Diskussionssituation, fragt die Gemein-

247Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

schaft mit Hilfe der aufgezeichneten Daten, an welchen unveränderlichen Regeln der Wirklichkeit und an welchen selbst gewählten Normen sie die eigenen Handlungen ausrichten will. In einer unreflektierten und zur Gewohnheit gewordenen Praxis wird sich die Gemeinschaft den erzeugten Diagrammen und eingefahrenen Interpretationsroutinen unterwerfen, so als seien sie die eigentliche, unveränderliche Wirklichkeit.

Anmerkungen

1 Vgl. frühere Beiträge des Verf. zum Thema: Steffen Bogen / Felix Thürlemann, „Jenseits der Opposition von Text und Bild. Überlegungen zu einer Theorie des Diagramms und des Diagrammatischen“, in: Die Bildwelt der Diagramme Joachims von Fiore. Zur Medialität religiös-politischer Programme im Mittelalter, herausgegeben von Alexander Patschowsky (Ostfildern: Thorbecke, 2003), 1–22, Steffen Bogen, „Schattenriss und Sonnenuhr. Überlegungen zu einer kunsthistorischen Diagram-matik“, Zeitschrift für Kunstgeschichte 68. 2 (2005):153–176. Grundlegende philoso-phische Monographien mit einem ähnlichen, von Charles S. Peirce ausgehenden Ansatz: Frederik Stjernfelt, Diagrammatology. An Investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics, (Dordrecht: Springer, 2007), Sybille Krämer, „Operative Bildlichkeit. Von der ‚Grammatologie‘ zu einer ‚Diagrammatologie‘?“, in Logik des Bildlichen. Zur Kritik der ikonischen Vernunft, herausgegeben von Martina Hessler u. Dieter Mersch, (Bielefeld: Transcript, 2009), 94–123 (eine Monographie der Verfasserin ist in Vorbereitung). Ein aktueller Überblick über das Forschungs-feld: Matthias Bauer, Christoph Ernst, Diagrammatik. Einführung in ein kultur- und medienwissenschaftliches Forschungsfeld (Bielefeld: transcript 2010).

2 Sun-Joo Shin, The iconic logic of Peirce’s graphs, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2002), Peter Bernhard, Euler-Diagramme. Zur Morphologie einer Repäsentationsform in der Logik (Paderborn, mentis, 2001).

3 Steffen Bogen, „Repräsentative Maschinenzeichnungen und Perspektivkunst. Zur Verbindung neuzeitlicher Malerei mit graphischen Sprachen der Technik“, in Konstruierte Sichtbarkeiten. Wissenschafts- und Technikbilder seit der Frühen Neuzeit, herausgegeben von Martina Heßler (München: Fink, 2006), 131–152.

4 Edward R. Tufte, The visual display of quantitative information, (Cheshire, Conn.: Graphics Press, 1983), William Playfair, The commercial and political atlas and Statistical breviary, edited and introduced by Howard Wainer (Cambridge: Univ. Press, 2005).

248 Zwischen innen und außen. Für eine Pragmatik des Diagrammatischen

5 Aristoteles, Minor Works. On colours; on things heard; physiognomics; on plants; on marvellous things heard; mechanical problems; on indivisible nines; situations and names of winds; on Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias Apollodor, edited by Walter S. Hett (London: Heinemann, 1963), Wolfgang Lefèvre, „Drawings in Ancient Treatises on Mechanics.“ In Homo Faber. Studies on Nature, Technology, and Science at the Time of Pompeii edited by Jürgen Renn (Rom: L’Erma di Bretschneider, 2002), 109–120. Grundlegend für Analysen eines ,lettered diagram‘: Reviel Netz, The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics. A Study in Cognitive History (Cambridge: University Press, 1999).

6 Eine Analyse dieses Beispiels mit Blick auf eine Theorie des Diagrammatischen findet sich bereits in: Bogen / Thürlemann, „Jenseits der Opposition von Text und Bild“ (op. cit. Anm. 1).

7 Vgl. Felix Thürlemann in diesem Band.8 Étienne-Jules Marey, La méthode graphique dans les sciences expérimentales et principa-

lement en physiologie et en médecine, (Paris: Masson, 1878). Zu bildwissenschaftlichen Annäherungen an Kurvendiagramme vgl. Ganz normale Bilder. Historische Beiträge zur visuellen Herstellung von Selbstverständlichkeit, herausgegeben von David Gugerli u. Barbara Orland (Zürich: Chronos, 2000).

Bildquellen

1 Leonhard Euler, Lettres à une Princesse d’ Allemagne sur divers sujets de physiqve et de philosophie; Bd. 2 , 1774, 54. Brief, S. 119.

2 Leonardo da Vinci, Codex Madrid I, hrsg. von Ladislao Reti, (Frankfurt a. M.: S. Fischer 1984), fol. 52 v.

3 William Playfair, The commercial and political atlas and Statistical breviary, London 1786.

4 Problemata Mechanica, edited by Walter S. Hett, (London: Heinemann 1963).5 Verf.6 Die Bildwelt der Diagramme Joachims von Fiore, hrsg. von Alexander Patschowsky,

(Ostfildern: Thorbecke 2003), S. 216, Bildtafel 1.7 Étienne-Jules Marey, La méthode graphique dans les sciences expérimentales et principale-

ment en physiologie et en médecine (Paris: Masson, 1878).8 http://deutsche-boerse.com

Showing Space, or:

Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

Bill Hillier, London

Introduction: Space and Wittgenstein

The aim of this paper is to explain a theory of space, and how it features, conceptually and practically, in everyday life. The theory, which is known as space syntax, bears on the work of Wittgenstein in three ways. First, from the point of view of language, space seems to the kind of problem that Wittgenstein identified for logic in the Tractatus, that what is expressed through language cannot be represented in language (TLP 4.12, 4.121). Practically speaking, this means that although natural language, like life, is built on a scaffolding of space and spatial relations, so much so that ‘language and space’ is now a key theme in cognitive neuroscience (Bloom et al. 1996), the patterns of space in which we live our lives are not representable in linguistic terms. The spatial relations and structures of our lives are in effect non-discursive: we live them but don’t know how to talk about them. The non-discursivity of space is a particular problem in architecture where the primary task is to create a pattern of space—a ‘layout’—adapted for functional purposes, yet there are no linguistic means to describe the differences between one layout and another, forcing architects to proceed by intuition, precedent or meta-phor. Yet architects must predict function from space, and so need a consist-ent language, if not a science of space. This poses the question: can there ever be a science of space when space is non-discursive in this sense? Space syntax then addresses the architectural problem of space, but anticipates that in doing so it will address the problem of space in general.

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 249–273.

250 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

The second point of contact with Wittgenstein is that graphical representa-tions played a critical role in the creation of the theory, and still play a critical role in its applications. These representations were able to show features of spatial patterns that language was not able to describe. But more unexpect-edly, perhaps, from a Wittgensteinian point of view, these representations led directly to seeing how we could quantify structural features of space, and so seek to render the non-discursive discursive. We can make the point in a Wittgensteinian way. In the Untersuchungen he says:

Our language can be regarded as an ancient city: a maze of little streets and squares, of old and new houses, of houses with extensions from various periods […] surrounded by a multitude of new suburbs [such as the symbolism of chemistry] with straight and regular streets and uniform houses. (PI § 18)

We can say that we sought to add a new suburb to language, based on a sci-ence of space, which will allow the spatial scaffolding of life to be described. But this also means that in Wittgensteinian terms we are trying to say the unsayable. The question is: do we succeed and what are the implications?

The third point of contact concerns what Wittgenstein would call the ‘formal unity’ of the ‘language of space’ at which we arrive. Once the struc-tural features of spatial relations are brought to light, we seem to discover that space is subject to something like laws, not in the form of universal behav-iours, but of the form ‘if we intervene physically in space in this way rather than that—say by placing an object in the centre of a room rather than a corner, or making the object rectangular rather than square—then the structural consequences for the ambient space are these.’ These ‘laws’ seem to be known intuitively to human beings, in the same sense that when we throw a ball of paper so that its parabola leads it to land in the waste paper basket, we ‘know’ the laws of mathematical physics—what cognitive science has called ‘intuitive physics.’ It seems to be these lawful potentials that human beings exploit in culturally differentiated ‘spatial games.’ We also find that the emergent forms of complexity, such as the spatial structures of cities, that accumulate from human spatial behaviours, manifest astonishing cross-cultural invariants. All this suggests that the human language of space, in spite of its power to generate differentiated cultural expression, is in some sense a universal language. Should we then conclude that space has the formal unity that the later Wittgenstein doubted for natural language?

251Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

In this paper then, we aim to clarify space by seeing it through key Wittgensteinian ideas. We do not aim to clarify Wittgenstein! But we end with a Wittgensteinian twist, which may suggest other areas where Wittgenstein’s thought might be explored, namely in the sciences of complexity. Although the emergent structures that arise in large and com-plex spatial systems can be represented graphically, and so shown clearly, and can even be tested against functional evidence for their verisimilitude to reality, they cannot so far be described within a formal language. They can, it seems, only be shown. As we will argue, this is a general problem in the sciences of complexity, so we seem to be back to square one, and the Tractatus, but with a more generalised view of the problem of showing!

In what follows, we deal with these questions in turn. Let me first try to show that space is a seriously Wittgensteinian problem.

Space as a Wittgensteinian Problem

If we are to talk about space and language, we should begin by addressing a fundamental theme in Wittgenstein’s writing, that language prescribed the limits to thought. It is hard to defend this point of view in the early twenty first century in the light of cognitive research, and the field where this can be said most emphatically is space. For example, according to Bowman:

If any domain has plausible claim to strong language-independent percep-tual and cognitive organisation, it is space. Our mental representations of space are constrained not only by our biology but also by their fit to the world out there. Little wonder it has seemed likely to many investigators that the language of space closely mirrors the contours of non-linguistic spatial understanding. Several kinds of empirical evidence support the assumption that children know a great deal about space before they can talk about it, and that they draw on this knowledge in acquiring spatial words. (Bowman, 1996: 387)

Johnson-Laird goes further: ‘Human reasoners use functionally spatial models to think about space, but they also appear to use such models in order to think in general’ ( Johnson-Laird, 1996: 460). How language handles space is then critical for both language and space.

252 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

The problem of space in human thought and language, then, seems almost to involve a contradiction. Thought is profoundly spatial, yet at the same time language lacks any means of describing the everyday spatial complexity in which we live. How can this be? We can begin by looking more carefully at how language is spatial. A key part of the spatial structuring of many lan-guages, including English, comes from the system of prepositions. In general, prepositions specify different spatial relations with considerable precision, but only between two or three entities. For example, ‘inside’ implies an ‘outside’ and something which distinguishes one from the other, ‘through’ implies a kind of origin and a destination as well as an entity passed through, ‘beyond’ specifies an origin and a place the other side of an intervening place, and so on. Where more entities are specified, as in the English ‘among’, then there is less precision in the spatial relations, and, in the case of ‘among’, the set of entities into which the ‘among’ entity is set is treated as a single entity, a grouping without further spatial form. Prepositions also differ in the kinds of relation they specify. For example, ‘next to’ is a symmetrical relation, in that if a is next to b, then b is next to a, while ‘above’ or ‘under’ are asymmetric relations, in that if a is above b then b cannot be above a. ‘Between’ then can be seen to specify both symmetrical relations between the two outside entities, and an asymmetrical relation between them and the inner entity. Preposi-tions also specify the numbers of objects in particular places in a scheme of relations. For example, you cannot be between or among one entity or inside more than one, unless one is inside the other.

There seems, in effect, to be something like a formal structure underlying the set of spatial prepositions. Each preposition specifies a scheme of spatial relations, with both abstract and concrete properties, and comes as a kind of irreducible bundle, so that it is quite hard to specify what each means without using the word itself. For example, it is quite hard to say exactly what ‘between’ means without at some stage wanting to say ‘between’. We could perhaps try to say that there is an object with another object at one side and another on the opposite side, but this describes a line of three objects without pointing to the central one as being in a special relation to the other two as ‘between’ does. Or imagine a line of houses. Each, except the end two, is ‘between’ a pair of others, but we would not say this if we were looking at the line, which appears to us as a series of ‘next to’ relations. If we were living at number 10, though, we might well see ourselves as being between number 9 and number 11. So in effect betweenness needs to be pointed to, and is hard to indicate in

253Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

any other way. This seems a very clear case of Wittgensteinian ‘showing’ and what is shown is the scheme of relations bundled up in the word. The word, we might say, is a form of showing.

It is because prepositions bundle up relations in words that they seem to offer a kind of bridge between the perceptual and the conceptual. We see them, and show them, all at once, and what is shown are irreducible schemes of spatial relations. It is this that makes them suitable vehicles for abstract as well as concrete thought. But more significantly, it is perhaps possible at this stage of our evolution for this kind of bundling to be possible with up to three objects. Perhaps superior intelligences in the future will be able to do this with four, five or many more entities. But for the time being, we are in a situation in which our languages are pervasively spatial, yet lack any kind of terminology to describe even the simplest kind of everyday spatial complexity. Space then seems a very clear case of what is transmitted through language not being expressible in language.

Defining Spatial Configuration

So how do we proceed with the problem of spatial non-discursivity? (For a more extended treatment see Hillier & Hanson 1984 and Hillier 1996) Prepositions, as little schemes of spatial relations with both abstract and concrete properties, offer a clue. Can we somehow extend this mix of ab-stract and concrete to more complex patterns? We suggest this is possible by defining spatial configuration formally as spatial relations which take into account other relations. We must begin by saying exactly what we mean by this. How can relations affect other relations?

In Figure 1 (overleaf) we show top left a two cell plan with an opening between two spaces, a and b. The relation of a and b is symmetrical, meaning that a is to b as b is to a—just as if a is b’s neighbour then b is a’s neighbour. We then introduce a third space, c—in fact the outside—and in the middle case link both a and b to c, but in the right case link a but not b, to c, so we must pass through a to get to b from c. The relation between a and b has not changed intrinsically, and remains exactly the same as it was, but if we consider the third space, in the middle case the relation between a and b with respect to c is still symmetrical, but in the right case is has become asymmetrical, in that we must pass through a to get to b from c, but we do not need to pass through b

254 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

to get to a from c. So the presence of a third element has changed the relation between a and b with respect to that element. This is what we mean by spatial configuration, in contrast to the simpler concept of spatial relations. Elements acquire values by virtue of their relation to all other elements in the system.

We can show this more clearly through a simple but powerful representa-tion, and one which played a critical role in creating space syntax: the ‘justi-fied’ graph, as in the bottom line in Figure 1. This means that you select a node as a ‘root’, and align all those connected to it one layer above, all those two steps from it two layers above, and so on, with the effect that you can see the configuration. With this representation, we can easily see what turn out to be the two key configurational properties of space. The first addresses the question ‘do you have to pass through intervening nodes to get from one node to another?’ We can call this the depth or, in space syntax parlance, the integration property—the less spaces are deep from each other the more integrated they are, and the more accessible they are as destinations from all other nodes. The second is: are there different routes from one node to another, which we can call the choice property, and how likely is each node to be used on a route between any pair of nodes. Any choice of routes implies rings or cycles in the graphs, since in any graph without rings there will be exactly one route from any node to any other node. These will turn out to be

Fig. 1

Plans

Justified graphs

d = depth to all other nodes

td = total depth to all other nodes

a

a b a b

c c

a

b

b a b a b

d = 2 d = 2

d = 3

d = 2

d = 3

d = 2 td = 6 td = 8

255Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

the critical social properties of space, and because we can see how to detect their presence in simple cases we can learn to measure them in complex cases. How much integration and choice is there in a particular graph? The resulting values will turn out to have social meanings and even social effects.

Showing Configuration

We can also show how the justified graph can make accessible more complex configurational properties to intuition, to show them, in Wittgenstein’s terms. The top line in Figure 2 shows the plans of notional 8-cell houses. As plans it is difficult to say much about them apart from making a list of local relations. Of course, by living in the houses we would quickly intuit the configurational differences, and functional possibilities and inhibitions. But they would remain non-discursive. In the bottom line we see in the j-graphs from the outside immediately the configuration properties of depth and rings, so we can see how shallow or deep, ringy or tree like each graph is, more or less at a glance.

But we are still in the realm of seeing more clearly what can not be expressed in language. To take the next step, we must learn to measure the presence of these properties. This will lead us to the most fundamental prop-erty of graphs from a spatial point of view: graphs differ in the properties of integration and choice when seen from the points of view of different nodes

7 4 8

3 5

21

6

5 8 7

3 4

16

2

1 2 7

6 3

54

8

45

6

3 7

2 1 82 6 1 2 5 8 2 1 8

outside

7

32

8

4

1

5 6 3

1

5 6

8

7

4

2 3 2 1

2

3

4 5

6 7

8

1

6

5

4

8 7

outside outside outside

Fig. 2 Plans and j-graphs of 8-cell houses

256 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

within the graph. Consider the two graphs in Figure 3. The two seem quite different in terms of the configurational properties we have described, but in fact the two are the same graph seen from two different points of view, namely spaces 5 (the shallow graph on the left) and 10 (the deep graph on the right). So we can say the graph is integrated from the point of view of space 5, and segregated from the point of view of space 10. This is the fundamental prop-erty of graphs that is exploited by buildings and cities, from the scale of the domestic dwelling to that of metropolitan Tokyo: graphs are different from different points of view.

To capture these differences means measuring the depth and choice values of the system when seen from the point of view of each space in the complex. These are essentially the familiar mathematical measures of closeness (depth) and betweenness (choice) (they were not familiar when we first developed them!), though with certain syntactic normalizations to allow comparisons of systems of different sizes. Once we have this we can give a spatial meaning to the pattern of functions in a building. For example, as in Figure 4, which repre-sents the real case of a house in Normandy in France (Hillier et al 1987), we commonly find that a ‘living room’ or a ‘kitchen’ is not just a space with certain furnishings and implements, but also a certain configurational position in the house, and a certain way of relating to all other spaces. These differ-ences can be clarified and demonstrated by assigning values to spaces which index how it is related to all the other spaces in the house. In this way, we can find a clear and culturally variable spatial meaning to the idea of function.

4 8 9

37 2 1

5 6

107

4

8

5

93

1

210

614

7

8 2 3

5 10

9

6 Fig. 3

Two j-graphs illustrating

different points of view.

257Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

A form-function relation exists because function has been realised spatially through the positioning of the function in the layout as a whole. So ideas are seen to be objectively present in the layout itself, and its pattern of assigned functions, as well as in minds.

These values give us the configurational properties of individual spaces with respect to the whole, and this is sufficient to give a picture of functional patterns. If we may be permitted a little Wittgensteinian immodesty, this formulation solves a key theoretical problem in architecture. Although a lead-ing element of the architect’s trade is to match the spatial form of a building to its functioning, there is no theory to inform how this can be done other that of the most generalised kind. There is no design level theory capable of informing decisions about the relations between spatial form and functioning. A key reason for this is that most buildings are made up of the same kinds of spaces—room, corridors, courts, and so on—varying in size but not much else, so most functioning happens in a similar range of spaces. It was only by showing that the key properties of spaces were those which linked it to the pattern of space as a whole, that each space acquired properties which were distinctive to its function, as for example in the French house in Figure 4, a salle commune must be integrated into the plan to work as an everyday gather-ing space, while a grande salle needs to be segregated from everyday activity to preserve its identity as a special space. Space syntax shows in effect that it is the extrinsic properties of spaces which relate to function in a non-trivial way, because this is the way spaces acquire distinct identities in the plan.

Fig. 4

Spatial aspects of a

house in Normandy.

total depth from grande salle: 31

total depth from outside: 21

total depth from salle commune: 18

grandesalle

salle commune

vest

ibu

le

couloir

salle

vest

ibu

lela

veri

e

de

bar

ras

lait

eri

e

bur

eau

258 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

But what we still lack is a picture of any kind of the pattern of the whole. Configurational value gives a picture of the whole from a certain point of view, but no discursive picture of the whole that we see when we look at the layout. At this level we have not translated the non-discursive into the discur-sive. However, we can take an important step in this direction by using anoth-er syntactic device: the translation of numbers into colours. By representing bands of numerical values as colours, and always from red (or ‘hot) for strong values on any variable through to blue (or ‘cold’) for weak, the picture of the whole can be shown in Wittgensteinian terms, but still not of course described in any kind of language. Here then is a strong, simple and clear example of something that is an expression of the spatial relations that are to be found throughout language not being sayable in language, but only shown—in this case by a graphical trick!

More Complex Representations

But so far we have looked only at the first, simple steps in space syntax. To take the next steps we need to consider how to represent space in order to make configurational calculations. So far we have used rooms as spatial elements. But cities, and indeed many buildings, do not have rooms, or any-thing that can be easily recognised as well-defined spatial elements. So how, in such cases, can space be represented to allow configurational computations?

To answer this we need a little philosophy! Through our education, we acquire the habit of seeing space in a Cartesian way as ‘extension without

Fig. 5 Warm and cold colours representing the total depth value.

grandesalle

salle commune

vest

ibu

le

couloir

salle

vest

ibu

lela

veri

e

de

bar

ras

lait

eri

e

bur

eau

259Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

the object’, and so as the background to objects, and in architecture we extend this to seeing space as the background to human activity. But as soon as we try to translate this idea into human space, all is lost. We are condemned not to understand it. The reason is simple. Space is intrinsic to human activity, not a background to it. Movement is fundamentally linear, whether we are leaving a room or crossing a city. Interaction is convex, because all interactors must be co-present. Our experience of space as we move about in buildings or cities is of strange jagged shapes we call isovists, and somehow we use these to put together an intelligible picture of where we are. Once we understand this, we see that we shape space in ways which reflect the different types of human activity and experience, and through this the space we make becomes humanised. This is where we have to begin if we want to understand space analytically.

We can now define space syntax as a set of methodologies for making configurational analyses of space represented in different ways as points, lines, convex spaces and isovists, and at different radii from each home element. Let us show you the power—including the predictive power—of these analyses. Visual integration analysis means taking a layout as a set of points at an ar-bitrarily fine scale, and calculating how many visual steps are needed to see all points in the layout from each point. In effect it analyses the whole pattern of visual fields in a layout and assigns integration values to the roots of each visual field. We then colour up from red for strong through the blue for weak as usual and so extract a visual integration structure from the layout.

Fig. 6 Shapes of human activity and experience.

people

people move in lines interact in convex spaces see changing visual fields as they move

around built environments

spaces

physical boundaries

260 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

For example, Figure 7 shows the visual integration structure for the Tate Britain gallery, a structure which links galleries together and links the whole pattern to the entrance (we call it a shallow core). On the right are traces of visitors entering the gallery and moving about for ten minutes. Each vis-itor takes an individual path through the layout, but when we look at the aggregate of traces, we see that the pattern of traces and the structure of visual integration resemble each other strongly. The similarity of the two patterns can be checked statistically, and in fact something like 70 % of the differences in individual movement patterns can be accounted for by the visual integration structure of the layout. This leaves no doubt that visitors are using the spatial layout of the gallery, consciously or unconsciously, as their main navigational aid. The spatial form and functional pattern of the building ressemble each other, not through design intention but as an emergent effect.

Now reflecting on this case and that of the French house we can begin to see that space works in two ways. A spatial layout can reflect and embody a social pattern, as in the case of the French house, where space was laid out and categorised to give reality to a culturally given pattern of activity, and so reinforce and reproduce it. So we can perpetuate things about ourselves and our cultures by building them into space, and so making them seem inevita-ble and natural. We can call this the conservative use of space, since space is

Fig. 7 Left: Trace of 100 people entering Right: Visual integration structure.

Tate Britain and moving for 10 minutes.

261Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

being use to reflect and so reproduce a given social pattern by the control of copresence. But space can also shape a social pattern, as in the case of the Tate Britain movement study, since by shaping movement, space also creates a pattern of natural co-presence in space, and so potential encounter and potential social relation arising from co-presence. We can call this the genera-tive use of space, since we are using space to create the potentials for new co-presence and potentially for social patterns. We will see in due course that this dual potential of space is one of the keys to understanding space in cities.

The Discovery of Spatial Laws

Once we have the concept of measuring configuration as the relations between all the spatial elements in the system and all others, then whatever representation we use, we can easily discover spatial laws. These laws do not take the form of universal behaviours, but govern the ways in which different types of spatial configuration arise from the placing and shaping of objects in space—which is what architects do.

For example, as Figure 8 shows, if we take a square object and place it within a bounded square space, and move the object from corner to centre edge and then to centre, with each step we decrease the degree of visual integration in the ambient space, as well as changing its pattern.

Fig. 8

Decrease of

visual integration

due to changing

positions of a

square object

within a bounded

square space.

1.12925 1.18978 1.20283

1.27228 1.30565 1.31105

262 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

We find the same with metric integration. The mean length of trips in the ambient space increases as we move the object from corner to centre. If we change the shape of the object from square to rectangular while conserving the area, as in Figure 9, we find again that visual integration decreases and mean trip length increases, and again the pattern changes:

These effects can be explained easily by means of a diagram—Figure 10—and some simple calculations. As we move a partition in a line of cells from centre to edge, the total inter-visibility from each cell to all others increases, though of course the total area remains constant. So both this and inter-accessibility effect arise from the simple fact that to measure either we need to square the numbers of points on either side of the blockage (Hillier 2009). All we need to know is that twice the square of a number, n, will be a smaller number than (n-1)2 + (n+1)2:

2n2 < (n-1)2 + (n+1)2 (1)

We call these all-points-to-all-others-measures configurational metrics. We use them when instead of being interested in, say, the distance from a to b, we are interested in the distance, metric, visual or topological, from each point or element in the system to all others. So we see that the configurational metrics we use in real human space are not the same as geometry and in fact behave in a quite different, though still lawful, way.

These simple laws have some highly interesting effects. They mean that a large space and a small space are, from the point of view of intervisibility

Fig. 9

Decrease of

visual integration

due to changing

the shape of an

object placed

within a bounded

square space.

1.39799 1.48587

263Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

within the spaces, ‘larger’ than two similarly sized spaces of equal total area, and that a long line and a short line are ‘longer’ than two lines of similar length and equal total length. They also mean that small blocks placed in the centre of a system are more integrating than small blocks placed on the edge of the system. All these lawful phenomena are found pervasively in cities. The laws are, we believe, intuitively known to human beings in the sense, as we said, of ‘intuitive physics’. We feel the laws of physics in our minds—even in our arms—when we manipulate objects by throwing them or moving them. This could be shown by examining human spatial behav-iour and by spatial experimentation (Hillier 2009). But the most power-ful evidence that these laws are known to human beings comes from the degree to which evidence for them is found in the largest and most complex spatial objects that human beings make: cities. The fact is that in spite of the cultural differences we find in the forms of cities in different parts of the world, and in spite of the differences in the circumstances in which they are created, there is an underlying universal city made up of an astonishing range of invariants common to all cities.

Fig. 10 Increasing intervisibility from all points to all others

as a partition is moved from centre to edge.

Four points see four cells on both sides, so 2(4)2 = 32 or half (0.5) of the potential for 8 cells.

Five points see 5 cells on one side, and three see 3 on the other, so 52 + 32 = 34 or 0.53125 of the potential for 8 cells.

Six points see 6 cells on one side, and two see 2 on the other, so 62 + 22 = 40 or 0.625 of the potential for 8 cells.

Seven points see 7 cells on one side, and one sees 1 cell on the other, so 72 + 12 = 50 or 0.71825 of the potential for 8 cells.

Eight points see 8 cells, so 82 + 02 = 64 or all of the potential for 8 cells.

2n2 < (n-1)2 + (n+1)2

264 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

Cities as Spatial Configurations

To analyse a city spatially in syntactic terms means analysing its street network. But before we do so, simply by measuring and counting we can discover invariants. To illustrate this we can use arbitrarily selected areas of London and Toyko, both largely ‘organic’ cities, and about as far from each other in distance and socio-cultural background as it is possible for cities to be. By representing both as least line maps (the fewest lines that cover the network and make all connections) we find:• that at all scales, from local areas to whole cities, cities are made up of a

very small number of long lines and a very large number of short lines (Hillier 2002), so much so that in terms of the line length distributions in their least line maps cities have been argued to have scale-free properties (Carvalho & Penn 2004). This is just as true of more geometric cities such as Chicago and Athens, as it is for more ‘organic’ (meaning lacking obvious geometry) such as Tokyo or London,

• that in ‘organic’ cities (as defined above), the longer the line the more likely it is to be end-connected to another by a nearly straight connec-tion (between about 5 and 25 degrees), creating sequences of such lines, which the eye instinctively identifies when looking at the map, and the shorter the line the more likely it is to intersect with others at near right angles, creating local clusters of such lines. In more geometrical cities,

Fig. 11 Least line maps of areas of Tokyo (left) and London (right).

500 m 1000 m

265Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

a similar pattern can be found but with more often straight rather than nearly straight long lines,

• that through these metric and geometric regularities, cities’ street networks acquire a dual structure, made up of a dominant foreground network, marked by linear continuity (and so in effect route continuity) and a background network, whose more localised character is formed through shorter lines and less linear continuity.

Applying syntactic measures to least line maps of cities—in this case treat-ing the street segment between junctions as the spatial element and using least angle change, rather than simple metric distance as the measures of distance (since this has been shown to be how people read and move about in cities—see Hillier & Iida 2005), we bring to light further regularities. For example:• by measuring least angle integration (normalised mathematical ‘closeness’—

or more simply the relative accessibility of each street segment from all others) analysis without radius restriction (so the most ‘global’ form of the analysis), a dominant structure is identified approximating the form of what we call a deformed wheel, meaning a ‘hub’ of lines in the syntactic centres, strong ‘spokes’ linking centre to edge and strong ‘rim’ lines. Figure 12, for example, shows the underlying deformed wheel pattern in both metropolitan Tokyo (with multiple rims) and London within the M25.

Fig. 12 Least angle integration (normalised closeness) for metropolitan Tokyo (left) and

London within the M25 (right) in each case showing a variant of the ‘deformed

wheel’ structure, with multiple rims in the case of Tokyo.

266 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

The syntactic measure of least angle choice (mathematical ‘betweenness’, or the potential of each segment for through movement on routes from all segments to all others) then commonly identifies a network spread through the system, though strongest in the more syntactically central locations (see Figure 13). In other words, in spite of the differences in socio-economic and temporal circumstances in which cities grow, they seem to converge on com-mon generic forms which have metric, geometric and configurational prop-erties. However the similarities between cities does not stop there. On close examination, for example:• all cities seem to exhibit a property we call pervasive centrality, meaning that

‘central’ functions such as retail and catering concentrations diffuse through-out the network at all scales, from the city as a whole to the local network of streets. For example, Figure 14 is Mike Batty’s image of the 168 largest centres in London within the M25. By comparing Figure 14 to Figure 13 we find a strong ‘eyeball’ correspondence. However, the image also makes clear that the global properties shown in the map are not sufficient in themselves to identify the location of centres. We typically find for example that along the length of a high global movement potential alignment we find the centre occurring only in certain locations. For example, if we take the Edgeware Road between the North Circular Road and Oxford street, there are three high streets with the rest fairly free of shops. In each case, the centre occur where local grid intensification (a dense and smaller scale local grid) co-incides

Fig. 13 Least angle choice (betweenness) analysis of Tokyo (left) and London (right) showing

the network pattern in both cases.

267Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

with the globally strong alignment. The pattern is far more complex than en-visaged in theories of polycentrality. It is notable also that pervasive centrality seems spatially sustainable because it means that wherever you are you are close to a small centre and not far from a much larger one. (Hillier 2009)

If we reduce the radius of the measures we then find the—much more nu-merous—smaller scale centres. For example, at radius 750 metres, all of the ‘urban villages’ in a section of north west London are picked out in red.

Fig. 14

Mike Batty’s map

of the 168 main centres

and sub-centres in London

within the M25.

Fig. 15

Least angle through

movement potential at a

radius of 750 metres

in an area of north west

London with the

dark red lines picking out

the urban villages.

Fortune Green

West Hampstead

West Hampstead tube

Swiss Cottage

HampsteadSouth EndGreen

Pond Street

Belsize Park

Englands Lane

Regents Park Road

Belsize Village

Kilburn High Street

268 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

The regularities that we find in cities with least angle analysis suggest a new definition of the city. Cities of all kinds, however they originate, seem to evolve into a foreground network of linked centres at all scales, from a couple of shops and a café through to whole sub-cities, set into a background network of largely residen-tial space. The foreground network is made up of a relatively small number of longer lines, connected at their ends by open angles, and forming a super-ordinate structure within which we find the background network, made up of much larger numbers of shorter lines, which tend to intersect each other and be connected at their ends by near right angles, and form local grid like clusters. We suggest this is the proper generic definition of what a city is as a large object.

The Dual City of Economic and Social Forces

So what forces give the city this shape. We believe the answer lies in two key new phenomena which research using space syntax has brought to light. The first we call spatial emergence: the network of space that links the buildings together into a single system acquires emergent structure from the ways in which objects are placed and shaped within it. As we have seen, this process is law-governed, and without an understanding of these laws the spatial form of cities cannot really be deciphered. The second phenomenon is spatial agency: the emergent spatial structure in itself has lawful effects on the functional patterns of the city by, in the first instance, shaping movement flows, and, through this, emergent land use patterns, since these in their nature either seek or avoid movement flows. Through its influence on movement, the urban grid turns a collection of building into a living city. Movement is literally the lifeblood of the city. It is these two linked processes of spatial emergence and spatial agency that set in train the self-organising processes through which cities acquire their more or less universal spatial form.

What then drives these processes? In fact, the universal functional structure associated with the dual network suggests the answer. Within the envelope created by cognitive constraints—the need for the city to be intelligible in order to be usable at all (see Hillier 2009)—we can now see how economic and social forces put their different imprints on the city. The foreground struc-ture, the network of linked centres, has emerged to maximise grid-induced movement, driven by micro-economic activity. Micro-economic activity takes

269Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

a universal spatial form and this type of foreground pattern is a near-universal in self-organised cities. The residential background network is configured to restrain and structure movement in the image of a particular culture, and so tends to be culturally idiosyncratic, often expressed through a different geom-etry which makes the city as a whole look spatially different. The first is an instance of the generative use of space, since it aims to generate co-presence and make new things happen, and the second conservative since it aims to use space to reinforce existing features of society. In effect, the dual structure has arisen through different effects of the same laws governing the emergence of grid structure and its functional effects. In the foreground space is more random, in the background more rule-governed, so with more conceptual intervention.

We can illustrate this most clearly in a city with more than one culture (now unfortunately separated): Nicosia (Figure 16). Top right is the Turkish quarter, bottom left the Greek quarter. Their line geometry is different. In the Turk-ish quarter, lines are shorter, their angles of incidence have a different range, and there is much less tendency for lines to pass through each other. Syntacti-cally, the Turkish area is much less integrated than the Greek area. We can also show that it is less intelligible, and has less synergy between the local and global aspects of space. Yet in spite of these strong cultural differences in the tissue of space, we still find Nicosia as a whole is held together by a clear deformed

Fig. 16

The old city of Nicosia

showing the deformed

wheel core in spite of

culturally differentiated

residential space.

270 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

wheel structure. This shows how micro-economic activity spatialises itself in a universal way to maximise movement and co-presence, while residence tends to reflect the spatial dimension of a particular culture, and the expression is in the first instance geometrical. Since residence is most of what cities are, this ‘cultural geometry’ tends to dominate our spatial impressions of cities.

Two Wittgensteinian Remarks

So we seem to have a theory of the city which links form to function, micro-structure to macrostructure, and differentiates between socio-cultural and micro-economic factors in creating the spatial form of the city. Have we then succeeded in our aim of creating a science of the non-discursive for space, and so emancipated ourselves from Wittgenstein’s strictures? There are two key issues. Does space have a formal unity (since there cannot be a science of space if it does not)? And have we described structure and function in spatial phenomena (since without this we cannot make predictions from theory)? Two Wittgensteinian remarks seem in order.

The first concerns the relation between the microeconomic and cultural aspects of urban form, as found in the foreground and background networks. The former seems to reflect the universals of human micro-economic behavior, the latter the relativity of human cultural behavior. Should we then see the ‘language of space’ as being composed of spatial games, or does it have ‘formal unity’ (to use Wittgenstein’s own expression in the Untersuchungen)?

In our view, the evidence indicates strongly that there is a single language of space and that it has formal unity because it is based on the underlying laws we have described. We would go farther and suggest that it is because the language of space is a formally unified language that differentiated cultural expression is possible. For example, the spatial and functional differences between the fore-ground and background grids arise because the laws governing the emergence of spatial patterns through the placing and shaping of buildings, and those link-ing patterns of space to patterns of movement and co-presence, are being used in different parts of the network to create different functional outcomes. Both are in this sense the expression of the same laws, but used in one case to maxi-mize movement and co-presence and in the other to restrict and structure it.

The same applies to the difference between background grids that we find in different cities, and even in the same city (as in the case of Nicosia). The

271Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

same spatial means are used to give different degrees and patterns of relative segregation. To put it at its simplest, the spatial language which permits the creation of patterns of integration also permits the creation of patterns of segregation. And because the language is unified in fact, we can use the same methodology to give parametric characterisations of different spatial cultures (Hillier 2002). Different cultures, in effect, are using the same language to say different things, rather than using different languages. We must conclude then that space as a language does have the formal unity that the later Wittgenstein denied for natural language.

The second Wittgensteinian remark concerns the near-invariant structures for cities which space syntax has brought to light. In what sense are these scientific entities? Here we do after all encounter a severe Wittgensteinian problem. Although the structures that we see by ‘colouring up’ maps undoubt-edly exist, in that they are in reality patterns of mathematical values whose correspondence with reality can be tested by observing and correlating them with function, there is no scientific way to describe the pattern itself. What we can do mathematically, of course, is to take the set of values and examine their distribution statistically. In this way we can discover, for example, that the distribution of the length of lines of sight and access in all cities is scale-free, meaning that at whatever scale we examine space, from a small area to the whole city, we will always find a fractal pattern with few long lines and many short lines. But analyses of this kind are statistical in nature and so operate in an abstract space, and make no mention of the actual patterns of connections of different kinds of line which give the city its structure. We can only show these patterns and wave our hand at them, and hope our audience will agree with the—usually metaphorical, such as ‘deformed wheel’—way we describe them. Remarkably, we are in effect in the same kind of mental position we were in with the word ‘between’. We can point to it and show it, but we cannot describe it within the formal language we have developed for space.

This is in fact a fundamental problem in the ‘sciences of complexity’. Everywhere in nature we find complex processes which generate simple emergent structures which then ‘forget’ the complexity of their creation and operate as autonomous relatively systems at the emergent level. As Cohen and Stewart (Cohen & Stewart 1993) argue: ‘We must … explain why, on every level of existence, we can deal with the world as though it were simple.’ In addressing complexity, they argue, science is asking the less interesting question. ‘The interesting question is precisely the opposite … where does the simplicity

272 Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

come from?’ These simple (in comparison to the processes that create them) emergent structures can be generated and identified, and their interactions studied, but their structures cannot yet be described in a rigorous scientific way.

The spatial structure of cities is a singularly clear example of this. The city structure evolves through a step by step bottom up process which we can more or less describe. But because the pattern of movement flows the structure generates reflects the global patterns of interconnectedness of spaces, not their local or intrinsic properties, we are compelled to acknowledge that the structure of the city works top down to set in train the functional processes which turn collections of buildings into living cities. Like so many emergent phenomena in nature, then, the structure of the city emerges bottom up, but works top-down. We can if we wish describe this structure by listing all the elements and connections, but this only re-describes the problem. It does not characterise the structure in such a way as to show what it is about this structure that works. So the structure that emerges and creates the living city we can only point to and say ‘look’. We are back, it seems, to the Tractatus!

273Showing Space, or: Can there be Sciences of the Non-Discursive?

Literature

Bloom, P., Petersen, M., Nadel, L. and Garrett M., (1996) Language and Space, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Bowman, M., (1996) ‘Learning how to structure space for language’, in P. Bloom, M. Petersen, L. Nadel and M. Garrett 1996. 385–436.

Carvalho, R., Penn, A., (2004) ‘Scaling and universality in the micro-structure of urban space’, in Physica A, 32, 539–547.

Cohen, J., Stewart, I. (1994) The Collapse of Chaos, Harmondsworth: Viking.Hillier, B., Hanson, J. (1984) The Social Logic of Space, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge

University Press.Hillier B., Hanson J., Graham H. (1987) ‘Ideas are in things: an application of the

space syntax method to discovering house genotypes’, in Environment and Planning B: Planning & Design,14, 363–385.

Hillier B., (1996) Space is the Machine, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Hillier B., (2002) ‘A theory of the city as object: how the social construction of urban

space is mediated by spatial laws’, in Urban Design International, 7, 3–4.Hillier, B., Iida, S. (2005) ‘Network and psychological effects in urban movement’, in

Cohn, A.G., Mark, D.M., eds., Spatial Information Theory: COSIT 2005 in Lecture Notes in Computer Science (LNCS) Volume 3693, 475–490. Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer.

Hillier B., (2009) ‘Studying cities to learn about minds’, in Environment and Planning B online.

Johnson-Laird P., (1996) ‘Space to think’, in P. Bloom, M. Petersen, L. Nadel and M. Garrett 1996.

Wittgenstein L., (1922) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (TLP), London: Routledge.Wittgenstein L., (1953) Philosophical Investigations (PI), Oxford: Blackwell (cited edition

Wiley-Blackwell 2009).

‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the

‘Epistemology of the Line’

Sybille Krämer, Berlin

‘The Mind’s Eye’ and Planarity

We live in a three-dimensional world; and yet, within this world we are sur-rounded by two-dimensional planes. We encounter them as images, book pages, displays, maps, movie screens, and computer screens. The fundamen-tal evolutionary logic of technical devices tends towards a ‘flattening out’; the end result of technological innovation is often the plane. Two-dimensional planes are ubiquitous; we are so familiar with them that we are hardly aware of the remarkable form of spatiality they constitute. Surfaces confront us as the outer skin of voluminous bodies; a ‘depth’ therefore always corresponds to a surface. A plane, however, is something extended without the dimen-sion of depth. Indeed, we treat surfaces as if they were planes. We do this especially when the function of a surface consists in rendering images or inscriptions visible. Their importance in carrying out this latter action cannot be overestimated: could the invention of the inscribed surface, we are tempted to ask, perhaps have meant for the mobility and creativity of the mind what the invention of the wheel meant for the mobility and productiv-ity of the human body?

What are the consequences for thought of introducing this artificial form of two-dimensional spatiality into the process of cognition? What does it mean for the acquisition and justification of knowledge?

Ever since the ‘iconic turn’1 challenged the claim to absolutism of the ‘linguis-tic turn’, it has been widely understood that images initiate not only æsthetic

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 275–293.

276 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

but also cognitive experience.2 This symposium also attends to the debate on epistemic intuition and visual thought. However, our focus in this paper lies less on visuality and iconicity per se, and more on the idea that both are necessarily linked to spatiality.3 We use spatial relations in order to depict epistemic, non-spatial states of affairs and to carry out palpable cognitive operations within those states. This offers a key to understanding the productivity of our think-ing in terms of the ‘extended mind’.4 Thus, we must examine iconicity both structurally, that is, as it is deployed through planar spatiality, and functionally, which is to say, in regard to its perceptive-tactile operativity. The ‘mind’s eye’ does not look behind appearances, it does not penetrate surfaces down to their hidden structures, but rather acts in cooperation with the writing and drawing hand upon the plane.

The Cartographic Impulse

Within the spectrum of knowledge-generating forms of visualisation, ranging from the X-ray to computer simulations, one subset, comprising notations, lists, tables, diagrams, graphs and maps, belongs in a category we may term ‘operative iconicity’5. We call this subset ‘the diagrammatical’; we call its members ‘inscriptions’. Its lowest common denominator is the inscribed plane that emerges from the interaction of point, line and plane. Out of this graphism arises what we will call the ‘epistemology of the line’.6 As we will see, this epistemology has important consequences for the subject at hand: the epistemic activity of the diagrammatical does not only charac-terise scientific knowledge, but also philosophy.7 What remains so far absent from the literature on epistemology is a reconstruction of the explicit and implicit diagrammatical dimensions of philosophy, which are not restricted, as is often assumed, to Charles Sanders Peirce.8 The following considerations are meant as a contribution to filling this absence. Their guiding hypothesis is that traces of a ‘cartographic impulse’ can be found even (or especially) within the tradition of philosophic reflection.

What, in turn, do we mean by ‘cartographic impulse’? To clarify this question, let us consider the peculiar representational conditions of maps.9

Through mapping, a three-dimensional territory that is largely difficult to view as a whole is translated into a readily comprehensible, two-dimensional plane. A real space of our lifeworld is transformed into the virtual space of

277‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

a topographical map.10 To accomplish this, a number of conceptual steps must be taken: first, the mapmaker must examine his subject from a highly external point of view, one that makes an overview possible in the first place. Then, a method of projection as well as a scale must be chosen. The purpose of the map is to make an unfamiliar terrain accessible to a user as a space of movement and action. This is, however, only possible through indexicality: by means of indexicality, a real person, a user, can transform him- or herself into a virtual point on the map. Only when this latter condition is fulfilled does the map become not only a representational object, but also an instrument for orienting oneself for action.

We thus encounter a decisive difference between two modalities of space in the use of maps: the difference between a virtual configurative space and a real action space. The map itself is exemplary of a configurative space in which places are arranged by their topographical order and determined by their relations to other places. The synchronic, synoptic nature of a configura-tive space presumes that the user’s position is outside of the configuration. But a map enables its users to act in the real space of the lifeworld. The ac-tion space comes into being by means of these activities, performed by the user, who has now also become a participant within the space. It is brought forth by the movements of actors and for its duration remains limited to the comple-tion of these actions. Orienting oneself with maps using virtual, two-dimensional configurations makes real, three-dimensional spaces of movement accessible. The symbolic configuration space that a map provides is meant to be trans-formed into a real space of activity. This also means that something is a map only when it is in use, only as the means of transforming arrangements into move-ments. Otherwise, the map remains merely an image, a structural picture.

Thus, when we speak of a ‘cartographic impulse’ in philosophical and epistemic respects, we mean graphic arrangements that can be transformed into a space of intellectual activity. Cognition is thus conceivable as spatially-oriented movement. Hence Kant’s provocative question: What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking? 11

Epistemology of the Line

How, then, do diagrammatical arrangements manage not only to represent space, but also to produce movements of thought within it? In order to answer

278 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

this question, we must clarify what ‘epistemology of the line’12 means. Let us recall that diagrammatical inscriptions, including notations, tables, graphs, diagrams, and maps, are based on the interaction of point, line and plane. In the following, we will concentrate on the line, although these considerations are also applicable to the phenomenon and concept of the point.

Considerable epistemic potential is already nested within the simple act of drawing a line. This potential reveals itself in two binary oppositions: it is at once sensual and non-sensual; it is both a dependent trace and a free design. These seeming paradoxes merit more detailed description:

(i) Perceptible/intelligible: The stroke on the page is perceptible; it is virtually two-dimensional; the subtle individual characteristics of the line’s course carry æsthetic weight. Yet within a schema of notation, dia-gram, or map, the stroke is valued as a one-dimensional line, representing a state that is therefore not perceptible, but rather only intelligible or ideal. Idealisation and flattening out are closely related. In the empirical stroke, we see a non-empirical line; in a phenomenon, we see a concept. The activity of the ‘mind’s eye’13 depends upon this ‘seeing-in’. It is connected with the tactile handling of the continuous line: perceptivity and tactility are combined.

(ii) Trace and Outline: The stroke is the result of a gesture; the succes-sion of a temporal action is carried over into the simultaneity of a spatial structure. As a trace of a gesture, the line has the potential to be deter-mined and to become the image of something. At the same time, the stroke is always a free form with which a ‘Not-Yet’ can be conceptualised, plans can be made, or something unreal or even impossible can be drawn up. Heteronomy and autonomy are combined: transmission and creativity are intertwined in the line’s productivity.

It is in embodying these functions that the line acquires its epistemic signifi-cance. In the tension between the hand that does and the eye that sees, the stroke constitutes the elementary action of operative iconicity. The plane of inscrip-tion creates a space for the movement of thought in which theoretical enti-ties are made visible and thus manageable. The perceptual nature of this act may be described as suddenly being able to see a non-empirical state of affairs within empirical arrangements. With regard to tactility, it means that operations of configuring and reconfiguring graphical markings simultaneously carry out

279‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

ideal/intellectual operations. The interstitial world of planar inscriptions medi-ates between intuition and thought; it intellectualises intuition and sensualises thinking. In brief: we think on paper.

Plato’s Simile of the Divided Line

Let us put our theoretical considerations to a practical test by attempting to reconstruct the diagrammatical structure of some instances of philosophical thought. We will demonstrate that the cartographic impulse and the space produced diagrammatically for the movement of thinking are both opera-tive phenomena within philosophy; we will show how they are put into place within the structure of thought. We shall begin with Plato and then proceed to Wittgenstein.

In the Republic (Politeia, 509d–511e), Plato develops what is known as the ‘Simile of the Divided Line’, in which Socrates orders the ontologi-cal structure of the world according to a relationship between original and image, further organizing this into sub-categories by degrees of knowability. To reproduce this structure, one must draw a line and divide it into two unequal sections, such that the smaller section depicts the visible and the larger section the intelligible. These two sections should then each be re-divided in the same proportion as the original division. A four-part division of realms of being is thus created, which at the same time embodies a series of levels of cognitive knowledge with a progressively increasing degree of theoretical clarity.

Within the region of the visible, the lowermost realm is comprised of im-ages, shadows and reflections, which correspond to the epistemic state eikasia, that is, conjecture. The next section of the visible encompasses the originals of these copies, the objects, plants and animals. The cognitive activity corre-sponding to these is pistis, faith or belief. Together, these two levels form the domain of ‘doxa’, that is, opinion. In the third subsection, which opens up the realm of the intelligible and thus of the ‘episteme’, reside general concepts and mathematical objects. The form of knowledge here is dianoia, that is, reasoning. The fourth section, in turn, is concerned with ideas as true being understood through noesis, the act of pure reason, which for Plato constitutes the highest form of understanding.

We must now take a closer look at the third level, where Plato locates mathematical objects, for him the proto-form of all scientific objects. As Plato

280 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

characterizes this form of cognizance, mathematicians use visible objects as images representing invisible ideas: while mathematical speech and proofs necessarily refer to perceptible figures such as particular circles or numbers, they deal not with these concrete figures, but rather with the general con-cepts ‘circle’ or ‘number’, which are themselves not visible, but rather purely intelligible. The form of cognizance of dianoia treats the visible as the percep-tible imaging of something that is purely intelligible. It is thus the distinctive feature of mathematical knowledge to depend indispensably on the sensory representation of its theoretical objects and at the same time always to remain conscious of the difference between the intuitive and the purely intelligible. This prevents images from becoming illusions.

In all modern editions, Plato’s Simile of the Divided Line appears only in verbal description. But perhaps the oldest extant copy of the Republic, con-tained in a manuscript held in Paris,14 does in fact contain a diagrammatic representation of Socrates’ four divisions of knowledge.

Three aspects of Plato’s use of images are instructive from a diagramma-tological perspective.(1) Iconicity as ontological principle: In contrast to the hostility towards images

often attributed to Plato, and to which philosophy’s larger suspicion of images was casually able to attach itself, it must be noted that iconicity is in fact the inner principle of Platonic ontology and epistemology. For Plato, everything that is real is defined by its capacity to be depicted by images. Even the highest level of being —the Forms —are introduced as originals, and thus as templates, for pictorial copies. Degrees of reality are held up against the measuring stick of the original-copy relationship. Correspondingly, Plato first introduced to philosophy the term theoria, which originally meant ‘viewing of a festive performance.’15

(2) Differentiation between the visible and the intelligible; bridging of this differ-entiation: Plato differentiates categorically between the perceptible and the intelligible, and thereby introduces a distinction that was for 2000 years to form the lifeblood of philosophy. The Simile of the Divided Line inaugurates this differentiation. At the same time, however, it identifies an area of epistemic activity —dianoia, characteristic of mathematics and the sciences —in which this difference is intentionally bridged, in that sen-sory objects are recognized as depicting the non-sensory. Decisive here is the fact that the sensory objects deployed in thinking are neither a final product nor an end-stage, but rather are passed through en route to

281‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

that which is not perceptible, but rather only intelligible. The bridging function of this third level, conceived of as an ‘interstitial world’, is the enabling factor behind movements of thought.

(3) Spatiality of thinking: Plato views cognizance as an activity characterized by an implicit spatiality. Thinking is directional; this direction is defined by the cartographically arranged space of the Simile of the Divided Line and can be characterized as an ascent, that is, a rise through ascending levels. Thus is the Allegory of the Cave in the next book of the Republic a continuation of the Simile of the Divided Line by other means:16 it visualizes not abstract lines but rather the concrete situation of a cave, and knowledge is here imagined as an ascent out of the cave and into daylight. This inherent spatiality corresponds to the methodical man-ner in which Plato, in the act of applying his own approach, deploys configurations of lines to visualize his own philosophy.17 In this regard, we can infer from the spatial-visual arrangement and extension of line segments their ontological and epistemic meanings. For Plato himself, the diagrammatic scene becomes the medium of philosophical insight. The diagram functions as an instrument for making evident a philosophical world-image.

Possible Connections

It is no coincidence that Plato’s visualisation of a philosophical world image is paralleled slightly later by the drawing of a geographical world image by the Greek mathematician, astronomer, and geographer Ptolemy. Ptolemy left a Guide to Geography (‘Geographiké’)18 which is deeply instructive in its diagram-matics. It contains, for example, a map that depicts the entire known world from an external observational standpoint —an achievement made possible only by the innovative conical projection method Ptolemy himself developed. He also introduced lines of latitude and longitude to form a homogenising system of geographical coordinates. The majority of his Atlas was created from one table, which indicated the respective degrees of longitude and lati-tude for 8000 localities. The world was thus depicted as a planar distribution of places arranged in a numerically determinable relation to one another. As there was no reliable process for reproducing maps in antiquity, Ptolemy developed a ‘do-it-yourself ’ method: he designed a rubric for travellers

282 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

to make their own maps. Based on his written table and innovative pro-jection method, every reader was able, at least in theory, to draw a map corresponding to his desired itinerary. Ptolemy’s work traverses various forms of diagrammatical representation: it is variously embodied in geometrical drawings, written-out tabulations of locations and pictorial maps. At the same time, his Guide to Geography does not simply embody an image of the world, but rather serves as an operation manual for producing world images.

The relationship between philosophy and geography has been little analysed. In passing we can briefly mention that placed next to the ancient parallel between Ptolemy and Plato, the Early Modern duo of Mercator and Descartes is no less instructive. It is unfortunately beyond the scope of this paper to explore the many correspondences between their work.

Wittgenstein

We shall now jump across the centuries to Wittgenstein. Is there a carto-graphic impulse articulated in Wittgenstein’s thought as well? And can its presence shed an instructive light on Wittgenstein’s way of thinking?

Let us summarise a few relevant points already well-known to students of Wittgenstein’s work. (i) Having studied engineering, Wittgenstein was conversant with technical drawing, and thus with the projection of the three-dimensional onto the two-dimensional.19 Wittgenstein’s training in draft-ing can be traced back to his schooldays.20 (ii) There is a vast number of sketches, schemata, drawings, diagrams, and figures in his ‘Nachlass’.21 (iii) Concepts of the visual constitute his basic conceptual repertoire. He is widely considered to have been a ‘visual thinker’ who assigned the role of providing evidence to the pictorial; he always treated philosophical problems graphi-cally.22 (iv) His reflections have for many scholars formed the basis of a ‘logic of the visual’.23

In brief: the extraordinary (indeed, eminent) role played by iconicity in Wittgenstein’s thought has been explored in multiple ways. So what contribu-tion can the identification of a cartographic impulse in his thinking add to all of this?

We assume that this impulse, understood in an epistemic sense, consists in transforming a graphic configurative space into a space for the actions of thinking. In fact, the relation between arrangements and intelligible activity

283‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

in Wittgenstein’s philosophical work plays a role that we can roughly express like this: thinking takes place in operating with and looking at configurations. We shall explain the connection between ‘seeing a configuration’ and ‘think-ing’ by means of two examples. The first refers to the relationship between seeing and thinking in the so-called change of aspect.24 The second refers to the relationship between different periods of Wittgenstein’s thinking.

(1) Change of Aspect: By famously invoking the duck-rabbit optical illu-sion, Wittgenstein is not attempting anything as ambitious as explicating a theory of perception. Instead, he wishes to show how complex our use of the word ‘see’ is: for that which occurs during aspect seeing is “half visual experience, half thought.”25 There are many versions of this duck-rabbit figure; Wittgenstein uses a simple line drawing derived from Jastrow. The drawing is not altered during the changing of aspect. But what is crucial here is that as the observer turns the figure over, he or she is connected to a reconfiguration of its spatial orientation. As a duck-schema—following the direction of the beak—the picture is oriented to the left: the point that marks the duck’s eye looks out to the left margin. As a rabbit-schema, the beak becomes the ears and the alignment is precisely the opposite: the point of the rabbit’s eye points to the image’s right margin. The change in aspect draws upon the fact that the inscribed surface contains in each case the alignment’s opposite orientation. For Wittgenstein, the role of thinking is embodied during the change of aspect by the moment of its transfiguration. This turning over is that which we cannot quite see; rather, we slip into the invisible domain of thought. Thinking is analogous to the act of spatially re-orienting the two-dimensional space of optical illusion. Could we perhaps say that philosophical thinking is analogous to the act of re-orienting oneself ?

We thus see that Wittgenstein’s schema —functioning as a visual alignment inserted into the flow of his text —opens up a space of intellectual operation in which the reader can perform a distinct cognitive act: we see the aspect, but we perform the change of aspect without actually seeing the change. For this reason, the flip-flop-picture is more than an explanation of ‘seeing-as’. In addition, it evokes an epistemic ‘seeing-in’.26 The reader should expe-rience in the drawing the insight that seeing and thinking are connected and thus understand the complexity of the grammar of ‘seeing’. We see in

284 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

the optical illusion an ambiguous drawing, which should make evident the impossibility of being able to see the change of aspect itself. As paradoxical as this appears to be, Wittgenstein demonstrates with his duck-rabbit figure what cannot be rendered visible—and this is precisely what is characteristic of the epistemic handling of diagrammatic inscriptions that we have speci-fied as a ‘seeing of the conceptual in graphical configurations.’ Incidentally, in his Simile of the Divided Line, Plato has already named this ‘making visible of the invisible’: it is the epistemic device ‘dianoia’, which is put into place when, for example, the mathematician sees an inextensible point represented within an empirical one.

(2) The Relationship of the Early and Later Wittgenstein. The Wittgen-stein of the Tractatus behaves like a logical cartographer of the world. With the aid of the picture theory of the proposition27 and nourished by an inter-nal inclination toward a structure in which thought, proposition, and world intersect, he gives us the world as an intuited—albeit limited—whole.28 The spatial positioning is in this case the vertical; it embodies that one correct per-spective in which the world and our model of the world become congruent. In contrast, the Wittgenstein of the Philosophical Investigations behaves like an ethnographer of our forms of life; he only reaches insights when he exchanges his standpoint as an observer for a participatory perspec-tive. The spatial positioning is in this case the horizontal, in which the world is encountered as a multitude of heterogeneous language games and life forms, which amongst themselves cannot be hierarchically ordered.29 They can only be represented as a synoptic plurality —‘sketches of a landscape’ that come into the world on ‘these long and meandering journeys’.30 In the Tractatus, model and world coincide; in the Philosophi-cal Investigations, the ‘sketches of landscapes’ cannot be made congruent amongst themselves. Thus it only remains to order them in the form of an ‘album’.31 The world becomes a continual change of aspect between various two-dimensionally ordered world images.

This distinction between Wittgenstein’s early vertical perspective and his later participatory, horizontal perspective is illuminating. Nevertheless, it is apparent that Wittgenstein, in describing representations that depend upon the participatory perspective within an action space, always returns to the idea of ‘sketches of landscapes’ that must be arranged as an ‘album’. It is

285‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

thus our assumption that Wittgenstein never broke away from the diagram-matical32 synopticity33 that was the nucleus of his interest in the pictorial. His debt to the spatiality of the planar, which we can understand as the phenom-enology of everything pictorial, manifests itself as a diagrammatical trace in Wittgenstein’s pronounced philosophical renunciation of ‘depth’.

We wish to clarify Wittgenstein’s renunciation of the dimension of depth using two examples: first, his concept of the ‘perspicuous representation’ (‘übersichtliche Darstellung’) and secondly, his approach to formalism.

(i) Wittgenstein favours the idea of ‘perspicuous representation’34 as well as that of morphological procedure.35 Descriptions take the place of expla-nations36 because phenomena are synoptically aligned and therefore their relationship can only be visualised by the gradual appearance among them of a figure, form or pattern. In other words, to describe is to make visible by way of alignment. Hence Wittgenstein’s injunction: ‘don’t think, but look!’37 Certainly, there are different kinds of groupings and—returning to Goethe—Wittgenstein assumes that one possibility for alignment con-sists in finding a standard of comparison or paradigm in relation to which all remaining phenomena can be ordered according to their similarity or dissimilarity. The scale of the ideal against which all other phenomena are measured is thus not independently inferred, but rather stems direct-ly from the circle of appearances. Which morphological relationship is produced depends upon which phenomenon is chosen as a standard of comparison. Clearly, on the horizon of this morphological process, there is no longer any gradation between essence and appearance, between ideals and realisations, between surfaces and deep structures. Wittgenstein cites Goethe approvingly: ‘Don’t look for anything behind the phenomena; they themselves are the theory’.38

(ii) A recurring impulse in Wittgenstein is the renunciation of hierarchisation.39 It is present in his rejection of Bertrand Russell’s theory of types, insofar as this theory falls back upon the linguistic hierarchy of languages. It also appears in his critical discussion of Gottlob Frege’s concept of ‘meaning’: for Wittgenstein, the meaning of a sign does not exist as an entity beyond or behind the sign, but rather lies exclusively in its use.40 Above all, the paradigmatic orientation toward planarity manifests itself in its relation to mathematics, which he interprets in terms of sign-games41 which are nonetheless embedded, applicable, and useful in everyday life; they mani-

286 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

fest themselves in his dismissal of the descriptive character of mathemati-cal language, which he notably interprets as normative.42 All computation and proof is based on procedures of sign-transformation, which are made visible as planar configurations of figurative character.43 Proofs are repro-ducible pictures whose notable feature is in turn their ‘perspicuity’.44

The rejection of the dimension of depth and hierarchisation represents Wittgenstein’s proximity to formalism;45 and this proximity does not only relate to mathematics, but also reveals a main feature of his entire philoso-phy. Wittgenstein is a thinker of flat ontology and planar epistemology; this is perhaps the most radical form of realizing the ‘cartographic impulse’ within philosophy.

Summary

(i) Diagrammatic inscriptions in the form of notations, tables, graphs, diagrams, and maps belong to the domain of visual language. They are as significant for the working of the ‘extended mind’ as auditory language. Epistemic connections are ‘translated’ into spatial relations and constituted at the same time. ‘Mind’ comes into being in the interaction of eye, hand and brain.

(ii) Point, line and plane constitute the elementary repertoire of graphematics. They produce a two-dimensional configurative space that can be implemented as a space for the movements of thought. Cognition is oriented by thinking on paper. Diagrammatic inscriptions serve not only to represent and communicate epistemic states of affairs, but also to produce and explain them.

(iii) The epistemology of the line is based upon the double life of the line: the empirical stroke is perceptible, the one-dimensional line is merely con-ceivable. Based on this dual character of the sensual/intelligible, the lines of two-dimensional planes become the ‘place’ in which the difference between intuition and thought are both produced and bridged.

(iv) The metamorphosis of configurative spaces into movement spaces is called a ‘cartographic impulse’. The conversion of graphematic structural

287‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

spaces into spaces for the activity of thought is a central aspect of our reasoning acts. While the role of notational and graphical inscriptions in the sciences has been repeatedly explored both historically and systemati-cally, a diagrammatological reconstruction of philosophy—with the excep-tion of Peirce—is still needed. Plato, Aristotle, Nicholas of Cusa, Descartes, Leibniz, Lambert, Kant, Peirce, Wittgenstein and Deleuze, among others, will be crucial for this reconstruction.

(v) With his Simile of the Divided Line (Politeia, 509d – 511e), Plato demon-strates the epistemic signature of his ontology by means of a proportioned line. Cognition is specified in terms of spatial ascent. Although Plato’s philos-ophy locates the essential beyond appearance, his Simile of the Divided Line imagines the perceptible and the intelligible by means of the homogeneous line on one plane, allowing the gap between them to be bridged by ‘dianoia’ —scientific understanding that uses the visible as an image of the intelligible. The cartographic impulse takes Plato ‘beyond Plato’.

(vi) Wittgenstein is an anti-Platonist: for him there is no difference between essence and appearance. Wittgenstein’s ontology is ‘flat’; his representation is pervaded by characteristics of visual-projective thought, which he had first encountered in his engineering studies. For him, ‘cognition’ is the way in which phenomena are ordered and depicted via projection and arranged in perspicuous representations. Nevertheless, he concedes in his remarks on the optical illusion of the duck-rabbit that cognition is associated with that which remains invisible —in this particular case, the moment of the change in aspect itself. To articulate it paradoxically: within the diagrammatic scene, Wittgenstein makes visible not what is invisible, but rather an invisibility.

288 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

Notes

1 Boehm 2001; Mitchell 2008.2 Earnshaw 1992; Heintz/Huber 2001; Lynch 1998; Tufte 1997.3 Châtelet 2000, 38 ff.; Summers 2003, 43 ff.4 Clark/Chalmers 1998: Clark 2008.5 Krämer 2009, 114–115.6 Krämer 2010. 7 Gehring/Keutner et al. (eds.) 1992.8 On Peirce: Stjernfelt 2000; Stjernfelt 2007.9 Krämer 2008, chapter 18: Karten, Kartieren, Kartographie 298–337.10 ‘Real space is the space we find ourselves sharing with other people and things;

virtual space is space represented on a surface, space we “seem to see”.’ Summers 2003, 43.

11 Kant 1977.12 See Krämer 2010. 13 Krämer (forthcoming) ‘The eye of the mind’.14 Information by Dieter Harlfinger, Director of the Aristotle Archive, Freie Univer-

sität Berlin. Reference to the manuscript: Cod. Gr. 1807, f22r.15 ‘Theoros’ originally means: The envoy of the polis to take part in religious celebra-

tions and oracles: König 1998, 1128. 16 Platon, Republica VII, 514–519.17 See also: Menon 82b–84c und 86e–87a, Theaitet 147c–148d, Politikos 266b.18 Ptolemaios 2006.19 König 2000.20 Hamilton 2001.21 Wittgenstein 2000; Nyíri 2004.22 Blich 1987, 284 f.; Gessmann 2009, 157 ff.; Mersch 2006, 925; Nyíri 2004, 110 ff.;

Kunzmann 1998, 126 ff.23 Mersch 2006; Mersch in Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 1,

Proceedings of the 33rd International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner (Frankfurt: ontos Verlag, 2011), 257–287.

24 Krämer 2009, 114–115.25 Wittgenstein 1984, I, 524. But also: ‘Kann ich beim Aufleuchten des Aspekts ein

Seherlebnis von einem Denkerlebnis trennen? – Wenn Du es trennst, dann scheint das Aufleuchten des Aspekts verloren zu gehen.’ Wittgenstein, 1984, VII, § 564, 423.

289‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

26 To the ‘seeing in’: Wollheim 1982, 205–226; Seel 2000, 284.27 Stenius 1969; Stenius 1975.28 Wittgenstein 1984, I, Tractatus 6.45.29 Krämer 2001, 111–121.30 Wittgenstein 1984, I, Philosophische Untersuchungen, Vorwort, 231 f.31 Wittgenstein 1984, I, Philosophische Untersuchungen, Vorwort, 232.32 To this ‘diagramatical character’ of Wittgenstein’s picture theory: Mersch 2006;

Schneider 2005.33 For the ‘synopticity’: Plaud 2010a, 256–257.34 Wittgenstein 1967; Wittgenstein I, Philosophische Untersuchungen § 122, 302.

See: Hacker 2004; Puhl 2001; Puhl 2006; Schulte 1989, 108–112. 35 To the morphological method and Wittgenstein’s relation to Goethe: Krämer

2001, 111–114; Plaud 2010b; Rowe 1991; Schulte 1984.36 ‘Und wir dürfen keinerlei Theorie aufstellen. Es darf nichts Hypothetisches in un-

sern Betrachtungen sein. Alle Erklärung muß fort, und nur Beschreibung an ihre Stelle treten.’ Wittgenstein 1984, I, Philosophische Untersuchungen § 109, 298f.

37 Wittgenstein 1984, I, Philosophische Untersuchungen § 66, 277.38 Wittgenstein 1984, VII, Bemerkungen über die Philosophie der Psychologie § 889, 163.39 Wittgenstein 1984, I, Philosophische Untersuchungen § 89, 291.40 Wittgenstein 1984, VI, Bemerkungen über die Grundlagen der Mathematik, Teil I, §§ 19 ff.;

Teil V §§ 2, 257 ff.41 ‘Wenn wir jedoch irgendetwas, das das Leben des Zeichens ausmacht, benennen

sollten, so würden wir sagen müssen, daß es sein Gebrauch ist.’ Wittgenstein 1984, V, Das Blaue Buch, 20.

42 ‘In der Mathematik ist alles Algorismus, nichts Bedeutung.’ Wittgenstein 1984, IV, Philosophische Grammatik, 468. To the normativity of mathematical language: Kroß ed. 2008; Ramharter/Weiberg 2006; Weiberg 2008.

43 ‘Der Beweis […] ist eine Figur, an deren einem Ende gewisse Sätze stehen und an deren anderen Ende ein Satz steht (den wir den ›bewiesenen‹ nennen).’ Wittgen-stein 1984, VI, Bemerkungen zu den Grundlagen der Malthematik, I, § 28, 48.

44 ‘›Ein mathematischer Beweis muß übersichtlich sein.‹ »Beweis« nennen wir nur eine Struktur, deren Reproduktion eine leicht lösbare Aufgabe ist. […] Der Beweis muß ein Bild sein, welches sich mit Sicherheit genau reproduzieren läßt.’ Wittgen-stein 1984, VI, Bemerkungen zu den Grundlagen der Mathematik, III, § 1, 143 .—To the surveyability and formalism of proof: Mühlhölzer 2005.

45 Mühlhölzer 2008.

290 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

Literature

Blich, Ben Baruch. 1987. ‘ “Natural kinds” as a kind of family resemblance’, Proceedings of the 12th International Wittgenstein symposium (August 1987): 285–289.

Boehm, Gottfried (ed.). 1994. Was ist ein Bild?, third edition (München: Fink, 2001), originally published in 1994.

Châtelet, Gilles. 2000. Figuring Space: Philosophy, Mathematics, and Physics (Dordrecht et al.: Kluwer, 2000).

Clark, Andy. 2008. ‘Pressing the Flesh: A Tension in the Study of the Embodied, embedded Mind?’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVI, No.1, 2008: 37–59.

Clark, Andy/Chalmers, David J.. 1998. ‘The extended mind’, Analysis 58 (1) (1998): 10–23.

Gehring, Petra/Keutner, Thomas et al. (eds.). 1992. Diagrammatik und Philosophie (Am-sterdam: Rodopi ,1992).

Earnshaw, Rae A. and Norman Wiseman. 1992. An Introduction Guide to Scientific Visuali-zation (New York: Springer, 1992).

Gessmann, Martin. 2009. Wittgenstein als Moralist. Eine medienphilosophische Relektüre (Bielefeld: transcript 2009).

Hacker, Peter M. S.. 2004. ‘Übersichtlichkeit und übersichtliche Darstellung’, Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 52.3 (2004): 405–420.

Hamilton, Kelly. 2001. ‘Wittgensteins and the Mind’s Eye’, in Wittgenstein. Biography and Philosophy, edited by J. C. Klagge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 53–97.

Heintz, Bettina/Huber, Jörg (eds.). 2001. Mit dem Auge denken. Strategien der Sichtbar-machung in wissenschaftlichen und virtuellen Welten (Zürich: Edition Voldemeer; Wien/New York: Springer, 2001).

Kant, Immanuel. 1977. ‘Was heißt: sich im Denken orientieren?’, Werke in 12 Bänden, Bd. 5, (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1977), 267–286.

König, Wolfgang. 2007. ‘Die Technische Hochschule Berlin, die Studienstätte des jun-gen Wittgenstein’, in Ludwig Wittgenstein. Ingenieur – Philosoph – Künstler, edited by G. Abel, M. Kroß, and M. Nedo (Berlin: Parerga, 2007).

Krämer, Sybille. 1991. Berechenbare Vernunft. Kalkül und Rationalismus im 17. Jahrhundert (Berlin/New York: de Gruyter, 1991).

Krämer, Sybille. 2006. Sprache – Sprechakt – Kommunikation. Sprachtheoretische Positionen im 20. Jahrhundert, third edition (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2006), originally published in 2001.

291‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

Krämer, Sybille. 2008. Medium, Bote, Übertragung. Kleine Metaphysik der Medialität (Frank-furt a. M.: Suhrkamp 2008).

Krämer, Sybille. 2009. ‘Operative Bildlichkeit. Von der “Grammatologie” zu einer “Diagrammatologie”? Reflexionen über erkennendes “Sehen” ’, in Logik des Bildli-chen. Zur Kritik der ikonischen Vernunft, edited by Martina Hessler, and Dieter Mersch (Bielefeld: transcript, 2009), 114–115.

Krämer, Sybille. 2010. ‘ “Epistemology of the line”. Reflections on the diagrammatical mind’, in Studies in Diagrammatology and Diagram Praxis (= Logic and Cognitive Sys-tems, Studies in Logic 24), edited by O. Pombo, and A. Gerner (London: College Publications, 2010), 13–39.

Krämer, Sybille. Forthcoming. ‘The “eye of the mind” and the eyes of the body: Des-cartes and Leibniz on truth, mathematics and visuality’, in Sensory Perception. Mind and Matter, edited by Friedrich G. Barth, P. Giampieri-Deutsch, and H. D. Klein (Wien/New York: Springer, forthcoming).

Kroß, Matthias (ed.). 2008. Ein Netz von Normen’. Wittgenstein und die Mathematik (Berlin: Parerga, 2008).

Kroß, Matthias. 2008. ‘Vorwort’, in ‘Ein Netz von Normen’. Wittgenstein und die Mathematik, edited by M. Kroß (Berlin: Parerga, 2008), 7–16.

Kunzmann, Peter. 1998. Dimension von Analogie. Wittgensteins Neuentdeckung eines klassischen Prinzips (Düsseldorf/Bonn: Parerga, 1998).

Lynch, Michael P.. 1998. Truth in Context: An Essay on Pluralism and Objectivity, (Cam-bridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1998).

McGinn, Marie. 1997. Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations (London: Routledge, 1997).

Mersch, Dieter. 2006. ‘Wittgensteins Bilddenken’, Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 54, 6 (2006): 925–942.

Mitchell, William. 2008. Bildtheorie, edited by Gustav Frank (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp 2008).Mühlhölzer, Felix. 2006. ‘ “A mathematical proof must be surveyable”—What Witt-

genstein meant by this and what it implies’, Grazer Philosophische Studien 71 (2006): 57–86.

Mühlhölzer, Felix. 2008. ‘Wittgenstein und der Formalismus’, in ‘Ein Netz von Normen’. Wittgenstein und die Mathematik, edited by Matthias Kroß (Berlin: Parerga, 2008), 107–148.

Nemeth, Elisabeth. Heinrich, Richard and Pichler, Wolfram (eds.). 2010. Bild und Bildlichkeit in Philosophie, Wissenschaft und Kunst, Beiträge des 33. Internationalen Wittgenstein Symposiums 8–14. 8. 2010 (Die Österreichische Ludwig Wittgenstein Gesellschaft: Kirchberg am Wechsel, 2010).

292 ‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

Nyíri, Kristóf. 2002. ‘Pictures as Instruments in the Philosophy of Wittgenstein’, in Wittgenstein und die Zukunft der Philosophie; Akten des 24. Internationalen Wittgenstein-Symposiums, edited by R. Haller, and K. Puhl (Wien: öbv&hpt, 2002).

Nyíri, Kristóf. 2004. ‘Wittgensteins Philosophie der Bilder’, in Vernetztes Wissen, edited by K. Nyíri (Wien: Passagen, 2004).

Plato, ‘Menon’, in Platon. Werke in acht Bänden; Griechisch und Deutsch, Bd. 2, edited by Gunther Eigler (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1973), 82b–84c and 86e–87a.

Plato: ‘Politeia’, in Platon. Werke in acht Bänden; Griechisch und Deutsch, Bd. 4, edited by Gunther Eigler (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1971), VII, 514–519.

Plato, ‘Theaitos’, in Platon. Werke in acht Bänden; Griechisch und Deutsch Bd. 6, edited by Gunther Eigler (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1970), 147c–148d.

Plato, ‘Politikos’, in Platon. Werke in acht Bänden; Griechisch und Deutsch Bd. 6, edited by Gunther Eigler (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1970), 266b.

Plaud, Sabine. 2010a. ‘Picturing as Mapping: A mark of continuity in Wittgenstein’s notion of representation’, in Bild und Bildlichkeit in Philosophie, Wissenschaft und Kunst, Beiträge des 33. Internationalen Wittgenstein Symposiums 8–14. 8. 2010, edited by E. Nemeth, R. Heinrich, and W. Pichler (Die Österreichische Ludwig Wittgenstein Gesellschaft: Kirchberg am Wechsel, 2010), 256–258.

Plaud, Sabine. 2010b. ‘Synoptic Views vs. Primal Phenomena: Wittgenstein on Goethe’s Morphology’, in Wittgenstein: Issues and Debates, edited by J. Padilla Gálves and E. Lemaire (Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Verlag, 2010).

Ptolemaios, Klaudius. 2006. Handbuch der Geographie, edited by A. Stückelberger, and G. Graßhoff (Basel: Schwabe Basel, 2006).

Puhl, Klaus. 2001. ‘Geschichte und Ritual. Wittgenstein und Foucault über genetische Erklärungen kultureller Praktiken’, in Metaphysik im postmetaphysischen Zeitalter/Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age, edited by Uwe Meixner (Wien: öbv&hpt, 2001), 15–25.

Puhl, Klaus. 2006. ‘Only connect … Perspicious Representations and the Logic of “Nachträglichkeit”’, Grazer Philosophische Studien 71 (2006): 23–38.

Ramharter, Esther/Weiberg, Anja. 2006. ‘Die Härte des logischen Muß’. Wittgensteins Be-merkungen über die Grundlagen der Mathematik (Berlin: Parerga, 2006).

Rowe, M. W.. 1991. „Goethe and Wittgenstein“, Philosophy 66 (1991): 283–293.Schneider, Hans Julius. 2005. ‘Satz – Bild – Wirklichkeit’, in Wittgensteins ‘große Maschi-

nenschrift’, edited by Stefan Majetschak (Frankfurt et al.: Peter Lang, 2005), 78–98.

293‘The Mind’s Eye’: Visualizing the Non-visual and the ‘Epistemology of the Line’

Schulte, Joachim. 1984. ‘Chor und Gesetz. Zur “morphologischen Methode” bei Goethe und Wittgenstein’, Grazer Philosophische Studien 21 (1984): 1–32.

Schulte, Joachim. 1989. Wittgenstein. Eine Einführung (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1989).Seel, Martin. 2000. Ästhetik des Erscheinens (München, Wien: Hanser, 2000). Stenius, Eric. 1969. Wittgensteins Tractatus. A Critical Exposition of its Main Lines of Thought

(Westport: Greenwood Press, 1969).Stenius, Eric. 1975. ‘Die Bildtheorie des Satzes’, Erkenntnis, Vol. 9, 1 (1975): 35–55.Stjernfelt, Frederic. 2000. ‘Diagrams as Centerpiece of a Peircian Epistemology’,

Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. XXXVI, No. 3 (Summer 2000): 357–384.

Stjernfelt, Frederic. 2007. Diagrammatology. An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenol-ogy, ontology, and semiotics (Dordrecht: Springer, 2007).

Summers, David. 2003. Real Spaces. World Art History and the Rise of Western Modernism (London: Phaidon, 2003).

Tufte, Edward R.. 1997. Visual Explanations: Images and Quantities, Evidence and Narrative (Cheshire, CT: Graphics Press, 1997).

Weiberg, Anja. 2008. ‘Rechnung versus Experiment. Mathematische Sätze als gram-matische Sätze’, in ‘Ein Netz von Normen’. Wittgenstein und die Mathematik, edited by Matthias Kroß (Berlin: Parerga, 2008), 17–39.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1967. ‘Bemerkungen über Frazers “The Golden Bough” ’, Syn-these 17 (1967): 233–253.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1984. Werkausgabe in 8 Bänden, I–VIII (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1984).

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2000. Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition. (Ox-ford University Press, 2000).

Wollheim, Richard. 1982. Objekte der Kunst, translated by M. Looser (Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp 1982).

Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

Andreas Roser, Linz und Passau

Funktionalität und Gebrauch sind keine Synonyme. Nicht jeder Sprachge-brauch im Medium der Wortsprache ist funktional. Die Nichtfunktionalität der Wortsprache verweist auf Medienübergänge, Medienverbindungen und Funktionalitätsveränderungen in der Verwendung von Texten. Zweifel am Immanenzcharakter wortsprachlicher Medien sind aus mehreren Gründen angebracht: Wenn in der Wortsprache – wie Wittgenstein es mehrfach for-mulierte – „alles ausgetragen“ 1 werden könnte, dann wäre beispielsweise ein Bildmedium immer ein Werkzeug eines Textmediums. Dieser Hypothese wird hier widersprochen; unabhängig von der Frage, ob Wittgenstein der Annahme war, alle Medien seien für die Zwecke der Wortsprache instrumentalisierbar und auch unabhängig von der These, es werde „alles“ in der Wortsprache ausgetragen. Dass „alles“ in „der“ Sprache ausgetragen wird, wäre freilich we-nig zu bezweifeln, sofern wir wüssten, was „alles“ und was „die Sprache“ ist oder auch nur sein könnte. Es gibt etliche Belege für die These, Wittgenstein sei nicht der Auffassung gewesen, Fotos, Zeichnungen, oder musikalische Nota-tionen – um nur Beispiele zu nennen – seien Instrumente der Wortsprache. Es gibt allerdings Belege im Nachlass Wittgensteins, die auf die gegenteilige Annahme hinweisen. Insbesondere die Funktion vieler Piktogramme in Wittgensteins nachgelassenen Schriften lassen sich als Belege für die Instru-mentalisierungshypothese visueller Medien anführen; in vielen Fälle aller-dings sind es gerade diese Piktogramme, die auch als Belege der gegenteili-gen These verwendet werden und eine Autonomie visueller Medienelemente

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 295–304.

296 Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

anzeigen. Doch das Ziel dieses Vortrages ist nicht eine vorrangige Klärung exege-tischer Probleme in den Texten Wittgensteins, sondern eine medienanalytische Klärung der Frage, ob wir nichtverbale Medien als Instrumente der Wort-sprache verwenden.

Eines scheint vorab offenkundig zu sein: Verbale Beschreibungen ersetzen keine visuellen Kontexte. Ein Text funktioniert als Text im Medium der Texte. Ein Bild teilt sich im Medium der Bilder mit. Wir stellen mit visuellen Mitteln her, was mit Texten nicht herzustellen ist. Texte sind zwar immer auch visu-elle Elemente (darin liegt ihr extraverbaler Gebrauchsaspekt) aber sie funk-tionieren nicht wie Fotos oder Gemälde. Verhielte es sich anders, könnten wir Gemälde z. B. durch Bildbeschreibungen ersetzen und sie beispielsweise anstelle eines Gemäldes verkaufen. Das wäre zwar möglich, ist aber in der Praxis des Mediengebrauches nicht zu beobachten.

Umgekehrt gilt: Nichtverbale Medien verlieren ihre mediale Funktion in einem verbalen Medium. Mit Worten zu sagen, was nur Bilder unter Bildern auf die Weise eines Bildes mitteilen, wäre der Versuch, Bilder durch Texte zu substituieren. Bilder sind keine Instrumente der Wortsprache; ihre verbale Nichtfunktionalität überträgt sich auf Wort-Bild-Verbindungen. Das ist die These, die zu begründen sein wird. Die These kann darauf verweisen, dass ein Satz auch als visuelles Muster in einer Bildsprache Verwendung finden kann. Als Ornament unter anderen visuellen Mustern verliert ein Satz seine Funktion als Satz unter Sätzen. Der Funktionsverlust eines Satzes ist in diesem Fall aber kein Indikator für einen Gebrauchsfehler der Wortsprache, denn ein Fehler ist nur dort möglich, wo Texte auch Texte verantworten können.

Ein Bild berührt nicht, was in und mit einem Text geschieht, denn wir können aus einem Satz – mit den Mitteln der Wortsprache – keine logischen und grammatischen Regeln für den Umgang mit visuellen Medien ableiten. Ein Bild kann mit einem Text verbunden sein, was immer auch mit einem Satz geschehen mag, der dieses Bild beschreibt. Umgekehrt gilt dies auch von einem Text, der auf unterschiedlichste Weise illustriert werden kann. Weder das Bild noch der Text für sich garantieren eine Medienverbindung. Medienverbindungen sind keine funktionalen Verbindung der beteiligten Medien, sondern ermöglichen den Funktionsübergang von einer Medienver-wendung zu einer anderen.

Ein Beispiel: Wir können die Zufallsabfolge der Kugelpositionen in einem Roulettespiel beschreiben und diese Beschreibung könnte mit Fotoprotokollen dokumentiert werden. Die Verbindung des Satzes „Die Kugel liegt auf der

297Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

24“ mit einem Foto, das die Kugel auf eben dieser Position zeigt, ist in diesem Falle keine Funktion der verbalen Beschreibung des Bildes. Das Foto ist einer verbale Beschreibung zugeordnet, weil es sich in der Beobachtung eines Er-eignisses zufällig so ergeben hat, nicht aber, weil ein Satz der Wortsprache ein Roulettespiel gleichsam nach Regeln des Wortsprachengebrauches steuern könnte. Ein Sprachspiel der Wortsprache regelt nicht die Bedeutung des Sat-zes „Zufällig liegt die Kugel auf der 24“, denn eine Konvention kann zwar re-geln, wie mit Zufallsergebnisse umzugehen ist, aber ein Zufallsergebnis kann sie nicht prognostizieren und auch nicht regelkonform beschreiben, denn es gibt keine Konvention für die Beschreibung eines Zufallsereignisses.

Die mediale Verbindung zwischen dem Satz „Ich sehe die Kugel auf der 24“ und einem Foto lässt sich auch nicht aus einem Protokollfoto ableiten. Obwohl wir wissen, was dieser Satz in diesem Kontext bedeutet (Abb.1). Bedeutungsstabilität der Beschreibung einer Zufallsfolge von Ereignissen ist dennoch möglich, weil ein-und-dasselbe Protokoll-Foto für wahre und falsche Aussagen gleichermaßen Verwendung finden kann.

Abb. 1 Beschreibungen und visuelles Protokoll der Position einer Roulettekugel

Beschreibung 1

Beschreibung 2

Beschreibung 3

Beschreibung 4

In der Verbindung von Satzzeichen und Fotografien finden wir diese stabilen Bedeutungen, weil Texte und Fotoelemente eine mediale Verbindung einge-gangen sind, die nicht in ihren medialen Bestandteilen lag, nicht aus der Her-kunft der beteiligten Medienelemente abzuleiten war. Zufallsereignisse wie beispielsweise Roulette-Ergebnisse oder Lottozahlen benötigen für ihre verbale Beschreibung diese Medienschnittstellen. Wir stellen diese Verbindungen zwi-schen unterschiedlichen Medien her und wir gebrauchen solche Verbindungen,

298 Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

aber aus ihrem Gebrauch folgt keine Konvention und keine Konvention folgt diesem Gebrauch; immer vorausgesetzt, wir können einen funktionalen von einem nichtfunktionalen Mediengebrauch unterscheiden. Das entscheidende Argument für die oben angeführte These ist der Nachweis eines nichtfunkti-onalen Mediengebrauchs, der im angeführten Beispiel an Funktionsverlusten der Wortsprache zu erkennen ist. Solche Funktionsverluste im Gebrauch der Wortsprache sind konstitutiv für Medienübergänge zwischen Texten und Bil-dern. Ein Satz, der mit einem Foto verbunden ist, funktioniert nicht länger wie ein Satz unter Sätzen. In Verbindung beispielsweise mit einem Foto wird er als etwas verwendet, das sowohl als Bild als auch als Text gelesen werden kann. Ein Satz – als ornamentales Muster betrachtet – verliert seine Funktionalität unter Sätzen; das Foto, als Teil des Satzes verwendet, kann nicht länger wie ein Foto funktionieren, sondern gliedert sich in die Funktionalität des Wort-sprachengebrauches ein. Die Verbindung zwischen Texten und Fotos in einem Medienprotokoll ist eine Verbindung unterschiedlicher Gebrauchsformen unterschiedlicher Medien. Sätze, die in eine solche Medienverbindung ein- treten, können Übergänge zu beliebigen Bildern herstellen, verändern dadurch aber ihre konventionelle Bedeutung. Dieser Funktionsverlust zeigt eine Grenze der Funktionalität des Medium „Wortsprache“ auf.

Alles wird in Medien ausgetragen

Otto Neurath beschäftigte sich über viele Jahre hinweg mit dem Projekt, visuelle Botschaften zu entwickeln, die eine bedeutungsstabile und eindeu-tig verbalisierbare Botschaft enthalten sollten. Neurath ist allerdings nicht der Frage nachgegangen, wie die mediale Verschränkung von visuellen Bot-schaften und Texten innerhalb eines Textes zu beschreiben wäre. Ludwig Wittgenstein hingegen, in dessen Nachlass sich deutlich mehr als tausend Piktogramme finden, verwendet diese Skizzen und Zeichnungen überwie-gend instrumentell, zugleich aber nicht als Instrumente einer Bildsprache. Beiden Philosophen gemeinsam ist die Auffassung, alles werde in der Sprache ausgetragen. Was allerdings unter dieser „Sprache“ zu verstehen ist, wird von ihnen völlig unterschiedlich beantwortet. Für Neurath ist es die Bildsprache, die sich der Wortsprache bedient, und das Leitmedium jeder verbalen Trans-formation visueller Inhalte ist. Für Wittgenstein hingegen sind Bilder ihrer-seits nur Instrumente der Wortsprache: Ein Bild zeigt nur, was mit Sätzen zur

299Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

Darstellung gebracht werden kann. Dennoch lassen beide Konzepte ein gemeinsames Programm erkennen: das Programm der wechselseitigen Übersetz-barkeit von Texten in Bilder und von Bildern in Texte.

Neurath suchte nach einer idealtypischen wortsprachlichen Bedeutung typographischer Bildelemente; der mittlere und späte Wittgenstein hingegen erklärte den Begriff der „Bedeutung“ unter Berufung auf Gebrauchsbedeu-tungen der Wortsprache, in der Bilder – verbal instrumentalisiert – Werk-zeuge der Wortsprache sind.

Beide Ansätze zeigen dennoch ein gemeinsames Thema: Bedeutungsstabilität in Medienübergängen, die weder allein in der Analyse des Wortsprachengebrau-ches noch in der Analyse des Gebrauchs einer Bildsprache (Fotos unter Foto-grafien) zu finden ist, sondern ausschließlich in der Verbindung unterschied-licher Medien und unterschiedlicher Medienelemente.2

Dennoch können wir auf geordnete Weise über etwas sprechen, das als visuelles Element dem Gebrauch der Wortsprache nicht zu entnehmen ist. Ein Medium hat die Möglichkeit zu funktionieren oder nicht zu funktionieren nur in Verbindung mit anderen Medien. Es muss also eine Form der Syn-chronisation geben, um von einem Medium behaupten zu können, es sei mit einem anderen verbunden. Ein Medium ist mit einem anderen synchronisiert, wenn es zu keinen Missverständnissen in der Medienkommunikation kommt. Die Praxis zeigt, dass dies der Regelfall unserer Verständigung ist, wenn wir unterschiedliche Medien zugleich verwenden.

Medienverbindungen, Medienschnittstellen bzw. gemischt-mediale Dar-stellungen werden von uns im Praxisgebrauch aller Medien auf immer neue Weise hergestellt. Etwas herzustellen setzt aber keine Konvention voraus, sonst könnte nur hergestellt werden, was bereits bekannt ist.

Der nichtfunktionale Wortgebrauch

Wir finden Wort-Bild-Verbindungen und damit auch mediale Schnittstellen in vielen alltäglichen Situationen, in denn wir mit Worten ein Szenarium beschreiben, das durch visuelle Inhalte zu ergänzen ist. Ein Beispiel für eine solche Medien-Schnittstelle in unserer Alltagskommunikation sind Begrü-ßungsrituale:

Werden wir einen begrüßen, den wir vielleicht zum ersten Mal an die-sem Tag auf der Straße treffen? Werden wir diese Person auch grüßen,

300 Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

wenn wir ihr bereits mehrfach an diesem Tag begegnet sind? Wird die geografische Breite, die Wetterlage und die Windrichtung bzw. die Nei-gungsrichtung des Regenschirms in diesem Begrüßungsritual eine Rolle spielen oder überhaupt die allgemeine körperliche und psychische Verfas-sung der beteiligten Personen? Welchen Einfluss haben Begleitpersonen des Begrüßten und des Begrüßenden in einer solchen Begrüßungssituation? Wird beispielsweise eine Frau ihren Mann auf der Straße begrüßen, wenn er mit seiner Freundin unterwegs ist – oder umgekehrt?

Die Liste der Situationen des Grüßens und Begrüßtwerdens ist die Liste der in der Wortsprache nicht prognostizierbaren weil kontingenten Einzel-fälle. Ist der Zufall des Beschriebenen in der Beschreibung enthalten, dann lässt sich kein allgemeines und auch kein besonderes Merkmal dieses Zufalls benennen oder beschreiben. Dennoch haben wir mit diesen Einzelfällen in der Begrüßungspraxis kein Problem, denn wir visualisieren unsere Worte, inszenieren dieselben verbalen Rituale auf unterschiedliche Weise und ver-leihen unseren Worten durch diese Visualisierung Gebrauchsstabilität.

Diese Tatsache verlangt eine Erklärung, die sich nicht neuerlich auf kontingente Umstände berufen darf. Welche Grammatik aber verleiht den zahllosen möglichen Begrüßungsritualen die Bedeutungsstabilität? Warum verstehen wir Begrüßungen auch in Situationen, die nicht bekannt sind und nicht antizipiert werden konnten? Eine mögliche Antwort wäre: Die Verbindung eines Satzes mit einem visuellen Inhalt, z. B. auch mit einem Foto, funktioniert weder wie ein Satz noch wie ein Foto, denn eine solche Verbindung kann keine nur verbale und keine ausschließlich visuelle Funkti-on haben; sie verleiht unseren Worten eine neue Gebrauchsform. Dies mag auch ein Grund dafür sein, warum wir keine Sprachspielverzeichnisse und Regelverzeichnisse des alltäglichen Sprachgebrauchs benötigen, um uns in der Sprache zu orientieren. Wir verwenden ein breites Repertoire von Verhaltensweisen, um starre Medienübergängen herzustellen. Der tatsäch-liche Sprachgebrauch wird zwischen Medien nicht durch Regelverzeichnis-se mit Leben erfüllt, sondern durch Verhaltensweisen, mit deren Hilfe wir Medienschnittstellen herstellen und festlegen. Gebrauchsstabilität liegt in den überall auffindbaren nichtfunktionalen Schnittstellen unterschied-licher Medien. Wir könnten hier auch von Konventionsverschränkungen sprechen, die selbst die nichtkonventionelle Eigenschaft haben, nämlich neu zu sein und eine Gebrauchsform zu erzeugen, die nicht aus anderen Gebrauchsformen ableitbar ist.

301Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

Die Wortsprache ist eben nicht in allen Fällen einer Werkzeugkiste ver-gleichbar, in der wir stets und ausnahmslos nach dem passenden Werkzeug für einen bestimmten Zweck suchen. Diese Werkzeugmetapher ist häufig irreführend.

Verliert ein Satz seine Funktionalität in der Wortsprache, bleibt er als visuelles Element (als typografische Zeichenfolge) erhalten. Für Fotografien beispielsweise gilt dies nicht, denn ein Foto kann seine visuelle Mitteilungs-funktion nicht verlieren, es teilt sich selbst mit, auch dann, wenn es seinen Kontext verliert. („Das Bild sagt sich selbst.“ 3). Ein Bild benötigt keinen visuellen Kontext, um verwendet werden zu können. Von einem Satz hin-gegen lässt sich nicht behaupten, er teile etwas „jenseits“ seines sprachlichen Kontextes mit. Bilder funktionieren auch in diesem Falle anders als Texte. Texte, die wir als Bilder (z. B. als typografische Ornamente) betrachten, sind Texte, die ihre ursprüngliche Funktion verloren und die Funktion eines visuellen Mediums übernommen haben. Einen Satz zu verwenden bedeutet deshalb nicht a priori, ihn als Werkzeug der Wortsprache zu verwenden. Wir könnten hier den bekannten naturalistischen Fehlschluss durch den Typus des medialen Fehlschlusses erweitern: Es wäre ein medialer und funktionalistischer Fehlschluss, aus Funktionen des Wortsprachengebrauches auf Funktionen des Bild- sprachengebrauches schließen zu wollen.

Wenn Ornamente, Fotos oder andere visuelle Elemente nicht wie Sätze funktionieren, Sätze aber ihrerseits als visuelle Muster betrachtet werden kön-nen, dann muss es Sätze geben, die nicht wie Sätze, sondern als visuelle Mus-ter funktionieren. Sätze, die nur so aussehen, als ob sie wie Sätze unter Sät-zen funktionieren, verweisen in diesem Fall aber nicht auf sprachlichen oder grammatischen Unsinn, sondern auf Medienverschränkungen, die diesen Sätzen ihre Gebrauchsform entziehen bzw. diese verändern.

Wird ein Satz als visuelles Medium verwendet, verliert er seine Funkti-on als verbales Medium, muss aber seine Funktion als visuelles Medium in diesem Falle nicht verlieren, denn Sätze sind immer grafische Muster, auch wenn diese Eigenschaft ihre Gebrauchsfunktion innerhalb der Wortsprache nicht maßgeblich bestimmt. Es muss also Sätze und visuelle Elemente in einem Sprachspiel geben, die in der Wortsprache nichtfunktional sind, d. h. in einem Sprachspiel nicht verwendet werden können, damit es Sätze und visuelle Elemente geben kann, die funktional sind bzw. verwendet werden können. Funktionalität und Nichtfunktionalität bedingen sich in der Wort-sprache wechselseitig.

302 Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

Diese Abgrenzung der Beschreibung der Gebrauchsarten eines Satzes beantwortet aber noch nicht die Frage, woran wir nichtfunktionale Medien-elemente erkennen können.

„Sehen als …“, „Lesen als …“

Gäbe es eine Theorie der unhintergehbaren Funktionalität der Wortsprache, dann hätte man sich mit ihr jeder Möglichkeit beraubt, den Gebrauch eines Satzes im Unterschied zu seinem Nichtgebrauch beschreiben zu können. Eine transzendentalphilosophische Interpretation Wittgensteinscher Sprachspiele wäre nicht in der Lage, Gebrauchsübergänge zwischen Medien zu beschrei-ben, weil sich ein Medium nicht in ein anderes Medium verwandeln könnte. Die Grenze eines Mediums – in diesem Falle der verbalen Sprache – wäre die Grenze der Sprache überhaupt. Eine transzendentalphilosophische Interpre-tation der Sprachimmanenz könnte also nicht erklären, warum ein Medium anders funktioniert als ein anderes und warum das, was in einem Medium geschieht, ein anderes Medium nichts angeht.

Innerhalb der Wortsprache scheint die funktionale Differenz zwischen der Sprache und ihrem Beschreibungsgegenstand zwar zu entfallen, denn beschrieben ist, was der Wortgebrauch zu einem Beschriebenen macht. Ein Irrtum aber liegt in der Auffassung, ein Satz verliere jede Funktion, wenn er nicht mehr als Satz unter Sätzen funktioniere. Hier wird die gegenteilige These vertreten: Ein Satz der Wortsprache kann unterschiedliche Funktionen in unterschiedlichen Medien annehmen und andere Funktionen in anderen Medien verlieren. Der wechselnden Medialität, der Medialitätsdynamik der Zeichen, wurde bisher vermutlich zu wenig Aufmerksamkeit geschenkt. Betrachten wir die folgende hybride Medienkonstruktion:

Abb. 2 „Der ist .”

Wir könnten hier von einer gemischt-medialen Mitteilung sprechen, in der wir lesen und sehen können, wovon die Rede ist. Die Gebrauchsnähe unter-schiedlicher Medienelemente stellt auch in diesem Fall eine Verbindung zwi-schen Medienelementen hier, wenn auch zwischen Elementen unterschied-

303Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

licher Medien, zwischen Texten und geometrischen Mustern. Die Frage ist, ob sich diese gemischt-mediale Konstruktion wie ein Satz der Normalsprache analysieren lässt.

„Der … ist … .“ steht offenkundig nicht für einen analysierbaren Satz der deutschen Sprache.

Auch neben enthält keine Mitteilung, die allein durch diese beiden visuellen Elemente verständlich wäre und dennoch beobachten wir hier eine neue Verbindung von Worten und geometrischen Formen bzw. farbigen Bild-elementen. Wir erkennen das Neue dieser Verbindung an der Nichtableit-barkeit dieser Wort-Bild-Verbindung aus dem Gebrauch der Wortsprache. Es gibt keine konventionelle Regel in der Wortsprache, die uns nahelegen würde, diese Konstruktion wie einen Satz der Wortsprache zu behandeln. Es bedarf aber keiner der uns bekannten Grammatiken, um Medienverbindungen dieser und ähnlicher Form in Gebrauch zu bringen bzw. zu verstehen. Wir bringen etwas in Gebrauch, setzen es medial in Verkehr, wenn wir es für den weiteren Gebrauch anbieten, ohne es einem anderen Gebrauch zu entnehmen.

Eine gemischt mediale Grammatik hilft uns zu verstehen, wie gramma-tische Innovationen entstehen. Auch Patentschriften, die als gemischt-me-diale Beschreibungen von Worten und Grafiken weltweit als verbindliche Dokumente gelten, beschreiben Innovationen, ohne sich eines bereits be-kannten Gebrauchskontextes bedienen zu können. Die sogenannte „absolute Neuheitserfordernis“ schließt von vornherein aus, etwas als Erfindung anzu-erkennen, das aus Konventionellem ableitbar wäre oder nur eine Modifikati-on bekannter technischer Gebrauchsformen enthielte.

Die Nichtfunktionalität eines Textes in technischen Patentschriften finden wir in den neuen Kombinationen der mit dem Text verbundenen Zeichnun-gen und visuellen Erläuterungen. Diese technischen Wort-Bild-Verbindungen bieten ein hohes Maß an Gebrauchs- und Bedeutungsstabilität, denn Patent-schriften müssen international verständlich sein, jenseits aller kulturellen oder regionalen Lebens- und Sprachformen.

Eine Beschreibung technischer Innovationen wird vernünftigerweise nicht nach Konventionen suchen, ein Nichtkonventionelles, weil erfinderisch Neues, konventionell aus bereits Bekannten ableiten zu wollen. Die Nichtfunktionali-tät eines Mediums in einer neuen Medienverbindung ist eine Voraussetzungs-bedingung dafür, die Wortsprache durch andere Medien medial erweitern zu können, ohne „Meta-Medien“ vorauszusetzen. Dass die Wortsprache kein Meta-Medium aller medialen Gebrauchsformen ist, zeigt sich in der

304 Anmerkungen zur Grammatik der Wort-Bild-Verbindungen

Abgrenzbarkeit ihrer Gebrauchsformen gegenüber anderen Gebrauchsformen anderer Medien, die ihr, der Wortsprache, keine Rechenschaft schuldig sind. Der Versuch, Medienverbindungen zu beschreiben, führt uns zu Beispielen ihrer Gebrauchsnähe, die verbunden sind mit Funktionsübergängen zwischen den miteinander verbundenen Medien. Vermeintliche Fehler in einem Sprach-spiel könnten deshalb in vielen Fällen auch Hinweise auf Medienübergänge und Medienverschränkungen sein. Ob es sich so verhält, kann aber nicht allein durch die Analyse verbaler Sprache gezeigt werden, sondern setzt eine Darstel-lung des Gebrauches auch anderer mit dem Wortsprachengebrauch synchroni-sierter Medien voraus. Medien werden synchronisiert verwendet, wenn wir die Medienübergänge herstellen können, ohne uns auf Konventionen berufen zu müssen. Künstlerische und technische Innovationen bedürfen keiner Berufung auf konventionelle Gebrauchsformen eines Mediums. Eine Theorie des inno-vativen Mediengebrauchs müsste diese Überlegungen an ihren Anfang stellen.

Patentschriften bieten uns klassische Muster der Nichtkonventionalität einer Grammatik bzw. der Gebrauchsform unterschiedlicher Medien, bei gleichzeitig maximaler Klarheit und Deutlichkeit der Beschreibung. Leider fehlt eine Theorie, die uns begreiflich macht, wie das – bei maximaler Nicht-konventionalität – möglich ist bzw. sein kann. Es fehlt uns eine Theorie, die verständlich macht, wie Patentschriften zugleich kommunizierbar und neu sein können.

Anmerkungen

1 Vgl. MS 156b, p. 6r „Für uns wird alles in der Sprache ausgetragen“; MS 210, p. 36; MS 213, p. 379, p. 388r: „In der Sprache wird alles ausgetragen“. In: Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition CD-Rom: Text and Facsimile, Oxford University Press, 2001.

2 Im Sinne einer Arbeitsdefinition können wir ein Medium jede gebrauchs- spezifische Mitteilungsform nennen, deren Verwendungsform nur mit den Mitteln dieses Mediums und innerhalb dieses Mediums beschrieben werden kann.

3 Vgl. Wittgenstein „Das Bild sagt mir also sich selbst.“, MS 115, p. 1, 10; MS 146, p. 5, 28, MS 146, p. 28, 63; MS 227a, p. 267; MS 228, p. 113; MS 230, p. 16. In: Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition CD-Rom: Text and Facsimile, Oxford University Press, 2001.

Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment Corrollarial and Theorematical Experiments With Diagrams

Frederik Stjernfelt, Aarhus

I hope that, before I cease to be useful in this world, I may be able to define better than I now can what the distinctive essence of theoric thought is. I can at present say this much with some confidence. It is the directing of the attention to a sort of object not explicitly referred to in the enunciation of the problem at hand … (Peirce ‘Specimens of Mathematical Mazes’, 1908, NEM III, p. 622)

A central aspect of Peirce’s doctrine of diagrammatical reasoning is the idea of using the diagram as a tool for making deductions by performing rule-bound experiments on the diagram. This paper discusses Peirce’s distinc-tion between two classes of diagram proofs, ‘corollarial’ and ‘theorematical’, respectively—a distinction he himself saw as his first major discovery. Theorematical reasoning concerns diagram experimentation involving the introduction of new material—in particular, I shall investigate the issue of the structure of theorematical diagram experiments, propose three types of such experiments and connect them to the role played by hypostatic abstractions in those experiments.

The increasing interest in Peirce’s philosophy of logic as well as his philosophy of science highlights the importance of his notion of deductive reasoning as based on diagrams. As argued by several authors in Moore 2010 (Tiercelin and Cooke), this can be taken as providing an original solution of the dilemma which has haunted much philosophy of mathematics since Benacerraf ’s famous 1973 ‘Mathematical Truth’ article against Platonism (in Benacerraf and Putnam 1983). Benacerraf ’s paper argued against Platon-ism and the existence of abstract objects in mathematics by setting up the following dilemma:

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 305–340.

306 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

1) Mathematics claims the existence of abstract objects outside of time and space; 2) Acquisition of knowledge takes place by means of a causal process connecting an object with a knowing subject. But as abstract objects are causally inert, we must either accept Platonism and reject causal epistemology—or we must embrace causal epistemology and refuse Platonism. Due to the prominence of causal reference theories at the time, Benacerraf ’s choice seemed obvious: abstract objects and Platonism must be discarded in the face of the seeming evidence of causal epistemology. Literally taken, Benacerraf ’s argument would, in fact, eliminate not only ab-stract objects but a series of other aspects of the world, such as many proper-ties (color, pitch, shape …) which may also be suspected for being causally inert in the billard-ball causation theory of the second horn of the dilemma.

Causal reference theories hardly hold the attraction which they did in the 1970s, and the role of diagram experiments in an alternative, Peircean way of cutting the cake is the following. To Peirce, deduction and mathemati-cal reasoning are one and the same. Mathematics is defined by two things, methodologically and substantially, respectively. The former comes from the definition of mathematics that he inherited from his father, the mathema-tician Benjamin Peirce: mathematics is the science that draws necessary conclusions. Peirce’s own addition to this doctrine pertains to the subject matter of those necessities: the object of mathematics is hypotheses concern-ing the forms of relations. All mathematical knowledge thus has a hypothetical structure: if such and such entities and structures are supposed to exist, then this and that follows. We might call this weaker variant of commitment to ab-stract objects ‘hypothetical Platonism’. This admission liberates you, of course, from the presupposition of a strange, space-time-less realm of real existence—but it commits you, on the other hand, to further existence modes than that of particular individuals, which is why diehard nominalists will hardly feel attracted by Peirce’s alternative. Peirce’s doctrine operates with no less than two further existence modes than that of individuals, namely that of possibility —‘May-Bes’—and that of real possibility—‘Would-Bes’. Mathematics being hypothetical through-and-through then forms a subset of the latter. The crucial role of diagrams, now, is that the notion of reasoning by diagram experiments furnishes an epistemological alternative to Benaceraffian causal reference. The idea is that diagrams form the epistemological means of access-ing hypothetical abstract objects. They do that in two steps, as it were. One step is taking a diagram token, a drawing on paper, blackboard, computer screen,

307Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

or in the imagination, and subjecting it to ‘prescission’, the imaginary strip-ping it of accidental qualities so that only the relevant, controllable, general, schematic relations are left—permissing the observer to grasp, through the token, its type. This process of prescission, of course, is not arbitrary nor subjective and is governed by symbols and rules, explicitly or implicitly. Once the type is grasped, it may, by the intermediary of its physical token, be subjected to experimental manipulation, in imagination or on a physical diagram replica, or both. Certain types of transformation are allowed, others not so, corresponding to truth-preserving logical reasoning steps. So diagram experimentation constitutes the if-then hypothetical structure of mathematics and thus gives mathematical knowledge its conditional, modal character.

The observation of diagram tokens/types, of course, is prefigured in the perception of ordinary objects as tokens of types—just like the prescission process stripping the token of its accidental qualities in order to access its type is a more formalized version of similar processes when we address natural kinds by stripping away accidental properties in order to constitute catego-ries like red, chairs, running—or even the category of an individual persist-ing in time despite its changing appearances. General structures and shapes of reality are present already in the perceptual stream, and it is no wonder we, as biological beings, have become adapted to focus upon such features in perceptual structures. This very ability, however, may now be recycled apart from its basis in real objects to be put to use to purified imaginary objects like those of mathematics.

This argument pertains to pure, mathematical diagram reasoning; now what about the vast amount of applied diagrams representing empirical states-of-affairs? Peirce’s system of the sciences offers an explanation of the efficacy of such diagrams—namely that they inherit, explicitly or implicitly, the mathematical structure of pure diagrams and add further constraints to those diagrams stemming from the special science of the domain to which they pertain.1 Thus, all deductive reasoning, everyday or scientific, is taken to involve a mathematical-diagrammatical scaffolding, and nec-essary inferences in all sciences as well as in everyday reasoning employ mathematics, implicitly or explicitly. In Stjernfelt (2007), I have attempted a reconstruction of Peirce’s overall doctrine of diagrams and diagrammatical reasoning, arguing that this cluster of ideas forms the center of a Peircean epistemology as well as it constitutes an important contribution to contem-porary realist semiotics in general.

308 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

In this paper, I shall take a closer look at the notion of diagram experiment based on Peirce’s famous distinction between two such classes of experiments, giving rise to Corollarial and Theorematical reasoning, respectively. On the base of this distinction, a series of important issues are addressed. To what degree does this distinction capture different formal classes of problem difficulty? How may we distinguish between different types of Theorematic reasoning? And what is the relation between diagram experi-ments and hypostatic abstraction?

In the years after 1900, Peirce returns over and over again to the Corollar-ial/Theorematical-distinction, famously celebrating it as his own first “real discovery” (in his Carnegie application 1902). The overall idea is that corol-larial deduction has a conclusion which fleshes out a proposition which lay already implicitly in the premisses—thus conforming to the Kantian idea of logical conclusions offering nothing which was not already defined in the premisses. By contrast, theorematic (or theorematogenic, or theoretic, or theoric) reasoning forms a more demanding and creative type of reasoning where some new elements must be experimentally added to the premisses before reaching the conclusion.

Take a simple example: asking the question of the size of the perimeter of a square with the side s, the conclusion may be reached based on the very defi-nition of a square as a quadrangle with four equal sides—or by a very simple diagram experiment of counting sides, using the following diagram:

Fig.1: Square with the side s

The result of 4s is easily reached by both of these means. By comparison, the famous Euclidean proof of the angle sum of the triangle being equal to two right angles may serve as an example of theorematic reasoning:

Fig. 2: Angle sum of a triangle

A E

DCB

309Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

This proof requires the addition of auxiliary lines to the triangle—here CE and CD, parallel to AB and prolonging BC, respectively—to establish the proof based on the fact that the three angles meeting at C have the same sizes as those of the triangle. BCA participates in both of the two sums, ACE is equivalent to BAC, while ECD is equivalent to ABC.2 The sum of the three angles meeting at C—BCA, ACE, and ECD—is obviously two right angles. But this is impossible to derive from mere definitions of ‘angle’ and ‘triangle’ just like it is impossible to prove from the triangle diagram without any additions.

The terminology of corollarial/theorematic comes from Euclid whose editors named simple inferences corollaries—while propositions to be proved were theorems. Peirce judges that some of Euclid’s theorems are, in fact, mere corollaries—the overall distinction is taken to rely upon the necessity of experimenting by adding new elements to the diagram, elements which disap-pear in the final, general statement of the proof. The theorem that the angle sum of a triangle equals two right angles does not, for example, in any way refer to the subsidiary lines necessary to reach the proof. The basic issue behind this distinction is, of course, the duplicity of mathematics, being apodictic and inexhaustible at one and the same time. How is it possible that mathematicians find results by necessity while at the same time new, unexpected discoveries abound among these results, just like in the empirical sciences? This issue troubled Peirce for a long time. Already when constructing his first formal language for logic, in his 1885 masterpiece ‘On the Algebra of Logic’, he reasoned:

It has long been a puzzle how it could be that, on the one hand, mathemat-ics is purely deductive in its nature, and draws its conclusions apodictically, while on the other hand, it presents as rich and apparently unending a series of surprising discoveries as any observational science. Various have been the attempts to solve the paradox by breaking down one or other of these asser-tions, but without success. The truth, however, appears to be that all deduc-tive reasoning, even simple syllogism, involves an element of observation; namely, deduction consists in constructing an icon or diagram the relations of whose parts shall present a complete analogy with those of the parts of the object of reasoning, of experimenting upon this image in the imagination, and of observing the result so as to discover unnoticed and hidden relations among the parts. (CP 3.363)

310 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

Here, the inexhaustibility of mathematics is explained by means of Peirce’s first, germ-like diagram reasoning doctrine—as a generalization, interestingly, of his linear algebra of logic, far from the ordinary conception of diagrams. The ‘unnoticed and hidden’ relations obtainable by diagram observation, of course, are what are later taken to require theorematic deduction, in addition to mere inference from definitions.

Even if the problem addressed by the distinction is thus an early concern in Peirce, it seems only in the years after 1900 that he explicitly coins the corollarial/theorematic distinction and sets out to elaborate it. Only in 1901, we seem to witness the nascent terminology of the distinction appearing:

1901 Oct 12

If my present view, held for four or five years, is right that Abduction Deduction Induction are Premarian, Secundarian, and Tertian, then there ought to be two types of Deduction & three of Induction […] Now I don’t recognize any such two types of Deduction. […] We can distinguish Deductions into those which are corollarific and those which are theorematogeneous. The former merely require the careful consideration of the conclusion, the latter involve outside considerations,—subsidiary lines, etc. But this seems a methodeutic not a criti-cal distinction. (Logic Notebook Ms. 339, p. 362; earlier on the page, Peirce at-tempts to distinguish proposition deductions and term deductions).

Later, Peirce will include the corollarial/theorematic distinction in his critical table of inference types—but this early quote points to the fact that the latter part of the distinction sits uneasily on the critical/methodeutic divide (today, we would rather speak of logic versus heuristics or theory of science). Theo-rematic reasoning requires an inventiveness or even ingenuity which makes it alien to a narrow concept of logic—even if its results, on the other hand, remain purely deductive.

This apparently simple distinction covers a whole bunch of interesting issues: that of the much more outspoken experimental character of theore-matical reasoning as compared to corollarial reasoning, that of finding suit-able new elements to add, that of instantiating those elements in particulars (only a particular set of lines in the angle sum example will lead to the proof), that of the character of those elements, that of the relation of the diagram experiment to verbal instructions and definitions, that of the strategy of

311Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

finding the proper elements to add. Probably for this reason, Peirce’s descrip-tion of theorematical reasoning differs to some extent from time to time.

Theorematic diagram experiments in Peirce

Let us run through Peirce’s different definitions.1) The basic idea is the indirect conception that theorematical reasoning,

unlike corollarial reasoning, is not reducible to inferences from concept defi-nitions: ‘An accurate definition of Corollarial Demonstration would require a long explanation; but it will suffice to say that it limits itself to considerations already introduced or else involved in the Explication of its conclusion; while Theorematic Demonstration resorts to a more complicated process of thought.’ (‘A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God’, 1908, CP 6.471, EPII, p. 442) This brief definition of theorematic reasoning, of course, is merely negative and contrastive vis-à-vis Kant’s description of logic as tautological, and most of Peirce’s descriptions of the pair of concepts take their point of departure in the inability of certain theorems to be proved by corollarial reasoning:

Deductions are of two kinds, which I call corollarial and theorematic. The corol-larial are those reasonings by which all corollaries and the majority of what is called theorems are deduced; the theorematic are those by which the major theorems are deduced. If you take the thesis of a corollary, i. e., the proposition to be proved, and carefully analyze its meaning, by substituting for each term its definition, you will find that its truth follows. (‘On the Logic of Drawing History from Ancient Documents’, 1901, CP 7.204, EPII, p. 96—after which the quote continues with a more positive definition of theorematic reasoning (cf. below)).

Even if corollarial reasoning counts as the ideal and should be preferred whenever possible because of its simplicity, a certain class of ‘major theo-rems’ require more than careful description in terms of concept analysis. This necessity stems from the general impossibility of defining things, in all cases, so that all their properties will be corollaries from their definition. Peirce ad-dresses this when claiming that the best translation of Greek ‘episteme’ is ‘comprehension’ which is ‘… the ability to define a thing in such a manner that all its properties shall be corollaries from its definition. Now it may be

312 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

that we shall ultimately be able to do that, say for light or electricity. On the other hand, it may equally turn out that it forever remains as impossible as it certainly is to define number in such a way that Fermat’s or Wilson’s theorems should be simple corollaries from the definition.’ (‘On Science and Natural Classes’, 1902, EPII, p. 129). Even if much in arithmetics is corollarial (such as Kant’s famous 7+5=12 which Peirce refuses to admit the status of synthetic a priori for the same reason), complicated theorems of arithmetics are not.3

So the impossibility of defining things, in all cases, so that all their essential properties flow from the definition, obviously forms the first argument for the necessity of theorematic reasoning.

2) A basic way of describing theorematic reasoning more positively, now, is as involving the addition of new elements to the premisses (abstrac-tions or not, foreign ideas or existential instantiations of general objects the existence of which is granted by the universe of discourse). Peirce seems to have received this idea about the introduction of a new element from no less than George Boole’s widow in 1898:

The widow of the great Boole has lately written a little book in which she points out that, in solving a mathematical problem, we usually introduce some part or element into the construction which, when it has served our purpose, is removed. Of that nature is a scale of quantity, together with the apparatus by which it is transported unchanged from one part of the diagram to another, for the purpose of comparing those two parts. Something of this general descrip-tion seems to be indispensable in mathematics. (‘The Logic of Mathematics in Relation to Education’, 1898, CP 3.561)

—and his overall development of the corollarial/theorematic distinction now covers the following decade. The addition of such objects is taken to be the subject of an additional lemma to the premisses, supported by a postulate. Continuing the above quote from ‘On the Logic …’ (1901), Peirce writes:

But when it comes to proving a major theorem, you will very often find you have need of a lemma, which is a demonstrable proposition about something outside the subject of inquiry; and even if a lemma does not have to be demon-strated, it is necessary to introduce the definition of something which the thesis of the theorem does not contemplate. In the most remarkable cases, this is some abstraction; that is to say, a subject whose existence consists in some fact about

313Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

other things. Such, for example, are operations considered as in themselves subject to operation; lines, which are nothing but descriptions of the motion of a particle, considered as being themselves movable; collections; numbers; and the like. (‘On the Logic of Drawing History from Ancient Documents’, 1901, CP 7.204, EPII, p. 96).

In Peirce’s debatable analysis, lines are abstractions from the trajectory of particles—so the subsidiary lines in the angle sum proof are taken to be examples of the introduction of abstractions. Be that as it may4, the quote given here overlooks the important issue of the selection of those lines. The postulate in Euclid that given a line and a point, a line through the point may be drawn which is parallel to the line given, obviously lies behind the lemma of introduc-ing the two particular auxiliary lines in the proof. But not any lines added to the original triangle would lead us to the proof. So the selection of particular objects to add becomes an important issue. Hintikka, in his famous development of Peirce’s notion of theorematic reasoning, takes this ‘existential instantiation’ in the shape of ‘witness individuals’ to constitute the core of theorematical reasoning, adding further quantified variables to those referred to in the prem-isses. Sun-Joo Shin (2010) emphasizes the importance of this individualizing step in reasoning: much has been spoken, since the British empiricists, of the access to the triangle in general, but the inverse movement, that of select-ing the right individuals to add in a proof, has received much less attention. Hintikka insists that the addition of individuals to the premisses constitutes the very core of Peirce’s idea: ‘What makes deduction theorematic according to Peirce is that in it we must envisage other individuals than those needed to instantiate the premise of an argument.’ (1980, 110)—also other than those needed to express its conclusion, we may add. This is what constitutes the basis of Peirce’s ‘brilliant insight […] that this geometrical distinction can be gener-alized to all deductive reasoning.’ (1980, 109). Thus, in Hintikka’s reconstruction, ‘… a valid deductive step is theorematic, if it increases the number of layers of quantifiers in the proposition in question.’ (1980, 110). To Hintikka, this solves the ancient Aristotelian riddle of logical incontinence—how can it be that one may fail to grasp the sum total of logical consequences of the amount of knowl-edge in one’s possession. This is because many of those consequences require the theorematic addidion of further individuals for their proof, and Hintikka surmises that the difficulty of a problem is roughly proportional to the amount of new individuals needed for its solution (Hintikka 1980, 113; Stjernfelt

314 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

2007, 107–8). This particularity of auxiliary individuals, much discussed after Hintikka’s reinterpretation of theorematical reasoning, is surprisingly rarely addressed in Peirce; however, this late quote connects the basis of the additional elements in a general postulate with the particularity of those elements:

Of my two divisions of Deductions, one is into Corollarial and Theorematic Deduction. The former requires nothing more than a logical analysis of the premisses to furnish the conclusion. The latter involves as one of its premisses a postulate, or proposition asserting the possibility of any object which lies in certain definite general relation to any existing objects of a certain kind. E. g. Between any two points on a line it is possible to place a third. Now to derive from this postulate the particular consequence that will lead to the conclu-sion requires not merely sagacity or Aristotle’s eustokha […] but also imaginative genius in all its complexity of resources. (Ms. 764, reel 16, 1282–83, late, seemingly 1910–11)

Here, the requirement of imaginative genius—implicitly compared to the laborious teasing out of corollarial definition consequences—is highlighted as required for finding the appropriate particular elements to add. Shin (1997; 2010) also insists upon the importance of selecting the right individuals, among many possible, to conduct the proof.5

Other times, it is rather the general or abstract (which is not the same) character of the added elements which is emphasized: ‘To the Diagram of the truth of the Premisses something else has to be added, which is usually a mere May-be, and then the conclusion appears.’ (letter to James 25. dec 1909, EPII, 502). A May-be, in Peirce’s late metaphysics, is a possibility which is, of course, general. Especially when talking about the added elements in this general way, Peirce insists they are foreign to the theorem which the proof intends to establish:

What I call the theorematic reasoning in mathematics consists in so introducing a foreign idea, using it, and finally deducing a conclusion from which it is elimi-nated. Every such proof rests, however, upon judgments in which the foreign idea is first introduced, and which are simply self-evident. (Carnegie Application (L75), 1902, NEM IV, p. 42).6

The question is: are the additional elements particular instantiations select-ed on the basis of general possibilities granted in the relevant universe of

315Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

discourse (like the subsidiary lines of the angle sum proof granted by Euclid’s postulates), or does the addition concern a new, general principle or idea? Judson Webb, in an important paper on Hintikka’s philosophy of logic, also points to the fact that, in discussing different proofs of Desargues’ theorem, Peirce involves different types of theorematic reasoning: ‘There are just two distinct kinds of things we can introduce into a proof that do not appear in such a theorem: auxiliary lines and the idea of length. The former are only new objects of the same kind occurring in the theorem, while the latter is a new concept that is “foreign” to it.’ (Webb 2006, 249). Peirce, however, did not seem to pay explicit attention to this important distinction to which we shall return later.

He did, however, introduce another distinction between subtypes of theorematic reasoning. In the famous description of the two kinds of deduc-tion in the Carnegie application, the description in terms of new elements gives rise to a subdivision of theorematic reasoning based on the abstract or non-abstract character of that reasoning:

My first real discovery about mathematical procedure was that there are two kinds of necessary reasoning, which I call the corollarial and the the-orematic, because the corollaries affixed to the propositions of Euclid are usually arguments of one kind, while the more important theorems are of the other. The peculiarity of theorematic reasoning is that it considers something not implied at all in the conceptions so far gained, which nei-ther the definition of the object of research nor anything yet known about could of themselves suggest, although they give room for it. Euclid, for ex-ample, will add lines to his diagram which are not at all required or sug-gested by any previous proposition, and which the conclusion that he reaches by this means says nothing about. I show that no considerable advance can be made in thought of any kind without theorematic reasoning. When we come to consider the heuretic part of mathematical procedure, the question how such suggestions are obtained will be the central point of the discussion. Passing over smaller discoveries, the principal result of my closer studies of it has been the very great part which an operation plays in it which through-out modern times has been taken for nothing better than a proper butt of ridicule. It is the operation of abstraction, in the proper sense of the term, which, for example, converts the proposition “Opium puts people to sleep” into “Opium has a dormitive virtue”. This turns out to be so essential to the

316 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

greater strides of mathematical demonstration that it is proper to divide all theorematic reasoning into the non-abstractional and the abstractional. I am able to prove that the most practically important results of mathematics could not in any way be attained without this operation of abstraction. It is there-fore necessary for logic to distinguish sharply between good abstraction and bad abstraction. (Carnegie Application (L75), Draft C, 90–102, NEM IV, p. 49).

This distinction between abstractional and non-abstractional theorematical reasoning has been taken up by Stephen Levy and Michael Hoffmann (1997; forthcoming) in their efforts to outline taxonomies of theorematic reasoning. But is it the case that this idea might, simultaneously, constitute a basis for the distinction between theorematic reasoning by means of existential instantia-tion on the one hand and the introduction of new, foreign ideas on the other? Peirce does not further develop his distinction between abstractional and non-abstractional theorematic reasoning, so it is difficult to decide. Suffice it to say that it is not evident these two distinctions are identical or even co-extensive; the introduction of certain abstract objects may be permitted in the formal-ism used and in that sense not being new or foreign (just like the introduction of lines in a geometric proof or a variable in an equation)—the foreign idea seems to comprise a special class of abstractions only.

3) An interesting feature of the descriptions in terms of added elements quoted here is that they do not refer to deductions in terms of diagram experiments. Diagram experiment, however, is taken to constitute the center of deduction in general, and of theorematic deduction in particular. In a parallel draft for the Carnegie application, Peirce thus characterizes theore-matic reasoning as follows:

Theorematic deduction is deduction in which it is necessary to experiment in the imagination upon the image of the premiss in order from the result of such experiment to make corollarial deductions to the truth of the conclusion. The subdivisions of theorematic deduction are of very high theoretical impor-tance. (Carnegie Application (L75), 1902, NEM IV, p. 38).

The year after, in the masterful Syllabus accompanying his Lowell lectures, Peirce connects the experimental character of theorematic reasoning to the ingenuity required as well as to observation; it ‘… is one which, having represented the conditions of the conclusion in a diagram, performs an

317Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

ingenious experiment upon the digram, and by the observation of the diagram so modified, ascertains the truth of the conclusion.’ (Syllabus, 1903, CP 2.267, EPII, p. 298). In one of the drafts of the Lowell lectures, Peirce connects these two descriptions, now taking the addition of new material to be a subtype of experiment:

I draw a distinction between Corollarial consequences and Theorematic con-sequences. A corollarial consequence is one the truth of which will become evident simply upon attentive observation of a diagram constructed so as to represent the conditions stated in the conclusion. A theorematic consequence is one which only becomes evident after some experiment has been performed upon the diagram, such as the addition to it of parts not necessarily referred to in the statement of the conclusion. (Lowell Lectures, Ms. 456, (p. 49; ISP 28) transcription by Helmut Pape).

Here, it is not made explicit which other types of experiment there might be besides the addition of new elements. In an early account for diagram experi-mentation, however, Peirce provides such an example:

Deduction is that mode of reasoning which examines the state of things asserted in the premisses, forms a diagram of that state of things, perceives in the parts of that diagram relations not explicitly mentioned in the premises, satisfies it-self by mental experiments upon the diagram that these relations would always subsist, or at least would do so in a certain proportion of cases, and concludes their necessary, or probable, truth. For example, let the premiss be that there are four marked points upon a line which has neither extremity nor furcation. Then, by means of a diagram,

we may conclude that there are two pairs of points such that in passing along the line in any way from one to the other point of either pair, one point of the second pair will be passed an odd number of times and the other point an even (or zero) number of times. This is deduction. (Untitled manuscript, c. 1896, 1.66)7

In this example, the diagram experiment is undertaken by following a trajectory along the closed curve, until realizing that each full turn will add 2 to the number of passages of each point pair—so with respect to odd/even, the result will stay the same as the very first half trajectory, passing one point

318 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

1 time, the other point 0 times. This experiment hardly introduces any new ideas at all, but it does involve instantiation, this time of a trajectory moving in the diagram. So the new elements added may also be actions performed on the diagram. In the ‘Minute Logic’ of 1902, Peirce hints at those other experiment possibilities:

Just now, I wish to point out that after the schema has been constructed according to the precept virtually contained in the thesis, the assertion of the theorem is not evidently true, even for the individual schema; nor will any amount of hard thinking of the philosophers’ corollarial kind ever render it evident. Thinking in general terms is not enough. It is necessary that something should be DONE. In geometry, subsidiary lines are drawn. In algebra permissible transformations are made. Thereupon, the faculty of observation is called into play. Some relation between the parts of the schema is remarked. But would this relation subsist in every possible case? Mere corollarial reasoning will sometimes assure us of this. But, generally speaking, it may be necessary to draw distinct schemata to represent alterna-tive possibilities. Theorematic reasoning invariably depends upon experimen-tation with individual schemata. (‘Minute Logic’, CP 4.233, c. 1902)

Here, the mere introduction of new elements or ideas as additional general terms is not deemed sufficient—the experiment is supposed to perform an action manipulating the diagram—drawing the auxiliary lines—or, in the algebraical example, undertaking transformation granted by the relevant symbol manipulation rules. In the Euclidean example, transformations includ-ing the movement of geometrical objects on the plane permitted (rotations, mirrorings, translations, etc.) obviously form a class of experiments different from those of introducing new elements, just like, in arithmetics, the transfor-mation possibilities given by calculation rules (and more generally, in algebra, symbol manipulation rules), provide such experiment possibilities.

An important issue here—both related to the “addition of new elements or foreign ideas” and to the “experiment” aspects—is the relation between theorematic reasoning and abduction. A finished piece of theorematic reason-ing, of course, is deductive—the conclusion follows with necessity from the premisses. But in the course of conducting the experiment, an abductive phase appears when investigating which experimental procedure, among many, to follow; which new elements or foreign ideas to introduce. This may require

319Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

repeated, trial-and-error abductive guessing, until the final structure of the proof is found—maybe after years or centuries. Exactly the fact that neither premisses nor theorem needs to contain any mentioning of the experiment or the introduction of new elements makes the abductive character of experimen-tation clear. Of course, once the right step has been found, abductive searching may cease and the deductive character of the final proof stands out.

4) A further description of the corollarial/theorematic distinction makes it correspond to reasoning with words or schemata, respectively. The quote just given from the ‘Minute Logic’ continues with the conclusion that

We shall find that, in the last analysis, the same thing is true of the corollarial reasoning, too; even the Aristotelian “demonstration why.” Only in this case, the very words serve as schemata. Accordingly, we may say that corollarial, or “philosophical” reasoning is reasoning with words; while theorematic, or math-ematical reasoning proper, is reasoning with specially constructed schemata. (‘Minute Logic’, CP 4.233, c. 1902).

This complicated claim identifies corollarial reasoning with philosophical reasoning in words (implicitly placing a severe limitation on the powers of such reasoning), as compared to the constructive power of theorematic reasoning using specially constructed schemata and being able to make ‘demonstration that’. Immediately, however, words are also taken to consti-tute such schemata, even if maybe simpler and less directly accessible than ‘specially constructed’ schemata. The ubiquity of such schemata also outside of science (maps, graphs and tables in newspapers, media, commodities, etc.) points to the fact that the distinction between words and constructed schemata does not, as it might be immediately asumed, coincide with that of everyday reasoning and science. Rather, the idea that conceptual reasoning forms a simple version of schematic reasoning points to the idea of the distinction be-tween corollarial and theorematic as being a gradient continuum rather than two mutually exclusive classes—also supported by the fact that theorematic reasoning examples differ enormously in complexity and the amount of new elements required. We shall return to this below.

5) A final characterization of theorematic reasoning is that of requir-ing a new point of view of the problem. We find a simple version of this in Ms. 773 (Reel 16, MF 1434–35): ‘I spoke of Deduction as the compulsive kind of reasonings. Almost all the theoric inferences are positively creative. That is,

320 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

they create, not existing things, but entia rationis which are quite as real. This blackboard is black. Theoric deduction concludes that the board possesses the quality of blackness and that blackness is a simple object, called an ens rationis because that theoric thought created it.’ Here, the hypostatic abstraction from ‘black’ to ‘blackness’ is taken as an example of theoric deduction.

Here is a terminological problem. In many cases, ‘theoric’ is used inter-changeably with ‘theorematic’; in other contexts, Peirce seems to intend a slightly different meaning by the concept ‘theoric’. One of his paradigm examples is that of Desargues’ theorem (two triangles which are centrally in perspective are also axially in perspective, usually referred to by Peirce as ‘the ten point theorem’)8—a 17. century geometry proof recently rediscovered in Peirce’s time by von Staudt in the context of projective geometry. Here, Peirce uses the notion of ‘theoric’ to refer to the ‘new point of view’ which may introduce a third dimension to the diagrammatical representation of the 2-d theorem, thereby making it much more immediately graspable than much more cumbersome proofs using lenghts of lines:

Fig. 3

The two triangles lying in a central perspective as seen from the point 0 have the intersections of their sides coinciding on the same line (axial perspective). This figure (Hilbert and Cohn-Vossen, quoted from Hoffmann, forthcom-ing p. 18) shows how a three-dimensional interpretation of the originally 2-d planar diagram makes it easy to grasp that the two planes of the trian-gles meet at the line g. Peirce returns over and over again to this proof, taking it as a central example of ‘theoric’ or ‘theorematic’ reasoning. An alternative proof remains restricted to two dimensions but rests upon another theorematic addition, namely that of the length of lines which is also not mentioned in the original theorem.

Michael Hoffmann has made a strong case that this adoption of a new

321Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

point of view should be called ‘theoric’, differing from theorematic reasoning because it simply constitutes a gestalt shift in the conception of the prob-lem rather than the necessary experimental introduction of new elements in the deduction process (Hoffmann, forthcoming). Hoffmann’s interpretation is based on the use of the term ‘theoric’ in Ms. 318 and Ms. 754, both of them from 1907. From the large Ms. 318 on pragmatism, Hoffmann quotes the fol-lowing description of ‘theoric’ reasoning which consists ‘… in the transforma-tion of the problem,—or its statement,—due to viewing it from another point of view’ (ibid., CSP 68 = ISP 225). In the brief Ms. 754 (notes for a ‘talk to the Phil. club’ April 12, 1907), Peirce writes:

I formerly, quite dubiously, divided Deductions into the Corollarial & the Theorematic. Explain these. Deduction will better be called Demonstration. But further study leads me to lop off a corollarial part from the Theorematic Deductions, which follows that part that originates a new point of view. This part of the theorematic procedure, I will call theôric reasoning. It is very plainly allied to retroduction, from which it only differs as far as I now see in being indisputable. (Peirce, quoted in: Hoffmann, forthcoming, p. 27, n13)9

The core of theorematic reasoning, following this quote, is taken to be the theoric introduction of a new viewpoint—the rest seems to be mere corol-larial reasoning. I am not convinced, though, that Peirce, by the introduction of the term ‘theoric’ in 1907 intends a new concept, completely different from that of ‘theorematic’. In the Ms. 754 quote just given—which forms a hapax, the only place, to my knowledge, where Peirce uses both of the notions ‘theo-ric’ and ‘theorematic’—the former is introduced as a central part of the latter. Shortly afterwards, in the April 1908 issue of The Monist, Peirce publishes the ‘Amazing Mazes’ in whose ‘First curiosity’ he defines ‘theoric’ in complete parallel to the usual definitions of ‘theorematic’ contrasting ‘corollarial’:

I shall term the step of so introducing into a demonstration a new idea not explicitly or directly contained in the premisses of the reasoning or in the condition of the proposition which gets proved by the aid of this introduc-tion, a theoric step. (CP 4.613).

So, I just take ‘theoric’ to be another example of Peirce’s proliferating neologisms where the same concept gives rise to the coining of many, dif-

322 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

ferent terminological expressions for that concept. Hoffmann, on the other hand, remains right in pointing to the fact that Peirce’s analysis of the recur-rent example of Desargues’ theorem does not coincide with his other exam-ples and descriptions of theorematic reasoning—I would say it adds a further aspect to the description of varieties of theorematic reasoning. Adding a third dimension to the diagram of Desargues’ theorem is adding a new element in another way than adding a particular line to an Euclidean diagram, because it induces a ‘transformation’ in the whole way of viewing the problem. When returning to Desargues’ theorem the next year, in a letter to William James in 1909 (L224, NEM III, p. 471), Peirce now characterizes the Desargues proof as ‘theorematic’ and the introduction of a third dimension as yet another example of ‘additions to the diagram.’ The ‘theoric’ examples thus rather point to the fact that the range of possible additions and experiments in theorematical reasoning is fairly large, involving elements of highly different dimensionality, generality, and abstractness.

To sum up Peirce’s different descriptions of theorematic reasoning, we can say they exceed the mere explication from the combination of definitions by introducing something further, be it new elements (particular or general), be it experiments by diagram manipulation, be it the substitution of schemata for words, or be it the gestalt shift of seeing the whole problem from another point of view.10

Theorematical reasoning, relative to psychology? —or to logic systems chosen?

But why could we not see the differences between corollarial reasoning and the different types of theorematic reasoning as a difference in reasoning psy-chology only? The former reasonings are generally taken to be easy while the latter require ingenuity—could we not reduce the difference between them to a difference between psychological resources needed to solve the problems? When only we are taught which lines to select in the angle sum proof or how to introduce the third dimension in Desargues’ proof, these proofs become just as easy to conduct as corollarial proofs. The corollarial/theorematical distinction would thus be reduced to one of psychology of learning, of the peculiarity of human reasoning capabilities to which some problems appear easy and other appear more difficult? Peirce, always alien

323Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

to psychologism in logic, does not consider this possibility and maintains the idea that it is the very structure of the problem and the formal resources for its proof itself which gives rise to the distinction.11 Here, we take Peirce’s stance in assuming that the difference in problem complexity is no purely psychological phenomenon.

A related idea rests on the fact that proofs of the same theorem may take many different forms—cf. the Desargues example—and so a logical parallel to such psychological ideas will be the following question: After a successful theorematic proof, could we not simply add the theorematic additions to the original set of premisses, the original statement of the problem—then the ensuing proof would become corollarial only and easy to perform? From time to time, Peirce toyed with the idea that proofs once having been theore-matical might be transformed into the simpler form of corollarial reasoning by the change of logical system: ‘Perhaps when any branch of mathematics is worked up into its most perfect form all its theorems will be converted into corollaries.’ (‘Sketch of Dichotomic Mathematics’, c. 1903?, NEM III, p. 289). That corollarial proofs must be preferred to theorematic proofs for the same theorems, if available, follows from the obvious ideal that simpler proofs must be preferred to more complicated proofs of the same theorem—but this ideal does not grant that all of the latter may, in fact, be translated into the former. And even if some theorematical proofs may be translated into corollarial proofs, Peirce generally finds such an idea—not so far from a positive solution to Hilbert’s Entscheidungsproblem—impossible, as we already saw in the 1902 quote where he deemed it impossible ‘… to define number in such a way that Fermat’s or Wilson’s theorems should be simple corollaries from the definition.’ (‘On Science and Natural Classes’, 1902, EPII, p. 129).

At one occasion, in the ‘Amazing Mazes’, Peirce clearly distinguished between theorematic reasoning as such and the repetition of an already established theorematic proof, as well as between proofs necessarily requiring theorematic tools and theorematic proofs reducible to corollaries. (As in the ‘Amazing Mazes’ in general, Peirce here uses ‘theoric’ for ‘theorematic’). A theorematic proof which may—if possible—be transformed into a simpler corollarial proof caused by the introduction of a better formal representation system, is called a ‘theorem-corollary’—somewhat a misnomer. The repeti-tion of a theorematic proof, once it has become familiar, ‘a matter of course’, and thus as easy as corollarial reasoning, he terms ‘theoremation’—this must,

324 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

of course, be distinguished from the former by still possessing the theore-matic structure. Finally, the theorematic introduction of the new element in order to establish the proof is, by contrast, named a “major theorem”:

Now to propositions which can only be proved by the aid of theoric steps (or which, at any rate, could hardly otherwise be proved), I propose to restrict the application of the hitherto vague word “theorem,” calling all others, which are deducible from their premisses by the general principles of logic, by the name of corollaries. A theorem, in this sense, once it is proved, almost invariably clears the way to the corollarial or easy theorematic proof of other proposi-tions whose demonstrations had before been beyond the powers of the math-ematicians. That is the first secondary advantage of a theoric step. The other such advantage is that when a theoric step has once been invented, it may be imitated, and its analogues applied in proving other propositions. This consid-eration suggests the propriety of distinguishing between varieties of theorems, although the distinctions cannot be sharply drawn. Moreover, a theorem may pass over into the class of corollaries, in consequence of an improvement in the system of logic. In that case, its new title may be appended to its old one, and it may be called a theorem-corollary. There are several such, pointed out by De Morgan, among the theorems of Euclid, to whom they were theorems and are reckoned as such, though to a modern exact logician they are only corollar-ies. If a proposition requires, indeed, for its demonstration, a theoric step, but only one of a familiar kind, that has become quite a matter of course, it may be called a theoremation. If the needed theoric step is a novel one, the proposition which employs it most fully may be termed a major theorem; for even if it does not, as yet, appear particularly important, it is likely eventually to prove so. If the theoric invention is susceptible of wide. (‘Amazing Mazes’, 1908, CP 4.613)

The terminology of these distinctions seems not particularly well-chosen, one referring to the process (‘theoremation’) two to the result (‘theorem-corollary’, ‘major theorem’), and the syncretistic notion ‘theorem-corollary’ doesn’t seem to be a good means to indicate that the proposition in question is a corollary of one set of axioms, but not of another. The overall conceptual argument, however, clearly establishes the distinction between theorematic reasoning as such on the one hand, the issue of its dependency upon axiom and rule systems on other hand—and, finally, the psychological issue of its becoming familiar with repetition. As Hintikka (1983, 112) argues, the fact that some

325Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

theorematical proofs become corollarial under other rule systems does not at all obliterate the corollarial-theorematical distinction, rather it makes clear that the distinction is relative to the logic system used and will remain, albeit differently, in any such system.

Types of theorematic diagram experiments

As we have seen, Peirce developed the distinction of corollarial and theo-rematical diagram deductions during the last 15 years of his life, and both explicitly and implicitly, he proposed different subtypes of theorematical deductions. He explicitly proposed a distinction between theorematic rea-soning with or without abstractions, and more implicitly, distinctions may be inferred from his examples: manipulating with the diagram versus adding new material; the new elements added being objects, foreign ideas or new points of view. Apparently, he realized that all this laid out a whole field for further investigation:

I wish a historical study were made of all the remarkable theoric steps and no-ticeable classes of theoric steps. I do not mean a mere narrative, but a critical examination of just what and of what mode the logical efficacy of the differ-ent steps has been. Then, upon this work as a foundation, should be erected a logical classification of theoric steps; and this should be crowned with a new methodeutic of necessary reasoning. (‘Amazing Mazes’, 1908, CP 4.615)

The ultimate goal for such a research, as so much in Peirce, is heuristic (‘methodeutic’): it should be undertaken in order to find better methods for deduction within the confines of the research process as such. The plurality of theorematic subtypes involved, already more or less vaguely glimpsed, may be no wonder, given the basic negative definition of somehow trans-gressing the merely definition-based corollarial reasoning. In how many ways is it possible to transgress corollarial reasoning? Given Peirce’s overall continuism, we might surmise that these different subtypes of theorematic reasoning rather form a continuum from the simplest corollarial examples in the one end to the most complicated theorematical specimens in the other end. Hintikka proposed one arithmetic measuring stick for such a gradual scale—the amount of ad-ditional individuals needed in the proof. But this only goes for one subtype of

326 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

theorematic reasoning, that of the introduction of further quantified particulars. Among the many species of theorematical reasoning to investigate, we

shall propose three logical levels of theorematical diagram experiment. Let us go back to the simple Euclidean example with the angle sum proof. Here, the introduction of auxiliary lines gives a basic example of the introduction of new particular objects. They are not in any way extraordinary—their very possibility is granted by basic Euclidean axioms and postulates. The only ex-traordinary thing about them is, as Shin argues, the selection of the right lines among the infinity of many possible.

A higher level of diagram experiment addresses the change of selected details of the very formalism making the former experiment possible. The famous geometrical example, of course, is the change of the parallel axiom12 which made possible the angle sum proof. This axiom was originally changed in order to try to find an ad absurdum proof: if a changed parallel axiom lead to inconsistencies in geometry, this would prove the parallel axiom was a theorem of the theory, and the rather cumbersome postulate could change status and become a theorem of geometry rather than part of the premisses. Famously, these attempts failed and lead, instead, to new systems of non-Euclidean geometries by Bolyai, Lobachevsky, Riemann, etc. in the mid-19th century. The parallel axiom could be changed, now, in two basic directions: instead of one possible parallel, given a line and a point, no parallel lines could be drawn through the point, or an infinity of parallel lines could be drawn—resulting in elliptic and hyperbolic geometries, respectively. But the very change of the parallel axiom is obviously an experiment with a wholly different status than the addition of auxiliary lines in the angle sum proof. Here, the very definition of which objects are taken to be possible in the formalism is changed—and a theorem such as the angle sum theorem will consequently be revised—in the former case, the angle sum will be more than 180 degrees, in the latter, less. Generally, experiments varying axioms, postulates, object definitions, transformation rules etc. of a theory must be ascribed a status different from the mere introduction of an object allowed by the existing rule system.

A still higher level, now, may be grasped from the same example. After the realization that three different types of geometries may result from the change of the parallel axiom, an experiment on an even higher level was possible: to vary and synthesize all such geometries and organize them on one continuum so that Euclidean geometry now forms a point with zero curvature of space

327Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

on a line with different elliptic geometries having different positive curvatures, hyperbolic geometries having different negative curvatures (Bolyai, Riemann). By doing so, those pioneers undertook a step characterized by Peirce before he discovered the corollarial-theorematic distinction:

Mathematical reasoning consists in thinking how things already remarked may be conceived as making a part of a hitherto unremarked system, especially by means of the introduction of the hypothesis of continuity where no continu-ity had hitherto been thought of. (‘Review of Spinoza’s Ethic’ 1894, in: Peirce, 1975–1987, II, pp. 84–85)

This third step realizes how Euclidean geometry and the infinite number of elliptic and hyperbolic geometries form part of ‘a hitherto unremarked system’ given by variation of curvature—exactly by taking them to be connected by the continuous variation of curvature.

Of course, still higher syntheses are possible—in geometry, the generaliza-tions of the Erlangen program, defining different geometries by which invari-ances their transformation procedures allow for (thus finding a higher-order unremarked system of which both (non-)Euclidean geometries, projective geometry, and topology form a part)—or the generalization by Hilbert, tak-ing the axiomatic structure of geometries as fixed while the interpretation of which model of objects they refer to could be subject to variation—or the generalization of category theory allowing for the co-articulation of geometry with different branches of mathematics, etc.

Such syntheses, however, seem to repeat the two latter types of theore-matic experiments on higher levels. Thus, the three theorematic levels distin-guished here—the introduction of a new object, and the two types of intro-ducing a foreign idea, the experiment with one or more of the basic object or rule definitions, and the establishment of a system of different versions of those definitions, seem to to give us a hypothesis of three different types of theorematic diagram experiment.

The three levels in applied diagrams

Let us argue by example in discussing diagram experiments of these three kinds in applied diagrams, taking the geographical example of topographical

328 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

maps. Here, the tracing of a route on the map from one location to another must constitute an example of corollarial reasoning. It does introduce new elements—the real or imaginary drawing of a line on the map, respecting, in addition to the mathematical aspects of the diagram, additional features of physico-geographical ontology: the trajectory should follow roads, not cross lakes, swamps, buildings, mountains etc. Geography, of course, is no fully axiomatized science, and the regional ontology of geography makes the additional geographical diagram constraints more vague than the exact math-ematical aspects of the same diagram. A practical example of corollarial map reasoning may be the Danish police detective Jørn ‘Old Man’ Holm’s compu-ter program, immediately plotting huge amounts of cell phone information related to suspects on a map:

Fig. 4

Calls from the same cell phone are marked by the same colour. This diagram representation does not add anything new to previously existing information —except for the synthesizing a lot of single informations on one map, infor-mation which otherwise would have to be gathered from long lists of single pieces of longitude-latitude information of cell phone masts, cell phone

329Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

numbers and call-up times. The synthesis of such information on one and the same diagram makes it possible to grasp in one glance gestalt information about cell phone trajectories on the map which would otherwise require com-plicated, time-demanding and not immediately convincing argumentation in court. Diagrammatic argumentation, by contrast, proves highly efficient in court where Holm has been called as an expert witness in many severe cases about drug smuggling, trafficking etc. Obviously, it becomes harder for a defendant to stay with his explanation that he spent the whole day in front of his tv set when a diagram proves that his cell-phone travelled from one end of the country and back the same day. Such information synthesis on a diagram constitutes an example of corollarial reasoning—unproblematically adding to the mathematical diagram aspects of points and lines those of the regional ontologies of geography and human communication.

Now, we may argue that the introduction of a new object in the diagram, e. g. in the shape of a ruler, marks a first small step in theorematical reason-ing. It permits us to compare distances across the map—and even if having become an everyday utensil in our time and automatized in GPS and else-where, the ruler must have been a major breakthrough when the first distance calculation on a map was actually performed.

Still higher species of diagram experiment with maps may be gathered from science. A recent such example stems from Jared Diamond’s celebrated book Guns, Germs, and Steel, tracing the roots of domesticated agriculture on Earth since the beginning of the neolithic period. A basic argument in the book comes from Diamond’s diagram experiment with a world map (Diamond 2005, 177):

Fig. 5

330 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

Diamond’s basic observation is that among the three major continental com-plexes, Eurasia, Africa, and the Americas, there is a seminal difference—the former is roughly oriented East-West, while the latter are both oriented North-South. This almost trivial diagram experiment receives its non-triviali-ty (which qualifies it as a piece of theorematic reasoning) from the underlying combination of biogeography with human culture in the regional ontology of the diagram. The domestication of plants and animals is a watershed event in human culture giving rise to the agricultural revolution and the development of large-scale, layered societies. Domestication presupposes the presence of easily domesticated species and the stable human settlement over many gen-erations in the environment favoring the survival of these species. But local domestications only get the ability to dominate the development of human civilization if they are able to spread from there to other areas and cultures. But biogeographically, species are tied to local climate,—and local climate roughly depends on the latitude, forming isotherms across a temperature gradient falling from Equator towards the Poles. So the piecing together of these pieces of geographical ontology into a system depends upon a diagram experiment: once you have domesticated a species, where may it spread? Most favourably it spreads in the overall East-West direction, along isotherms, keeping climate conditions approximately constant—as opposed to traveling in the North-South direction where climate changes drastically with latitude. By this piece of a priori diagram reasoning—based on the combination of biogeographical ontology and the ontology of human culture development—Eurasia stands out as a privileged site for the original domestication of agri-cultural species (as opposed to Africa which might immediately be taken as a better candiate, original cradle of the human species as it is). Empirical find-ings subsequently corroborate this piece of theorematic reasoning: the fertile crescent of present-day Israel, Palestine, Syria, and Iraq seems to form the origin of many of the most important domestic species of the whole world, while the Far East comes in second. These areas were able to communicate domestications along the East-West axis and export them to Europe and the Far East. Of course, theorematicity must be a vaguer concept in empirical examples like this, where the ontologies of biogeography and of culture are not exhaustively described, but still an argument may be made which runs as follows. The complex of three basic propositions 1) domestication of a species is a local event, 2) requiring stable human settlement in the natural niche of the species 3) and the spread of such species must favor isotherms,

331Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

combined with the diagram experiment of searching the world map where the most favorable isotherms occur, constitutes a piece of theorematic reasoning. It introduces a new object on the map—the possible spreading trajectories of domesticated animal and plant species—and thus hypothesizes a general regularity on the globe. This experiment on the map involves the combination of concepts from different regional ontologies, of geography, biogeography, meteorology, cultural history—in some sense, it synthesizes different world maps charting findings in these different disciplines as a prerequisite of the experiment. Thus, it provides a new argument for which cultures were able to survive. But it does not introduce a foreign idea.

A further geographical example may be the more famous diagram experi-ment by the German geographer and explorer Alfred Wegener leading to the plate-tectonics of current geology. Famously, Wegener was toying with a map and noticing that the West coast of Africa strangely fit like a puzzle piece into the East coast of South America:

Fig. 6

The coastline fit of

South America and Africa,

supplemented with

geological similarities, from Wegener 1929, p. 73

(the illustration adapted

by Wegener from

Alexander du Toit).

332 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

This lead to Wegener’s groundbreaking 1912 idea (‘Die Entstehung der Kon-tinente’) that these continents had once been one—a controversial argument initially ridiculed, but much later corroborated by the findings of geological and biological similarities along the two coasts and finally accepted after the discovery of the mid-Atlantic mountain range as the decisive indication that the ocean does in fact ‘grow’ in the middle. This diagram experiment belongs to a second level as compared to the Jared Diamond example. Here, not only new objects or connections are introduced—here a completely new idea is introduced, namely that of continents moving over time. Taken on the level of pure diagrams, of course, nothing is strange—all Wegener did was to take a geometrical object and make a classical rigid Euclidean movement in order

Fig. 7

Reconstructions of the world

map accordig to the continental

drift theory , from Wegener 1929, p. 19

333Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

to let it face another object. This is permitted by geometry, but, of course, not by the regional ontology of pre-Wegener geography. So Wegener’s diagram experiment changed an axiom of geography, as it were—the assumption of long-term stability of large-scale features of the Earth surface—and so introduced not only a new object, but a foreign idea, that of continents moving on a geological timescale.

An example of a third level diagram experiment in geography might be taken from the same piece of history of science: the reinterpretation of the whole of the surface of the Earth in terms of moving continental plates, inverting their present movements and extrapolating them into the past in order to trace the origins of the continents. Mountain ranges were now seen as the results of continent collisions and volcanic areas as the result of chasms between plates going in each their direction. This permitted the coordinated diagram experiment reconstructing the original ur-continent of Pangaea. Wegener already presented the idea of the ur-continent in his 1915 book, it was baptized Pangaea at at 1928 conference, and was presented like this in the 1929 version of his book Die Entstehung der Kontinente und Ozeane shortly before his death in 1930 (see Fig. 7).

Here, the particular change of an axiom lead to the systematic reinter-pretation of a whole conceptual structure of geographical and geological ontology, effectively integrating the two into one discipline by seeing the same forces in work all over the surface of the Earth—in some ways comparable to the systematization of geometries after degrees of curvature.

Theorematic reasoning and Hypostatic Abstraction

We may sum up our hypothesis of three basic levels of Theorematic reasoning as follows:

1) Addition of new individuals to the premises2) Higher-level experiment with variation of axiom or transformation rule3) Establishment of system of different axioms or rules

Now, what is the relations of them to Hypostatic Abstraction—the proce-dure Peirce described as making a second-level substantive out of a first-level predicate, thereby creating a new object of thought? As we have seen in this

334 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

paper, Peirce sometimes distinguishes non-abstract from abstract theoremat-ic reasonings; while in an early quote he almost identifies abstraction with theorematic reasoning. Immediately, the talk about individual instantiation in the first theorematic reasoning type seems to preclude that abstraction should play any role here. Peirce’s debatable analysis of lines as abstractions from the trajectories of moving particles would make the subsidiary lines in the angle sum proof abstract objects added in the proof. In any case, the importance of this step lies in the selection of the individual lines needed for the proof which is not a matter of abstraction. Likewise, such lines do not add an idea which could be said to be foreign to the theorem to be proved. Maybe the first-level addition of new individuals could comprise both abstract and non-abstract cases.

Different, however, seems the case of the second level of theorematic reasoning, implying that something in the rule system is taken as object of experiment, leading to a ‘foreign idea’. If the parallel axiom is what defines the hypostatic abstraction of ‘parallelness’ or ‘being parallel’, then the varia-tion of that axiom introduces competing definitions of that abstraction—the ‘foreign ideas’ of that level.

The third level, then, would be that of making a whole system out of hypostatic abstractions—this system constituting itself, then, a complex hypostatic abstraction on a higher level, involving such new hypostatic terms as ‘curvature of space’. This level seems characterized by ‘the introduction of the hypothesis of continuity where no continuity had hitherto been thought of ’, as Peirce had it—establishing continua of hypostatic abstractions from the second level.

No doubt, the relation between theorematic reasoning and abstraction allows for many sophistications which is beyond our scope to investigate here. This must be left for further reasoning.

Thanks to Michael Hoffmann, Ahti Pietarinen, Sun-Joo Shin, and André de Tienne for comments and help.

335Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

Notes

1 Taking Comte’s principle (a science is below a another science from which it takes its principles, and above another science whose principles borrows from it) as basis for his classifications of the sciences, Peirce places mathematics on top as the science from which all other sciences borrow principles.

2 These equivalences between alternate angles, of course, are granted by Euclid’s Proposition 29: If two straight lines are parallel, then a straight line that meets them makes the alternate angles equal.

3 Shin’s investigation of syntheticity in Kant and Peirce concludes as follows (1997, 37): ‘Even though Peirce himself did not engage in a full evaluation of Kant’s analytic/synthetic distinction, we can now acquire a quite comprehensive picture of this matter. Peirce’s theory of mathematics locates the origin of Kant’s synthetic-ity in two different sources: One is the historical fact that Kant was writing before the discovery of quantification theory, and the other is Kant’s appreciation of dif-ferent kinds of reasoning. The former source is responsible for Kant’s claim about the statement “7 + 5 = 12”, but his claim about the statement. “A triangle’s angles sum to 180 degrees” is related to the latter. The development of logic cleared away the first source of syntheticity, and we know that this origin of Kant’s syntheticity is not sustainable any more.’ Consequently, the other, more sound aspect of Kant’s syntheticity relies in his appreciation of two different modes of reasoning, logical and mathematical,—which were reconstructed by Peirce as corrolarial and theore-matical reasoning, respectively. See also Stjernfelt 2007, ch. 8.

4 As abstractions come in many levels, and abstract/concrete is not coextensive with general/particular, the issue whether the subsidiary lines should be taken as abstractions or particulars or both needs not bother us.

5 The selection of the right elements to add is abductive. In the angle sum case, the addition of parallel lines is probably prompted by the previous knowledge of Proposition 29 dealing with the relation between parallel lines and the size of alter-nate angles—because the theorem to be proved is about angle sizes. So even if the selection itself is not deductive but merely abductive, the abduction is motivated by a certain likeness between the theorem and possibilities offered by previous theo-rems proved.

6 A parallel quote, emphazising the theorematic step as the addition of a new idea, is the following: ‘I shall term the step of so introducing into a demonstration a new idea not explicitly or directly contained in the premisses of the reasoning or in the condition of the proposition which gets proved by the aid of this introduction, a

336 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

theoric step.’ (‘Amazing Mazes’, 1908, CP 4.613)7 The shortest presentation is probably: ‘For mathematical reasoning consists in con-

structing a diagram according to a general precept, in observing certain relations between parts of that diagram not explicitly required by the precept, showing that these relations will hold for all such diagrams, and in formulating this conclusion in general terms. All valid necessary reasoning is in fact thus diagrammatic.’ (‘Les-sons from the History of Science’, 1896, CP 1.54) The object of mathematics will be pure diagrams of any kind, while ordinary reasoning as well as the empiri-cal sciences will use diagrams applied in being constrained by existing relations— empirical data and regional ontology— as well.

8 A detailed attempt at developing the distinction between corollarial and theore-matical reasoning in ‘The Logic of History’ (1901, NEM IV) takes the proof of (x + y) + z = x + (y + z) as example of the former and the proof that ‘every mul-titude is less than a multitude’ (≈ there is no largest set) as example of the latter. The overall argument, however, is not very clear. Especially the latter proof which seems to be a sort of diagonal argument implying a power set construction is not very clearly presented, and even if Peirce concludes it ‘requires the invention of an idea not at all forced upon us by the terms of the thesis’, he does not make explicit what that new idea should be, apart from not being derivable from the definition of the concept ‘fewer’ (a clearer example of Peirce’s version of Cantor’s power set theorem can be found a few years earlier in ‘The Logic of Relatives’ (1897, CP 3.548). Similarly, at the end of ‘Logic of History’, Peirce has a brief and clear summary of the Power Set Theorem: ‘I proved that there is no maximum mul-titude by considering the collection of all possible collections of the numbers of a collection. Now a collection is an abstraction …’ (1901, NEM IV, p. 11), but still there is no indication of what the ‘new idea’ introduced should be. Certainly not the abstraction of ‘collection’ which is presupposed by the multitudes of the premisses—rather the power set notion of the set of all possible subsets of a given set. Peirce seems to have realized the early discussion of corollarial/theorematical in ‘The Logic of History’ was less than satisfying; according to the Robin catalogue on the Ms. (691), Peirce added the following note to the Ms.: ‘These pages are to be used in the chapter of the Logic treating Deductive Reasoning. But the theory needs completion.’

9 Here, I quote Ms. 754 from Hoffmann (forthcoming) as the ISP page 8 is missing from the Microfilm edition where it seems to belong between pages 5 and 6.

10 Maybe the very concept of theorematical reasoning is necessarily open—given the inexhaustibility of mathematics, it may not be granted we should be able to chart

337Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

all possible subtypes of such reasoning beforehand?11 A related issue is the degree of conscious access to reasoning processes: ‘If, howev-

er, as the English suppose, the feeling of rationality is the product of a sort of sub-conscious reasoning—by which I mean an operation which would be a reasoning if it were fully conscious and deliberate—the accompanying feeling of evidence may well be due to a dim recollection of the experimentation with diagrams.’ (CP 2.172) The experience of evidence resulting from rational reasoning may, in some cases, depend upon subconscious reasoning. A recurring argument in Peirce, however, points to the fact that such reasoning—and, even more, that of com-puters—lacks self-control as the hallmark of real reasoning. As to mechanization of reasoning, Peirce often discusses the corollarial/theorematical distinction with reference to computers (‘logic machines’). His overall idea is that the former will generally be mechanizable, while the latter lie beyond mechanization because their introduction of new elements by experiment requires creativity and ingenuity. These ideas might be seen as a vague anticipation of later discoveries of decision limitations in the philosophy of mathematics and computation (Gödel’s incom-pleteness theorem, or Turing’s related halting problem), but they are not simply equivalent. These limitations have another character than Peirce’s distinction, because they limit the range even of purely mechanical decision procedures which Peirce would, in all probability, categorize as corollarial.

12 Strictly speaking, the parallel postulate. It has become common usage to call it an axiom.

Literature

Benacerraf, P. with H. Putnam (eds.) 1983 Philosophy of Mathematics, Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press.

Brunning, Jacqueline and Forster, Paul (eds.) 1997 The Rule of Reason. The Philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

Cooke, E. 2010 ‘Peirce’s General Theory of Inquiry and the Problem of Mathematics’, in Moore 2010, 169–292.

Diamond, Jared 2005 Guns, Germs and Steel, London: Vintage, 2005 [1997].Dipert, Randall 1995 ‘Peirce’s Underestimated Place in the History of Logic: A

Response to Quine’, in Ketner 1995, 32–58.— 1997 ‘Peirce’s Philosophical Conception of Sets’, in Houser et al. (eds.) 1997.— 2004 ‘Peirce’s Deductive Logic: Its Development, Influence, and Philosophical

338 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

Significance’, in Misak 2004, 287–324.Dougherty, Charles J. 1983 ‘Peirce’s Phenomenological Defense of Deduction’, in

Freeman 1983, 167–177.Fisch, Max 1986 ‘Peirce’s Progress from Nominalism Towards Realism’, in Fisch (eds.

K. L. Ketner and C. J. W. Kloesel) Peirce, Semeiotic, and Pragmatism, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 184–200.

Freeman, Eugene (ed.) 1983 The Relevance of Charles Peirce, La Salle, Illinois 1983: The Hegeler Institute.

Hintikka, Jaakko 1983 ‘C. S. Peirce’s “First Real Discovery” and Its Contemporary Relevance’, in E. Freeman (ed.) The Relevance of Charles Peirce, La Salle, Ill. 1983: The Hegeler Institute, 107–118.

— 1997 ‘The Place of C. S. Peirce in the History of Logical Theory’, in J. Brunning and P. Forster (eds.) The Rule of Reason, Toronto etc.: University of Toronto Press 1997, 13–33 (also in Hintikka 1997, p. 140–61).

— 1997a Lingua Universalis vs. Calculus Ratiocinator. An Ultimate Presupposition of Twen-tieth-Century Philosophy, Dordrecht etc. 1997: Kluwer.

Hoffmann, Michael 2005 Erkenntnisentwicklung. Ein semiotisch-pragmatischer Ansatz, Frankfurt: Klostermann.

— 2006 ‘Seeing Problems, Seeing Solutions. Abduction and Diagrammatic Reasoning in a theory of Scientific Discovery’, Working Paper #2006.15, Georgia Institute of Technology.

— forthcoming ‘ “Theoric Transformations” and a New Classification of Abductive Inferences’, in: Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society.

Houser, Nathan, Don D. Roberts and James van Evra (eds.) 1997 Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Levy, Stephen H. 1997 ‘Peirce’s Theoremic/Corollarial Distinction and the Intercon-nections between Mathematics and Logic’, in Houser et al. (1997), p. 85–110.

Moore, Matthew E. 2010 (ed.) New Essays on Peirce’s Mathematical Philosophy, Chicago and La Salle: Open Court.

Peirce, Charles S. 1976 New Elements of Mathematics, (ed. C. Eisele) I–IV, The Hague: Mouton.

— 1975–87 Contributions to the Nation, I–IV (ed. K. L. Ketner & J. E. Cook), Lubbock TX: Texas Technological University Press.

— 1992 Reasoning and the Logic of Things, (eds. Ketner and Putnam), Camb.Mass.: Harvard University Press.

— 1992 The Essential Peirce, vol. I. (1867–1893), [EPI], eds. N. Houser and C. Kloesel, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

339Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

— 1997 Pragmatism as a Principle, (ed. A. Turrisi), Albany: SUNY Press.— 1998 Collected Papers [CP, references given by volume number and paragraph],

I–VIII, (ed. Hartshorne and Weiss; Burks) London: Thoemmes Press (1931–58).— 1998 The Essential Peirce, vol. II (1893–1913) [EPII], eds. N. Houser and C. Kloesel,

Bloomington: Indiana University Press. — 2010 Philosophy of Mathematics. Selected Writings, ed. M. Moore, Bloomington and

Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.— (no year) ‘Logic, Considered as Semeiotic’ [LCS], constructed from manuscript

L 75 by Joseph Ransdell (1902) (http://www.cspeirce.com/menu/library/bycsp/l75/ver1/l75v1-01.htm).

— Manuscripts at the Houghton Library referred to by Ms. numbers in the Microfilm edition 1966 The Charles S. Peirce Papers, Microfilm Edition, Thirty Reels with Two Supplementary Reels Later Added. Cambridge: Harvard University Library Photo-graphic Service. Manuscript numbers also refer to the Robin catalogue of the Mss.(Robin 1967). As to manuscript page numbers, ‘CSP’ refers to Peirce’s pagina-tion (which is not unanimous since several parallel drafts may belong to the same Ms.), while ‘ISP’ refers to the pagination of the Mss. by the Institute for Studies in Pragmaticism, also used by the Peirce Edition Project in Indianapolis. When ISP numbers are not available, numbers refer to the sequence of the microfilm reel, e. g. ‘Reel 16, 1434–35’ meaning the 1434th and 1435th page of reel 16.

Robin, Richard 1967 Annotated Catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce, Worcester Mass.: University of Massachusetts Press 1967.

Shin, Sun-Joo 1994 The Logical Status of Diagrams, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

— 1997 ‘Kant’s Syntheticity Revised by Peirce’, Synthese 113, 1–41. — 2000 The Iconic Logic of Peirce’s Graphs, Cambridge MA: MIT. — 2010 ‘Peirce’s Two Ways of Abstraction’, in Moore 2010, 41–58.Stjernfelt, Frederik 2007 Diagrammatology. An Investigation on the Borderlines of Phenom-

enology, Ontology, and Semiotics, Dordrecht: Springer Verlag.— forthcoming a) ‘Signs Conveying Information. On the range of Peirce’s notion of

propositions: Dicisigns’, in Journal of Signs and Semiotic Systems.— forthcoming b) ‘The evolution of semiotic self-control. Sign evolution as the on-

going subdivision, articulation and making explict of a basic metabolic argument structure’, in T. Schilhab, F. Stjernfelt, and T. Deacon (eds.) New Perspectives on the Symbolic Species, Yale University Press.

— forthcoming c) ‘The Generality of Signs. Anti-Psychologism in the Foundations of Semiotics—and its Actual Relevance’, in Semiotica.

340 Peirce’s Notion of Diagram Experiment

Tiercelin, Claudine 2010 ‘Peirce on Mathematical Objects and Mathematical Object-ivity’, in Moore 2010, 81–122.

Webb, Judson 2006 ‘Constructions, Intuitions, and Theorems’, in Randall E. Auxier and Lewis Edwin Hahn (eds.) The Philosophy of Jaakko Hintikka, Chicago etc.: Open Court, p. 196–301.

Wegener, Alfred 1912 ‘Die Entstehung der Kontinente’, Geologische Rundschau 3(4), 276–292.

— 1929 Die Entstehung der Kontinente und Ozeane [The Origin of Continents and Oceans] (4 ed.). Braunschweig: Friedrich Vieweg & Sohn.

Figurenbild und Diagramm Lot und seine Töchter (Louvre, RF 1185)

Felix Thürlemann, Konstanz

Gegenstand und Fragestellung

Die nachfolgenden Überlegungen haben ein einziges Werk zum Gegenstand: ein unsigniertes niederländisches Tafelgemälde des frühen 16. Jahrhunderts, das die Geschichte von Lot und seinen Töchtern nach Genesis Kapitel 19 darstellt (Abb. 1).1 Das seit 1900 zum Bestand des Louvre gehörende Gemälde konnte bislang noch mit keinem bekannten Malernamen sicher in Verbin-dung gebracht werden und nimmt deshalb, obwohl von höchster künstleri-scher Qualität, in der Kunstgeschichte eine eher marginale Position ein. Das kleinformatige Historienbild – es misst 48 auf 34 cm – ist auch ein Meister-werk der Landschaftsmalerei. Historie und Weltlandschaft (in der Form einer bravourösen Nachtdarstellung mit mehreren Lichtquellen): dieses Miteinan-der passt gut zum dargestellten alttestamentlichen Thema, einer Geschichte, die vom Untergang zweier Städte und der geplanten Vernichtung aller ihrer Einwohner, aber auch von der anschließenden Rettung eines einzigen Ge-rechten und seines Geschlechts aufgrund des Inzests mit seinen beiden Töch-tern handelt.

Das Gemälde wurde früher fälschlicherweise Lucas van Leyden zuge-schrieben.2 Im Louvre lautet die Beschriftung heute „Leyden oder Antwer-pen, um 1525–30“, wobei die Entstehungszeit wohl etwas früher anzusetzen ist. Stilistisch gehört das Gemälde meiner Ansicht nach zur Kerngruppe jener Werke, die Max Jakob Friedländer unter dem Namen ‚Jan de Cock‘ zusam-mengefasst hat.3

Das Werk hatte einen berühmten Verehrer, den französischen Schriftstel-ler und Theatertheoretiker Antonin Artaud, der es bei einem seiner Besuche im Louvre entdeckte und 1931 unter dem Titel „La mise en scène et la mé-

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 341–364.

342 Figurenbild und Diagramm

taphysique“ ausführlich beschrieb und kongenial deutete.4 Artaud fasste die Tafel als Idealmodell für das von ihm konzipierte Theater auf, ein Theater, das auch ohne Worte auskommen kann: „Dieses Gemälde ist das, was das Theater sein sollte“, lautet die Quintessenz seines Textes.5

Ich möchte das Pariser Gemälde im Folgenden von einer bildtheoretischen Warte aus betrachten. Meine These lautet, dass das Werk – aber bis zu einem gewissen Ausmaß jede Art von komponierter Figurenmalerei – einem Dia-gramm vergleichbar ist oder zumindest diagrammatische Elemente enthält, auch wenn sich im allgemeinen Verständnis – aber auch entsprechend der bildtheoretischen Doxa – Figurenbild und Diagramm grundlegend vonein-ander unterscheiden.

Die Pariser Darstellung der Geschichte von Lot und seinen Töchtern entspricht im Wesentlichen dem klassischen Konzept des Gemäldes, wie es von den Vertretern der italienischen Frührenaissance Filippo Brunelleschi und Leon Battista Alberti experimentell entwickelt und theoretisch begrün-det worden ist: eine mit Hilfe raffiniert abgestufter Farbnuancen geschaffene Vorspiegelung eines rechteckig gerahmten Fensterausblicks auf die Welt. Die Szene simuliert mit verschiedenen gestalterischen Mitteln einen Weltaus-schnitt, der sich von den im Vordergrund ‚zum Greifen nahe‘ dargestellten Weinflaschen bis zum fernen Horizont erstreckt, an dem die Silhouette einer ins Meer gebauten Stadt zu erkennen ist.

Der simulierte Sachverhalt ist ebenso ungewöhnlich wie komplex: Wun-derbare kosmische Ereignissen sind mit einer außerordentlichen, ja skandalö-sen menschlichen Handlung kombiniert. Dennoch stellt sich ein überzeugen-der effet de réel ein. ‚So ist es gewesen!‘ oder genauer: ‚So könnte es gewesen sein, damals als …‘ Das Gemälde evoziert eine Vorstellung, die der Leser des biblischen Textes nur vage als so genanntes ‚inneres Bild‘ zu realisieren braucht. Es sind die Konventionen des Figurenbildes, die den Maler gezwun-gen haben, das im Text nur allgemein Formulierte, wie den Begriff ‚Stadt‘, als ein ganz bestimmtes architektonisches Gefüge, als eine mögliche Stadt zu imaginieren. Das neue Bildkonzept der Renaissance verlangte die Individua-lisierung des Gezeigten.

Eine weitere Konvention zwang den Maler dazu, den Ausblick grundsätz-lich einer Art Momentaufnahme gleichzusetzen, für seine Darstellung einen Augenblick aus dem Verlauf der biblischen Erzählung auszuwählen. Der Be-griff ‚Momentaufnahme‘ ist anachronistisch, doch war es die nachträgliche Erfindung des mechanischen Mediums der Fotografie, die das albertianische

343Figurenbild und Diagramm

Abb. 1 Anonym (‚Jan de Cock‘), Lot und seine Töchter, um 1520. Paris, Louvre

344 Figurenbild und Diagramm

Konzept des perspektivisch konstruierten Fensterausblickes auf ideale Weise realisiert hat. Der Maler unseres Bildes hat sich, wie wir sehen werden, an die Norm der punktuellen Zeitauffassung nicht ganz gehalten, was übrigens in der vorfotografischen Zeit durchaus üblich und allgemein akzeptiert war. Dennoch musste er besondere Strategien entwickeln, um mit einem unbeweg-ten Fensterausblick eine Geschichte erzählen zu können.

Stellen wir dem Gemälde ein visuelles Objekt gegenüber, das etwa gleich-zeitig entstanden ist, aber mit diesem auf den ersten Blick nichts gemein hat. Es ist das, was man üblicherweise ein ‚Diagramm‘ nennt (Abb. 2): eine Linien-zeichnung, ungerahmt, direkt in das Trägermedium Papier eingeschrieben, in den Textspiegel eingefügt. Es handelt sich um ein zweifach axialsymmetrisch geordnetes Gefüge von doppelt gezogenen geraden Linien und Kreisen, in das einzelne Wörter eingesetzt sind. Wir bemerken Charakteristika, die denen des Figurenbildes konträr sind: ein symmetrisch geordnetes Zusammenspiel von geometrisch gezogenen Linien ohne Individualität, ohne farbige Nuan-cierung, gefüllt mit sprachlichen Allgemeinbegriffen. Nicht die Schilderung einer bestimmten Geschichte ist hier das Ziel, sondern die Manifestation von

Abb. 2

Gregor Reisch

Margarita philosophica, Basel 1517,

Holzschnitt zu Lib. II, Trac. III, Cap. IV

345Figurenbild und Diagramm

allgemein gültigen Gesetzen. Der Gegensatz zwischen den beiden ‚Bildern‘ (Abb. 1 und Abb. 2) könnte kaum größer sein.

Es ist verständlich, wenn die Bildwissenschaft zu Beginn ihrer Entwick-lung versucht, mit klaren typologischen Setzungen einzelne Manifestationen aus dem großen Universum der vom Menschen zu Kommunikationszwecken hergestellten visuellen Artefakte, wie das ‚Figurenbild‘ und das ‚Diagramm‘, möglichst deutlich voneinander abzuheben. Ich möchte im Folgenden jedoch den gegenteiligen Weg einschlagen und die Frage stellen, was ein Figurenbild mit einem Diagramm gemein haben könnte. Doch bevor ich diese Frage zu beant-worten versuche, möchte ich mich dem Pariser Gemälde, das mir als Beispiel dient, mit einer ersten Beschreibung und Elementen für eine Analyse nähern.6

Doppelte Gliederung

Die Komposition ist entlang einer von links oben nach rechts unten absteigen-den Diagonale gegliedert (Schema a). Diese erste Gliederung entspricht einer raum-zeitlichen Differenzierung des dargestellten Sachverhaltes: Die rechte obere Hälfte stellt nach einer traditionellen Formel gleichzeitig das Ferne und das Vergangene dar: Wir sehen weit weg die zerstörte Stadt, aus der Lot zusammen mit seiner Familie geflohen ist. Die linke untere Hälfte hingegen führt dem Betrachter die Gegenwart, bzw. die unmittelbare Zukunft, den Akt

des Inzestes, in Nahansicht vor.Die Bildfläche ist jedoch gleichzei-

tig nach einem orthogonalen Schema gegliedert (Schema b). Die Horizont-linie des Meeres und die Vertikale des schlanken, jungen Baumes – er durch-quert beinahe die ganze Bildfläche – gliedern diese zusätzlich in vier unter-schiedlich große rechteckige Zonen,

Abb. 3

Schema a:

Raum-zeitliche Differenzierung des

dargestellten Sachverhaltes.

346 Figurenbild und Diagramm

die ich im folgenden ‚Quadranten‘ nenne. Jeder der vier Quadranten ist durch eine besondere Thematik charakterisiert. Die figurative, raumsimu-lierende Logik des Gemäldes als einem kohärenten ‚Fensterausblick‘ wird durch eine thematische Logik überblendet, die auf einer Aufteilung der Bildfläche nach den Kategorien der Vertikalität (oben vs. unten) und Horizon-talität (links vs. rechts) beruht.7

Das Gemälde besitzt eine komplexe narrative Struktur, welche die zuvor in den einzelnen Quadranten getrennt manifestierten Themenbereiche mit verschiedenen Mitteln wieder aufeinander bezieht: Im Mittelgrund, unter-halb der Stadt Sodom – sie versinkt, durch ein starkes Beben und durch Feuer, das vom Himmel fällt, zerstört im Meer – kann man, kleinformatig dargestellt, die Mitglieder von Lots Familie erkennen, wie sie aus der Stadt fliehen. Die bedrohten Figuren, die gerade eine unsichere Brücke in Rich-tung auf den fest verankerten rettenden Felsvorsprung links überqueren, he-ben sich wie ein kleines Schattentheater von der schwefelgelb erleuchteten Meeresfläche ab. Die Spitze des Zuges nehmen Lot und seine beiden Töch-ter ein. Es folgt ein Esel, der ihnen als Lasttier dient. Schließlich erkennt man – bereits in einer gewissen Distanz – die Mutter, Lots Frau, wie sie sich zur Stadt hin umwendet. Es ist der Augenblick, in dem sie in die Salzsäule verwandelt wird.

Abb. 4

Schema b:

Thematische Quadranten.

347Figurenbild und Diagramm

Wiederaufnahmen

Die drei Figuren an der Spitze des Zuges, Lot und seine beiden Töchter, sind ein zweites Mal im linken unteren Quadranten der Bildfläche dargestellt. Lot sitzt, die ältere Tochter eng umschlungen, zu Füssen des Baumes und bietet dieser Wein in einer Schale an; die jüngere, aufreizend gekleidete Tochter steht daneben und ist daran, weiteren Wein aus einer der Reiseflaschen in einen Krug umzufüllen. In einem Paralleldiskurs der Dinge – Flaschen, Wein und Krug – wird die sexuelle Vereinigung, die mit ihrer Hilfe zustande kom-men wird, bereits angedeutet.

Doch auch die Mutter ist im Bild wieder aufgenommen. Sie erscheint ein zweites Mal, erneut leblos, im Felsen des linken oberen Quadranten in der Form eines riesigen, mit einem Schleier bedeckten Frauenkopfes. Die Tatsa-che, dass dieser Kopf, den der Betrachter im Profil wahrnimmt, zur unterge-henden Stadt hin ausgerichtet ist, spricht dafür, dass es sich hier tatsächlich um eine zweite Darstellung der zur Salzsäule verwandelten Mutter handelt.

Es bleibt der Esel. Auch er ist ein zweites Mal dargestellt, aber sozusagen in einem späteren Zustand. Der Esel erscheint im rechten unteren Qua-dranten nochmals, als Skelett, zu Füßen eines verfaulten, abgestorbenen Baumstrunks.

Man kann feststellen, dass die fünf Figuren des Schattenrisses, die auf der Bildfläche ein zweites Mal im größeren Format wieder aufgenommen sind, dem orthogonalen Schema ent-sprechend verteilt sind, wie es durch die Horizontlinie und den aufragen-den Baum gebildet wird: Lot und seine beiden Töchter besetzen den Quadranten unten/links, Lots Frau den Quadranten oben/links, der Esel den Quadranten unten/rechts. Im Quadranten oben/rechts ist die Stadt Sodom dargestellt, wie sie vom himm-

Abb. 5

Detail aus Abb. 1:

Das brennende Sodom.

348 Figurenbild und Diagramm

lischen Feuer zerstört brennend im Meer versinkt. Auf dem Marktplatz, der wie eine schiefe Ebene in die Diagonale gekippt ist, irren die Menschen hil-fesuchend umher, während über ihnen die Spitze des gotischen Stadtturms vom Beben erschüttert abbricht (Abb. 5). Die Detailaufnahme dieser gespens-tischen Szene mit ihren raffiniert gesetzten Lichteffekten, Schlagschatten und Wasserspiegelungen gibt einen Eindruck von der überragenden malerischen Qualität des Gemäldes und der Beobachtungsgabe seines Autors, die sich gleichzeitig auf optische Kenntnisse stützt.

Verschleifungen

Es ist freilich festzuhalten, dass die Quadranten nicht geometrisch scharf von-einander abgesetzt sind. Die Horizontlinie des Meeres ist mehrfach markiert, und auch die durch den ondulierten Stamm des jungen Baumes angezeigte Vertikale ist beweglich. Dem Maler war offenbar daran gelegen, die Grenzen zwischen den einzelnen Quadranten in feinen Übergängen miteinander zu verschleifen. So breitet sich der Mantel von Lots älterer Tochter in den Qua-dranten unten rechts mit dem faulenden Baumstrunk hinein aus, und ein Teil des Skelettes ragt umgekehrt in den linken unteren Quadranten hinein. Wir werden auf diese unscharfe Trennlinie zurückkommen.

Abb. 6

Schema c:

ZerstörungErstarrung

ZerfallZeugung

349Figurenbild und Diagramm

Dennoch erscheint die Aufteilung der Bildfläche entsprechend dem orthogo-nalen Netz für die Wahrnehmung des Werkes relevant. Sie wird unterstrichen durch die Tatsache, dass jeder Quadrant – als eine mehr oder weniger klar be-grenzte rechteckige Zone – eine thematische Einheit besitzt, die jeweils zwang-los mit einem abstrakten Begriff bezeichnet werden kann (vgl. Schema c):

Der Quadrant oben rechts, in dem die Stadt Sodom zusammen mit ihren Ein-wohnern von mehreren Katastrophen gleichzeitig heimgesucht wird, kann mit dem Begriff Zerstörung bezeichnet werden, dies im doppelten Sinne: als Vernichtung der Bewohner und der materiellen Güter.

Dem rechten oberen Quadranten steht links unten diagonal die Szene gegen-über, in der sich der Inzest vorbereitet. Entsprechend dem Text der Bibel ist dieser die Konsequenz der Zerstörung der Bewohner zweier Städte, von denen einzig Lot und seine beiden Töchter verschont bleiben, nachdem auch Lots Frau – aufgrund ihres Ungehorsams – als mögliche Gebärerin ausgeschieden ist. Der Diagonale entspricht ein starker semantischer Ge-gensatz: Wenn der Quadrant oben rechts das Thema der ‚Zerstörung‘, der Vernichtung allen Lebens, manifestiert, verweist die Inzestszene unten links auf Zeugung, auf die Hervorbringung bzw. Weitergabe des Lebens.

Der Quadrant links oben, in dem die äußere Form von Lots Frau in Stein konserviert ist, kann dem Thema Erstarrung zugeordnet werden.

Eine letzte thematische Einheit manifestiert der Quadrant unten rechts, den man aufgrund des Skeletts und des faulenden Baumstrunks mit dem Be-griff des Zerfalls belegen kann. Im Gegensatz zu dem diagonal entgegen-stehenden Quadranten der ‚Erstarrung‘ links oben zersetzt sich hier die Form, indem die Materie in einen neuen Aggregatszustand übergeht. Die Auflösung der Form kommt in diesem Bereich einer ikonoklastischen Wen-dung des Bildes gegen sich selbst gleich: Die Farb- und Helligkeitskontraste werden reduziert, sodass die einzelnen Formen nur noch undeutlich wahr-genommen werden können, und die Darstellung zu einer unartikulierten dunklen Fläche hin tendiert.

Obwohl die einzelnen Quadranten aufgrund der in ihnen jeweils dargestell-ten Ereignisse und Objekte einen starken semantischen Eigenwert besitzen, ist die inhaltliche Kohärenz des Werkes als ganzem offensichtlich. Alle vier Teile, die wir mit Zerstörung, Erstarrung, Zeugung und Zersetzung charakte-risiert haben, handeln von Leben und Tod. Es drängt sich geradezu auf, die

350 Figurenbild und Diagramm

vier Termini nach dem logischen Begriffsquadrat neu zu formulieren, wie es in jüngerer Zeit in Anlehnung an die bekannte aristotelische quadrata formula (Abb. 2) entwickelt worden ist (Schema d). Anders jedoch als dies heute beim logischen Quadrat üblich ist, sind im Gemälde die starken, konträren Oppo-sitionen nicht auf der oberen Horizontale angeordnet. So stehen einander die beiden starken Begriffe, Leben und Tod, entlang der von links unten nach rechts oben aufsteigenden Diagonalen gegenüber. Die übrigen beiden Begrif-fe, ‚Erstarrung‘ und ‚Zerfall‘, die auf der absteigenden Diagonale von links oben nach rechts unten platziert sind, können den negierten Begriffen Nicht-Tod und Nicht-Leben gleichgesetzt werden.

Diagrammatik

Mit der systematischen Verteilung der Figuren auf der Bildfläche, die den existentiellen Grundbegriffen um den Hauptgegensatz von ‚Leben‘ und ‚Tod‘ zugewiesen werden können, verrät das Gemälde einen dezidiert diagramma-tischen Zugriff. Dieser besteht darin, elementare semantische Oppositionen topologischen Kategorien zuzuordnen, um so die Artikulation des Sinnes für den Betrachter sinnlich nachvollziehbar zu machen.8 Gleichzeitig aber bleibt das Gemälde ein traditionelles Figurenbild. Anders als im Diagramm sind keine Wörter auf der Bildfläche verteilt, sondern einzelne Szenen, Akteure und Dinge, die in ihrer spezifischen Gestaltung die fundamentalen Konzep-te ‚Zerstörung‘, ‚Zeugung‘, ‚Erstarrung‘ und ,Zersetzung‘ veranschaulichen.

Abb. 7

Schema d

TodNicht-Tod

Nicht-LebenLeben

351Figurenbild und Diagramm

Die begriffliche Fixierung der Kategorien ist dabei – dies muss unterstrichen werden – eine Leistung des Rezipienten. Sie ist auch intersubjektiv nicht voll-ständig festgelegt. Andere Akzentuierungen nach anderen Begriffsklassen und Kategorien sind denkbar. Die Begriffsbildung muss zudem bei der Betrach-tung des Werkes nicht bewusst realisiert und verbal expliziert werden. Das Gemälde kann immer auch gleichsam ‚naiv‘ betrachtet werden, als kohären-ter Blick auf eine vielgestaltige Welt, die von den handelnden Figuren der biblischen Geschichte bevölkert ist.

Alle handelnden Figuren sind, wie wir gesehen haben, jeweils zweimal dar-gestellt: ein erstes Mal zusammen im kleinen Schattentheater der Fluchtszene (unten rechts) und ein zweites Mal – in vergrößerter Wiederaufnahme – auf die Quadranten der Bildfläche verteilt. Die dergestalt verteilten Figuren stellen Episoden dar, in denen die in der kleinen Szene initiierte Erzählung weiterge-sponnen wird; sie sind aber gleichzeitig die systematische Explikation des Sin-nes, der die Erzählung als ganze trägt. So wird die malerische Schilderung der Geschichte von Lot und seinen Töchtern zu einer Reflexion über Leben und Tod und über das Schicksal des Menschen in der Welt. Durch die diagramma-tische Unterfütterung ist das Figurenbild mehr als eine bloße Illustration der biblischen Episode, es kann als eine eigenständige Deutung des Textes verstan-den werden.

Die diagrammatische Gestaltung hat zuerst den Maler zu systematischen Einschreibungen weiterer Figuren angeregt – und wird auch die Rezipienten zu entsprechenden weiteren Beobachtungen anregen. So ist die rechte Bild-hälfte hauptsächlich vom zerstörerischen Feuer beleuchtet, das vom Himmel fällt, während die Inzestszene der linken Bildhälfte ihr Licht vom aufsteigen-den, in einem Feuerkorb gezähmten Feuer empfängt. So werden im Gemäl-de – wiederum entsprechend der generellen kompositorischen Gliederung – zwei Formen des Feuers gegeneinander ausgespielt. Hinzu kommt, als weitere Himmelserscheinung, der Komet in der linken oberen Ecke, der zuvor den Bewohnern der Stadt das drohende Unheil angekündigt hat.9

Die erwähnten dynamischen Elemente – die beiden in gegensätzliche Richtungen sich bewegenden Feuer und der Komet als Wanderstern – unter-streichen den diagrammatischen Charakter des Gemäldes. Wie Steffen Bogen im Anschluss an Charles S. Peirce betont hat, hat das Diagramm einen dy-namischen Charakter. Das Diagramm ist eine Art ‚Denkmaschine‘, die erst dadurch Bedeutung hervorbringt, dass der Rezipient an ihr, gestützt auf den konkreten visuellen Sachverhalt, bestimmte kognitive Operationen vollzieht.

352 Figurenbild und Diagramm

Auch das Gemälde des Louvre regt den Betrachter dazu an, solche Opera-tionen im Sinne einer imaginären Weiterarbeit am dargestellten situativen Bestand vorzunehmen.10

Der Maler hat in sein Gemälde eine ganze Reihe von allusiven Metaphern eingebaut, die den Betrachter dazu auffordern, die Szene über den Moment der Darstellung hin weiterzudenken. So hat bereits Oskar Bätschmann in seiner 1981 publizierten hermeneutischen Analyse des Pariser Gemäldes darauf hingewiesen, dass das durch ein kräftiges Rot markierte rechte Knie Lots auf die Öffnung des ganz in Rot dargestellten ersten Zeltes weist und so den bevorstehenden Beischlaf mit seiner älteren Tochter in versteckter, aber durchaus suggestiver Form anzeigt.11 Die gleiche visuelle Metapher wieder-holt sich bei dem ebenfalls übertrieben angewinkelten rechten Arm der Wein einschenkenden jüngeren Tochter, der auf die Öffnung des zweiten Zeltes im Hintergrund weist. Die gleiche Metapher manifestiert sich schließlich ein drittes Mal, diesmal unter negativen Vorzeichen, im Verhältnis zwischen dem Quadranten der ‚Zeugung‘ links unten und dem Quadranten der ‚Erstarrung‘ links oben. Hinter dem großen roten Zelt entdeckt man die weiße Spitze eines dritten Zeltes, die mit einem auffälligen Dekor von Schlangenlinien markiert ist. Diese Spitze ist wie ein ‚Pfeil‘ auf das Felsentor unterhalb des versteinerten Kopfes von Lots Frau gerichtet, durch das ein Weg schlängelnd hindurch-führt. Man geht sicher nicht zu weit, wenn man in diesem Zusammenspiel der beiden Figuren, der Zeltspitze und des Felsentors, eine komplexe Metapher der unmöglich gewordenen sexuellen Verbindung zwischen Lot und seiner Frau sieht. Diese wird im Bild durch die beiden ‚möglichen‘ Verbindungen, die Inzesthandlungen zwischen Lot und seinen Töchtern, ersetzt.

Verlauf und Fortsetzung der Geschichte

Der Text der Bibel berichtet, wie die Geschichte nach dem doppelten Inzest Lots weiter geht (Gen 19.37 f.): Jede der beiden Töchter wird einen Sohn gebären, Moab und Ben-Ammi, die ihrerseits zwei Geschlechter begründen werden, jenes der Moabiter und jenes der Ammoniter, wodurch Lots Nach-kommenschaft gerettet ist. Doch es stellt sich die Frage: Suggeriert auch das Gemälde des Louvre ein solches positives Ende? Ich denke nicht.

Das bereits erwähnte Felsentor ist Teil eines komplexen Zirkulationssys-tems, eines Weges, der alle vier Quadranten des Gemäldes untereinander

353Figurenbild und Diagramm

verbindet (Schema e). Es handelt sich vorerst um den Weg, der von Lot und seiner Familie abgeschritten wird, und zwar in dem Maße, wie die Geschichte voranschreitet. Es ist aber auch ein Weg, der für den Betrachter eingerichtet ist, um ihm die Erzählung als geordnete Sequenz von Episoden darzubieten. Da jede Episode einem Quadranten und damit einem thematischen Konzept zugeordnet ist, erscheint die Geschichte gleichzeitig als sukzessive Transfor-mation innerhalb der Termini des logischen Quadrates.12

Der Weg beginnt (Nummer 1) beim runden Turm, Teil des Befestigungs-werkes der Stadt Sodom, die vom göttlichen Strafgericht heimgesucht wird. Lots Familie entkommt der ‚Zerstörung‘. Der Weg verlässt für einen Augenblick den Bildraum, um auf der Höhe der Brücke über das Meer wieder sichtbar zu werden. Von hier steigt er hinter dem Felsmassiv zum Felsentor hoch (Num-mer 2), dem Bereich der ‚Erstarrung‘, wo Lots Frau im Modus der doppelten Mimesis13 als leblose und damit unfruchtbare Felskonfiguration dargestellt ist. Der Weg durchquert das Felsentor in einer S-Linie, um schließlich am Plateau im Vordergrund (Nummer 3) zu enden, wo Lot und seine beiden Töchter ihre Zelte aufgeschlagen haben und wo schließlich – im Bereich der ‚Zeugung‘ – der Inzest vollzogen wird. Mit dieser Szene sind wir in der Gegenwart angelangt.

Die Geschichte endet aber nicht hier, auch wenn die Hauptfiguren hier zum letzten Mal dargestellt sind. Der Maler hat das inzestuöse Paar, Lot und seine ältere Tochter, zu Füssen eines schlanken Baumes platziert, der die Bild-fläche entlang der Vertikalen teilt.

Abb. 8

Schema e

12

3 4?

354 Figurenbild und Diagramm

Dieser Baum verweist – über die sprachlich fixierte Metapher des ‚Stamm-baums‘ – zweifellos auf das künftige Geschlecht, das aus der Vereinigung des Va-ters mit seiner Tochter hervorgehen wird. Doch der Maler hat den jungen Baum mit einem abgestorbenen, faulenden Baumstrunk im vierten Quadranten par-allelisiert. Der Baum erscheint so gleichsam zweimal, als junger Spross und als abgestorbener Rest, der bald ganz zerfallen und wieder zu Erde werden wird.

Die Analogisierung geht weiter (Schema f ): So wie dem lebendigen Stamm (B) das inzestuöse Paar (P) beigeordnet ist, ist dem Baumstrunk (B´) das Skelett (S) beigeordnet. Damit zeichnet sich die Konfiguration einer Raute ab. Die Fi-gurenkonstellation ist ein kleines Diagramm: Dem postulierten Schema kann, da beide Figurenpaare – B/B´ und P/S – durch die Opposition von Leben und Tod charakterisiert sind, der logische Status einer Verhältnisgleichung zugeschrieben werden: So wie der Baum zerfällt, also B zu B´ wird, wird auch P zu S werden. Ausgedeutscht bedeutet dies: Auch die beiden Individuen un-ter dem Baum werden sterben und als Skelette enden.14

Damit korrigiert die Pariser Tafel den optimistischen Ausgang der bibli-schen Erzählung. In der Epoche der Renaissance bringt das Gemälde neu die Dimension des individuellen Wohlergehens in die Geschichte von Lot ein und gleicht es mit dem Schicksal des Geschlechts ab: Auch wenn Lots Geschlecht dank der rechtzeitigen Flucht der Familie aus dem sündigen Sodom und des späteren Inzests des Vaters mit seinen beiden Töchtern überleben wird, als Individuum wird auch Lot und werden die Mitglieder seiner Familie dem Tod unterworfen bleiben. Sie werden einzeln das gleiche Schicksal erleiden wie die Menschen, die bei der Zerstörung von Sodom und Gomorra umge-

Abb. 9

Schema f

B

P

B‘

S

355Figurenbild und Diagramm

kommen sind. Nach einem langen Umweg, der Flucht aus der Stadt und dem mühsamen Weg über gefährliche Brücken und hohe Gebirge, enden auch die Überlebenden schließlich unten rechts im Quadranten der ‚Zersetzung‘, wo sich ihre Körper auflösen, um zu Staub zu werden.15

Ein des Lateinischen mächtiger Maler

Wir haben in unserer Bildanalyse bislang fast ausschließlich werkimmanent argumentiert. Ziel war es, die diagrammatische Logik sichtbar zu machen, die das Gemälde in seiner spezifischen Gestaltung trägt und so zu einem kohären-ten Sinngefüge macht, das zwar auf den biblischen Prätext verweist, diesen aber neu deutet. Zum Abschluss soll nun versucht werden, die Analyse zusätz-lich historisch zu verankern. Das Gemälde des Louvre ist nicht nur eine künst-lerische und maltechnische Bravourleistung, es ist in seiner Ikonographie und Erzählstruktur auch ungewöhnlich originell. Keine andere mir bekannte Dar-stellung der Geschichte von Lot und seinen Töchtern versucht, die biblische Erzählung auf vergleichbare Weise in einem umfassenden kosmologischen Kontext zu verorten, wie dies das vorliegende Gemälde tut. Es formuliert in seinem Zusammenspiel von biblischer Historie und Weltlandschaft einen all-gemeingültigen, gleichsam philosophischen Anspruch. Der anonyme Maler hat die visuelle Umsetzung der biblischen Episode zum Anlass genommen, um über die Welt und den Platz des Menschen in ihr grundsätzlich nachzu-denken. Dabei hat er sich, wie ich nun zeigen möchte, nicht nur mit dem in seiner Zeit verbreiteten philosophischen und theologischen Gedankengut aus-einandergesetzt, er tat dies unter anderem als Leser eines lateinisch verfassten Werkes, was für einen Maler jener Zeit überraschend ist.

Auf die Spur dieses Textes hat mich das logische Quadrat geführt, mit dem die kompositorische Struktur des Werkes verwandt ist. Das logische Quadrat (vgl. Abb. 2) ist als gezeichnetes Diagramm zum ersten Mal in der kleinen, traditionell Apuleius zugeschriebenen Schrift Peri hermeneias belegt.16 Der lateinisch verfasste Text ist ein Kommentar zu einem im Mittelalter und in der frühen Neuzeit viel gelesenen und ausgiebig kommentierten natur-philosophischen Traktat des Aristoteles, der traditionell unter dem lateini-schen Titel De generatione et corruptione gehandelt wurde. Generatio und corruptio, ‚Zeugung‘ und ‚Zerfall‘, lauten aber auch die beiden Begriffe, mit denen ich intuitiv die beiden unteren Quadranten bezeichnet hatte.

356 Figurenbild und Diagramm

Tatsächlich führen im Gemälde einige Spuren zum erwähnten aristoteli-schen Traktat. So werden von Aristoteles zwei Arten von Feuer unterschieden, eines, das sich der Natur gemäß nach von unten nach oben bewegt, und eines, das ‚naturwidrig‘ von oben nach unten bewegt wird.17 Diese beiden Feuer – das aufsteigende, gezähmte und das vom Himmel fallende, zerstörerische – werden, wir erinnern uns, auch im Lotgemälde gegeneinander geführt.18

Dass ein Maler zu Beginn des 16. Jahrhunderts den Traktat des Aristoteles im Wortlaut gelesen haben könnte, ist unwahrscheinlich. Das traditionelle philoso-phische Wissen wurde damals vor allem über Enzyklopädien verbreitet, etwa über die Margarita philosophica des Straßburger Kartäuserpaters Gregor Reisch, einem der ganz großen Bestseller des frühen 16. Jahrhunderts. Dieses Werk, aus dem wir bereits die Seite mit dem logischen Quadrat (Abb. 2) abgebildet haben, hat der anonyme niederländische Maler des Lotbildes, wie ich meine, nicht nur in den Händen gehabt; er hat es gelesen und zwar in einer der beiden mit Holzschnitten illustrierten Basler Ausgaben, die 1508 und 1517 erschienen sind.19

In Gregor Reischs noch stark scholastisch geprägter Synthese des damali-gen Wissens spielt die Naturphilosophie, wie sie Aristoteles in De generatione et corruptione mit Bezug auf seine Elementenlehre entwickelt hat, eine zentrale Rolle. Das 8. Buch von Reischs Enzyklopädie ist im Wesentlichen eine kom-mentierte Zusammenfassung der Hauptthesen von Aristoteles’ Traktat in der Form eines Dialogs zwischen einem discipulus und dem magister. So ist das 33. Kapitel des 8. Buches unter anderem der Frage gewidmet, wie sich „Zeugung und Zerfall von Schöpfung und Vernichtung“ unterscheiden: De Generatione et corruptione quomodo dífferunt a creatione et a nihilatione, was Zeugung im einfa-chen Sinne bedeute, usf. Dabei können einzelne Motive im Pariser Gemälde wie visuelle Kommentare zu entsprechenden Stellen in der Margarita philoso-phica verstanden werden. So erklärt der Magister im gleichen 33. Kapitel in einer mit Forma cadaveris bezeichneten Passage, dass der Zerfall des Körpers nicht sogleich zur materia prima zurückführe. Die Form des Kadavers sei nicht essentialis, sondern accidentalis. Zum Skelett abgestorben würde der Körper weiter bis zur endlichen Aschewerdung (incinerationem) zerfallen.20

Bildgestütztes Denken

Ein erster Hinweis darauf, dass der Maler eine der beiden Basler Ausgaben von Reischs Margarita philosophica benutzt hat, ist die Randillustration zum

357Figurenbild und Diagramm

8. Kapitel des 9. Buches, in dem die unterschiedlichen Arten von Feuer zu-sammengefasst werden (Abb. 10). Im Holzschnitt werden in der Mitte die beiden von Aristoteles nach ihren konträren Bewegungsrichtungen unter-schiedenen Feuertypen gegeneinander geführt, das aufsteigende Feuer, das mit dem Begriff asubascendens und das absteigende, das mit dem Gegenbegriff asubdescendens bezeichnet wird. (Die ungewöhnliche Vorsilbe ‚asub-‘ stammt aus der arabischen Kommentarliteratur des Aristoteles.)21

Ein weiterer Hinweis darauf, dass der Maler die Margarita philosophica in einer der erwähnten Basler Ausgaben konsultiert hat, ist der Holzschnitt zum Kapitel 9.17, das unter dem Titel De terrae motu dem Phänomen des Erdbe-bens gewidmet ist. Er zeigt die vom Erdbeben erschütterte Stadt, genauso wie das Pariser Gemälde, in die Diagonale gekippt und mit einer Turmspitze, die gerade abbricht (Abb. 5 und Abb. 11).

Der Verweis auf die aristotelische Naturphilosophie in der Vermittlung durch die Margarita philosophica darf freilich in seiner Bedeutung nicht über-schätzt werden. Der Text ist zuerst einmal weder die ‚Quelle‘ des Bildes noch dessen ‚Erklärung‘. Die Entdeckung zeigt jedoch, dass sich der Maler mit der

Abb. 10

Gregor Reisch

Margarita philosophica, Basel 1517,

Holzschnitt zu Lib. IX, Cap. VIII

358 Figurenbild und Diagramm

in Reischs Enzyklopädie vermittelten aristotelischen Naturphilosophie aus-einandergesetzt hat. Dabei hat er sich – dies ist das Entscheidende – in ei-ner Kultur der Wissensvermittlung bewegt, in der Diagramme jeder Art eine zentrale Rolle spielten. So ist auch die Margarita philosophica voll von figürli-chen und schematischen Darstellungen aller Art. Hier und in vielen anderen Werken der Zeit ist ein bildgestütztes Denken am Werk, das die Welt nach elementaren topologischen Kategorien ordnet, Figuren entsprechend katego-rialer Gegensätze im Bildraum verteilt oder szenische Darstellungen mit Li-niengefügen und Begriffen überschreibt. Dabei werden der figürliche und der diagrammatische Bildmodus regelmäßig miteinander verschränkt, wie etwa im Holschnitt, der dazu dient, den Nachweis von der sphärischen Gestalt der Erde zu veranschaulichen (Abb. 12).

Ebenso wichtig jedoch wie diese und andere Darstellungen ist der Inhalt der Enzyklopädie, der noch ganz dem kombinatorischen kategorialen Den-ken verpflichtet ist, das Aristoteles’ Naturphilosophie prägt. Nach Aristoteles ist jedes natürliche Phänomen das Ergebnis eines Zusammenwirkens elemen-tarer Kategorien. Jeder Körper ist letztendlich ein Kompositum aus einzelnen

Abb. 11

Gregor Reisch

Margarita philosophica, Basel 1517,

Holzschnitt zu Lib. IX, Cap. XVIII

359Figurenbild und Diagramm

der vier Elemente, wobei jedes Element aus zwei Termini der beiden Katego-rien ‚trocken/feucht‘ und ‚warm/kalt‘ gebildet ist. Umgekehrt bedeutet dies, dass alles Sichtbare auf abstrakte Kategorien hin analysierbar ist. Dies hat zur Konsequenz, dass jede im Bild dargestellte Figur im Grunde mit jeder ande-ren verwandt ist und so mit jeder anderen vergleichbar wird, aber auch, dass alles Sichtbare das Resultat eines ständigen Prozesses der Transformation ist.Das vom Himmel fallende zerstörerische Feuer ist die Umkehrung des auf-steigenden gezähmten Feuers; das Skelett und der faulende Baumstrunk kön-nen als Zerfallsformen des Menschen bzw. Tieres und des Baumes aufgefasst werden, und so fort … Die biblische Geschichte von Lot und seiner Familie bot sich einer solchen aristotelischen Lektüre mit ihrer zirkulären Geschichts-konzeption geradezu an. Bereits die prägnante Episode mit Lots Frau ist eine Geschichte der Verwandlung, eine Geschichte, in der ein Mensch – aristote-lisch gesprochen – bei gleich bleibender Form die Materie wechselt, versa est in statuam salis, wie es in der lateinischen Bibel (Gen 19.26) heißt.

Das Pariser Gemälde mit der Geschichte von Lot und seinen Töchtern ist kein Diagramm im engeren Sinne, aber es besitzt eine prägnante komposi-

Abb. 12

Gregor Reisch

Margarita philosophica, Basel 1517,

Holzschnitt zu Lib. VII, Trac. I, Cap. XLIII

360 Figurenbild und Diagramm

torische Struktur, sodass die dargestellte Szene, der simulierte Weltausblick, wie von einem Diagramm unterfüttert erscheint. Der Maler hat die einzelnen Szenen und Gegenstände so auf der Bildfläche verteilt, dass sie bei einer kon-zeptuellen Lektüre Begriffe repräsentieren, die sich entlang der topologischen Kategorien links/rechts und oben/unten zu inhaltlichen Gegensatzpaaren ordnen.

Wer ‚diagrammatisch‘ sagt, meint immer auch Prozesshaftigkeit. Diagram-me sind Instrumente des Denkens. Sie dienen uns dazu, mit ihrer Hilfe Denk- operationen auszuführen. Sie erlauben es, in der Möglichkeitsform Überle-gungen oder Handlungsoptionen zu formulieren, die über das Dargestellte hinausgehen. Auch das Pariser Gemälde ist wie jedes Diagramm ein Ordnungs-muster, das darauf wartet, vom Rezipienten in Bewegung versetzt zu werden. Der Betrachter, der die Bildfläche verstehend ordnet, verfolgt die Gruppe der Flüchtigen und verbindet dabei die Bildräume untereinander, die gleichzeitig den elementaren Positionen von Zerstörung, Erstarrung, Zeugung und Zerfall entsprechen.

Es ist vor allem die diagrammatische Armatur, die es dem niederländischen Maler zu Beginn des 16. Jahrhunderts erlaubt hat, die biblische Episode mit Bezug auf sein individualistisch geprägtes Weltbild neu zu deuten. Das Gemäl-de des Louvre ist nicht bloß die ‚Illustration‘ einer uralten Geschichte, es deutet diese Geschichte mit den Mitteln einer impliziten Diagrammatik neu.

361Figurenbild und Diagramm

Anmerkungen

1 Der vorliegende Text hat eine ungewöhnlich lange Genese von dreißig Jahren und verdankt entsprechend viel dem Rat und kritischen Kommentar zahlreicher Freunde und Wissenschaftler. Am Anfang stand die Begegnung mit Oskar Bätsch-mann und die Lektüre seines Aufsatzes „Lot und seine Töchter im Louvre: Meta-phorik, Antithetik und Ambiguität in einem niederländischen Gemälde des frü-hen 16. Jahrhundert,“ Städel-Jahrbuch N.F. 8 (1981): 159–185. Diese Bildanalyse, gleichzeitig ein grundlegender Beitrag zu einer kunstgeschichtlichen Hermeneutik, regte den Autor zu einem Versuch an, das Werk mit Bezug auf die semiotische Erzähltheorie zu untersuchen. Auf Einladung von Algirdas Julien Greimas wurde sie in dessen Seminar an der Pariser École des Hautes Etudes erstmals vorgetragen und anschließend unter dem Titel „La double spatialité en peinture: espace simulé et topologie planaire,“ Actes sémiotiques. Bulletin 20 (1981): 34–46, publiziert. Eine italienische Übersetzung unter dem Titel „La doppia spazialità in pittura: spazio simulato et topologia planare – A proposito di Loth e le figlie“ erschien in Leggere l’opera d’arte: Dal figurativo all’astratto, herausgegeben von Lucia Corrain und Ma-rio Valenti (Bologna: Progetto Leonardo, 1991): 55–64, mit einem „Postscriptum“ nachgedruckt in Semiotiche della pittura: I classici, le ricerche, herausgegeben von Lu-cia Corrain (Rom: Meltemi, 2004): 29–38. Der wissenschaftliche Dialog mit Stef-fen Bogen an der Universität Konstanz war Anlass, den Aspekt der Diagrammatik im Gemälde weiter zu reflektieren: Steffen Bogen und Felix Thürlemann, „Jenseits der Opposition von Text und Bild: Überlegungen zu einer Theorie des Diagramms und des Diagrammatischen,“ in Die Bildwelt der Diagramme Joachims von Fiore: Zur Medialität religiös-politischer Programme im Mittelalter, herausgegeben von Alexander Patschovsky (Ostfildern: Thorbecke, 2003): 1–22, bes. 19–21. Die Vermutung, die diagrammatische Struktur des Werkes und seine Thematik könnten einen Bezug zur aristotelischen Naturphilosophie haben, wurde erstmals am 10. Juni 2009 in dem von Jean-Hubert Martin und Michel Weemans organisierten Kolloquium Le paysage anthropomorphe à la Renaissance als Hypothese vorgestellt. Das Kolloquium fand anlässlich der Ausstellung Une image peut en cacher une autre: Arcimboldo, Dalí, Raetz im Grand-Palais in Paris statt. Dort wurde auch das Gemälde aus dem Lou-vre gezeigt. Siehe den Katalog der Ausstellung (Paris: Editions de la Réunion des musées nationaux, 2009), Nr. 62 (mit einer Notiz des Autors). Die damals von Frank Lestringnant dem Autor gegenüber geäußerte Vermutung, das aristotelische Gedankengut sei dem Maler über eine zeitgenössische Enzyklopädie vermittelt worden, hat sich als zutreffend herausgestellt und wird hier weiter begründet.

362 Figurenbild und Diagramm

2 Siehe Max Jakob Friedländer, Die altniederländische Malerei, vol. 10: Lucas van Leyden und andere holländische Meister seiner Zeit (Berlin: Paul Cassirer, 1932), englische Aus-gabe: Early Netherlandish Paintings, vol. 10: Lucas van Leyden and other Dutch Masters of His Time (Leyden / Brüssel: A. W. Sijthoff / La Connaissance, 1973), 89, wo das Werk zusammen mit zwei querformatigen Varianten abgebildet ist (englische Aus-gabe, plates 92 und 93).

3 Da nach neueren Archivfunden der vermutlich aus Leyden stammende und in Antwerpen tätige Jan de Cock bereits 1521 starb und ein Holzschnitt, den Fried-länder zum Kernbestand des Œuvres zählte, 1522 datiert ist, kann der Name ‚Jan de Cock‘ heute nur noch den Wert eines Notnamens haben. Wir setzen den Künst-lernamen deshalb in Anführungszeichen. Zum neuesten Stand der Forschung siehe Marc Rudolf de Vrij, Jan Wellens de Cock: Antwerp Mannerist Associate (Zwanenburg: M. R. V. Publishers, 2009). In de Vrijs Werkkatalog wird das Gemälde des Louvre nur nebenbei als Variante einer weiteren querformatigen Fassung im Institute of Arts in Detroit (cat. 5, 158f) erwähnt. Zum Todesjahr 1521 von Jan de Cock siehe Jan van der Stock, Printing images in Antwerp: The introduction of printmaking in a city, fifteenth century to 1585 (Rotterdam: Sound & Vision Interactive, 1998), 259.

4 Antonin Artaud, „La mise en scène et la métaphysique“ in A. A., Œuvres complètes, vol. 4 (Paris: Gallimard 1964), 40–57.

5 Artaud, Œuvres (wie Anm. 4), 44: „Je dis en tout cas que cette peinture est ce que le théâtre devrait être, s’il savait parler le langage qui lui appartient.“

6 Siehe jedoch Frederik Stjernfelt, Diagrammatology: an investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics (Göttingen: Springer, 2007), 278: „ … all pictures, also in the ordinary art-history-meaning of the word, are also diagrams – primarily maps in the general meaning of the term suggested.“ Überhaupt trifft sich die nachfolgende Untersuchung in vielen entscheidenden Punkten mit den Thesen und methodologischen Grundannahmen zum Verhältnis von (Kunst-)bild und Diagramm, wie Stjernfelt sie ausgehend von Charles Sanders Peirce’ Dia-grammtheorie formuliert hat. Stjernfelts Kapitel 13, 275–288, ist einer Untersu-chung eines figürlichen und eines abstrakten Gemäldes als Diagramme gewidmet.

7 Bätschmann (wie Anm. 1), 159, spricht von „Doppelwertigkeit von Flächen- und Raumteilung“, doch berücksichtigt er in seiner Analyse nur die diagonale Teilung der Bildfläche.

8 Für diese Form der Semiose hat Algirdas Julien Greimas den Begriff ‚semi-sym-bolisch‘ geprägt. Siehe Jean-Marie Floch und Felix Thürlemann, Stichwort ‚semi-symbolique (système, langage, code –)‘ in A. J. Greimas / J. Courtés (Hg.), Sémiotique: dictionnaire raisonné de la théorie du langage, vol. 2 (Paris: Hachette, 1986), 203–206.

363Figurenbild und Diagramm

9 Nach Bätschmann (wie Anm. 1), 179, hat der Komet eine doppelte Valenz: „Im Bild wird die Frage nach der Wahrheit der Rettung entwickelt […] durch den Kometen, der für die Katastrophe Zeichen des vergangenen, für Lot des künftigen Unheils ist.“

10 Vgl. Stjernfelt (wie Anm. 6), 279: „Thus analysis of art […] involves a crucial ab-ductive component.“

11 Vgl. Bätschmann (wie Anm. 1), 168 f.: „Die Aufstellung der Zelte wie die Ver-teilung der Weinkrüge wandeln die Disposition der Figuren ab. Die beiden eng beieinander stehenden Weinkrüge wiederholen das Paar und partizipieren an der zärtlichen Zuneigung und zugleich am Ausschluß der zweiten Tochter, ihres Wein-kruges und des ihr zugeordneten alleinstehenden Zeltes.“

12 Auch Frederik Stjernfelt betont diesen Aspekt. Siehe Stjernfelt (wie Anm. 6), 279: „I may construct a space, in which I can imagine my body moving around; this very wandering route inside the landscape has the characteristics of a diagram manipulation.“

13 Zum Begriff der ‚doppelten Mimesis‘ siehe Felix Thürlemann, “L’aquarelle de Dü-rer ‚fenedier klawsen‘: La double mimesis dans l’analyse picturale d’un lieu géogra-phique,“ Revue de l’Art 137 (2002/3): 9–18.

14 Bereits Bätschmann (wie Anm. 1), 170, hat auf diesen prospektiven Aspekt mit Bezug auf die Metaphern, die die sexuelle Vereinigung andeuten, hingewiesen: „Die Metaphorik, die im Fall der Darstellung der Szene des Inzests darauf sich entwickelt, gibt der bildlichen Darstellung die Möglichkeit, in der Erzählung über das unmittelbar Gezeigte hinaus fortzufahren und zugleich auch den Fortgang der Geschichte zu enthüllen.“

15 Wolfgang Kemp, Die Räume der Maler: Zur Bilderzählung seit Giotto (München: C. H. Beck, 1996), 57 ff., hat in seinen Analysen zweier Predella-Täfelchen von Simone Martini und Ambrogio Lorenzetti gezeigt, wie die beiden Sieneser Maler den simulierten architektonischen Raum in einer ambivalenten, gleichzeitig flä-chigen und tiefenräumlichen Gliederung so aufgeteilt haben, dass der Betrachter beim ‚Abschreiten‘ der im Bild angelegten Wege die wichtigsten Episoden der dar-gestellten Wundergeschichte in ihrer logischen Entwicklung nachvollziehen kann. Im Pariser Lot-Gemälde setzt ‚Jan de Cock‘ den von ihm simulierten landschaftli-chen Raum in gleicher Weise im Dienste der Bilderzählung ein. Ich danke Wolf-ram Pichler, der mich an dieses Kapitel in Kemps Buch erinnert hat.

16 Liber ΠΕΠI ΕΠMHNΕIΑΣ, in Paul Thomas (Hg.), Apulei Platonici Madaurensis, De philosophia libri (Leipzig: Teubner, 1908): 176–194. Vgl. H. Schepers, Stich-wort „Quadrat, logisches,“ in Joachim Ritter / Karlfried Gründer (Hg.), Historisches

364 Figurenbild und Diagramm

Wörterbuch der Philosophie, vol. 7, (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1971–2007): Sp. 1733–1736.

17 Aristoteles, De generatione et corruptione, II. 6. In deutscher Übersetzung lautet die Passage: „Ferner da es sich zeigt, daß die Körper sowohl durch Vergewaltigung und naturwidrig als auch naturgemäß bewegt werden (wie z. B. das Feuer nach Oben nicht durch Vergewaltigung, wohl aber nach Unten durch Vergewaltigung), dem Gewaltmäßigen aber das Naturgemäße entgegengesetzt ist, es aber das Ge-waltmäßige gibt, so gibt es also auch das naturgemäße Bewegtwerden.“ Zitiert nach: Carl von Prantl (Hg.), Aristoteles, Vier Bücher über das Himmelsgebäude und zwei Bücher über Entstehen und Vergehen (Leipzig: Engelmann, 1857): 461.

18 Bätschmann (wie Anm. 1), 173, sieht seinerseits im „aufsteigenden Baum“ ein „ak-tives Gegenbild zum Fall des Feuers“.

19 Zu Reischs Enzyklopädie siehe neuerdings (mit Hinweisen auf die ältere Lite-ratur) Steffen Siegel, „Architektur des Wissens: Die figurative Ordnung der ar-tes in Gregor Reischs Margarita Philosophica,“ in Frank Büttner / Gabriele Wim-böck (Hg.), Das Bild als Autorität: die normierende Kraft des Bildes (Münster: LIT Verlag, 2004), 343–362. Verschiedene Ausgaben der Margarita Philosophica sind digital zugänglich: http://www.digitale-sammlungen.de/index.html?c=autoren_index&l=de&ab=Reisch%2C+Gregor, Zugriff am 21. 9. 2010. Die letzte, vom Verfasser selbst besorgte Ausgabe (Basel: Michael Furter, 1517) ist auch als Reprint greifbar: Gregor Reisch, Margarita philosophica, mit einem Vorwort, einer Einlei-tung und einem neuen Inhaltsverzeichnis von Lutz Geldsetzer (Düsseldorf: Stern-Verlag Janssen & Co., 1973). Die Holzschnitte der beiden in Basel 1508 und 1517 erschienenen Ausgaben sind identisch.

20 „Alia est generatio simpliciter: qua forma substantialis non statim in materiam pri-mam inducitur: sed in compositum ex materia prima et forma substantiali commu-niore: ut cum anima corpori physico et organico unitur. Similiter corruptio huius non statim usque ad materiam primam protenditur. Forma autem cadaveris que in recessu anime in corpore reperitur: non essentialis sed accidentalis est: sub qua corpus in ulteriorem incinerationem continuo tendit.“ Gregor Reisch, Margarita philosophica, ed. Geldsetzer (wie Anm. 16), 358.

21 Siehe Wolf Peter Klein, Die Geschichte der meteorologischen Kommunikation in Deutsch-land: eine historische Fallstudie zur Entwicklung der Wissenschaftssprachen (Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1999), 74.

Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

David Wagner, Vienna

That Ludwig Wittgenstein was interested in maps and map-making comes as no surprise. After all, he compares the form of a philosophical question to our common experience of disorientation—‘I don’t know my way about.’ (PI § 123)1—and likens his Philosophical Investigations (PI) to an album contain-ing sketches of a landscape which has been explored in a criss-cross manner. In this paper I present metaphors of perfect maps provided by Jorge Luis Borges, Lewis Carroll and Josiah Royce, and set these against remarks by Wittgenstein and Charles Sanders Peirce.

Even this—slightly expanded—version of the talk I gave at the 33rd International Wittgenstein Symposium is, however, far from a survey of literary maps and their inspirational potential for philosophy. I would simply like to offer a series of glimpses at literary maps that might enrich a larger picture.

The larger picture consists in the view that the young Wittgenstein subscribed to a picture-theory of truth, a correspondence theory that under-stands correspondence between the structure of truth-bearers and states of affairs as congruence. While this is uncontroversial, I would here like to add illustrations that make it plausible that Wittgenstein had no reason to aban-don his picture-theory, rather, that his thinking about maps—if understood as an expression of this theoretical position—, particularly in the writings from 1930 to the gestation of the Brown and Blue Books, may have evolved from this early Tractarian notion.

If one looks at the most pertinent metaphor for the picture-theory, the mirroring or picturing of formal relations in the way markings on a map mirror the structure of that portion of the world of which it is a map, it is helpful to consider extreme examples of maps. Unsurveyable maps as thought

Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, volume 2, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner. © ontos Verlag, Frankfurt · Lancaster · Paris · New Brunswick, 2011, 365–376.

366 Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

experiments by writers and philosophers show us why surveyability is such a key quality of a map.

While part one of this paper revolves around an essentialistic picture theory that supposes that there is but one ideal language mapping the sayable, and one ideal of exactness, part two of the paper explores the idea that various maps with various practical purposes make the existence of the one all-encompassing language obsolete.

Seeing connections

In his collection of fake historical fragments entitled Museum [1946] the Argentinean writer Jorge Luis Borges provides us with a description of ‘perfect’ map-making. His short text, titled ‘On Scientific Rigor (Del rigor en la ciencia)’ is an imaginary example of scientific self-destruction. Apparently taken from a 17th century history book, the story tells of a nameless Empire in which Schools of Cartography are held captive by their picture of exactitude:

… In the Empire in question, the Cartographer’s Art reached such a degree of Perfection that the map of a single Province took up an entire City, and the map of the Empire covered an entire Province. After a while these Outsized Maps were no longer sufficient, and the Schools of Cartography created a Map of the Empire that was the size of the Empire, matching it point by point. Later Generations, which were less Devoted to the Study of Cartography, found this Map Irrelevant, and with it more than a little Irreverence left it exposed to the Inclemencies of the Sun and Winter. In the Western desert there are still Ruins of the Map, inhabited by Animals and Beggars. No other relics of the Geographic Discipline can be found anywhere else in the Land.2

The core idea of this story may have sprung from an earlier work, one by Lewis Carroll. The novel in which we find it, Lewis Carroll’s Sylvie and Bruno Concluded [1893], was well-known to Borges3 and admired by such diverse writers as James Joyce and Ludwig Wittgenstein4. As in the version of Borges, we are presented with a map too big for its own good:

“What a useful thing a pocket-map is!” I remarked.“That’s another thing we’ve learned from your Nation,” said Mein Herr,

367Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

“map-making. But we’ve carried it much further than you. What do you consider the largest map that would be really useful?”“About six inches to the mile.”“Only six inches!” exclaimed Mein Herr. “We very soon got to six yards to the mile. Then we tried a hundred yards to the mile. And then came the grandest idea of all! We actually made a map of the country, on the scale of a mile to the mile!”“Have you used it much?” I enquired.“It has never been spread out, yet,” said Mein Herr: “the farmers objected: they said it would cover the whole country, and shut out the sunlight! So we now use the country itself, as its own map, and I assure you it does nearly as well. […]” 5

Using a country as its own map is comparable to Jonathan Swift’s Lagadonian language. Wittgenstein knew Gulliver’s Travels [1726] well, in fact, he even read an abridged version of it with his pupils at the primary school in Tratten-bach.6 In chapter five Samuel Gulliver visits the Grand Academy of Lagado on the island of Balnibarbi, where he learns about the scientific endeavours to create a perfect language:

We next went to the school of languages, where three professors sat in consulta-tion upon improving that of their own country. The first project was to shorten discourse, by cutting polysyllables into one, and leaving out verbs and participles; because in reality all things imaginable are but nouns. The other project was a scheme for entirely abolishing all words whatsoever; and this was urged as a great advantage in point of health as well as brevity. For it is plain that every word we speak is, in some degree, a diminution of our lungs by corrosion, and consequently contributes to the shortening of our lives. An expedient was therefore offered, and since words are only names for things, it would be more convenient for all men to carry about them such things as were necessary to express a particular business they are to discourse on. […] [M]any of the most learned and wise adhere to the new scheme of expressing themselves by things; which has only this inconvenience attending it, that if a man’s business be very great, and of various kinds, he must be obliged, in proportion, to carry a greater bundle of things upon his back, unless he can af-ford one or two strong servants to attend him. I have often beheld two of these sages almost sinking under the weight of their packs, like peddlers among us;

368 Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

who, when they met in the street, would lay down their loads, open their sacks, and hold conversation for an hour together; then put up their implements, help each other to resume their burdens, and take their leave.7

In PI § 6 Wittgenstein reminds us that ostensive teaching of words may establish ‘an associative connection between word and thing’, which means, amongst other things, that ‘a picture of the object comes before the child’s mind when it hears the word’ (PI § 6). This is quite desirable, for example when we read poetry or novels, but it also has its disadvantages: We tend to take our pictorial associations for granted and forget that what words mean is not simply given. Using words across a variety of contexts, we tend to forget the language-game which caused us to associate a certain picture in the first place, ‘the language in which it is at home’ (PI § 116).

The more obvious problem illustrated by the Lagadonian language, however, is the fact that Lagadonian does not offer a solution to misunder-standings, to erroneous interpretations. While we can speak in English about an English sentence, Lagadonians only have rebus puzzles. For how would a Lagadonian in his ‘perfect’ language communicate that the red square he is showing to someone is only meant to convey the colour red, but not its rectan-gular shape? By pointing to it?

Just as maps do not simply show us isolated markings but provide markings in relation to each other, the picture-theory is not so much concerned with singular words and the objects they pick out, but with structural complexes: sentences. To see structures means that one has selected certain relations above others. And this is why unsurveyable maps like the ones by Borges and Carroll fail: They show too much. They are the endpoints of cartography, where abundance of detail has won over clarity of communication.

Before I move on, let me summarise. Swift’s Lagadonian language shares one important feature with Borges’ and Carroll’s maps: it is highly impractical. While the giant maps block out the sun and at best serve as shelter for the poor, they have stopped being maps, since the purpose of a map is to give instructions we can follow, that we may transfer its picture into our actions:

Die Verwendung einer Landkarte besteht darin, daß wir uns in irgendeiner Weise nach ihr richten; daß wir ihr Bild in unsere Handlungen übertragen. (Wittgenstein, MS 114, p. 51)

369Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

Faced with these gigantic maps, the problem one encounters is the very reason maps were invented in the first place. For maps are drawn to provide us with orientation in a country ‘deficient in surveyability. A surveyable representation produces precisely that understanding which consists in “seeing connections” ’ (PI § 122) and dissolves the feeling of not knowing one’s way about:

Es ist, wie wenn ich ein winziges Gesichtsfeld und ein schlechtes Gedächtnis hätte, und nun, durch hin und her blicken, mich auf einer großen Landkarte auszukennen lernen sollte. Man würde in so einem Falle fortwährend Zusam-menhänge vergessen, verkennen, sie langwierig suchen, wo sie nicht sind. (Wittgenstein, MS 117, p. 220)

Seeing differences

Our third map is by Josiah Royce, who invented it for a supplementary es-say of his opus magnum The World and the Individual [1899]8. To Borges this ‘philosophical’ map is clearly on a par with the best of literary inventions.9

Bertrand Russell discusses it in chapter 8 (‘Infinite Cardinal Numbers’) of his Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy [1919].—I quote Russell:

A “reflexive” class is one which is similar to a proper part of itself. (A “proper part” is a part short of the whole.) A “reflexive” cardinal number is the cardinal number of a reflexive class. We have now to consider this property of reflexiveness. One of the most striking instances of a “reflexion” is Royce’s illustration of the map: he imagines it decided to make a map of England upon a part of the surface of England. A map, if it is accurate, has a perfect one-one correspond-ence with its original; thus our map, which is part, is in one-one relation with the whole, and must contain the same number of points as the whole, which must therefore be a reflexive number. Royce is interested in the fact that the map, if it is correct, must contain a map of the map, which must in turn contain a map of the map of the map, and so on ad infinitum.10

One interesting aspect of Royce’s map is the feeling of dizziness that grabs hold of the reader, as he tries to reconstruct the map-within-the-map in his mind. A disorientation of another kind.

370 Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

Ever since Carl Friedrich Gauss wrote his treatise ‘Allgemeine Auflösung der Aufgabe: Die Theile einer gegebnen Fläche auf einer andern gegebnen Fläche so abzubilden, dass die Abbildung dem Abgebildeten in den klein-sten Theilen ähnlich wird’ [1825], the terms prototype (Urbild ) and projected pictorial form (Abbild ) have been at home in the world of map-making. One important aspect of geodesic projection is the fact that prototype and depic-tion are never identical, they only come to be very much alike. In the case of a strong likeness—preserving both angles and shapes of infinitesimally small figures—one speaks of a conformal projection. A ‘conformal’ map simply conforms to the principle of angle-preservation.11

Few, if any, philosophers know more about maps than the geodesist and mathematician Charles Sanders Peirce. It is in his review of The World and the Individual that Peirce writes about Royce’s perfect map and finds in it a confirmation of his own ideas concerning the self. Even though Royce states Georg Cantor’s serial one-to-one mapping of odd-numbers onto integers as his source of inspiration, Peirce immediately thinks of Gaussian conformal projection:

[Royce] resorts to Gauss’s conception of Abbild, which has played a great role in mathematics. That is to say, he likens the idea representing the entire life to a map of a country lying upon the territory of that country. Imagine a map of England, absolutely perfect in its minutest details, to lie upon the soil of England, without covering the entire country it maps. Upon this map would be shown the very ground where the map lies, and the map itself, in all its minutest details. In this map of the map, the map will be shown again; and so on end-lessly. […] It is to be noticed that, each successive map lying well inside the one which it immediately represents […] the endless series of maps will converge to a single point, which represents itself throughout each and every map of the series. In the case of the idea, that point would be the self-consciousness of the idea. An idea, being a state of mind with a conscious purpose, must evidently be self-conscious.12

Peirce considers the map-within-the-map an apt metaphor for a self-repre-sentative system. He even goes one step further than Royce: Peirce insists that self-reference—in the map-metaphor that single point, where all maps of differing sizes converge—is essential to the continuum that gives us the feeling of remaining the same person over time:

371Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

the man’s Self encloses intermediate selves—the domestic Self, the business Self, the better Self, the evil spirit that sometimes usurps his sovereignty. […] Every reality, then, is a Self, and the selves are intimately connected, as if they formed a continuum. Each one is, so to say, a delineation; with mathematical truth we may say, incongruous though the metaphor is, that each is a quasi-map of the entire field of all the selves […]13

Speculations like these are not Russell’s cup of tea. Regarding Royce’s infinite maps-within-maps he simply says: ‘This point is interesting, but need not occupy us at this moment. In fact, we shall do well to pass from pictur-esque illustrations to such as are more completely definite, and for this purpose cannot do better than consider the number-series itself.’14

Wittgenstein, who loved to dwell on picturesque illustrations, may have thought otherwise. He was well aware of the fact that in a contextual sense every useful map is a map-within-a-map. For what use would a map of Oxfordshire be to someone lost in Lower Austria? Just as the meaning of words relies on their context, a map only makes sense where (and for what purpose) we need it.

Even though the series of maps in Royce’s thought experiment converge to a single point, each successive map depicts one specific aspect of the country, has its particular use. The information given on political maps, climate maps, road maps, underground maps, topographic maps and so on may converge at particular points, but as each map tells a different story, none of the maps will give all the information. The specific requirements for these maps inform the picture language (Bildsprache) the map-maker chooses. From the perspective of its user one could say that the one single perfect map does not exist, because each map is judged according to the require-ments it meets.15

Using a map means following its rules, thus we may copy a map of trails by walking according to the information it gives (cf. MS 153b, 8v). This has important implications if one contemplates how a model of language may resemble a map. Language as a projection of reality, mirroring how the map shows relations of the landscape it depicts (cf. WA2: 184 1). But instead of solving linguistic problems of meaning, this metaphor only makes them more apparent. To really understand the map, to be able to read it and connect it to the landscape, requires that one does not overlook the differences amongst its markings:

372 Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

Vergleich der verschiedenen Arten von Linien auf der Landkarte, mit den Wortarten in den Sätzen. Der nichts davon versteht, sieht eine Menge von Linien und weiß nicht, daß sie sehr verschiedene Bedeutungen haben; es sind Straßen, Grenzen, Schichtenlinien, Meridiane, Schraffen, u. a.. Denke dir auf dem Plan wäre ein Weg eingezeichnet und (mit einigen Linien) durchstrichen – um anzudeuten, daß es diesen Weg gegeben habe, aber nicht mehr gebe. – (Wittgenstein, MS 116, p. 28)

Seeing various lines on a map, without knowing what they stand for, may result in taking their linearity as the most important feature certainly one way of being held captive by a picture.

In 1930 Wittgenstein points out that certain features of commands and expectations can be made clear by reference to maps. Following an order (Befehl ), we follow certain rules and the map becomes the picture we interpret: ‘Die Landkarte ist das Bild[,] das interpretiert wird.’ (WA2: 295 3) Here the map may still be a metaphor for language—but it does not simply show its relation, it requires an active interpretation. To understand the map is not the same as looking at it like an uninvolved spectator. We have to put ourselves—see our position—in relation to the markings on the map.16

But then, in close vicinity, Wittgenstein gives another example: Distances depicted on a map tend to ground the expectation for our arrival at a certain point in time: ‘[…] die Landkarte ist das Bild unserer Erwartung[,] indem sie zeigt[,] daß wir in einer Stunde dort und dort hin kommen.’ (23. 7. 1930, WA2: 295 3) Here the map is the cause of our expectations, its relations make us expect something—like a command may make us act in a certain way. One fact remains the same, however: In order to serve as an image of our expec-tations, we must be in a position to read the markings on the map, to interpret the distances and make sense of it all.

In the lecture notes taken in 1933 by his students Alice Ambrose and Margaret Macdonald known as The Yellow Book, Ludwig Wittgenstein compares language to a country and map-making becomes the task of the philosopher. The method he suggests is akin to getting to know a country by repeated walks. The work of the philosopher of language is a survey culminating in a synoptic view:

One difficulty with philosophy is that we lack a synoptic view. We encounter the kind of difficulty we should have with the geography of a country for which we

373Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

had no map, or else a map of isolated bits. The country we are talking about is language, and the geography its grammar. We can walk about the country quite well, but when forced to make a map, we go wrong. A map will show different roads through the same country, any one of which we can take, though not two, just as in philosophy we must take up problems one by one though in fact each problem leads to a multitude of others. We must wait until we come round to the starting point before we can proceed to another section, that is, before we can either treat of the problem we first attacked or proceed to another. In philosophy matters are not simple enough for us to say “Let’s get a rough idea”, for we do not know the country except by knowing the connections between the roads. So I suggest repetition as a means of surveying the connections. (YB 2001, 43)

While Wittgenstein is at that time still unhappy about knowing only ‘iso- lated bits’ and a synoptic view figures as the ideal he strives for, it seems that providing sketches of a landscape is what he resigned himself to in the end.17

Conclusion

The above was meant to show that apparently useless maps may be useful after all. If only as inspirational material for philosophers. For Wittgenstein might just as well have heeded Descartes’ advice that the best way out of a thicket is to continue in the direction once chosen.18 Had Wittgenstein walked in a straight line rather than repeatedly taking detours, we would be one work of philosophy poorer, for it is his criss-cross manner of mapping thought that makes the landscape of his Philosophical Investigations so intriguing.

374 Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

Notes

1 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, the German text, with an English translation by G. E. M. Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte, revised fourth edition by P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte (New York: Wiley, 2009).—All references are made to the respective paragraphs using the siglum IP. Other reference keys to Wittgensteins writings are indicated in the bibliography.

2 Borges, Jorge Luis. ‘On Scientific Rigor’, in: Selected Poems, edited by Alexander Coleman (New York: Viking), 139.

3 E. g. Borges, Jorge Luis. 1999b. Selected Non-Fictions, edited by Eliot Weinberger, (New York: Viking), 215.

4 Cf. Pitcher George. 1967. ‘Wittgenstein, Nonsense and Lewis Carroll’, in: Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Man and His Philosophy, edited by K. T. Fann (New York: Dell), Fn5.—More information on occurrences of Carroll’s writings in Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Nachlass may be found in my paper ‘The Uses of Nonsense: Ludwig Wittgenstein reads Lewis Carroll’ in: Wittgenstein-Studien 3/2012, edited by Wilhelm Lütterfelds, Stefan Majetschak, Richard Raatzsch and Wilhelm Vossenkuhl (DeGruyter, 2012) (in preparation).

5 Carroll, Lewis. 1991. The Complete Sylvie and Bruno, (San Francisco: Mercury House), 265.

6 Cf. Letter to Ludwig Hänsel (30. 11. 1920) in: Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2004. Complete Correspondence. The Innsbruck Electronic Edition. Edited by Monika Seekirchner, Anton Unterkirchner and Brian McGuinness. Charlottesville, Virginia: Intelex (Web-Edition).

7 Swift, Jonathan. 1892. Gulliver’s Travels, (London: T. Nelson and Sons) 193 f.8 Cf. Royce, Josiah. 1923. The World and the Individual, First Series (New York:

Macmillan), 502 ff.9 Cf. Borges, Jorge Luis. 1966. Das Eine und die Vielen. Essays zur Literatur (München:

Hanser), 152.10 Russell, Bertrand. 1920. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, second edition

(London: George Allen & Unwin) 80.11 Cf. Gauss, Carl Friedrich. 1873. Werke, Band IV, (Göttingen: Königl. Ges. der

Wissenschaften), 189 ff.12 Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1979. Contributions to THE NATION, pt. 3 (Lubbock: Texas

Tech Univ. Press) 83.13 Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1979. Contributions to THE NATION, pt. 3 (Lubbock: Texas

Tech Univ. Press.) 84.

375Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

14 Russell, Bertrand. 1920. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, second edition. (London: George Allen & Unwin), 80.

15 A related point is made by Hana Gründler in her perceptive paper ‘ “Eine Menge von Landschaftsskizzen.” Zur Bedeutung des Zeichnerischen in Ludwig Wittgensteins Spätphilosophie’ in volume one of Image and Imaging in Philosophy, Science and the Arts, Proceedings of the 33rd International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium, edited by Richard Heinrich, Elisabeth Nemeth, Wolfram Pichler and David Wagner (Heusenstamm bei Frankfurt: ontos Verlag, 2011), 1–22.— Gründler points out that it is less easy to discern the borders of an object in line drawing, once singular clear contours have been replaced by the multiplicity of lines that constitute a sketch. The apparent loss of clarity comes, however, hand in hand with a more natural depiction of the object—one gains the impression of volume. Artists and philosophers both generate perspectives on their object of interest without claiming that any of their respective views is the only viable one.

16 Cf. this example from February 1931 (MS 110): ‘Ich erkläre jemanden einen Plan und wie er zu gehen hat und sage, auf eine Stelle des Planes zeigend: “Hier stehen wir; du gehst … .” Nun sieht er die Karte anders. Verstehen ist nicht: ein Bild sehen, sondern, ein Bild in einer bestimmten Position.’ (WA3: 197 10 f.)

17 Hana Gründler suggests that Wittgenstein intentionally chose the form of sketch-ing his thoughts rather than presenting them in a more worked-out and orderly fashion, because he imagined his ideal reader to be someone who prefers thought-provoking impulses to philosophical treatises. Cf. Gründler ‘Landschaftsskizzen’ (as in note 15), 11.

18 Cf. Descartes, René. 1953. ‘Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison’ in: Œvres et Lettres, (Paris: Gallimard), 142.

Literature

Borges, Jorge Luis. 1966. Das Eine und die Vielen. Essays zur Literatur. München: Hanser.–––. 1999a. ‘On Scientific Rigor’, in: Coleman, Alexander (ed.), Selected Poems, New

York [et al.]: Viking, 139.–––. 1999b. Selected Non-Fictions, edited by Eliot Weinberger, New York [et al.]: Viking.Carroll, Lewis. 1991. The Complete Sylvie and Bruno, San Francisco: Mercury House.Descartes, René. 1953. ‘Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison’ in: Œvres

et Lettres, Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, Paris: Gallimard, 125–179.Gauss, Carl Friedrich. 1873. Werke, Band IV, Göttingen: Königl. Ges. der Wissenschaften.

376 Glimpses of Unsurveyable Maps

Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1979. Contributions to THE NATION, pt. 3, Lubbock: Texas Tech Univ. Press.

Pitcher, George. 1967. ‘Wittgenstein, Nonsense and Lewis Carroll’, in: Fann, K. T. (ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Man and His Philosophy, N. Y.: Dell.

Royce, Josiah. 1923. The World and the Individual, First Series, New York: Macmillan.Russell, Bertrand. 1920. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, second edition.

London: George Allen & Unwin.Swift, Jonathan. 1892. Gulliver’s Travels, London: T. Nelson and Sons.Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1999a. Wiener Ausgabe, Studien Ausgabe, volume two [= MS

107 and MS 108]. Vienna / New York: Springer. (WA2)–––.1999b. Wiener Ausgabe, Studien Ausgabe, volume three [= MS 109 and MS 110].

Vienna / New York: Springer. (WA3)–––. 2000. Wittgenstein’s Nachlass, The Bergen Electronic Edition, Oxford University

Press, University of Bergen, The Wittgenstein Trustees. (MS)–––. 2001. ‘The Yellow Book (Selected Parts)’. In: Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge,

1932–1935, from the notes of Alice Ambrose and Margaret Macdonald, edited by Alice Ambrose. New York: Prometheus, 41–73. (YB)

–––. 2009. Philosophical Investigations, revised fourth edition by P. M. S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte. New York: Wiley. (PI)

–––. Complete Correspondence. The Innsbruck Electronic Edition. Edited by Monika Seekirchner, Anton Unterkirchner and Brian McGuinness. Charlottesville, Virginia: Intelex (Web-Edition). (ICE)

List of Authors

Christopher BurkeUniversity of ReadingDepartment of Typography & Graphic CommunicationWhiteknightsReading RG6 6AUUnited [email protected]

Steffen BogenUniversität Konstanz Institut für Kunstwissenschaft/KunstgeschichteFach D 15278457 [email protected]

Richard HeinrichUniversität Wien Institut für PhilosophieUniversitätsstraße 71010 [email protected]

Bill HillierThe BartlettUniversity College LondonSpace Research GroupLondon WC1E 6BTUnited [email protected]

378 List of Authors

Sophie HochhäuslCornell University (PhD Student)Ithaca, NY 14850U. S. [email protected]

Eric KindelUniversity of ReadingDepartment of Typography & Graphic CommunicationWhiteknightsReading RG6 6AUUnited [email protected]

Hadwig KraeutlerÖsterreichische Galerie BelvedereMuseologie, Projekte, KonzeptePrinz-Eugen-Straße 271030 [email protected]

Sybille KrämerFreie Universität BerlinInstitut für PhilosophieArbeitsbereich Sprach- u. MedienphilosophieHabelschwerdter Allee 3012161 [email protected]

379List of Authors

Bart LootsmaLeopold-Franzens-Universität InnsbruckLehrstuhl für Architekturtheorie 6020 [email protected]

Karl H. MüllerWiener Institut für Sozialwissenschaftliche Dokumentation und MethodikLiechtensteinstraße 22a/2/171090 [email protected]

Elisabeth NemethUniversität Wien Institut für PhilosophieUniversitätsstraße 71010 [email protected]

Sybilla NikolowUniversität BielefeldInstitut für Wissenschafts- und Technikforschung (IWT)33501 [email protected]

380 List of Authors

Wolfram PichlerUniversität Wien Institut für KunstgeschichteUniversitätscampus Hof 9Spitalgasse 21090 [email protected]

Armin ReautschnigWiener Institut für Sozialwissenschaftliche Dokumentation und MethodikLiechtensteinstraße 22a/2/171090 [email protected]

Andreas RoserAnton Bruckner Privatuniversität & Universität [email protected]

Friedrich StadlerUniversität Wien Institut für Philosophie & Institut für ZeitgeschichteUniversitätsstraße 71010 [email protected]

Frederik StjernfeltAarhus University Center for SemioticsBuilding 1467Jens Chr. Skous Vej 78000 Aarhus CDenmark

381List of Authors

[email protected]

Felix ThürlemannUniversität Konstanz Institut für Kunstwissenschaft/KunstgeschichteFach D 15278457 [email protected]

David WagnerUniversität Wien Institut für PhilosophieUniversitätsstraße 71010 [email protected]