"Interpretation, Intention, and Truth"

14
Interpretation, Intention, and Truth Author(s): Richard Shusterman Source: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 46, No. 3 (Spring, 1988), pp. 399-411 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The American Society for Aesthetics Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/431110 Accessed: 16/03/2010 10:51 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Blackwell Publishing and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. http://www.jstor.org

Transcript of "Interpretation, Intention, and Truth"

Interpretation, Intention, and TruthAuthor(s): Richard ShustermanSource: The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 46, No. 3 (Spring, 1988), pp. 399-411Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The American Society for AestheticsStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/431110Accessed: 16/03/2010 10:51

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unlessyou have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and youmay use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained athttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Blackwell Publishing and The American Society for Aesthetics are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.

http://www.jstor.org

RICHARD SHUSTERMAN

Interpretation, Intention, and Truth

I.

ONE OF THE MOST SALIENT and powerful trends in the last few decades of literary theory has been the attempt to discredit and displace the tradi- tional project of intentionalist interpretation, the idea that the meaning of a text is to be identified with or found in the intention of its author. Intentionalism surely suffered a sharp and more than momentary blow with the rise of the New Criticism and its influential doctrine of the intentional fallacy, articulated by Wimsatt and Beardsley.1 But more recent and perhaps still more devastating have been the poststructuralist doctrine of "the death of the Author," heralded by Barthes,2 and the related rise of the poetics of reader response.

Yet despite the forceful onslaught of these influential doctrines, Anglo-American literary theory has been reluctant to abandon com- pletely the idea that texts mean what they're intended to mean. Influential as it was, New Critical anti-intentionalism soon faced what Beardsley called the "intentionalist backlash."3 It came not only from the phenomenologically based theory of E. D. Hirsch, but through various analytically motivated theories based on a Gricean (and ultimately Austinian) account of meaning in terms of speech acts. For we must remember that though Austin more famously defined the illocutionary act as "a conventional act," he also regarded it, qua act, as having an essential intentional aspect,4 a point which escaped neither Strawson nor Derrida.5 Indeed for all his anti-intentionalist zeal, Beardsley seems compelled by his Austinian speech-act theory of literature (that a "poem is an imitation of a compound illocutionary act") to admit that

RICHARD SHUSTERMAN is associate professor of philos- ophy at Temple University.

at least one intention of the author must be recognized in literary interpretation, namely, his intention to produce a literary work of art rather than an ordinary speech act.6

The Austinian-Gricean line of intentionalist defense has been recently reformulated with a vengeance in Knapp and Michaels's powerful essay "Against Theory," which has provoked so much controversy and discussion as to gen- erate a book about it.7 Their defense of inten- tionalism is not explicitly directed against Beardsley and Wimsatt (whose New Critical program has already been superseded by more recent and fashionable theories) but primarily at today's prevailing anti-intentionalists--the post- structuralist textualists like de Man-who see literary texts as intentionless language rather than intended speech acts, which instead are what Knapp and Michaels maintain all language must always be.8 Holding that "meanings are always intentional," they argue that therefore "what a text means and what its author intends it to mean are identical."9

With philosophy of language's growing rec- ognition that sentence and utterance meaning cannot be fully explained in purely extensional terms, that language is in some (but not neces- sarily mentalistic) sense intrinsically and irre- ducibly intentional, it is hard not to sympathize with the rehabilitation of intention as an ines- capably relevant factor in literary interpretation. However, to admit this does not commit us to denying the point of the intentional fallacy thesis and accepting the alternative of Knapp and Michaels. We must be careful not to con- fuse the seemingly incontrovertible assertion that all linguistic or textual meaning is inten- tional with the very challengeable assertion that the meaning of a text is identical with the author's intention or intended meaning.

This is precisely Knapp and Michaels's

? 1988 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

SHUSTERMAN

mistake. By simplistically conflating "mean- ing" with "authorially intended meaning" they thereby absurdly preclude the possibility of someone's speech or writing failing to mean what it was intended to mean, a possibility which is indeed a very frequent actuality. Re- jecting this conflation, one can still grant the identification of meaning with intention or in- tended meaning in more than the holistic sense that there could be no linguistic meaning with- out a background of human intentionality, no "possibility of language prior to and indepen- dent of intention."10' One can even hold that every individual linguistic text requires some particular intention for its meaning. A string of letters accidentally produced by a computer or by the movement of the tide on the sand would still depend for its meaning on an intentional act, here the intention of the reader to see the marks as a meaningful text, as language rather than simply marks. However, even if we deny with Knapp and Michaels that "there can in fact be intentionless meanings" and accept their premise that texts seen as "intentionless . . . become meaningless as well" and thus that in some sense "what is intended and what is meant are identical," it still does not follow that "the meaning of a text is simply identical to the author's intended meaning."1' All that follows is that the meaning of a text is inseparable from some intention (or group of intentions) or an- other. But the necessary meaning-securing in- tentions could belong to readers of the text rather than to its original author. Thus Knapp and Michaels's argument fails to clinch the case for identifying the text's meaning with authorial intention, unless we are prepared to count any of its readers as the author. But such a drastic remedy would undermine their whole project of intentionalist, author-orientated criticism by dis- mantling the very notion of author.

Their failure however is very instructive in its unstated erroneous assumption that the only sort of intentions that matter for textual meaning and criticism are the author's. This assumption is symptomatic of theory's typical and mistaken neglect of readers' intentions and their variety and importance. It is striking that this neglect of the variety of legitimate reading intentions per- vades not only the intentionalist and anti- intentionalist theories of interpretation in the Anglo-American metacritical tradition. It more

surprisingly also extends to continentally in- spired poststructuralist theories of interpretation which frequently congratulate themselves for providing the salubrious proper emphasis on the crucial contributory role of the reader in consti- tuting the meaning of the text. In what follows I shall be reviewing some of the most influential theories from both these traditions in order to demonstrate their attitude of neglect or dismiss- ive homogenization of readers' intentions, and to suggest some of their latent motives and implicit principles and presuppositions. My crit- icism of these theories and their guiding mo- tives, principles, and presumptions will involve relating them to very fundamental philosophical misconceptions regarding meaning, understand- ing, and knowledge. This in turn will require at least some schematic suggestions as to better alternative accounts of such notions.

II.

Even before going into the details of any specific theory, we can easily see why aca- demic theorists and critics would prefer to deal only with the intention of the author. For this provides, at least in theory, a single, determi- nate, unchanging focus and standard for all the different readings or interpretations of the work to converge upon and be judged by their fidelity to such intention. But, moreover, since this unique and fixed meaning is only available in theory, it also allows (if not encourages) a continuing diversity of interpretive efforts and approaches.

In short, the elusive notion of authorial in- tention paradoxically provides both the security of the possibility of achieving objective truth and convergence in literary interpretation (something that the academic industry requires for its legitimation as a scientific, positivist enterprise productive of formulatable, teachable truths) and also the security that this objective truth or meaning cannot be conclusively or once and for all demonstrated, thereby ensuring that the demand for continued interpretive efforts and new readings will not be extinguished.'2 This demand is perhaps even more crucial than truth to the academic industry, where the pro- duction of ever-new interpretations and critical perspectives is necessary for its own reproduc- tion and advancement (as it is for the personal careers of its participants).

400

Interpretation, Intention, and Truth

The implicit recognition that the value of continued demand and productivity outweighs that of legitimation through the ideas of determinacy and truth can explain why aca- demic criticism has so enthusiastically em- braced first the banishment of the author (al- ready in New Criticism) and then the further banishment of the circumscribed, determinate work so as to exult in the productive freedom of pluralistic textuality (as expressed in Barthes and deconstruction). Understandably, those who oppose this free-wheeling, creative inter- pretive productivity express the fear that such practice will destroy the coherence of criticism as a scholarly cognitive discipline converging on the truth.'3

Literary theorists of the more conservative Anglo-American tradition, so long preoccupied with the question of authorial intention as to ignore that of the reader, have characteristically assumed that the interpreting reader's intention is (or should be) essentially uniform and that it is (or should be) essentially cognitive. The case of Beardsley is instructive. In arguing (against Hirsch) for the logical (and possibly real) dif- ference between a text's meaning and what its author intended it to mean, Beardsley initially recognizes that this difference permits at least two different interpretive projects: "to discover the textual meaning . . . and to discover the authorial meaning." But then he simply as- sumes monistically that there must be only one interpretive aim or practice that could be "proper." We are therefore compelled to choose from among the diverse "possible inter- pretive tasks or inquiries . . . which of them is the proper function of the literary interpreter," his "general and essential task"; and Beardsley of course recommends the choice of textual meaning because of its greater availability and allegedly richer aesthetic rewards.14 However, once this choice is made the interpreter's aim is not aesthetic richness per se, but truth or correctness, where interpretations "must be in principle capable of being shown to be true or false."'5 For Beardsley, then, the only proper aim is discovery of the text's nonauthorially defined but determinate meaning (through pub- lic linguistic rules) which will not permit con- tradictory interpretive statements to be correct.

The Anglo-American theorists Beardsley at- tacks for opposing his view nevertheless share

Beardsley's assumption that legitimate interpre- tation essentially aims at descriptive truth or some relativized cognitive analogue. Thus Hirsch is committed to the goal of "knowledge in interpretation," believing that literary study is and should be a form of "humanistic knowledge," an "empirical inquiry" and "cog- nitive discipline," where qualified interpreters, ''working together or in competition, can add to the knowledge" of literature.'6 Indeed Hirsch's advocacy of authorial intention as the criterion of textual meaning is made only to secure the goal of objective interpretive knowledge, his argument being that only a text's determinacy of meaning will allow such knowledge and that only authorial intention can provide such determinacy. Thus, though aware that "autho- rial intention is not the only possible norm of interpretation," Hirsch holds "it is the only practical norm for a cognitive discipline of interpretation." 17 Without it there is simply too much freedom, indeterminacy, and instability in the public linguistic conventions governing meaning to secure convergence on a single interpretation with which the work's meaning (and thus the work itself as a meaningful entity) may be identified, thereby providing a stable object for literary study and criticism.

Margolis, Beardsley's other major target, might seem an exception to the assumption of cognitive monism in interpretive intentions, since he advocates a "robust relativism" which frees interpretive validity not only from autho- rial intention but also from strict determinacy of meaning, thereby allowing the possible validity of conflicting interpretations. Yet though he liberally accepts the plurality and noncon- vergence of interpretive approaches (Marxist, Freudian, existentialist, etc.); though he es- chews the idea of a single, exclusive, and exhaustive interpretive truth in order to advo- cate a plurality of interpretations whose validity may be affirmed and defended in relative terms of "plausibility"; and, finally, though he plu- ralistically divides the standard interpretive en- terprise into two logically distinct (though hardly independent) activities or moments- "describing" and "interpreting," Margolis ul- timately makes the same assumption of inter- pretive uniformity at the fundamental logical level. Critical interpretation, as contrasted with interpretive performance (to which it is in many

401

SHUSTERMAN

ways quite similar) is essentially a cognitive enterprise aimed at generating true or "truth- like" propositions. Rejecting the prescriptivist and emotivist views which see interpretive state- ments as quasi-imperatival or affective rather than propositional, Margolis argues that their reasonable claim that interpretive judgments "do not take the values 'true' and 'false' does not entail that such judgments lack a proposi- tional form or are unable to take substitute values of a suitable [truth-like or cognitive] kind"; and he indeed goes on to insist that "epistemic values of some sort can be assigned to interpretations."18 His advocacy of the no- tions of plausibility and implausibility repre- sents his attempt to provide such truthlike values or, as he puts it, " 'truth-values' other than true and false."19 Likewise, his advocacy of relativism rests on the faith "that relativism is not in principle incompatible with a cognitive conception of interpretation; . . . that the de- fense of plural, non-converging interpretations is not, on cognitive grounds, incoherent."20

Indeed, far from rejecting the factor of prop- ositional truth from interpretation, Margolis contends that any plausible interpretation of a work must be based on descriptions of the work that are (and are determinably) true rather than merely relativistically plausible: "interpretative claims must be compatible with what is (mini- mally) descriptively true of a given work.... No plausible account may be incompatible with an admittedly true statement. "21 It is what Margolis calls "description," as distinguished from interpretation but as the necessary substra- tum for it, which provides the true statements on which any plausible interpretation must be based. Descriptions, unlike interpretations, are simply true or false of the literary work inde- pendent of relativizing critical context. They display the intolerance of incompatibles (which Beardsley and Hirsch ascribe to interpreta- tions): either "an object . . . has or has not the properties . . . described."22

On Margolis's model, true descriptions are to plausible interpretations what facts are to scien- tific theories whose truth cannot be decisively demonstrated. Facts or descriptions both pro- vide the evidential basis for the explanatory theory or interpretation and also constitute what that (scientific or interpretive) theory is sup- posed to explain. Moreover, though both inter-

pretations and scientific theories go beyond the descriptively true or factually given (and thus allow the plausibility of conflicting accounts), they surely rest on the true.23 However, though both go beyond true statements, they seem to differ importantly in the fact (noted by Margolis) that aesthetic interpretation, unlike scientific theory, helps significantly to consti- tute the reality it treats, developing the meaning of the work it interprets. " 'Interpreting' . . . suggests a touch of virtuousity, an element of performance, a shift from a stable object whose properties are enumerable to an object whose properties pose something of a puzzle or chal- lenge-with emphasis . . . on some inventive use of the materials present, on the added contribution of the interpreter, and on a certain openness toward possible alternative inter- pretations," beyond the borders of what is descriptively true of the work.24

Margolis here cleverly tries to satisfy and balance the fundamentally conflicting demands of continued productivity and truth, as indeed Beardsley and Hirsch also tried to in their own implicit and unknowing manner. If for Hirsch the author's intention satisfied the claim of truth, its elusiveness promised the claim of continuing interpretation. If for Beardsley truth could be secured through public conventions of meaning, continued productivity of interpreta- tion was assured through the fact that these conventions were continually changing. For Margolis, truth is given in description's account of the work of art's hard and undeniable prop- erties, while interpretation's creative contribu- tion toward extending the work beyond those core descriptive properties allows for a contin- ued, never-ending interpretive productivity, based and constrained by truth but not confined to it.

Margolis's account of interpretive logic seems clearly superior to Hirsch's and Beardsley's, not only because it more accu- rately reflects the dominant trend in actual practice, but because it can positively allow for, explain, and even encourage the contempora- neous production of different plausible ways of interpreting a work, and yet maintain all the while that interpretation contains and presents truth about the work, through the descriptive truths on which it is based. His strategy of distinguishing the moments of description and

402

Interpretation, Intention, and Truth

interpretation (with its consequent division of labor into truth and productivity) would be an ideal solution were it not for the fact that the distinction cannot be maintained in a firm, principled, more-than-pragmatic way.

First of all, we must remember that every description of a work of art involves an inter- pretation of it, since it involves a selection of what to describe, what aspects of the work are important as to be worth describing. No descrip- tion describes everything, egalitarianly reflect- ing all that can be said truly about a work. But what more acutely undermines the idea of any firm and definite distinction between descrip- tive truth (presenting the work's core of incon- trovertible properties) and interpretive elabora- tion is that what is taken as descriptively true (the so-called hard facts on which interpretation is based) will often shamelessly depend on which interpretation of the work we come to adopt.25 For example, Hamlet's love for his father (which he both declares and might seem to express in his mourning, melancholy behav- ior) has been taken as a descriptive "hard fact" of the play. But if we come to adopt the very plausible Freudian interpretation of Hamlet's mood, delay, and behavior towards his mother, this apparent firm fact evaporates into Hamlet's self-deluding rationalization.26 More generally, we can be led from what we originally see as simple facts about the work to reach an inter- pretation of the work which dislodges or recasts the facts by showing the work in such a way that the original descriptions no longer ring true or adequate. (Indeed narrative art and the enjoy- able surprises in reading are often based on this sort of phenomenon.)

Thus, any distinction between describing and interpreting (as between understanding and in- terpreting) can only be relative and formal. It must be a pragmatic, shifting, heuristic distinc- tion, not an unchanging one which would pro- vide a firm and incorruptible core of determi- nate truth for simple and final description. In other words, it is not that we all agree how to describe the facts and differ only in what interpretations we elaborate from them. It is rather that the descriptive facts are simply whatever we all strongly agree upon, while interpretations are simply what commands less consensus and displays (and tolerates) wider divergence.

The idea of an essential core of fixed, deter- minate, descriptive properties which constitute the work of art and are to be represented (even if augmented or extended) by valid inter- pretation cannot be successfully maintained; and its untenability undermines theories like Margolis's (and Beardsley's and Hirsch's) which rest on it. Its weakness has been sensed and ferociously exploited by deconstructionist theorists for whom the absence of an unchang- ing reproducible core of descriptive content or truths about the work's meaning entails the conclusion that interpreting always must in- volve change and distortion, that "all readings are misreadings."

III.

Deconstructors, hardly less (though differ- ently) than the Anglo-American theorists dis- cussed thus far, have tended to ignore the variety of reader's intentions and to assume monistically that they always are and cannot help but be transformational or revisionistic in some way. Harold Bloom provides an excellent example both of the tendency to a monism of misreading and of the professionalistic parochi- alism and productive pressures which foster it. In preaching "the defensive necessity of 'mis- prision' or strong 'misreading,' " he insists that we "read to usurp, just as the poet writes to usurp," and the essential thing all seek to usurp is power or influence (which means a certain freedom from past influence).27 Bloom makes the common but erroneous assumption of conflating reader with professional critic or interpreter, and thus equating the act of reading with the critical performance of formulating or presenting a critical interpretation. Such an interpretation, in order to makes its professional way-to emerge from the domination of prior interpretations which influenced it and to be singled out for study among the many critical interpretations the given work has already re- ceived (themselves often the product of profes- sional pressures to provide published interpre- tations or "readings")-must make some claim to originality, if not also to truth, to distinguish itself. There is something more to the profes- sional reader-interpreting critic than the simple desire to understand and enjoy. He must make his mark by creating his own interpretation

403

SHUSTERMAN

which will influence others. When Bloom ear- lier says, "Reading . . . is a belated and all- but-impossible act, and if strong is always a misreading," he comes close to recognizing that there are other readers, malignly implicated as weak, who are free enough from literary ambition as to perhaps submit themselves suf- ficiently to a text and thus manage to read it. But Bloom immediately goes on to dismiss the importance of such reading, since it is only "[t]he strong reader . . . whose readings will matter to others as well as to himself.'"28 Only the critic who writes a novel interpretation, rather than a mere reader who simply performs a reading, will make his mark on the profes- sional map, will enjoy the power (and avoid the anxiety) of influence which so preoccupies Bloom as professional critic.

If we find Bloom's argument for "the neces- sity of misreading" unconvincingly based on an unjustified dismissal of lay, uncreative, "weak readers," his fellow deconstructors are quick to bring heavier epistemological arguments to show that even the most submissive non- professional is virtually compelled to misread. Their fundamental line of argument is that all linguistic meaning and hence textual meaning is essentially context-dependent; and thus since contexts inexorably change, the meaning of a text cannot be exactly reproduced or recovered in a faithful reading. Building on Saussure, Derrida and his disciples see linguistic meaning not as based and anchored on a prior extra- linguistic reality of things or positive essences to which language refers and from which it gets its meaning. Linguistic meaning is rather a product of the differential relations (paradig- matic and syntagmatic) between the various elements of the language system, which is ever open to new elements and continually trans- forming itself, and thus does not really consti- tute a structuralist system in the normal, closed, completely regulated sense. Language, with its root of difference, is instead a changing "sys- tematic play of differences" which "is incom- patible with the static, synchronic, taxonomic, ahistoric motives in the concept of structure" and displays "an irreducible and generative multiplicity.' 29 This protean vision of language is then coupled with a naively pre- Wittgensteinean picture of understanding as the recapturing or reproduction of a particular in-

tentional content or meaning-object so as to render true reading and understanding a hope- less pursuit.

Thus Culler maintains that the notions of "[r]eading and understanding [claim to] pre- serve or reproduce a content or meaning, main- tain its identity, while misunderstanding and misreading distort it; they produce or introduce difference."30 Yet he goes on to argue that this claim is groundless, since language (and hence its understanding) is always changing with con- text and thus always involves some difference, thereby making absolute identity, preservation, or replication of meaning an impossibility. As Culler pithily puts it, "meaning is context- bound but context is boundless," new contex- tual features . . . alter illocutionary force."3' Since meaning can never be completely circum- scribed contextually so as to permit its perfect replication, then true reading or interpretation is rendered impossible: "all readings are mis- readings."32 While Bloom holds that all good readers intentionally or purposively misread to usurp, even if this intention or purpose is not consciously known to them, Culler homoge- nizes and totalizes readerly intentions by con- tending that with respect to the particular issue of misreading they do not really matter. For whatever the intentions of the reading subject (whose status as a fully autonomous agent is anyway challenged), he or she cannot help but misread since linguistic meaning necessarily can never repeat itself. (And given the necessity of misreading and the impossibility of true understanding, Culler seems largely to concur with Bloom in advocating manipulative "knowledge and feelings of mastery" as read- ing's highest, most rewarding achievement, even if he also admits that such claims to knowledge and mastery are at best provisional and are put into question by deconstruction's own skeptical arguments and habits of master- ful misreading.)33

However, Culler's argument for the necessity of misreading is not compelling. For at least one of its two central premises is dangerously false. It is hard to deny deconstruction's (perhaps overstated) tenet that language is to some extent in perpetual change and development, though we need to remember that much of this change is hardly significant and sometimes barely per- ceptible, and occurs on the dominant back-

404

Interpretation, Intention, and Truth

ground of some sort of continuity. But the second premise, which construes reading, un- derstanding, and interpretation as the recovery or reproduction of an identical semantic object, "a content or meaning," is a terribly perverse but pervasive philosophical picture which has long captivated and misguided our theorizing. It reflects an erroneous and ungrounded hypo- statization (and consequent fetishization) of meaning as a separate and autonomous object (a semantic counterpart of independently existing material objects) rather than something whose existence is essentially relational and inextrica- ble from human socio-linguistic practices. Such a view of meaning as an independent object available for inspection and having determinate features or contours which can be correctly or incorrectly described in the manner of material objects is also at the very core of the objectivist theories of interpretation advanced by Hirsch and Beardsley, and even informs Margolis's robust relativism (in its descriptive moment). Thus, beneath their apparently enormous differ- ence and opposition, both deconstruction and the more conservative objectivist or cognitivist theories of interpretation are united by a more fundamental shared view of meaning (as an object) and of interpretive understanding (as its mirroring reproduction or faithful discursive representation).

However, as Wittgenstein labored to teach us, meaning is not a separate object or content but merely the correlate of understanding some- thing. And understanding something is not the mirroring correspondence or capturing or repro- duction of some fixed and determinate inten- tional object or semantic content. It is funda- mentally an ability to handle or respond to that thing in certain accepted ways which are con- sensually shared, sanctioned, and inculcated by the community (forming part of the fabric of its form of life) but which are nonetheless flexible and open to (divergent) interpretation and emen- dation. What counts as the proper response of true understanding not only depends on the normative practices of the given society but also varies with respect to contexts within it. We should expect, for example, different responses of understanding to figure in the ordinary, the literary, and the psychoanalytic understandings of an utterance. Wittgenstein himself seemed to recognize that understanding does not have only

one general criterion. He held that the two general criteria for understanding the meaning of a word are the ability to use it correctly and the ability to explain its meaning, yet he also contends that one general criterion for under- standing a poem would be to read it with suitable expression or cadence.34

IV.

Why, in spite of Wittgenstein's critique and the natural skeptical impulse to balk at positing immaterial meanings as separate objects or entities, do such seasoned philosophers still countenance or implicitly assume such an idea? One possible reply could be developed from certain doctrines of "the Frankfurt school" of critical theory, particularly of Adorno, Horkheimer, and Marcuse, who were greatly concerned with the problem of reification. For these thinkers (as for Habermas, their succes- sor) critical theory is not limited to literary matters and metacriticism but denotes a gen- eral, global approach of critique encompassing not only most areas of philosophy but just as centrally political, economic, sociological, and psychological theory and practice.35 A Frank- furt school approach might explain the perva- sive hypostatization, reification, and conse- quent fetishization of literary meaning as an object (remember the New Critical notion of "the verbal icon") by relating this to still more basic epistemological assumptions and motives.

Like other reifications, reifying meanings into objects could be seen as deriving from an overriding positivist bias toward technical, in- strumental, and capitalist thinking, where what is conceived as existing needs to be construed in quantifiable, commodifiable items. Authors cre- ate works with meanings which readers pur- chase and consume as aesthetic commodities, and which scholars accumulate and develop, establishing through the mutual funding of in- terpretations a substantial stock of accredited meanings for given works. Understanding in this technical mode is ultimately motivated by the desire for instrumental control and mastery. Not only is deconstructionist misreading clearly directed towards a masterful manipulative con- trol of the elements of our textual, literary environment. Even the apparent submissiveness of Hirsch and Beardsley displays a masked will

405

SHUSTERMAN

for instrumental control. We submit ourselves to such (authorial or textual) authority in order to uncover the work's true (but hidden) mean- ing, knowledge of which will enable us to use the work better and will empower us to share and speak with the work's authority, and there- fore better control its effects. All this is on analogy with science's reification of the facts of nature, sought in the guise of submissive, theoretical disinterestedness but really moti- vated by the aim of better controlling, exploit- ing, or even transforming them.

It is almost irresistibly natural to speak of meanings as objects (rather than as relations or functions of texts and readers) because we tend to reify everything. Philosophers are famous for considering questions of ontology in terms of tables, chairs, and pens, and tend to think of whatever exists as existing in the manner of what Austin used to call "middle-sized dry goods." It proves difficult to make an excep- tion for meanings, particularly when, as with literary meanings, they are seen as valuable commodities, the products of academic labor, to be collected and wielded as cognitive cultural capital.

This way of explaining reification of mean- ing is no doubt intriguing and, at least in moods of disenchantment, quite enchanting. However, critical theory's claims and arguments are very hard to validate in any clear and systematic, logical manner. For they are cast in an alto- gether different philosophical idiom from that of standard logico-linguistic analysis. They seem to inhabit a very different world or at least level of philosophical inquiry from that of the interpretive theories we have been discussing, nor do they seem assimilable to or assessable by the explanations and methodology of standard empirical sociological research. I cannot pause here for a properly detailed appraisal of critical theory's account of reification, which is not to deny that it warrants serious consideration.

The salient philosophical (and common- sensical) tendency to objectify meaning might find a better explanation and perhaps even justification from another, more elevated mo- tive-the desire for knowledge and truth. Surely, one could argue, when we read and try to understand or interpret a literary work, we are aiming at knowledge of its meaning, at what it really and truly means. But how can there be

any truth or knowledge about meaning if there is no object of meaning to be true about. Without such "an object of knowledge," a determinate objectified meaning, as Hirsch in fact argues, all truth and "knowledge in interpretation" would be impossible. Indeed, for him, without firm determinate objects of knowledge there could not be any sort of knowledge at all.36

Clearly, what underlies this justification of the reification of meaning is a correspondence theory of truth and knowledge, which, as we have seen, informs not only Hirsch's interpre- tive cognitivism but also that of Beardsley and Margolis. Yet this correspondence theory is extremely problematic and now very much in retreat for a variety of reasons.37 The idea of truth as simple correspondence to reality is too vague; and to speak more specifically (in the idiom of the early logical atomists) of corre- spondence to facts or states of affairs immedi- ately raises the sort of problems which frus- trated the atomist project. For example, since we can't seem to individuate or refer to these facts apart from the true propositions which

express them, how can we meaningfully differ- entiate between propositions and the facts which make them true, so as to allow for any compar- ison or correspondence? How are we, more- over, to understand negative truths without having to swallow the indigestibly bizarre no- tion of negative facts?

To appeal to the idea of correspondence to

objects is no less problematic. For objects can

only be identified or referred to in terms of some conceptualization or linguistic description of them, and there are various ways which

language carves out a domain into different

objects. There is no single description of the world, and no transcendental nonlinguistic God's-

eye perspective of its objects that would be available for us to appeal to, that would even be

intelligible to us as language users. Thus given that the objects we perceive are always concep- tually, linguistically mediated there can be no workable notion of an unmediated object "as in itself it really is" for correspondence theories to

get a handle on. (And if the very notion of an unmediated object is pragmatically meaning- less, so by extension, as Davidson argues, becomes the very idea of a conceptual scheme or framework imposed on such an unmediated

406

Interpretation, Intention, and Truth

objective reality.)38 It is hard to avoid Rorty's pragmatist conclusion that the idea of truth as correspondence to reality is "an uncashable and outworn metaphor"; and indeed Margolis has more recently come to see its inapplicability to the human sciences, including literary criti- cism, where what instead seems required is rather a notion of objectivity as consensuality.39

The prime reason for the pervasive, implicit, and stubbornly entrenched adherence to the idea of interpretive truth as correspondence to the work's meaning is the anxiety that in abandon- ing it we are abandoning all claims to interpre- tive knowledge. This fear is unfounded, and not merely because there are alternative (coherence and pragmatist) theories of truth which might legitimate such claims. For even if such alter- natives and indeed all theories of truth are unsuccessful or misguided, there remains the crucial point that truth does not exhaust knowl- edge. There is more to knowledge than knowl- edge of truths. Russell, of course, speaks of knowledge of things by acquaintance as a sep- arate and indeed more primary form of knowl- edge. And if we find his theory problematic (e.g., in confusing sensation with sensual knowledge), there is still the undeniable form of knowledge which Ryle called "knowing how," and which clearly cannot always be reduced to knowledge of truths.40 Knowing how to dance, to ride a bicycle, to behave respectfully or insultingly, to express oneself in gestures or in English, is not simply reducible to knowledge of any set of articulable truths. Such knowledge is instead constituted by an ability, a disposi- tional capacity to perform in certain ways in general conformity (rather than rigid slavish adherence) to certain socially endorsed prac- tices, criteria, and models, which may be largely unarticulated and may admit of contest- ing alternative interpretations. Having such dis- positional practical knowledge often requires, in Wittgenstein's phrase. "knowing how to go on," how to make reasonable, fruitful, or at least defensible projections of the relevant prac- tices beyond the range of past applications and criteria.

I wish to suggest that interpretive knowledge of a literary work may be seen in this fashion as a performed ability to respond to the literary work in ways within or conforming to the range of acceptable (either already accepted or co-

gently defensible) response. On this account, our aims in reading and interpretation are not to dig out and describe the objectified meaning already carefully buried in the text by its author, but rather to develop and transmit a richly meaningful response to the text. The project is not to describe the work's given and definitive sense but rather to make sense of the work. But no uniformity of interpretive intentions is thereby implied, since there are a vast variety of socially entrenched yet mutually competing in- terpretive strategies for making sense of texts. One of these is the traditional strategy of authorial intention, a structuring principle to make sense of a text by reconstructing how its author made sense of it. As knowledge is not limited to truth, it is not inconsistent with pluralism and the validity of conflicting, non- convergent responses; and their number is legion.

It should, moreover, be remembered that the various responses of understanding or making sense of a text are not always a matter of constructing or reconstructing some articulated sense or argument which we can identify as the work's informing principle or message. This quest for a core, structuring meaning is only one kind of appropriate response. It is such a common one that, as Eliot shrewdly remarked, many a poet will provide such a "meaning'' to "satisfy one habit of the reader." But, as he also noted, there are other forms of poetry and poetic understanding where there is no meaning of this sort, "so that the reader, bewildered, gropes about for what is absent, and puzzles his head for a kind of 'meaning' which is not there, and is not meant to be there."41

Before concluding, we must consider one last justificatory argument for objectified meanings as the target or goal of reading and interpreta- tion. The argument is basically that without some reified meaning-object with which to identify a work of literature there would be no adequate way to individuate or refer to it as a common object of response or understanding, and thus there would be no possibility of fruitful critical dialogue concerning the work and how it should be understood. Surely to understand a literary work (or anything) must be to under- stand something, but without an objectified meaning there would be no common meaning- ful object for readers and critics to understand.

407

SHUSTERMAN

Obviously, we do not want to identify a literary work merely with any one (or the sum total) of its physically inscribed or orally artic- ulated token texts. For, as Hirsch suggests, without the assumption of meaning these texts are simply marks on paper or noises in the air, and without the assumption of some common meaning binding them together (as tokens of a type) they would be unrelated objects and events. But if the text's identity as something meaningful is only a product of human inten- tionality, then as its readers find in it rather different meanings, how can we continue to identify it as the same work? It rather seems to disintegrate into as many works as there are different meanings intended by different read- ers. There then would be no common work for different readers to react to or interpret differ- ently, no common object for critical discussion. Since we do seem to be able to discuss literary works, it is argued transcendentally that there must be some common intentional object we are discussing, whether we identify it with the author's intention (Hirsch) or with the objective meaning allegedly inscribed in and univocally retrievable from the text itself through so-called rules of language (Beardsley).

Indeed, even if we abandon our faith in real critical communication, there remains the prob- lem that our own individual understanding of a text as meaningful would still seem to require that there be an intentional object to understand. The argument for reified literary meanings thus appears as one manifestation of a more general and very basic and persuasive argument for the necessity of grounding all cognition on some sort of determinate independent objects of cog- nition. This argument is not only part of Brentano and Husserl's phenomenological her- itage, it is also very much part of the analytic heritage of Moore and Russell's refutation of idealism. In both cases, it is held that conscious- ness or experience must be directed at some- thing. That is, it must be consciousness or experience of something other than itself, some object of consciousness or experience, in order to be consciousness or experience at all.

Persuasive as this argument is, it does not, I think, compel us to reify independent meanings or indeed any substantial and determinate ob- jects independent of and unmediated by lan- guage. The demand for an object of cognition

or interpretation is only a grammatical or func- tional one, implying nothing about the nature of the object except that it can be identified and referred to. But then we must realize that the only way to identify or refer to an object is by talking about it (or at least thinking about it under some linguistic description). For this reason, Rorty suggests that pragmatically speak- ing, objects can be reduced to ways of talking, which presumably would involve (after Wittgenstein) ways of acting as well. And this pragmatic de-reification would neither deny nor be discountenanced by our inclination to char- acterize our most central and inalienable ways of talking as "ways of talking about objects."

Reducing objects to ways of talking does not mean we are free to choose what and how we experience things, for we are far from free in how we talk. We are constrained not merely by custom but by the undesirable consequences that might result from departing from the ac- cepted idiom or practice. We are not only initially compelled, through our societal train- ing and acculturation, to talk about and under- stand literary works in certain ways which highlight their coherence, depth, and reflection on the problems of life. We are impelled to continue this practice by the fear that so much beauty will be lost to us by interpreting them differently.

In any case, all we apparently need and can get from common objects as the requisite foci of understanding can be derived from the sort of statements needed to identify such objects. As Rorty remarks, the "know-how" of understand- ing "does not require that we postulate an object-the very text itself, or the true meaning of the text, or the very lump itself or the real essence of the lump-which is present to con- sciousness. ... All that is required is that agreement should be obtainable about what we are talking about-and this just means agree- ment on a reasonable number of propositions using the relevant term."42 In this manner, we can reach an agreement about our objects of interpretation without there being any anteced- ently fixed and determinate objects for us to agree upon.

The requisite agreement on propositions which pragmatically identify for us a common focus for understanding, a common "object" of interpretation, can at different times be

408

Interpretation, Intention, and Truth

constituted by different groups of propositions. In this way we can easily explain how the identity of a literary work can change signifi- cantly over time without our having to explain the mystery of how it can change its properties and meaning after it has already been written or "completed" by its author. Nor would we need to continue agonizing over the puzzling ques- tion of whether or not, given such change, it really is the same work, assuming the question must have a definite answer, as indeed it should once we assume the work's status as an inde- pendent determinate object or entity. In the same way, we can explain how different readers and critics can understand the same work dif- ferently: though they agree on some proposi- tions about the work, enough to establish iden- tity of reference, they disagree about many others. These and a host of related and awk- wardly longstanding philosophical puzzles as- sociated with what is traditionally known as the problem of the work of art's identity simply evaporate once we no longer have to think of the work as an independent object, a reified, determinate repository of meaning.

Instead, on the nonfoundationalist, pragma- tist account I have been sketching here, the literary work turns out to be a continuous and contested construction of the efforts to deter- mine its understanding, description, and inter- pretation; that is, of efforts to determine how and what the work will be taken to be, which amounts, pragmatically speaking, to how and what it actually is.43 Though such efforts to determine understanding can perhaps be said to begin with the author (if we forget the memo- rable fact that literary and linguistic traditions are already determining his determining ef- forts), the intentions which continue to guide and shape understanding are not always those of the author. Moreover, and more importantly, they are not always, if ever, aimed at the mirroring truth of a fixed and determinate object.

1 Wimsatt and Beardsley's attack on intentionalism began as early as 1943 with an entry in J. T. Shipley's Dictionary of World Literature, predating their classic paper "The Intentional Fallacy" which first appeared in 1946 in the Sewanee Review and has since been reprinted in Wimsatt's The Verbal Icon (University of Kentucky Press, 1958) and in numerous anthologies.

2 See R. Barthes, "The Death of the Author," in Image, Music, Text (New York, 1977), pp. 142-48.

3 See M. C. Beardsley, The Possibility of Criticism (Wayne State University Press, 1973), p. 17.

4 See J. L. Austin, How To Do Things With Words (Oxford University Press, 1976), pp. 105, 106, 110, and 146, where Austin says that we need to know "the specific way in which they are intended, first to be in order or not in order, and second to be 'right' or 'wrong.' "

5 See P. F. Strawson, "Intention and Convention in Speech Acts," Philosophical Review 73 (1964): 439-60. See also J. Derrida, "Signature Event Context," in Glyph 1 (Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977), pp. 172-97 (reprinted in his Margins of Philosophy [University of Chicago Press, 1982]).

6 Beardsley, pp. 58-61. 7 See S. Knapp and W. B. Michaels, "Against

Theory," in Against Theory, ed. W. J. T. Mitchell (Uni- versity of Chicago Press, 1985), pp. 11-30.

8 In a recent sequel entitled "Against Theory 2: Hermeneutics and Deconstruction" (Critical Inquiry 14 [1987]: 49-69), Knapp and Michaels extend their inten- tionalist critique to the hermeneutic theories of Gadamer and Ricoeur, the semiotic conventionalism of Goodman and Elgin, and the deconstructionist textualism of Derrida. However, their basic line of argument does not change: There is just no way "that a text can mean something other than what its author intended" nor can there be "any plausible criteria of textual identity (e.g., in terms of syntax, linguistic conventions, or traditions of identifica- tion) that can function independent of authorial intention" (p. 50), simply because without some determining intention texts could neither mean nor be identified as such. Knapp and Michael's argument thus remains vulnerable to the critique I offer below of confusing the notion of "authorial intention to mean" with that of "intentional meaning" tout court.

I should also note that Knapp and Michaels misrepre- sent Beardsley's anti-intentionalism as holding the view that textual meaning is "permanent and unchanging" (pp. 51, 68). On the contrary, the apparent fact that a text's meaning can change (through the changes in its words' meanings) long after an author is dead and thus unable to change his meaning is one of Beardsley's central arguments to prove that textual meaning is not logically identical to authorial meaning. See The Possibility of Criticism, p. 19.

9 "Against Theory," pp. 19, 24. Indeed, because of their firm premise that language necessarily "has intention already built into it" so that we can never "separate language and intention," Knapp and Michaels see the attempts of intentionalist theorists like Hirsch and Juhl to ground the connection between textual meaning and autho- rial intention as being otiose and misguided. In thus challenging the theoretical efforts of intentionalists and anti-intentionalists alike, their radical position is appropri- ately entitled "Against Theory."

'0 Ibid., p. 19. " Ibid., pp. 15, 16, 17, 12.

12 How elusive and spectral this notion is can be seen in the evasive formulation of its most forthright exponent, E. D. Hirsch. On the one hand, he tries to suggest its pragmatic value as a definite criterion or touchstone which would rule out interpretations inconsistent with what the empirical, historical author could have intended. But, afraid of psychologism and aware that literary (if not all) inten-

409

SHUSTERMAN

tions can be too complex to be mechanically deduced from the known historical and biographical facts alone and are anyway somehow socially informed, Hirsch retreats from locating the requisite authorial intention in an empirical author and instead turns the author into an imaginative construct, "the speaking subject" which "is not ... identical with the subjectivity of the author as an actual historical person." And this authorial-subject abstraction rather than providing a clear factual touchstone for inter- pretation needs to be interpretively constructed itself in terms of the text. See E. D. Hirsch, Validity in Interpreta- tion (Yale University Press, 1967), pp. 242-44.

13 See, for example, E. D. Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation (University of Chicago Press, 1987), pp. 12-13. It is very revealing however that in defending literary study as controlled and constrained by the aim of knowledge, Hirsch feels the need to guarantee its future productivity by expansionist measures of enlarging the scope and canon of literary studies.

"The recent over-emphasis on aesthetic values in literature has had a restrictive and inhibiting effect on literary criticism and literary study. The aesthetic concep- tion of literature has too rigidly limited the canon of literature and has too narrowly confined the scope of literary study, leaving present-day scholars with little to do that is at once 'legitimate' and important. I argue for the legiti- macy of several important parts of inquiry which have recently been excluded from 'literary' study; and I argue for the expansion of the literary canon" (p. 12, my emphasis).

Marxist theorists might note that such expansionism goes with Hirsch's capitalist image of criticism "as a corporate enterprise" and a "professional practice." See E. D. Hirsch, Validity in Interpretation, p. 109; and "On Justifying Interpretive Norms," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43, no. 1 (1984): 91.

14 Beardsley, pp. 31, 34 (Beardsley's emphasis). 15 Ibid., pp. 41-43. 16 Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation, pp. 1, 12; and

"On Justifying Interpretive Norms," 91. 17 Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation, p. 7. 18 J. Margolis, Art and Philosophy (Atlantic High-

lands, N.J., 1980). pp. 11 , 153-54, 163. 19 Ibid., p. 161. 20 Ibid., p. 150. 21 Ibid., p. 159. 22 Ibid., p. 111. 23 For Margolis's comparison of interpretations to

scientific hypotheses see ibid., pp. 157-60. 24 Ibid., p. 111. 25 This problem of the circular interdependence of

description and interpretation is a manifestation of the perhaps more basic circular interdependence of work- identity and interpretation, where accuracy of interpretation is measured against the work's identity, but where the latter can only be determined through the former. I discuss this problem at some length in "Four Problems in Aesthetics," International Philosophical Quarterly 22 (1982): 21-33, and in The Object of Literary Criticism (Amsterdam, 1984), pp. 50-64. This circularity is somewhat related to the hermeneutic circle's problem of understanding, fore- understanding, and interpretation. On this problem see my T7 S. Eliot and the Philosophy of Criticism (Columbia University Press, 1988), pp. 124-33.

26 I take this example from R. Wollheim, Art and its Objects (Harmondsworth, U.K., 1975), p. 107, where it is used to attack the interpretive theory of Morris Weitz. I have elsewhere shown that Weitz's and Margolis's theories share the very same logical structure and are open to the same nondescriptivist critique. See R. Shusterman, "The Logic of Interpretation," Philosophical Quarterly 28 (1978): 310-24.

27 See H. Bloom, Agon: Towards a Theory of Revi- sionism (Oxford University Press, 1982), pp. 16, 17, 24-25, 35-43.

28 H. Bloom, A Map of Misreading (Oxford University Press, 1975), p. 4.

29 J. Derrida, Positions (London, 1980), pp. 27-28, 45. For his famous rejection of any extralinguistic reality, see J. Derrida, Of Grammatology (Johns Hopkins Univer- sity Press, 1976), p. 158.

30 See J. Culler, On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism After Structuralism (Cornell University Press, 1982), p. 176.

31 Ibid., pp. 123, 128; and more generally pp. 121-30. 32 Ibid., pp. 175, 176.

33 See ibid., p. 225. 34 For Wittgenstein's views on meaning and under-

standing, see especially L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Grammar (Oxford, 1974), pp. 68-69; Philosophical Inves- tigations (Oxford, 1958), para. 143-242. For further elab- oration and clarification of Wittgenstein's position, see G. P. Baker and P. M. S. Hacker, Wittgenstein: Meaning and Understanding (Oxford, 1983), pp. 29-45, 321-46. The idea of oral reading as a means to or criterion of correct understanding of poetry is suggested in L. Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief (Oxford, 1970), pp. 4-5, 40.

35 For an example of the Frankfurt school critique of scientific, instrumental reason and its domination of nature and consequent reification and commodification of thought, see M. Horkheimer and T. Adomo, Dialectic of Enlighten- ment (New York, 1986), pp. xi-xii, 4, 9, 26-28, 40-41, 57. A very thorough and intelligible survey of the Frankfurt school can be found in D. Held, Introduction to Critical Theory (University of California Press, 1980).

36 Hirsch, The Aims of Interpretation, pp. 1-3. From this it might be further argued that without any stable and determinate objects there could be no meaningful produc- tive discourse, since the possibility of meaning would ultimately depend on reference to some such objects. This problem will be treated more fully below.

37 A distinction may be made between the correspon- dence theory of truth and that of knowledge, where only the correspondence theory of knowledge is said to require that the correspondent reality "as in itself it really is" be available for comparison and assessment of the knowledge claim. This distinction, however valuable, does not effect the theories we are considering here, which are concerned with claims to interpretive knowledge rather than mere interpretive truth.

38 See D. Davidson, "On the Very Idea of a Concep- tual Scheme," Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford University Press, 1984), pp. 183-98.

39 See R. Rorty, "Texts and Lumps," New Literary History 17 (1985): 3; and J. Margolis, "Relativism, His- tory, and Objectivity in the Human Studies," Journal for

410

Interpretation, Intention, and Truth

the Theory of Social Behavior 14 (1984): 1-23. In light of this very fundamental development in Margolis's philoso- phy there is little doubt that he would provide today a very different account of the logic of interpretation, at least with respect to what he discussed as "description."

40 For Russell's distinctions of knowledge of things versus knowledge of truths, and knowledge by acquaintance versus knowledge by description, see B. Russell, The Problems of Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 1971), and "Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description," in Mysticism and Logic (Harmondsworth, U.K., 1953), pp. 197-218. Criticism of Russell's view that mere sensory experiential acquaintance can count as knowl- edge may be found in D. Pears "Introduction" to his Russell's Logical Atomism (London, 1972). Ryle's discus-

sion of "'knowing how" can be found in G. Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London, 1949), pp. 25-61. The idea that there is more to knowledge, even scientific knowledge, than scientific truth is a theme recently emphasized by philoso- phers as different as Putnam and Lyotard. See H. Putnam, Meaning and the Moral Sciences (London, 1979), pp. 72-73; and Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condi- tion (University of Minnesota Press, 1984), pp. 31-41.

41 T. S. Eliot, The Use of Poetry and the Use of Criticism (London, 1964), p. 151.

42 Rorty, p. 12. 43 For elaboration of this point and more generally of

my pragmatist theory of interpretation, see R. Shusterman, "Croce on Interpretation: Deconstruction and Pragma- tism," forthcoming in New Literary History.

411