The Interface between Anthropology and Classical Archaeology in Greece

33
The Interface between Anthropology and Classical Archaeology in Greece David B. Small Sociology and Anthropology Lehigh University 1

Transcript of The Interface between Anthropology and Classical Archaeology in Greece

The Interface between Anthropology and Classical Archaeology in Greece

David B. Small

Sociology and Anthropology

Lehigh University

1

[email protected]

Abstract

An analysis of the relationship between anthropology and Classical archaeology in Greece shows that Greek archaeologists are split between those who work in prehistory and those who work in laterperiods. The prehistorians have used more anthropological models in their analyses than others. But they have forced the concept of the archaic state onto Mycenaean polities which do not fit the definition of archaic states and show elements of house-dominated estates who changed quickly from contact with the more developed polities of ancient Crete. Archaeologists who work in post-prehistorian periods in ancient Greece have utilized fewer anthropological models and are more closely allied with ancient historians than anthropologists. However, they work in an environment of multiple interacting small polities, offers them an opportunity to use their rich data base to proffer analytical frames for the study of small interacting polities elsewhere. This essay demonstrates how a frame of analysis from Greekarchaeology can be of use in analyzing Classic period Mayan polities.

When I was asked if I would contribute to a volume on the interface between archaeology and cultural anthropology, I was somewhat uneasy. As the single author discussing Classical archaeology, I was afraid that I would have to elaborate on the connection between Classical archaeology and anthropology in general (for examples, see Snodgrass 1985, Dyson 1981, Davis 2007). Such treatments have already been written. Except in a much abbreviated form, I had no interest in adding to this discussion As these scholars and others have already described, there are many impedimentsto classical archaeologists who would wish to employ anthropological concepts. Perhaps chief amongst those is the fact of the walls which exist between classical archaeologists, who are employed in classics or art history departments, and anthropological concepts, which residein departments of anthropology. Although many universities now argue for building strength in interdisciplinary enterprises, classical archaeologists still have to pay their mortgages by actively being

2

members of classics departments, which view philology as one of the prime movers of classical study. If classical archaeologists seek more theoretical concepts, more often than not, they turn to history, rather than to anthropology. Snodgrass (overview in Morris 1994: 39-40) has done much in the last 40 years to integrate Classical archaeology with questions from ancient Greek history. And several Classical archaeologists who work in Greece now look to framing concepts from history to elucidate the evolution of ancient Greece from the end of the Bronze Age (ca. 1100 BCE) to the first appearancesof developed poleis (ca. 700 BCE). But there are problems with this approach, especially in accepting a teleological outcome in social structure which lies in the presence of concepts of egalitarianism (Small in press a). The result of the power of analytical frames fromhistory and the disciplinary divide between Classics and anthropology means that there are few of us, trained in classical archaeology, who are comfortable enough to work in a full anthropological context. I work in a department of anthropology, but I can count on my fingers how many classical archaeologists in the United States are in a similar academic context.

Since the readership of this volume will be primarily anthropological archaeologists, I think the best treatment of the issue of Classical archaeology and cultural anthropology is an overview of the history of the use of anthropological theory (both from cultural anthropology itself and from anthropological archaeology) in Classical archaeology, discussing the way in which Classical archaeologists have employed them. In a twist, for a final observation I will discuss how Classical archaeology can provide a useful anthropological theory for the study of ancient cultures outside its field.

The Use of Theoretical Frames from Cultural Anthropology

Before I can discuss the issue of the application of theoretical frames from anthropology in Classical archaeology, I must supply some basic information, which anthropological archaeologists might not be closely aware of, but which is vital to understanding the different

3

attitudes of Classical archaeologists to anthropology and the way in which they use its theories. First, I need to make clear that I am omitting discussion of Roman archaeology. Roman archaeologists have been active in employing anthropological frames in their own field. While I have published essays on different aspects of Roman archaeology, cultural identity in Roman period seating arrangement in theaters, architecture of Roman period Palestine, for example, my own background is strongest in the study of ancient Greece and Mesoamerica(I have conducted research in Honduras on 7th-10th century Lenca rural compounds for 6 years). So, it is best if I stick to issues in these two ancient cultures.

An important additional point and one that must be understood by a general anthropological readership is the important division betweenprehistory and Classical archaeology in Greece. As a period, prehistory predates the later periods, Iron Age to Hellenistic (ca. 1100 to 175 BCE), and although prehistory should be a label which defines an era without writing, the parameters of prehistory in Greecedo not mesh with this definition. Prehistory, (I am excluding the Neolithic and earlier) for Greece is most often defined as the period of the early, middle, and late Helladic (mainland Greece), Cycladic (the islands between mainland Greece and Crete), and Minoan (Crete) cultures. The time span runs roughly from 3000 to 1100 BCE, when the Iron Age sequences begin. For most scholars the definition of prehistory in Greece has nothing to do with the presence of writing ornot. On Crete, different forms of writing (hieroglyphic, Linear A) existed from as early as 2000 BCE. On the mainland and on Crete Linear B first appears around 1450 BCE. Thus, the appearance of writing has little to do with the appellation prehistory in Greece. What can be discerned however is that it is not the appearance of writing that really defines prehistory in ancient Greece, but the way in which archaeologists use its written evidence. This is an issue which can best be seen, if we first look at the role of the past written record in Classical archaeology in Greece. Up until recently the relationship between archaeology and the Greek written record has been one where archaeology has taken a second seat to the information supplied by written material. The reality of the Greek past was revealed solely through its texts and archaeology played a secondary

4

role of filling out the written record with material pertaining to daily life. This relationship is an artifact of the practice of not analyzing the archaeological record in a manner which would have made it useful to historians. It lacked contextual detail; evidence based on statistical reasoning, and was overly fond of subjective artistic interpretations, which did not allow historians to use it in a manner which would have been productive (Finley 1975, 1987; Humphreys 1978). In general, Classical archaeology has moved beyond this position to one where archaeology now plays a more useful role. But the force of the written record is still very strong and supplies a master narrative which often supplies a frame for archaeological analysis. This master narrative sees evolution after 1100 BCE through a teleological frame which situates different periods as providing evidence of an evolution towards enfranchised citizenship, if not democracy.

Prehistory, on the other hand, does not use the written record inthe same fashion. Linear B, which is the only script which we can read, is not seen as superior to the archaeological record. It is contextualized in the larger archaeological record. For example, the location of Linear B tablets at Pylos is incorporated into a larger analytical frame which looks at their location in the palace in analyzing the role of record keeping in the life of the palace (Palaima and Wright 1985). This different use of the written record in prehistory can probably be attributed to two facts: Linear B was deciphered only recently and does not have the incredible force of theGreek written record, which has always been understood. Linear B is a writing system which was used for record keeping. It does not supply the rich information from Classical Greek writing, which includes philosophy, government records, daily life, laws etc.

With the differences between prehistory and the later periods in Greek archaeology outlined, I will discuss how anthropology is used inframing theories in prehistory and how it is used in the later periods. Turning to prehistory the first major use of anthropological theory was by Colin Renfrew in his seminal work, The Emergence of Civilization: the Radiocarbon Revolution. Not only did Renfrew refute long-standing concepts such as “Lux ex Oriente” that is, Mediterranean

5

civilization owing its growth to contact with the Near East, but he also introduced then current concepts of systems dynamics to work in prehistory. He put the Aegean prehistoric world into five subsystems:subsistence, technology, social, symbolic, and trade and communications. He also introduced the multiplier effect, which stated that evolution towards social complexity was dependent on at least two of these subsystems tied by a feedback loop. The publication of Emergence was in 1972 which meant that Renfrew was introducing Aegean prehistorians to anthropological trends which had begun in the 1960’s with the advent of processual archaeology.

With Renfrew’s charge, the doors to introducing anthropological theory into prehistory were opened. But it was not until the late 1970’s that important changes in Aegean prehistory were realized, whenscholars from the United States and the United Kingdom began to produce analyses of the Aegean past which utilized anthropological theory. There are now numerous examples. One is systems theory. While systems theory might have once been deemed outmoded, new uses ofthis theory have been used in powerful ways in new world archaeology and now in the prehistoric Aegean. One of the major proponents of itsuse is Karl Knappett, who has applied network analysis to the study oftrade and communication in the Aegean (mainland, Crete, Cyclades, Dodocenese, eastern Anatolia). Working with Tim Evans and Ray Rivers,he has presented a number of papers (Knappett and Nikolakopoulou 2005,2011; Knappett, Evans, Rivers 2008; Rivers, Knappett, Evans 2013) which show the applicability of network analysis, and demonstrate thatnetwork analysis can answer some important questions which pertain to the nature of communication after the massive eruption of Thera, an important island in Aegean trade and communication.

Redistribution has always been a major analytical frame in Aegeanprehistory. Prodded by early comparison of the economy outlined in the Linear B tablets from Pylos, Knossos, and Mycenae, with those understood from Near Eastern polities (for example, Finley 1954) Aegean prehistorians were constructing models of Mycenaean economies which matched their idealized visions of redistribution in Mesopotamia. Recent work however has modified this assessment quite abit (Galaty Nakassis, Parkinson 2011) to the point where our

6

understanding of the “redistributive” nature of the Mycenaean period polities is much more nuanced and takes into consideration areas of limited redistributed economies.

Prehistorians’ use of Anthropological Theory Evolution

Several anthropological theories have been employed in the analysis of the evolution of Aegean communities. Quite a few scholarshave used neoevolutionary concepts. In a close look at the Early Helladic period Pullen (2011) has used the neoevolutionary scheme of chiefdoms evolving into states, which I suspect is born more by the tendency to frame the Mycenaean polities as states, rather than evidence of chiefdoms in the earlier Helladic periods. On the other hand Haggis (1999) eschews this neoevolutionary concept and argues forcompeting clans giving rise to the Minoan states. In a larger frame Parkinson and Galaty (2007) have incorporated concepts such as dual processualism, dynamic models, and world systems theory to explain thenature and the dynamics of polities on Crete and the mainland. In a sensitive treatment of the rise of the Mycenaean polities, Wright (2010) has incorporated concepts such transegalitarian societies, seeing those who established the Mycenaean polities as earlier aggrandizers forming positions of power through constructing connections to other elites. Although he does not refer to it specifically, his approach parallels work in complexity theory and resilience theory. More recently Weiberg and Finne (Weiberg 2012; Weiberg and Finne 2013) have actually studied changes in the Early Helladic on the mainland through a frame which uses the concept of resilience. Aspects of a complexity theory, coupled with heterarchy have also been utilized in framing the Prepalatial period on Crete (Schoep and Knappett 2004).

To a large extent archaeologists who have been working in the prehistory of ancient Greece have been actively using anthropological framing concepts. On the other hand, they have also been reluctant tolook at their own data as something which does not fit these borrowed concepts. Eschewing Renfrew’s early reluctance to label the Mycenaeanpolities as states, current scholars use a rather indefinite

7

definition of the archaic state, but cling to the concept that a statehas an organized and integrated control of the territory around it. As I have argued (Small 1998, 2007) the political and economic structure of the Mycenaean polities does not fit well into an archaic state frame. It only partially controlled the economic sphere around it, and only partially controlled it politically as well. This feature is alluded to in Parkinson and Galaty’s review of secondary state formation in the Aegean (2007), where a strong stimulus for the development of hierarchy in the Mycenaean centers came from connections to Minoan polities. They second my original analysis of the development Mycenaean polities and their characteristics as directly due to the fact that they were pulled into a larger network (Small 2007: 53). I would currently label this an example of an estate-dominated polity which has not been able to pull its surrounding territory into a larger political and economic whole.

The problem with using a state frame of analysis for the Mycenaean polities is that it easily leads to further incorrect assumptions on the nature of their political and economic makeup. As I have noted (2007), one of the most egregious examples of such an assumption is the creation of two provinces, with all their attendant characteristics of economic and political oversight, for the Pylos polity, based only on a list of place names on a Linear B tablet. Allwe actually know from this list is that it was divided into two designations: near and far (for the reconstruction of provinces see Bennet 1995, 1999; Davis and Bennet 1999; Kilian 1998; Shelmerdine 1973, 1981; Wright 1995). Rather than cover over the unique characteristics of the Mycenaean polities with an archaic state frame,prehistorians in the Aegean could be developing a model of polities rising from different houses gaining prominence in their home regions by networking with more developed polities elsewhere. The most obvious use for such a frame would be in the case of the Mayan polities, such as those in southeastern Belize, who evolved because ofcontact with larger Mayan polities to their west (Braswell et al. 2004).

When we move to the later periods in Greek archaeology, the situation becomes quite different. There are few scholars who study

8

these time periods who apply anthropological models to Greece. Those who do are often concerned with archaic state formation, small polity interaction, or death studies. When it comes to the formation of the archaic Greek state or polis, van der Vliet (2000, 2002, 2005, 2011) has used neoevolutionary frames, focusing on some of the particular features of the Greek archaic state or polis. I have concentrated on issues of social change on a community level (2009, 2011), applying some concepts from dual processual theory and concepts of social structure such as those of Giddens (1986). I have also applied complexity theory to the development of the Cretan polis (in press b).Malkin (2011) has applied network theory in an extremely productive way to look at the spread of Greek polities throughout the Mediterranean. Morris, whose interests span mortuary studies and social evolution has incorporated frames such as redistribution, gift exchange and the Saxe Goldman hypothesis in his mortuary analysis (1990, 1992). His work with social change has stuck much closer to frames taken from the study of history (2004). Whitley (1991, 2003) has basically applied some neoevolutionary concepts such as ranked societies to Greek social evolution from the 9th century BCE., as well as having applied some concepts of agency to the study of ancient Greek art (2002).

The overarching picture one gains from looking at the history of Greek Classical archaeology using anthropological models is that prehistorians are more in debt to anthropological thinking than post prehistorian classical archaeologists. Yet prehistorians are reluctant to use some of the particular examples of social complexity in application to the larger archaeological world. Archaeologists of later periods on the other hand have been far more limited than their prehistorian colleagues and lag behind them in their use of anthropology.

To date archaeologists working in ancient Greece have confined themselves to borrowing anthropological theory. As I noted, this is aproblem when it comes to understanding the unique features of the Mycenaean centers, but it also sells archaeology in Greece short. In what follows I want to show how the archaeology of ancient Greece can actually contribute to developing anthropological theory. My point is

9

that archaeology of the periods after prehistory, because it is essentially the archaeology of small polities, provides an over-lookedbut extremely important opportunity to study the general operational features of small polities and to apply some of those observations to the larger archaeological world.

The Small “States” World Context

In the archaeological past there have been numerous examples of small polities which have been variously termed “states” (see papers in Nichols and Charlton 1997). In the new world the basin of Mexico was periodically occupied by small states from 1700-1500 CE. Small Mayan polities were common further to the south in Central America from 300 BCE – 1100 CE. The Moche small states spanned the Peruvian coast from 500 BCE – 600 CE. There were various and periodic pre-Incan polities in the Andes from 500 BCE – 1400 CE . Europe was populated by small polities in Greece from 1100 BCE – 300 CE, and the small polities of Etruscan Italy flourished from 800-300 BCE. Perhapsthe earliest examples of small polities we have come Mesopotamia in the in the period 2600-1500 BCE. Harrapan small polities lay with thefertile Indus valley in the centuries from 500 BCE – 500 CE. Preimperial China lay fragmented with small polities from 2000 – 200 BCE. And finally Egypt was a land of small polities from hundreds of years before its unification ca. 3000 BCE.

Characteristics of Greek Small Polities

In my view one of the most valuable assets of Classical archaeology is that it examines a relatively well-understood example of an ancient culture which was not politically unified but composed of a variety of extremely active city-states (poleis) and looser polity configurations (ethne). The best way in which to analyze this community of small polities is through network theory (for some basic concepts see: Nohria 1994; Czarniawska and Hernes 2005), which takes into consideration the totalizing effect of the networked connections between entities. Questions often focus on issues of self-organization and the emergence of new configurations between units in change over time. Malkin (2003, 2011) has effectively used network theory in his work with colonization, and I (forthcoming) have

10

recently employed network concepts in my application of complexity theory to community evolution in Iron Age Greece (for networks in complexity theory see: Bentley and Maschner 2007; Kohler 2011). A critical feature of these small polities and their relationship to their network was that their control of this network was limited militarily and more importantly, economically, which had a profound effect on their evolution. Ancient Greek polities, whether they were poleis or ethne evolved as communities of similar institutional contexts within a pre-existing network of interaction which began as early as the trading network of the Euboeans in the early 8th century and continued up until the end of the period of Greek migration in the5th century.

They evolved and existed in an interconnected network of many dimensions. I have previously argued that one elite economic connection centered on staple goods (Small 1997), that is the control of the flow of wheat between parts of the Greek world. But that was not all, and I would quickly add that there were political, military, and religious connections between almost all of the polities. The powerful agents in these networks, it would seem, would have been elite men, who were connected to one another through the institution of xenia or guest friendship. This was an institution which was celebrated in “neutral” interpolital meeting contexts, such as a sanctuary. But just as importantly, it was also a theme for male gatherings in the home in the andron, with its focus on male identity and obligations. Examples of such connections are extremely numerous. We have evidence that elites from different polities were connecting with one another through the sanctuary of Delphi, even to the point where some apoikia were founded by families from different poleis. Noted examples would be the foundation of Pithekoussai, by families from Eretria and Khalkis shortly after 800 BCE, and Astakos by families from Megara and Athens near 720 BCE. We have other examples of Greek elites from different polities connecting as membersof koine through centers such as the Panionion in west Anatolia (Forrest 2000). Religious connections were extremely frequent as well. Greek elites were frequently visiting and holding positions of responsibility at various sanctuaries throughout the Greek world, withprimacy of place going to those, like Olympia, who also held athletic

11

contests. These sanctuaries often connected polities who were quite distant from one another, witnessed by the dedications of the Massalians at Olympia, and the creation or perpetuation of a common cult to Ephesian Artemis at Phokaia in Asia Minor and Emporion in the western Mediterranean.

Yet these connections had a distinctly deleterious effect on the polities themselves. The ability of elites to control an important economic sphere beyond the polis inhibited the internal evolution of arobust political economy with the polis. As Earle recently phrased it, political economies take on various forms, but “…a political economy…takes no special form, except the ability to mobilize and direct resources in support and extension of ruling institutions” (Earle 2011: 241). In most cases, except for Athens’ brief imperial episodes, and the extremely unusual Spartan conquest of Messenia, the Greek polis was not mobilizing or directing resources in support and extension of ruling institutions. Armies were structured so that equipping was the responsibility of the individual, and navies, even in Athens were supported to a great extent by private funds. The onlytime a military institution was used for social control was in the cases of tyrannies, which, by their very definition were outside the accepted customs of the polis. A great percentage of what we would consider public expenditure was under the aegis of private financing. Choragic liturgies paid for dramatic presentations, gymnastic liturgies for the development and running of the gymnasium, hestiac for public banquets, architheoric for sacred embassies, and arrephoricfor community processions. In essence, because the territorially limited polis could not control large scale trade, it was not able to pay for institutions which would have tied in directly to rulership. A case in point is when Athens gained its empire; it began to use extra territorial taxation to finance its navy and other institutions.But the empire was new and very much an institution with which Athens had little experience. This can be seen the barely nascent understanding of the assembly as to the potentials of such a larger political organization. It retained its myopic view of what taxation could do to create a rulership directed integration and leveled a tax on shipping in the empire. But the tax was not born from

12

considerations of growing any ruling institutions, because it was placed on Athenians as well as other peoples in the empire!

The condition of the Greek polis, limited in its ability to manipulate an economic base for its own institutional growth has even led Moshe Berent, (2000) quite rightly to label the ancient polis as “stateless”. Although I try to avoid the use of many labels in view past cultures, his charge that the ancient polis does not fit state types well is very instructive of the issues embedded in the use of labels which do more to mask unique cultural features as they attempt to fit a past society into their conceptual framework. Unfortunately debate over this issue has been limited to assembling trait lists which would identify ancient poleis as archaic states (Hansen 2002; van der Vliet 2005). Such debate does little to inform us further onthe nature of the internal structure of the community and its dynamics. The economics of the polis were such that it falls outsideour common state definitions. In a parallel study several years ago (Small 1995) I pointed out the marked difference between islands in the Pacific which did not have important economic control beyond theirshores and those that did. One example was the Trobriand Islands involved in the famous Kula ring, an institution within which men would travel from island to island creating important social and economic connections. The communities on the islands themselves however could not control this network and suffered, not only from an inability to employ the economic vigor of this network to build any ruling institutions, but were often subject to the maneuvering of these traders as they sought to gain social capital from their networkconnections. In direct contrast to the Kula situation, the Yapese were able to spread out and control the networking between islands, which supplied them with the basis for developing ruling institutions.

In addition to the effect of an extra-territorial economy on the polis, political connections between families in different polities could and often did lead to different factions within one polity uniting with those in another to foster internal division and often civil war within the polis. A clear case is the example of Thebes in 395 BCE, when different elite families in the city were allying

13

themselves with either Athenian families or Spartan. Some Theban elites were even harboring political exiles from Athens.

Summary of the ancient Greek Context

For the small polity in Greece between the collapse of the BronzeAge palaces and the advent of Macedonian power, we can point to a number of salient characteristics. The polities themselves grew up in a pre-existing intercommunity network. Except for brief instances,such as the Athenian empire, they were seldom able to reach out economically, politically, or militarily to control activity in this network. The results were detrimental to the strength of the polis, in that it had a very underdeveloped political economy, which did not fully allow it to create internal ruling hierarchies which were stable, and that it was subject to the play of factions within the network which would engender civil strife. Therefore we should able to use the Greek example, because its rich data base allows a somewhatfine-grained analysis, to suggest some concepts inherent in clusters of small polities which would be applicable to evolution in similar, but less well-understood ancient cultures.

The Classic Maya

I am going to compare the post prehistory Classical Greeks with the Classic and Preclassic Maya. I am not the first person who has suggested that there might be some benefit in cross-cultural analysis involving the Maya and ancient Greeks. Tartaron, a prehistorian (2008; but see also Parkinson and Galaty 2007) suggested that there were important parallels in the cultures of the Classic Maya and thoseof the Late Bronze Age on the Greek mainland, which would facilitate useful comparative analysis. I am pleased that Tartaron is making such an argument, but I think that a better parallel is between the Classical period poleis and the Classic period Maya. His points of similarity, history of research, hierarchical organization, dominant political class, use of writing, active economies with exchange of prestige goods, and elite using rituals, feasting, and warfare as means to power, could be points of similarity between many cultures. We also do not know that much about the range of actors within the Late Bronze Age polities to make a useful comparison to the Classic

14

Maya. I think it would be a more useful comparison, if a linking characteristic between the Maya and the Late Bronze Age polities were the concept of a dualistic economy (Scarborough and Valdez 2009), which has been elaborated for the Classic Maya, and carefully delineated for the Bronze Age (Halstead 1993, 2011; Shelmerdine 2011) . On the other hand, the Classic and Preclassic period Maya share many of the same organizational features with the Classical period Greeks. Maya polities were territorially small. They evolved in an active inter-polity economic and political network. The Preclassic and Classic period Maya (good overview Demarest 2004) had aregional system very similar to the Greeks and provide an excellent opportunity for insights gained from the study of this system to be applied to the Maya.

To what degree does the cultural situation of the Maya compare with that of the Classical Greeks -- to a great extent, and in important ways. Like the Classical Greeks, the Classic period Maya evolved out of an active inter polity network (Reese-Taylor and Walker2002). There is mounting evidence that the Late Preclassic witnessed the disintegration of large regional polities, like El Mirador, and their transformation into a landscape of smaller polities, with smaller controlling territories. One of the reasons for this change was increasing instability which arose from competition over long-distance trade routes, after El Mirador’s collapse. This competition was between elites who were trading in commodities such as jade, shell, obsidian, and pyrite. Kinship was most likely fluid at the moment and negotiated between elite lineages. Tokens of these connections were most likely high-value pottery such as Ixcanrio Orange Polychrome (Reese-Taylor and Walker 2002: figure 4.9), which isfound principally in burials and caches, and was probably associated with the moon goddess, Ix Chel. Such pottery was most likely exchanged between elites from different polities as various elites would gather at different polities for feasting events. In looking atthe presence of this pottery in a frame of social dynamics, it was probably used by powerful lineages and nascent dynasties who were constructing powerful relationships with ceramic production and

15

exchange. Reese-Taylor and Walker (2002) also contend that a later pottery, Dos Arroyos Polychrome, was associated with the rise of ruling elites in Tikal, who were developing alliances between elites from various polities as they were cementing their power at Tikal.

As Mayan polities moved into the Classic periods, especially toward the Late Classic, evidence for this exchange becomes even more pronounced with the appearance of high-quality Late Classic pictorial polychrome. Decorated often with depictions of rulers, affairs of feasting, or just well-designed art, these pots were presented to visitors at feasts, as tokens of political and economic ties between lineages from different polities. They were taken back to home polities by invited elites and must have held a high importance in theprofiles of different lineages, because there are several identified non-native elite pots in foreign contexts (Coggins 1975; Reents-Budet et al. 1994: 164-233; Reents-Budet et al. 2000; see also Halperin and Foias 2010).

So, Maya polities of the Classic period must have been nodes on alarger interactive network such as seen for the Greeks. Important connections were between elites from various polities. The connections were created by participation in feasting connects, and the pots themselves were powerful tokens of those connections. These connections were not limited to the ruling elites, but were part of the generalized elite network all together. Mayan polities were assembled of multiple elite lineages and not all could be rulers, but many were negotiating for increased power, possibly even rulership andthese interpolital connections must have played an important part. In this regard we should see identified subelite compounds such as LasSepulturas at Copan (Webster et al. 1989; Sheely 1991) as staging venues for interpolital feasting which could create competition with the ruling elite for local power.

This ruler/subelite relationship of partial independence is documented well in Guatemala. A dramatic example of compounds with semi-autonomous elite residences comes from the Lower Montagua Valley in Guatemala (Schortman and Ashmore 2012). In this valley several settlements were apparently occupied by different elite families each

16

of whom had an apparently different interpolital network within which it would operate. Factional distinctions can be seen at centers such as Las Quebradas, where different elite compounds had distinctly different symbols of authority. That the elites in these compounds were cooperating in larger factions through intercommunity network is signaled by the fact that people within this valley system apparently did not succumb to allying either with Copan or Quirigua after the apparent political instability launched by the beheading of Copan’s ruler Waxaklahun-Ub’ ah-K’awil, by the ruler, K’ ak’ Tiliw’ in 738 CE,after the Copan ruler raided Quirgua. This manner of networking created a great danger of internal instability within the Mayan polity. As Cioffi-Revilla and Landman(1999) have demonstrated, most of the Mayan polities were highly unstable, and it was only a few of the older polities, such as Tikal or Copan who had perhaps cemented internal hierarchy early on, who were able to enjoy any measure of internal stability. Polities without such a historical pedigree, suchas Bonampack or Uxmal were not able to withstand the force of networking outside the polity.

As successfully argued by multiple Mayan scholars, (Rice 2008; Stuart 2005), the basis of Mayan royal rule does not lie upon an accepted concept of political economy, where a ruler would use his economic power, be it the ownership of large tracts of land or slaves,to establish power in other contexts within a Mayan polity. Rather the power of the lord or ajau, lay in his role in the larger religiouscontext of the polity. In an important way he created power over others when he blood let, incensed/burnt, and danced. In each action he was creating divinity and creating connections to powerful deities who would ensure the good fortune or his kingdom, whether it was in agricultural abundance or in military victory. These observations have led some scholars such as Demarest (1984, 1992, 1997, 2004: 215-217) to underline the unstable internal structure of the Mayan polities and to use models, such as galactic polities, coined by Tambiah (1976) to describe polities in Southeast Asia with rulership based primarily on ideology and a great degree internal instability.

17

Benefits from Employing the Greek Model

The material evidence for ancient Greece is much richer than for the Maya, which prods us to ask if the richer observations gained fromour study of the ancient Greeks can aid us in work with the Maya. Theanswer is an obvious yes, in that it helps us place issues stemming from the Maya into richer analytical frames. One of the most salient features of our analysis of the small Greek polities was the internally underdeveloped political economy, which did not provide a good base for the development of rulership oversight of the economy and even impeded conquest states like Athens from effectively integrating its empire. There are three ways in which we might make use of this observation. The first is examining possible cases of increased bureaucratic oversight of within a single polity. Chase andChase (2003, 2006, 2009) have repeatedly made the argument that Caracol internally evolved a large bureaucracy in the Late Classic. They point to the archaeological record which contains evidence for architectural connections of market areas within the urban zone of thepolity. Chase and Chase would see these features as indicating that some sort of bureaucracy was controlling the distribution of goods in the polity. The application of observations gained from the study of the control of economics in ancient Greek polities can be of some assistance here. With knowledge that small polities could not often control economies outside their own territory, the exact importance ofthe connection of these internal market squares can be looked at with greater acuity than without. It is telling that they have problems with the over-used applications of ideal type (house societies, lineage-based societies etc.) models. These models do not give them much to work with in understanding internal economic oversight, and I would argue that some actual cross-cultural analysis between Caracol and polities in Classic Greece would prove to be to of greater utility.

My second point relates to the ability of small polities to integrate conquered lands under some sort of economic control, after periods of conquest. The last twenty years of research into the ancient Maya has seen an increasing awareness of political alliances and sometimes out right conquest of different polities by conquest

18

polities in the later part of the Classic period. At least by the Late Classic there was noticed inequality between many Mayan polities,with several polities in relationships of overlordship and subservience (first noted by Marcus 1976). Hieroglyphic references towar from this period tell us that there were at least four types of aggression and conquest between different polities (Chase and Chase 1998). There was the ch’ ak or axe-event, where a losing ruler was decapitated. There was hubi or destruction, probably referring to that of a community. Maya also described a chuc’ ak or capture of an individual, and a “star war”, which apparently referred to the major conquest and destruction of another polity.

The Maya historical landscape is populated with several differentinstances of recorded overlord/subservient relations. Yaxchilan over Machaquila in 664 and 729 CE; Piedras Negras over Pomona in 793 CE; Caracol over Ucanal in 800 CE; Caracol over Naranjo in 631 CE; and Caracol over Tikal in 562 CE. In general it seems that the unequal relationship between these polities was mainly along a political plane. The relationships between these polities were extremely unstable and in a state of constant change.

The use of observations gained from our work with the Greek couldbe of special interest in these cases. Did the fact that the Maya polities not have control over extra polity trade with its consequent underdeveloped political economy, create a situation whereby conquest did not lead to economic incorporation? The changing nature of these relationships would certainly suggest so. Important research could bedirected to isolating evidence for a rulership control of production and distribution within these warring states, to see whether or not the lack of incorporation could be blamed upon an underdeveloped political economy, such as we saw with Athens and its empire.

The issue of economics and political economies suggests one more fruitful research focus. What gave the Postclassic Maya, in polities such as Chichen Itza and Mayapan the apparent ability to incorporate territory economically? Comparisons to the Greek examples, which havea better understanding of small polity political economies, could put the issue into fruitful focus. What was the major internal difference

19

between these Postclassic communities and their Classic period predecessors when it came to the form of their political economies? Did the Postclassic Maya begin from an underdeveloped political economy, much like their earlier counterparts, and if so, when and through what agency did it change?

Final Thoughts

Classical Greek archaeology is finally coming of age. Its rich material database has allowed me, and hopefully others after me, to use concepts generated by its study to other world archaeological cultures. I have applied observations on the structure and dynamics of small polities, gained from my work with Classical Greece, to frameimportant questions for another archaeological culture composed of small polities, the ancient Maya. But there is so much more that we can begin doing. The Greek material offers excellent opportunities to focus on other characteristics in cross-cultural investigations. To take just one case, I see questions of the structure, position, and power of assemblies in small polities as critical to our understandingof past human societies. These communities who work through assemblies are not well understood. From the other side of Renfrew’s bridge, Richard Blanton (1998, Blanton and Fargher2008) has begun thistype of work, but it lacks the observations and framing which close work in Classical archaeology can supply. It is time for us to enrichthe study. Let’s move from a stage of “becoming of age” to one of robust adulthood.

20

References

Bennet, J. 1995. “Space through Time:  Diachronic Perspectives on the Spatial Organization of the Pylian State.” In POLITEIA:  Society and State in the Aegean Bronze Age, edited by W.-D. Niemeier and R. Laffineur, 587–602.Aegaeum 13. Liège/Austin: Universite de Liège/University of Texas at Austin Program in Aegean Scripts and Prehistory.

Bennet, J. 1999. “The Mycenaean Conceptualization of Space or Pylian Geography...yet Again.” In Floreant Studia Mycenaea. Akten Des X. Internationalen Mykenologischen Colloquiums in Salzburg Vom 1.-5. Mai 1995, edited by S. Deger-Jalkotzy, S. Hiller, O. Panagl, and G. Nightengale, 1:131–157. Vienna:Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften.

Bentley, R., and H. Maschner. 2007. “Complexity Theory.” In Handbook of Archaeological Theories, edited by R. Bently, H. Maschner, and C. Chippendale, 245–270. Lanham, Maryland: AltaMira Press.

Berent, M. 2000. “Anthropology and the Classics: War, Violence, and the Stateless Polis.” CQ 50 (1): 257–289. doi:10.2307/1558951.

_______. 2006. “The Stateless Polis:  a Reply to Critics.” Social Evolutionand History 5 (1): 141–163.

Blanton, R. 1998. “Beyond Centralization:  Steps Toward a Theory of Egalitarian Behavior in Archaic States.” In Archaic States, edited by G. Feinman and J. Marcus, 135–172. Santa Fe, New Mexico: School of American Research Press.

_______, and L. Fargher. 2008. Collective Action in the Formation of Pre-modern States. New York: Springer. http://public.eblib.com/EBLPublic/PublicView.do?ptiID=337707.

21

Braswell, Geoffrey E., Christian M. Prager, Cassandra R. Bill, Sonja A. Schwake, and Jennifer B. Braswell. 2004. “The Rise of Secondary States in the Southeastern Periphery of the Maya World: A Report on Recent Archaeological and Epigraphic Research at Pusilha, Belize.” Ancient Mesoamerica 15 (02): 219–233. doi:10.1017/S0956536104040143.

.

Chase, A., and D. Chase. 1996. “More Than Kin and King: Centralized Political Organization Among the Late Classic Maya.” CurrAnthr 37: 803–810.

_______. 1998. “Late Classic Maya Political Structure, Polity Size, and Warfare Arenas.” In Anatomia de Una Civilzacion Aproximaciones Interdisciplinarias a La Cultura Maya, edited by Andres Ciudad Ruiz, Yolanda Fernandez Marquinez, Jose Miguel Garcia Campillo, M. Josefa Iglesias Ponce de Leon, Alfonso Lacadena Garcia-Gallo, and Luis T. Sanz Castro,11–29. Madrid: Sociedad Espanola de Estudios Mayas.

_______. 2004. “Archaeological Perspectives on Classic Maya Social Organization from Caracol, Belize.” Ancient Mesoamerica 15: 139–147. doi:10.1017/S0956536104151080.

Chase, Arlen F., Diane Z. Chase, and Michael E. Smith. 2009. “STATES AND EMPIRES IN ANCIENT MESOAMERICA.” Ancient Mesoamerica 20 (02): 175–182.doi:10.1017/S0956536109990095.

Cioffi-Revilla, C., and T. Landman. 1999. “Evolution of Maya Polities in the Ancient Mesoamerican System.” International Studies Quarterly 43: 559–598. doi:10.1111/0020-8833.00137.

Czarniawska, B., and T. Hernes. 2005. Actor-Network Theory and Organizing. Copenhagen Business School Press.

Davis, Jack L. 2007. “Classical Archaeology and Anthropological Archaeology in North America: A Meeting of Minds at the Millennium?” In Archaeology at the Millennium, edited by Gary M. Feinman and T. Douglas

22

Price, 415–437. Springer US. http://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-0-387-72611-3_12.

Davis, J., and J. Bennet. 1999. “Making Mycenaeans: Warfare, Territorial Expansion, and Representations of the Other in the Pylian Kingdom.” In POLEMOS. Le Contexte Guerrier En Egée à L’âge Du Bronze. Aegaeum 19. Liège: Universite de Liège/University of Texas at Austin Program in Aegean Scripts and Prehistory.

Demarest, A. 1984. “Conclusiones y Especulaciones Acerca de El Mirador.” Mesoamerica 7: 138–150.

_______. 1992. “Ideology in Ancient Maya Cultural Evolution:  The Dynamics of Galactic Polities.” In Ideology and Pre-Columbian Civilizations, edited by A. Demarest and G. Conrad, 135–157. Santa Fe, New Mexico: School of American Research Press.

_______. 1997. “The Vanderbilt Petexbatun Regional Archaeological Project, 1989-1994:  Overview, History, and Major Results of a Multidisciplinary Study of the Classic Maya Collapse.” Ancient Mesoamerica8: 209–227.

Demarest, A. 2004. Ancient Maya: The Rise and Fall of a Rainforest Civilization. Cambridge University Press.

Dyson, S. 1981. “A Classical Archaeologist’s Response to the ‘New Archaeology’.” BASOR 242: 7–13. doi:10.2307/1356543.

Earle, T. 2011. “Redistribution in Aegean Palatial Societies. Redistribution and the Political Economy: The Evolution of an Idea.” AJA 115: 237–244. doi:10.3764/aja.115.2.0237.

Finley, Moses I. 1954. The World of Odysseus. New York Review Of Books.

Finley, Moses I. 1975. The Use and Abuse of History. Chatto and Windus.

Finley, Moses I. 1987. Ancient History: Evidence and Models. Penguin Books.

23

Forrest, W.G. 2000. “The Pre-polis Polis.” In Alternatives to Athens:  Varieties of Political Organization and Community in Ancient Greece, edited by R. Brock and S.Hodkinson, 280–292. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Freidel, D., and L. Schele. 1988. “Kingship in the Late Preclassic Maya Lowlands: The Instruments and Places of Ritual Power.” American Anthropologist 90 : 547–567. doi:10.1525/aa.1988.90.3.02a00020.

GALATY, MICHAEL L., DIMITRI NAKASSIS, and WILLIAM A. PARKINSON. 2011. “Redistribution in Aegean Palatial Societies. Introduction: Why Redistribution?” American Journal of Archaeology 115 (2) (April 1): 175–176. doi:10.3764/aja.115.2.0175.

Giddens, Anthony. 1986. The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration. University of California Press.

Halperin, C., and A. Foias. 2010. “Pottery Politics: Late Classic MayaPalace Production at Motul de San José, Petén, Guatemala.” JAnthArch 29 (3): 392–411. doi:10.1016/j.jaa.2010.06.001.

Halstead, P. 1993. “The Mycenaean Palatial Economy: Making the Most ofthe Gaps in the Evidence.” The Cambridge Classical Journal 38: 57–86. doi:10.1017/S0068673500001620.

_______. 2011. “Redistribution in Aegean Palatial Societies. Redistribution in Aegean Palatial Societies: Terminology, Scale, and Significance.” AJA 115 (2): 229–235. doi:10.3764/aja.115.2.0229.

Hansen, M. 2002. “Was the Polis a State or a Stateless Society?” In Even More Studies in the Ancient Greek Polis, edited by T. Nielsen, 17–47. Stuttgart: Steiner Verlag.

Hansen, M. 2004. An Inventory of Archaic and Classical Poleis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

_______. 2006. Polis: An Introduction to the Ancient Greek City-State. Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.

Houston, S., and Stuart D. 1996. “Of Gods, Glyphs and Kings: Divinity and Rulership Among the Classic Maya.” Antiquity 70 (268): 289–312.

24

Kardulias, P. 1999. World Systems Theory in Practice: Leadership, Production, and Exchange. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.

Kohler, T. 2011. “Complex Systems and Archaeology.” In Santa Fe Institute Working Paper. Santa Fe, New Mexico: Santa Fe Institute.

Haggis, D. 1999. “Staple Finance, Peak Sanctuaries, and Economic Complexity in Late Prepalatial Crete.” In From Minoan Farmers to Roman Traders: Sidelights on the Economy of Ancient Crete, edited by A. Chaniotis, 53–85.Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.

Humphreys, S. 1978. Anthropology and the Greeks. London: Routledge and K. Paul.

Kilian, Klaus. 1988. “The Emergence of Wanax Ideology in the MycenaeanPalaces.” Oxford Journal of Archaeology 7 (3) (November 1): 291–302. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0092.1988.tb00182.x.

Knappett, C., Evans, T. & R. Rivers, 2008. Modelling maritime interaction in the Aegean Bronze Age, Antiquity 82: 1009-24.

Knappett, C. & I. Nikolakopoulou, 2005. Exchange and affiliation networks in the MBA southern Aegean: Crete, Akrotiri and Miletus, in R. Laffineur & E. Greco (eds.), Emporia: Aegeans in East and West Mediterranean: 175-84. Université de Liège, University of Texas at Austin: Aegaeum 25.

Knappett, Carl, and I. Nikolakopoulou. 2011. “Inside Out? Materiality and Connectivity in the Aegean Archipelago.” In Cambridge Handbook of the Mediterranean World in the Bronze-Iron Ages, edited by A.B. Knapp and P. van Dommelen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://www.academia.edu/353429/Inside_Out_Materiality_and_Connectivity_in_the_Aegean_Archipelago.

Malkin, Irad. 2011. A Small Greek World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

_____ 2003. “Networks and the Emergence of Greek Identity.” Mediterranean Historical Review 18 (2): 56–74. doi:10.1080/0951896032000230480.

25

Marcus, J. 1976. Emblem and State in the Classic Maya Lowlands: An Epigraphic Approach to Territorial Organization. Washington DC: Dumbarton Oaks.

Martin, S, and N. Grube. 2008. Chronicle of the Maya Kings and Queens: Decipheringthe Dynasties of the Ancient Maya. London: Thames & Hudson.

Morris, Ian. 1990. Burial and Ancient Society: The Rise of the Greek City-State. Cambridge University Press.

_______. 1992. Death-Ritual and Social Structure in Classical Antiquity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

_______. 2004. “Economic Growth in Ancient Greece.” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 160 (4): 709–742.

Nakassis, D., Parkinson, W., and M. Galaty. 2011. “Redistribution in Aegean Palatial Societies. Redistributive Economies from a Theoreticaland Cross-Cultural Perspective.” AJA 115 (2): 177–184. doi:10.3764/aja.115.2.0177.

Nevett, L. 2007. “Greek Houses as a Source of Evidence for Social Relations.” BSAStudies 15: 5–10.

Nichols, D., and T. Charlton, ed. 1997. The Archaeology of City-States:  Cross Cultural Approaches. Washington, DC: Sheffield Academic Press.

Nohria, N. 1994. Networks and Organizations: Structure, Form and Action. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.

Palaima, Thomas G., and James C. Wright. 1985. “Ins and Outs of the Archives Rooms at Pylos: Form and Function in a Mycenaean Palace.” American Journal of Archaeology 89 (2) (April 1): 251–262. doi:10.2307/504328.

Parkinson, W., and M. Galaty. 2007. “Secondary States in Perspective: An Integrated Approach to State Formation in the Prehistoric Aegean.” American Anthropologist 109 (1): 113–129. doi:10.1525/aa.2007.109.1.113.

26

Pullen, D. 2011. “Redistribution in Aegean Palatial Societies. Before the Palaces:” AJA 115 (2): 185–195. doi:10.3764/aja.115.2.0185.

Reents-Budet, D. 1994. Painting the Maya Universe: Royal Ceramics of the Classic Period. Second Edition. Durham: Duke University Press.

_______. 1998. “Elite Maya Pottery and Artisans as Social Indicators.”Archeological Papers of the American Anthropological Association 8 (1): 71–89. doi:10.1525/ap3a.1998.8.1.71.

_____., Bishop, R., Taschek, J., and J. Ball. 2000. “Out of the PalaceDumps.” Ancient Mesoamerica 11 (01): 99–121.

Reese-Taylor, K., and D. Walker. 2002. “The Passage of the Late Preclassic into the Early Classic.” In Ancient Maya Political Economies, edited by M. Masson and D. Freidel, 87–122. Oxford: AltaMira Press.

Renfrew, C. 1980. “The Great Tradition Versus the Great Divide: Archaeology as Anthropology?” AJA 84 (3): 287–298. doi:10.2307/504703.

_______., and J. Cherry. 2009. Peer Polity Interaction and Socio-political Change. 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Rice, Prudence M. 2008. “Time, Power, and the Maya.” Latin American Antiquity 19 (3) (September 1): 275–298. doi:10.2307/25478231.

Rivers, R., C. Knappett, and T. Evans. 2013. “Network Models and Archaeological Spaces.” Academia. Accessed September 19. http://www.academia.edu/570078/Network_models_and_archaeological_spaces.

Scarborough, V., and F. Valdez. 2009. “An Alternative Order: The Dualistic Economies of the Ancient Maya.” Latin American Antiquity 20 (1): 207–227. doi:10.2307/40650083.

Shelmerdine, C. 2011. “The Individual and the State in Mycenaean Greece.” BICS 54 (1): 19–28. doi:10.1111/j.2041-5370.2011.00014.x.

27

Schoep, I., and C. Knappett. 2004. “Dual Emergence:  Evolving Heterarchy, Exploding Hierarchy.” In The Emergence of Civilization Revisited, edited by J. Barrett and P. Halstead, 21–37. Sheffield Studies in Aegean Archaeology 6. Oxford: Oxbow.

Schortman, E., and W. Ashmore. 2012. “History, Networks, and the Questfor Power: Ancient Political Competition in the Lower Motagua Valley, Guatemala.” JRAI 18 (1): 1–21. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9655.2011.01728.x.

Sheehy, J. 1991. “Structure and Change in a Late Classic Maya DomesticGroup at Copan, Honduras.” Ancient Mesoamerica 2 (01): 1–20. doi:10.1017/S095653610000033X.

Shelmerdine, C. 1973. “The Pylos Ma Tablets Reconsidered.” American Journal of Archaeology 85: 319–325.

Shelmerdine, C. 1981. “Nichoria in Context: A Major Town in the Pylos Kingdom.” American Journal of Archaeology 85 (3) (July 1): 319–325. doi:10.2307/504173.

Small, D. 1995. “Heterarchical Paths to Evolution: The Role of External Economies.” In Heterarchy and the Analysis of Complex Societies, 71–85. Archaeological Papers of the American Anthropological Association 6. Washington, DC: American Anthropological Association.

_______. 1997. “City-State Dynamics through a Greek Lens.” In Cross-Cultural Approaches to City-States, edited by T. Charlton and L. Nichols, 107–118. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press.

_______. 1998. “Surviving the Collapse: The Oikos and Structural Continuity Between Late Bronze Age and Later Greece.” In Mediterranean Peoples in Transition: Thirteenth to Early Tenth Centuries BCE, edited by S. Gitin, A. Mazar, and E. Stern, 283–291. Jerusalem: Hebrew University Press.

28

_______. 2007. “Mycenaean Polities: States or Estates?” In Rethinking Mycenaean Palaces II, edited by M. Galaty and W. Parkinson. 51. Los Angeles: Cotsen Institution of Archaeology.

_______. 2009. “The Dual-processual Model in Ancient Greece: Applying a Post-neoevolutionary Model to a Data-rich Environment.” Journal of Anthropological Archaeology 28 (2): 205–221.

_______. 2010. “The Archaic Polis of Azoria:  A Window into Cretan ‘Polital’ Social Structure.” JMA 23 (2): 197-217.

_______. 2011. “Contexts, Agency, and Social Change in Ancient Greece.” In State Formation in Italy and Greece:  Questioning the Neoevolutionist Paradigm, edited by N. Terrenato and D. Haggis, 197–217. Oxford: Oxbow.

Small, D. in press a. “Using Complexity Theory as a Heuristic Model for Understanding the Rise of Complexity in Iron Age Crete.” In Beyond Collapse:  Archaeological Perspectives on Resilience, Revitalization, and Transformation in Complex Societies, edited by R. Faulseit. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

Snodgrass, A., 1985. “The New Archaeology and the Classical Archaeologist.” AJA 89 (1): 31–37. doi:10.2307/504768.

Stuart, D. 2005. “Ideology and Classical Maya Kingship.” In A Catalyst of Ideas:  Anthropological Archaeology and the Legacy of Douglas W. Schwartz, edited by V.Scarborough, 257–286. Santa Fe, New Mexico: School of American Research Press.

Tambiah, S., 1976. World Conqueror and World Renouncer: a Study of Buddhism and Polity in Thailand against a Historical Background. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

_______. 1977. “The Galactic Polity: The Structure of Traditional Kingdoms in Southeast Asia*.” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 293 (1): 69–97. doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.1977.tb41806.x.

29

Tartaron, T. 2008. “Aegean Prehistory as World Archaeology: Recent Trends in the Archaeology of Bronze Age Greece.” Journal of Archaeological Research 16 (2): 83–161. doi:10.1007/s10814-007-9018-7.

Van der Vliet, E. 2000. “Models of Political Evolution and the Formation of the Polis.” Pharos.  Journal of the Netherlands Institute in Athens 8: 129–148.

_______. 2002. “Was the Polis a State or Stateless Society?” In Even More Studies in the Ancient Greek Polis, edited by T. Nielsen, 14–47. Papers fromthe Copenhagen Polis Centre 6. Stuttgart: Steiner Verlag.

_______. 2005. “Polis. The Problem of Statehood.” Social Evolution and History4 (2): 120–150.

_______. 2011. “The Early Greek Polis:  Regime Building and the Emergence of the State.” In State Formation in Italy and Greece:  Questioning the Neoevolutionist Paradigm, edited by N. Terrenato and D. Haggis, 119–134. Oxford: Oxbow.

Voutsaki, S. 2008. “Greek Archaeology: Theoretical Developments over the Last 40 Years.” Tijdschrift Voor Mediterrane Archeologie 20: 21–28.

Webster, D., W. Fash, Jr., C. Baudez, B. Riese, and W. Sanders, ed. 1989. The House of the Bacabs, Copan, Honduras. Studies in Pre-Columbian Art and Archaeology 29. Washington, DC: Dumbarton Oaks.

Weiberg, Erika. 2012. “What Can Resilience Theory Do for (Aegean) Archaeology?” In Matters of Scale: Processes and Courses of Events in Archaeology and Cultural History, edited by N.M. Burström and F. Fahlander, 146–165. Stockholm: Stockholm University. http://uu.diva-portal.org/smash/record.jsf?pid=diva2:572734.

Weiberg, Erika, and Martin Finné. 2013. “Mind or Matter? People-Environment Interactions and the Demise of Early Helladic II Society in the Northeastern Peloponnese.” American Journal of Archaeology 117 (1) (January 1): 1–31. doi:10.3764/aja.117.1.0001.

30

Whitley, J. 1991. “Social Diversity in Dark Age Greece.” ABSA 86 : 341–365.

Whitley, James. 2003. Style and Society in Dark Age Greece: The Changing Face of a Pre-literate Society, 1100-700 BC. Cambridge University Press.

Whitley, James. 2002. “Objects with Attitude: Biographical Facts and Fallacies in the Study of Late Bronze Age and Early Iron Age Warrior Graves.” Cambridge Archaeological Journal 12 (02): 217–232. doi:10.1017/S0959774302000112.

Wright, J. 1995. “From Chief to King in Mycenaean Greece.” In The Role of the Ruler in the Prehistorica Aegean, 63–80. Aegaeum 11. Austin: University of Texas Press.

Wright, J. 2010. “Towards a Social Archaeology of Middle Helladic Greece.” In Mesohelladika:  The Greek Mainland in the Middle Bronze Age, Actes Du Colloque International Organise Par l’Ecole Francaise d’Athens, En Collaboration Avec l’American School of Classical Studies at Athens et Le Netherlands Institute in Athens, Athenes, 8-12 Mars 200g, edited by A. Philippa-Touchais, S. Voutsaki, and J. Wright, 803–815. BCH Supplement 52. Paris: De Boccard..

31

32

33