State constitutions in the federal system

132

Transcript of State constitutions in the federal system

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

July 1989

Constitutions

Selected Issues and Opportunities

for State Initiatives

Preface The following study of state constitutional law

examines a vital aspect of the reinvigoration of the states in our federal union. The study also comple- ments ACIR's pathbreaking report State Constitu- tional Law: Cases and Materials (1988). In addition, this study sheds light on several issues that have been examined in various ways by the U.S. Advisory Com- mission on Intergovernmental Relations during the past three decades, especially balance in the federal system, the constitutional integrity of federalism, the strengthening of state capabilities, and the sorting out of responsibilities in the federal system.

The American federal system rests on two consti- tutional pillars: the 50 state constitutions and the United States Constitution. Metaphorically speak- ing, if one or the other pillar is cut down in size or raised too high, then the federal system becomes un- balanced. In manyrespects, this is what has happened to our federal system. The law of the U.S. Constitu- tion, particularly as developed by the U.S. Supreme Court during the past 50 years, has come to over- shadow state constitutional law to such an extent that state constitutions are, for many citizens, out of sight and out of mind. For example, ACIR's 1988 national poll (see Changing Public Attitudes on Governments and Taxes, 1988) found that fewer than half of the re- spondents even knew that their state has its own con- stitution. Yet state constitutions are important democratic governing documents, and they can be all the more important if their role in the federal system is understood properly. As such, a renewed apprecia- tion of state constitutional law is essential for restor- ing a better balance of national-state authority in the federal system.

A strengthening of the state constitutional pillar is also essential for protecting the constitutional in- tegrity of the federal system. This integrity depends not only on fidelity to the principles of federalism em- bodied in the U.S. Constitution but also on the inde- pendent vitality of the state constitutions. This state constitutional pillar was built first by Americans when they sought to establish home-rule republican

governments during the Revolutionary War and the period of Confederation. The U.S. Constitution, therefore, is one of limited, delegated powers. The state constitutions encompass, in principle if not now in practice, the many fundamental powers of govern- ance that have been reserved to the states and to the people by the Tenth Amendment to the U.S. Consti- tution. The erosion of these inherent state powers by an imperial vision of federal constitutional law threatens the very foundation of the federal system. The U.S. Constitution does not replace state consti- tutions; instead, it supplements those constitutions by providing for constitutional governance nation- wide on matters of general public interest and, in so doing, protects the states as co-sovereign constitu- tional polities and guarantees each state a republican form of government.

A renewal of the vitality of state constitutional law is also the foundation for strengthening state ca- pabilities. This is so for three reasons. First, in a con- stitutional democracy, any enhancement of state capabilities must take place within the context of con- stitutional rule. In the states, this means that the peo- ple must decide on the scope and powers of the state government. Second, most state constitutions con- tain a great deal of detail, much of which limits state government. Although contemporary reformers often criticize this detail as being too constraining for elected officials, it should be remembered that much of the detail represents efforts by past reformers to assert greater public control over government. The real question is not detail per se, but what kind of constitutional detail represents general public inter- ests rathcr than spccial interests, and what kind of de- tail is harmful rathcr than beneficial to state action. Third, state capabilities vis-a-vis the federal govern- ment cannot be enhanced significantly unless there is strength in, and respect for, the states as constitu- tional politics in their own right (see also ACIR's The Question of State Government Capability, 1985).

The development of state constitutional law is also relevant tothe sorting out of responsibilities in

ii Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

the federal system. One sees this sorting out occur- ring in the "new judicial federalism" whereby the U.S. Supreme Court has shown greater solicitude for independent state court protections of individual rights and liberties. If states had no important or in- dependent governing responsibilities, there would be no need for state constitutions. The very existence of dual constitutionalism signifies both a division and sharing of responsibilities between state and nation. Furthermore, many new issues emerging on the pub- lic scene are not easily encompassed by the U.S. Con- stitution, but are, or can be, encompassed by state constitutions.

We should add, however, that not everyone will be happy with all of the state constitutional law devel- opments reported in this study. Those who believe, for example, that federal courts have expanded cer- tain rights, such as criminal rights, too far will be dis- mayed by activist state supreme courts that have expanded rights even further. Others will be dis- mayed that many state courts are not yet active enough in developing state constitutional law. If one

values federalism, however, and the dual consti- tutionalism that underlies it, then one cannot let opinions about particular developments overshadow the more fundamental issues of the place that state constitutional law should occupy in a strong and bal- anced federal system. The prominence of that place is one question; whether that place should be liberal or conservative, activist or restraintist is another question.

It is the second question that has to be answered by the actual constitutional choices made by the citizens of each of the 50 states. Fortunately for the vitality of American democracy, state constitutions provide the general public with many direct and indi- rect vehicles for shaping the development of state constitutional law. Hence, state constitutions, unlike the U.S. Constitution, call on citizens to participate very directly in framing the fundamental law of their respective polities.

Robert B. Hawkins, Jr. Chairman

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations iii

Acknowledgments This report was prepared by a study team at the

Center for the Study of Federalism at Temple Uni- versity. The team members responsible for the vari- ous chapters are as follows:

Chapter 1:

Chapter 2:

Chapter 3:

Chapter 4:

Chapter 5:

Chapter 6:

Chapter 7:

Chapter 8:

Chapter 9:

Chapter 10:

Ellis Katz, Temple University

David Skover, Indiana University School of Law

Robert F. Williams, Rutgers School of Law, Camden

G. Alan Tarr, Rugters University

G. Alan Tarr and Robert F. Wil- liams

William W. Greenhalgh and Jeanne N. Lobelson, Georgetown Univer- sity Law Center

Peter J. Galie, Canisius College

Mary Cornelia Porter, I3arat Col- lege (Emerita) and William Bcans, Northern Illinois University School of Law

Ellis Katz, with the assistance of Charles Robinson, Temple Univer- sity

Ellis Katz

Each member of the study team read and com- mented extensively on all of the draft chapters, so that this final report is truly a joint effort.

Thanks are expressed to each of these authors, and also to the following individuals who participated in reviewing the study as it progressed through vari- ous stages: Phyllis Bamburger, Norman Beckman, Joyce Benjamin, John Callahan, Ronald K. L. Col- lins, William Colman, Vicki Jackson, Carolyn Jour- dan, John Kamensky, Mary Kazmerak, Susan Lauffer, Michael Libonati, James Martin, Hon. Mil- ton Mollen, Thomas R. Morris, John Pittinger, Stewart G. Pollock, Douglas Ross, Lee Ruck, Martin A. Schwartz, John Shannon, and Harry Swegle.

At ACIR, secretarial assistance was supplied by Lori A. Coffel.

ACIR is grateful for the help of all those who contributed advice, research materials, and critical review for this study. Full responsibility for the con- tent of the report, however, lies with the Commission and its staff.

John Kincaid Executive Director

Bruce D. McDowell Director

Government Policy Research

iv Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Contents Findings . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1

1 . State Constitutions "Complete" and "Balance" the Nation's Constitutional Framework: State Constitutions Are Essential . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1

. . . . . . . . . . 2 . The States Are Independent Polities with Their Own Philosophies of Government 1 3 . The United States Constitution Allows Substantial Room for the Development

of a Separate Discipline of State Constitutional Law .................................... 1 4 . State Constitutions Are the Business of Governors. Legislatures. the People. and the Courts . . 2

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5 . State Constitutional Law Is an Underdeveloped Field with Great Potential 2

Recommendations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3

Recommendation 1-Promoting Public Understanding of and Support for State Constitutional Law 3 Recommendation 2-Developing the Capability to Improve State Constitutional Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3

.......... Recommendation 3-Recognizing Shared Responsibility for State Constitutional Action 3 Recommendation 4-Recognizing the Importance of State Constitutional Law

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . in Rebalancing the Federal System 4

Part I: State Constitutions and Constitutional Law in the Federal System Chapterl-Introduction ................................................................ 7

. . . . . . . The Constitution of the United States: The Oldest Written Constitution in the World? 7 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The Constitution of the United States as an "Incomplete Document" 8

.............................................................. TheStatesasPolities 8 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The United States Constitution as a Constraint on the States 9

........................................ The Supreme Court and State Economic Policy 9 The Supreme Court and State Civil Liberties Policy ..................................... 10 The Nature of State Constitutions ................................................... 11

................................................. State Courts and State Constitutions 12 ..................................... State Constitutional Law and American Federalism 13

...................................................... The Organization of this Study 13

Chapter 2-Powers of and Restraints on "Our Federalism": State Authority under the Federal Constitution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Restraints on State Economic and Police Regulation 18 Authority for State Judicial Declaration of State Constitutional Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24

Part II: Recent Developments in State Constitutional Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Chapter 3-Government Structure under State Constitutions 37

The Function of State Constitutions Regarding Governmental Structure . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38 State Constitutions and Separation of Powers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The State Legislative Branch 39 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The State Executive Branch 41

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The State Judicial Branch 42 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Local Government and State Constitutions 44

Conclusion ....................................................................... 45

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations v

................................................. Chapter 4-The States and Civil Liberties 49 ........................................................ A State Civil Liberties Law? 49

......................................... Freedom of Speech under State Constitutions 51 Freedom of the Press under State Constitutions ........................................ 53

...................................................... Church and State in the States 54 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Chapter 5-Equality under State Constitutions 59 ........................................................ The First State Constitutions 60

Other Generally Applicable Equality Provisions in State Constitutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 60 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Case Study: Gender Equality in the States 62

Conclusion ....................................................................... 64

Chapter 6-The States and Criminal Procedure ............................................ 69 ...................................................... State Courts and Constitutions 69

State Use of Their Own Constitution ................................................. 70 ............................................... State Courts' Reliance on Federal Law 71

...................................................... StateandFederalProsecutions 73 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Avoiding Federal Use of Evidence 74

Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 Appendix-Cases since Michigan v . Long in Which a State Court Has Granted the Defendant

More Protections Than the Supreme Court Finds within the U.S. Constitution . . . . 79

Chapter 7-State Courts and Economic Rights . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 83 State Courts and Economic Rights in the 19th Century . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84 State Court Activity and Economic Rights. 1897-1987 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84 State Courts and Economic Rights: Constitutional Charge or Reactionary Residue? . . . . . . . . . . 88 Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91

Part III: State Constitutional Law and Public Policy

Chapter 8-State Supreme Courts and Workers' Compensation: Change and the Diffusion ofNew Ideas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Workers' Compensation: Problems and Proposals for Change . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Workers' Compensation and the Courts: An Overview

The Exclusivity Requirement and State Constitutional Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ................................................... State Supreme Court Policymaking

The Intentional Tort Doctrine: The Case Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . An Assessment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The California. West Virginia. Ohio. and Michigan Courts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

Chapter 9-State Constitutional Law and State Educational Policy ............................ 109 The States and Education: An Historical Perspective .................................... 109 The Federal Courts and State School Finance Laws . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 111

. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . State Courts. State Constitutions. and State School Finance Laws 111 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . State Legislatures. State Constitutions. and State School Finance Laws 113

Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 114

Part IV Conclusion

Chapter 10-State Constitutional Law: The Ongoing Search for Unity and Diversity intheAmericanFederalSystem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119

The Supreme Court and the Scarch for Balance . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119 State Constitutional Traditions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120 State Constitutional 1 aw and Individual T . ibcrties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120 State Constitutions and Equality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 State Constitutional Law and the Regulation of Property . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 State Constitutional Law and Public Policy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 122 Unity. Uniformity. and Diversity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 122

vi Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Findings State Constitutions "Complete" and "Balance" the Nation's Constitutional Framework State Constitutions Are Essential

The state constitutions and the U.S. Constitution are coordinate documents which, together, p-rovide the total framework for government withm the United States. Neither can stand alone. However, with the rise to prominence of federal constitutional law and the expansion of federal power, public and judicial understanding of state constitutional law has been weakened, so much so that when most people think of constitutional law, they think only of federal constitutional law.

Yet, all of the states in the original confederal Union had constitutions or charters of their own be- fore the U.S. Constitution was drafted and ratified in 1787-1788. Those state constitutions did thcn, and still do, provide the framework for many aspects of government not covered by the U.S. Constitution. In addition, they provide alternative approaches to as- pects of government also addressed in the U.S. Con- stitution. In some cases, state constitutions supple- ment and go beyond provisions in the U.S. Constitution.

Some of the matters addressed in the state con- stitutions, but not in the U.S. Constitution, are the structure, functions, and finances of state and local governments; the constitutional standing of local governments in disputes with the state; state-local re- lationships in the broadest sense; limits on the ability of the state to mandate functions and expenses on lo- cal governments; and the regulation of property, in- cluding the land development process. These are matters of immense significance for intergovernmen- tal relations and for the American federal system. It is impossible to appreciate the dynamics of this fed- eral system, and to realize its potential for producing diversity within unity, without a sound and fully de- veloped understanding of state constitutional law.

2. The States Are Independent Polities with Their Own Philosophies of Government Until the present U.S. Constitution was created,

the states were sovereign governments in their own right. In ratifying the U.S. Constitution, they dele- gated certain of their powers to the federal govern- ment and transferred a certain degree of sovereignty. However, they reserved all residual powers to them- selves and to the people.

The state constitutions are based on diverse un- derstandings and philosophies of government, are substantially easier to amend than the U.S. Constitu- tion, provide for direct citizen involvement in the process of amendment and change (unlike the fed- eral Constitution), have a tendency, therefore, to ac- cumulate detailed provisions that some people be- lieve should be left to statutory law, and have bills of rights that oftcn are different from the U.S. Bill of Rights. It is importiint to understand these differ- ences between state constitutional law and federal constitutional law a' the full potentials of the states, and of their local governmcnts, are to be realized within the American federal system.

3. The United States Constitution Allows Substantial Room for the Development of a Separate Discipline of State Constitutional Law The study of state constitutional law reveals a

number of federal constitutional doctrines that po- tentially limit federal intrusions into state and local affairs, and that limit the jurisdiction of the U.S. Su- preme Court and federal district courts over matters reserved to the states. For example:

A state constitutional grant of authority to state and local governments is unlikely to be preempted by federal courts when it (1) regulates a subject matter traditionally left to the slatcs, (2) uses historic police power objectives concerning health, safety or mor-

Advisory Commisslon on Intergovernmental Relations 1

als, (3) involves objectives that are compat- ible with or supplemental to the purposes of any federal regulation in the subjcct area, (4) concerns a subject area that has not been ex- plicitly preempted by federal law, and (5) af- fects dimensions of an activity not compre- hensively regulated by federal law.

The "dormant commerce clause" doctrine furthers the federal interest in national free trade, but exhibits a pronounced deference to state government rulemaking in the com- mercial realm when it (1) is designed to pro- mote traditional police power objectives, such as health or safety, rather than the busi- ness interests of the state's own residents, (2) treats out-of-state and in-state economic entities in an even-handed manner, and (3) does not vary from national standards to such an extent that it imposes conflicting obligations or cumulative burdens on multi- state businesses.

The doctrine of "adequate and independent state grounds" prevents the U.S. Supreme Court from reviewing a state high court judg- ment that plainly rests on a determination of state law.

The "abstention" and "equitable restraint" doctrines restrict the original jurisdiction of the federal district courts in favor of state court declarations of state constitutional and statutory law.

Thus, the federal judiciary has created certain opportunities, within its understanding of the U.S. Constitution, for state foresight and assumption of responsibility. The current movement to integrate state constitutions into the process of state lawmak- ing opens the possibility that the promises of diversity within unity in American federalism can be realized.

4. State Constitutions Are the Business of Governors, Legislatures, the People, and the Courts Most state constitutions are amended much

more easily and frequently than the U.S. Constitu- tion. Citizens promote or affirm these changes by in- itiative or referendum. In addition, governors and

legislatures frcqucn tly are involved in providing lead- ership for constitutional change. Interpretations by statc judgcs, who often are elected, are also a major force for changc. However, because of the direct role of citizen participation in state constitutional devel- opment, arncndmcnt plays a larger role in the change process than it docs for the U.S. Constitution. Judi- cial interprelation, which is the dominant means of giving new meanings to the U.S. Constitution, plays a smaller, though still important, role in keeping state constitutions up to date. Thus, the politically respon- sive nature of state constitutions is more directly ap- parent than that of the U.S. Constitution.

The prolific amendment capacity of state consti- tutions has yielded many reforms in recent years, as well as certain causes for concern. Examples of re- forms include home rule, strengthened executive management and budgeting, and more capable legis- latures. However, concerns arise when the state judi- ciaries, often subject to the electoral process, become embroiled in political campaigns, when legislators or governors promote excessive constitutional restric- tions on local governments, when citizens fail to vote for constitutional amendments that seem to be too obscure or complcx to understand, or when emo- tional issucs of the moment produce constitutional changes that lack foresight or sensitivity to certain groups of citizcns.

5. State Constilutional Law Is an Underdeveloped Field with Great Potential A 1988 Commission poll revealed that only 44

percent of Americans know that their state has its own constitution. Even among lawyers, state consti- tutional law is relatively unknown and little practiced. Compared to the U.S. Constitution, state constitu- tions are less frequently mentioned in the history and civics classes of public schools or the university, and regular reporting of state constitutional decisions, as well as the statistics of state court activities, has been, until very recently, quite rare. Even the law schools seldom offercourscs in state constitutional law. If the American fedcral system is to be properly balanced- giving full rein to the potentials of local governments, the states, and the national government-then the field of state constitutional law needs to be developed more fully.

2 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Recommendations Recommendation I

Promoting Public Understanding of and Support for State Constitutional Law

The Commission finds that widespread public understanding of and support for the vital role that state constitutions and state constilutional law play in maintaining a proper balance in the American fed- eral system is essential for the full development of the nation's potential. The importance of voter initia- tives and referendums in the process of revising state constitutions is a major reason for this finding. Yet, most citizens are unaware even of the existence of the 50 state constitutions.

The Commission recommends, therefore, that:

0 The Commission on the Bicentennial of the U.S. Constitution recognize the importance of state constitutions and constitutional law in "completing" the U.S. Constitution.

0 State bicentennial commissions and humani- ties councils include consideration of state constitutions in their public programming.

0 State associations of judges and legislators include consideration of state constitutions and constitutional developments in their continuing education programs.

State and local education agencies require schools to teach units in state history andlor government in which the state constitution and its development are discussed. (State judges, legislators, and executive officials should involve themselves in this activity.)

0 Colleges and universities give attention to state constitutions and state constitutional law on a par with that given to the U.S. Con- stitution in history and government courses.

0 The mass media provide regular coverage of state constitutional developments.

Recommendation 2 Developing the Capability

to Improve State Constitutional Law The Commission finds that adequate capability

to fully develop the. field of statc constitutional law does not ycl cxisl within the lcgal profession orwithin the political lcaclcrship of the states.

The Comnlission recommends, therefore, that law schools teach state constitutional law as part of their regular curriculum, that state bar examiners in- clude a section on state constitutional law in their bar exams, and that public and private institutions sup- port research on state constitutional law. Among the issues that should be addressed are: the interaction of state judicial, legislative, and executive agencies in the development of an independent state constitu- tional law; the implications for state constitutional law of elected judiciaries and constitutional docu- ments that are fairly easy to change; how develop- ments in state constitutional law spread from one state to another; and what legal and other barriers ex- ist to inhibit the development of an independent state constitutional law.

The Commission recommends, in addition, the establishment of a clearinghouse for information on state constilutional developments. Such a function could be underlakcn by an existing organization (such as the National Association of Attorneys General or the National Cenler for State Courts) or by a new or- ganization crealcd ibr the purpose.

Recommendation 3 Recognizing Shared Responsibility

for State Constitutional Action The Commission finds that the growing responsi-

bilities being placed on the states and their local gov- ernments require adequate and responsive provi- sions in state constitutional law. These matters must be addressed independently within each state. taking into account the unique traditions and philosophies of government that exist in each state as well as the

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 3

direct role played by citizens in the development of state constitutional law in contrast to federal consti- tutional law.

The Commission recommends, therefore, that citizens, legislatures, and governors recognize their own responsibilities for advancing and reforming state constitutional law rather than relinquishing that role entirely to the courts or consigning the most dif- ficult issues to the U.S. Supreme Court.

The Commission also recommends that each state give renewed attention to the adequacy and re- sponsiveness of its constitution for today's world, and that the development of state constitutional law be understood as a joint responsibility of the legislature, governor, courts, and citizens. The Commission en- courages state high courts to develop independent bodies of state constitutional law, but also to recog- nize that U.S. Supreme Court models of jurispru- dence are not always appropriate to the shared roles of citizens, legislatures, and governors in state consti- tutional change and enforcement.

The Commission further recommends that the high court or courts in each state establish principles for attorneys practicing before the courts of the state that would require them to look first to the state con- stitution as the basis for litigation rather than to the U.S. Constitution.

The Commission recommends, furthermore, that states take steps to identify and resolve intergov- ernmental issues and problems that may arise from existing state constitutional law. Given the decline in federal aid to local governments and the shifting of responsibilities taking place in the federal system, is- sues Iikely to need attention now include the provi- sion of adequate local government authority and ca- pacity to meet growing responsibilities, stronger state-local relationships to compensate for weakened federal-local relationships, and revised allocations of functions and financial responsibilities between the states and local governments and among local gov- ernments. State constitutions and statutes should provide for flexibility of form, function, and finance for local governments.

Recommendation 4 Recognizing the Importance of State Constitutional Law

in Rebalancing the Federal System

The Commission finds that the recently renewed interest in state constitutional law by judges, attor- neys, scholars, and state and local policymakers is an important development in American federalism. Re- balancing of responsibilities in the federal system is necessary in order to give state and local govern- ments greater authority and discretion to serve the needs of their citizens. One necessary feature of such

rebalancing is recognition of and respect for the co- equal importance of state constitutional law in the American system of constitutional government. The vitality of federalism rests on two constitutional pil- lars: (1) independent state constitutional law and (2) protections of fedcralism in U.S. constitutional law.

The Commission, therefore, commends the U.S. Supreme Court for honoring the "adequate and inde- pendent state grounds" doctrine, and recommends that the Court continue to honor this doctrine and to allow the states to experiment with solutions to the difficult issues that confront our society and to de- velop their own principles of state constitutional law appropriate to thc goalsand conditions of the people, institutions. and political subdivisions of the different states.

The Commission also rccornmends that both the Congress and thc Suprcme Court refrain from im- posing restrictions on the independence of the states and their political subdivisions unless there is clear federal constitutional authority to do so and (1) a clear threat to national unity, (2) a clear need for uni- form national policy, or (3) a clear conflict with ex- press provisions of the Constitution of the United States. It is as important, for example, to provide an- titrust immunity to the political subdivisions of the states as to the states themselves.

More specifically, the Commission recommends that the following fcderal constitutional doctrines be applied consistently by the courts to limit federal in- trusions into state and local affairs concerning mat- ters reserved to the states:

A state constitutional grant of authority to state and local governments should not be preempted by federal courts when it (1) regulates a subject matter traditionally left to the states, (2) uses historic police power objectives concerning health, safety, or mor- als. (3) involves objectives that are compat- ible with or supplemental to the purposes of any federal regulation in the subject area, (4) concerns a subject area that has not been ex- plicitly preempted by federal law, and (5) af- fects dimensions of an activity not compre- hensively regulated by federal law.

The "dormant commerce clause" doctrine, although it furthers the federal interest in national free trade, should also be used to bolster deference to state government rule- making in the commercial realm when it (1) is designed to promote traditional police power objectives, such as health or safety, rather than the business interests of the state's own residents, (2) treats out-of-state and in-state economic entities in an even- handed manner, and (3) does not vary from

4 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

national standards to such an extent that it imposes conflicting obligations or cumula- tive burdens on multistate businesses.

The doctrine of "adequate and independent state grounds" should be invoked to prevent the U.S. Supreme court from reviewing a state high court judgment that plainly rests on a determination of state law.

The "abstention" and "equitable restraint" doctrines should be invoked to restrict the original jurisdiction of the federal district courts in favor of state court declarations of state constitutional and statutory law.

The Commission recommends, furthcr, that, whenever possible and appropriate, state judges look to state constitutional provisions first, using the "ade- quate and independent grounds" doctrine, when de- ciding constitutional questions, rather than turning immediately to the U.S. Constitution. By interpret- ing state constitutional provisions independently of how similar provisions of the U.S. Constitution are

interpreted, state courts can protect their decisions from U.S. Supreme Court review and thereby foster the growth of an independent body of state constitu- tional law.

The Commission also recommends, as a supple- mentary measure of protection, that states increase their support for the State and Local Legal Center so as to maintain a strong presence on the manyfederal- ism issues that come before the U.S. Supreme Court.

The Commission once again urges the Congress to recognize and afr'irm the importance of state con- stitutional law in the American federal system and exercise restraint i n preempting state and local re- sponsibilities as wcll as in mandating responsibilities and expenses on state and local governments. To help bolster the ('ongress' resolve in these matters, the Commission recommends that the states estab- lish a "federalism impact process" by which they could respond, in a timely fashion, to contemplated actions by the Congress that might diminish state and local authority. The Academy for State and Local Government should be considered for this role.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 5

6 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 1

Introduction This study examines selected aspects of the place

of state constitutional law in the American system and of recent developments in state constitutional law, particularly as this body of law has becn dcvel- oped by state high courts. The study is not intendcd to be comprehensive because a full examination of the many facets of state constitutional law would require several large volumes. Instead, we have sought to fo- cus on certain aspects of state constitutional law that highlight the importance, variety, and innovativeness of developments in the states. This study looks, therefore, at the bearings of state constitutions on state government structure, civil liberties, equality, criminal rights (the exclusionary rule), economic and property rights, workers' compensation, and educa- tion.'

This study takes on particular importance when one considers the results of ACIR's 1988 national public opinion poll. Only 44 percent of American adults knew that their state has its own constitution, and 44 percent of the respondents did not know that their state constitution has its own bill of rights.* Per- haps these results are not surprising because, after all, so much attention has been given to federal con- stitutional law in recent decades that "constitutional law" today is virtually synonymous with federal con- stitutional law.

This eclipsing of state constitutional law in the minds of not only the general public but also many policymakers is one indicator of the condition of con- temporary American federalism. Kenewed attention to and interest in state constitutional law, therefore, must be viewed as part and parcel of any effort to re- store a better balance of national-state power in the federal system. The American system of dual consti- tutionalism represents a unique and highly successful experiment in democratic governance, one that needs constant attention if we are to continue to make it work, and work better.

The Constitution of the United States: The Oldest Written Constitution

in the World?

Anothcr indicator of thc cclipsingof state consti- tutions is that during 1987, the year of the bicenten- nial of the drafting of thc Constitution of the United States of America, that revered document was often said to be the oldest, still operative, written constitu- tion in the world. Even forgiving some exaggeration, the careful observer should recognize that the claim is not true. The oldest, still operative, written consti- tution in the world is the Constitution of Massachu- setts, written largely by John Adams and ratified by the citizens of Massachusetts in 1780, a full seven years before the Constitution of the United States was written in Philadelphia.3 The Constitution of the United States, of course, continues to be the oldest, still operative, written, national constitution in the world.

Beyond the nced for historical accuracy, the lon- gevity of the Massachusetts Constitution is important because it underscores the limited role that the United States Constitution was designed to serve in the American federal system. The thirteen original states were fully functioning constitutional entities before 1787. Delaware, Maryland, New Hampshire, New Jersey, North Carolina, Pennsylvania, South Carolina, and Virginia all enacted constitutions in 1776. Georgia and New York wrote constitutions the following year, 1777. Massachusetts adopted its con- stitution in 1780. Only Connecticut and Rhode Island continued to function under their colonial charters until they replaced them with constitutions in 1818 and 1842 respectively.4 Thus, Americans had consid- erable experience with written constitutions before the framers met in Philadelphia during the summer of 1787. Indeed, much of the debate that took place, both in the Constitutional Convention itself and in

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 7

the state ratifying conventions, dcmonstratcs how the framers of the U.S. Constitution built on these state constitutional experiencc~.~ In The Federalist, for cx- ample, one finds repeated references to state consti- tutions, both positive and negative.

The Constitution of the United States as an "Incomplete Document"

The Constitution of the United States is depend- ent on state constitutions in an even more profound and contemporary way. As Donald S. Lutz has sug- gested, the Constitution of the United States is "in- complete."6 It is predicated on the continued exis- tence and vitality of state constitutions. Unlike many constitutions in Europe and elsewhere in the world, the Constitution of the United States is silent, or mostly silent, on such fundamental constitutional matters as local government finance, education, and the structure of state and local government. These and other constitutional matters are left to the states to resolve, in keeping with their own needs, prefer- ences, and traditions. Thus, the "complete" Ameri- can constitution includes both the Constitution of the United States and the constitutions of the 50 states- both as they are written and as they are implemented and interpreted by judges and other government offi- cials.

The Constitution of the United States delegates limited, although important, powers to the national government. When exercising those delegated pow- ers, the laws of the United States are supreme. State laws, and even state constitutional provisions, must yield to these legitimate expressions of national authority. At the same time, because national author- ity is limited to those powers delegated by the U.S. Constitution, the states retain broad areas of policy- making authority to themselves. The areas of public policy reserved to the states are controlled not by the U.S. Constitution, but by the constitutions of the 50 individual states.

At least since 1937, however, the constitutional delegations of authority to the national government have been interpreted broadly; consequently, there is hardly an area of social or economic life that cannot be reached now by the national government. This is not to suggest that the national government can, con- stitutionally, control all areas of public policy, only that it can influence them. For example, few Ameri- cans would contend that the national government could mandate a uniform curriculum for thc nation's schools. At the same time, few would deny that the federal government has had a considerable impact on curriculum through its grant-in-aid system, its cur- riculum development projects, and its initiatives in such areas as bilingual education, the education of the handicapped, and school desegregation. Despite this federal presence, however, the states (and their

subdivisions) play the dominant role in setting educa- tion policy.

Today, few iwci3s of public policy belong exclu- sively either to Llic national government or to the states. Rather, policy responsibility is shared between the national government and the states. In some ar- eas, such as foreign poky, the federal government is the dominant actor; in others, such as education, the states play the principal role. Given the expansion of national authority, especially since 1937, one can ar- gue about how much policymaking "room" is left to the states. Nevertheless, it is important to recognize that just as we conceive of the federal government as a polity, both energized and constrained by the US. Constitution, so also must we think of the states as polities, encrgizetl and constrained by their own con- stitutions.

The States as Polities

From this perspective, the American states are polities within the framework of the American fed- eral system.? 71at is. the primary role of the states is to make policy choices dealing with that wide range of matters assigncd to them by their citizens and left open to them by the very incompleteness of the U.S. Constitution. 'To put the matter somewhat differ- ently, and without disparaging the crucial role of the states in the implementation of national programs, the states are political arenas for the forging of public policy, not administrative agencies for the implemen- tation of policy made by the national government.

As polities, the states require rules both for the management of political conflict and for the determi- nation of what is legitimate public policy. In some federal systems, these basic decisions are made in a single, national constitution. The states of India, for example, do not have their own constitutions; their political authority and organization are provided for in the national constitution.* In Brazil, while the states write their own constitutions, they make few important choices because they must conform to the detailed provisions of the national constitution.9 These arrangements may be appropriate for India and Brazil, where the national government is the principal arena for policymaking, but a different ar- rangement is necessary where the states play an im- portant policymaking role.

Furthermore, if the American states are policymakers, and have the right to enact constitu- tions to serve its thc lrameworks for that policymak- ing process, then we would expect considerably more variation, both in tcrms o f policy outcomes and policy processes, than wc might find in federal systems which are, in effect, merely decentralized administra- tive systems. Such diversity may be a blessing or a curse, depending on one's perspective. In the Ameri- can federal system, there is always a tension between

8 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

uniformity and diversity. Unfortunately, there is no clear formula to instruct us on when to opt for one or the other; rather, the choice more usually is made in the various arenas of the political process-legisla- tures, executive agencies, and courts.

The United States Constitution as a Constraint on the States

Of course, the U.S. Constitution serves as an overarching framework in which the states (and the federal government) perform their governing func- tions. This framework-as originally written, as amended, and as interpreted-constrains the states in many important ways.

First and clearly foremost, Article VI of the U.S. Constitution provides that "This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme law of the Land. . . ." This supremacy clause makes it clear that the Consti- tution, along with legitimate national laws and trea- ties, are superior to state enactments, including state constitutional provisions.

Sometimes, the words of the U.S. Constitution as they limit the states are fairly clear, as, for example, when the Constitution prohibits the states from "grant[ing] Letters of Marque and Reprisal; coin[ing] Money; [or] emit[ing] Bills of Credit. . . ,"lo although even these specific limitations are subject to some in- terpretation. The range of possible interpretations increases with the indefiniteness of the language, as, for example, when the Fourteenth Amendment re- quires the states to accord their residents "due proc- ess of law." Debates about the meaning of the Consti- tution are resolved primarily by the Supreme Court of the United States, so that, according to one ob- server, the Supreme Court is "the umpire of the fed- eral system."ll

This umpiring function is performed in three types of cases: (1) where there is an alleged conflict between a state constitutional provision or enact- ment and a provision of the Constitution of the United States, (2) where there is some conflict be- tween state and federal laws or treaties and the valid- ity of either or both is called into question, and (3) where the constitutionality of a fcderal law or treaty affecting national-state relations is challenged. The particular issue involved may concern an economic regulation or a personal liberty. Given that the U.S. Supreme Court applies different standards of review for each type of issue, each must be discussed sepa- rately.

The Supreme Court and State Economic Policy

When confronted with a claim that a state eco- nomic regulation violates some provision of the U.S. Constitution, the record of the U.S. Supreme Court

has been quite mixed. The charge that a state eco- nomic regulation violates the U.S. Constitution is usually based on one of several claims: (1) that the challenged state action is in violation of that provi- sion of the Fifth Amendment which prohibits the tak- ing of private property for public use without just compensation;Q (2) that a state regulation violates either the due process or equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment;l3 (3) that the state law is one "impairing the obligation of contracts" in viola- tion of Section 10 of' Article I;l4 (4) that a state law so favors its own citizens that it violates the interstate privileges and immunities clause of Article N, Sec- tion 2;'s (5) that the state law regulates an aspect of interstate commerce reserved exclusively to the na- tional government;l6 or (6) that a state revenue measure is, in Ihct, a duty on imports or exports in vio- lation of Article I, Section 10.17

These claims are treated more fully in chapter 2 of this study; herc it merely should be pointed out that the six claims fill1 into two different categories: (1) that the state has violated a right of its own resi- dents that is protected by the U.S. Constitution (e.g., the just compensation, impairment of contracts, due process, or equal protection provisions), and (2) that the state action has an unconstitutional "spillover ef- fect" on other states (e.g., the interstate commerce, privileges and immunities, or duty on imports or ex- ports provisions).

With regard to the first sort of claim-that the state has violated the property rights of its own citi- zens-the U.S. Supreme Court since the 1930s has come to the position of allowing the states consider- able discretion. only rarely striking down state ac- tions.18 Although there has been some revival of the "takings" provision of the Fifth Amendment,lQ the Supreme Court has shown little recent inclination to support claims of this first type.

However, the Supreme Court continues to playa more active role when confronted with claims that a state action advcrscly affects the rights or interests of other states or citizens of other states. For example, the Court will look closely at state actions that alleg- edly place an "undue burden" on interstate com- merce20 or appear to "discriminate" against other states or citizens of other states.21

These two palterns of decisions by the Supreme Court have important implications for state constitu- tions. First, to the extent that the U.S. Supreme Court no longer protects property rights against state actions, individuals must look to their state constitu- tion and state judiciary for the protection of their property rights. Sccond, the states would appear to have considerablc constitutional discretion in struc- turing economic relationships among their own citi- zens, so long as the state action has relatively little impact beyond its borders.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 9

The situation is considerably more complicated where there is an alleged conflict between state and federal laws affecting the same subject matter. Where the conflict is clear and irreconcilable, then, of course, the supremacy clause mandates that the state law must yield.22 When the conflict is not so clear, then the Supreme Court has taken on the role of deciding whether the federal law preempts the field and therefore precludes state regulation of the same subject matter. The standards for deciding whether a field has been preempted by the federal government have not been articulated very clearly,23 and at least one member of the Court-Chief Justice William Rehnquist-has argued that the Court should invoke the doctrine only when Congress has made a clear decision to preempt.24

Finally, decisions of the Supreme Court either upholding or striking down national legislation also have a profound effect on federalism. Prior to 1937, the Supreme Court frequently struck down national economic legislation, often on the grounds that the federal law invaded a field reserved to the states ex- clusively by theTenth Amendment.25 Since the "con- stitutional revolution" of 1937, however, the Court, with one exception,26 has abandoned the Tenth Amendment entirely. This abandonment has been so complete that one might conclude that there arc vir- tually no constitutional restraints on national author- ity except for those found in the Bill of Rights. Even recognizing the exaggeration, it still does suggest that to the extent that there are any restraints on federal authority, they are more likely to be found through the political process than through the courts.27

The Supreme Court and State Civil Liberties Policy

It should be recalled that the U.S. Bill of Rights, as originally added to the Constitution in 1791, ap- plied only to actions of the national government.28 For protection against state action, individuals had to look to the bills of rights of the state constitutions. This situation began to change in 1925, some 57 years after the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment. Although the U.S. Supreme Court was originally hesitant to use the due process and equal protection clauses as grounds for striking down state action as violative of the U.S. Bill of Rights,29 beginning in 192530 the Court started the gradual process of incor- porating provisions of the original Bill of Rights within the meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment, thereby making most provisions of the Bill of Rights as fully applicable against state action as they are against national action.

Furthermore, beginning in the 1950s and accel- erating during the 1960% the Court generally gave broad interpretations to most of the provisions of the Bill of Rights31-now made applicable against the

states through the process of "selective incorpora- tion."

The Supreme Court, as well as other federal and even state courts, also discovered what might be called "new rights" within the Constitution-the right of non-English speaking school children to be instructed in a language they can understand,32 the right of mental patients to treatment,33 the right of prisoners to be free of cruel and unusual punish- ment,34 and the right of married couples to privacy.35

Finally, the Court found new meaning in the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amend- ment. In addition to striking down state-imposed racial segregation in the schools,36 the Court ordered the reapportionmcnt of state legislatures according to the principle of "one man, one vote."37 The Court also struck down many state laws giving preference to men over womenP8 and held that indigent defen- dants have a right to counsel to appeal their convic- tions.39

Taken together, these four elements constitute the "revolution in civil rights and liberties" of the Warren Court em. Although these developments had their critics,40 supporters argued that they were long overdue, because if these unpopular causes were not championed by the Supreme Court of the United States, thcy were unlikely to receive serious consideration at all.4' Whatever merit this argument might have had in the 1950s and 1960s, it needs to be reevaluated in the context of the 1980s. Two impor- tant changes appear to make it somewhat less com- pelling.

First, state political processes are more receptive to the claims of minorities than they were during the 1950s and 1960s. The right to vote is much more widespread,42 legislatures are more representative,43 governors have gained more control over their administrations.44 civil services have been modern- ized,45 state courts have been unified and profes- sionalized,46 and, most generally, a wide range of in- terest groups now participate in what have become much more open political and governmental pro- cesses.47

Second, the nature of civil liberties issues is dif- ferent in the 1980s. For example, rights protecting citizens against blatant racial and sexual discrimina- tion, third-degree police tactics, and the suppression of books dealing with sex are all well established. While one should be "eternally vigilant"48 against any erosion of thcse basic rights, many of today's is- sues of civil rights and liberties are both more subtle and more complicated than those of the past. For ex- ample, today's issues of civil rights and liberties often involve a conflict between rights. What should one do, for example, when the claimed right of a journal- ist to withhold news sources in the name of freedom of the press conflicts with the right of a criminal de-

10 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

fendant to all information to plan his or her de- fense?4Q Or when the right of students to pray on the grounds of a public university in the name of religious freedom clashes with the right to be free of a religious establishment?50 Or when the right of a newspaper to publish conflicts with an individual's claim of pri- vaq?51 These are not issues of balancing society's need for security and order against the liberty of an individual; rather, they involve the claim of one indi- vidual to a civil liberty against a similar claim by an- other. At the same time, determining an appropriate remedy for an alleged violation of rights has become more complicated. There is, for example, consider- able dispute about the efficacy of the exclusionary rule as a remedy to the problem of unreasonable searches, especially when the violation appears more technical than willfu1.52 Other dilficult problems of remedy arise in prisoners' rights cases53 and some gender equity cases."

These two developments of the 1980s-the in- creased responsiveness of state political processes to civil liberties claims and the complexity of the issues themselves-may call into question the traditional justification for federal judicial activism offered in the 1960s. At least it should suggest the need for ex- perimentation with both forums and solutions.

There is some evidence that the U.S. Supreme Court has become sympathetic to these changes and is more willing to defer to the states on matters of civil rights and liberties. For example, the Court now may be somewhat more accepting of the standards of local communities in obscenity cases55 and substan- tially less willing to see cases transferred from state to federal courts in habeas corpus and other proceed- ings.56 Even more important, however, is the appar- ent willingness of the Court to see cases decided on state constitutional grounds without review by the Supreme Court.57 One must be careful not to overes- timate this tendency, but the trend does seem to pro- vide increased opportunities for states to deal with today's complicated issues of civil rights and liberties on the basis of their own constitutions, traditions, and standards.

While some observers applaud this "new judicial federalism," which would give greater scope to the states in defining civil rights and liberties, others doubt the capacity of the states to protect these rights adequately. There is no a priori answer to this ques- tion of whether the states will protect civil rights and liberties; instead, one must look to the record of state constitutions, state judiciaries, and state political processes.58

The Nature of State Constitutions State constitutions differ from the Constitution

of the United States in several ways. First, the Consti- tution of the United States, by and large, delegates

authority to the national government. As is well known, the national government has only those pow- ers delegated to it by the Constitution. The states and their citizens retain all powers not delegated to the national government or prohibited specifically to them. This means that state constitutions are more likely to contain limits on governmental authority than is the case with the national Constitution.

Second, state constitutions must deal with mat- ters barely touched on in the U.S. Constitution. State constitutions, for cxample, have detailed provisions on local government, elections, public education, and land management.

Third, slatc constitutions may be based on differ- ent undcrstanclings and philosophies of govern- ment.59 Thc Constitution of the United States is based on a EWcralist conception of the separation of powers, with a single strong chief executive, a bicam- eral legislature in which the states are represented equally in one chambcr, and life tenure for judges. State constitulions, on the other hand, may divide ex- ecutive authority among several statewide elected of- ficials and provide for the election of judges.

Fourth, state constitutions are easier to amend and change than is the U.S. Constitution. In fact, the 50 American states have had a total of 146 different constitutions since 3775.60 It may be that the relative stability of the U.S. Constitution has been made pos- sible, in part, because of the capacity of the states to adopt new constitutions to meet changing social and economic conditions.

Fifth, unlike the U.S. Constitution, state consti- tutions provide for direct citizen participation in the process of amendment and change. All state consti- tutions provide for citizen ratification of proposed constitutional amendments; 17 even provide for the initiation of amendments directly by the voters, thus bypassing the legislature altogether.61

Sixth, because state constitutions must contain limits on govcrnrnent, and because they are relatively easy to amend, some commentators have observed that state constilulions tcnd to become "cluttered" with details that would be best left to statutory law.62 Although this charge can easily be exaggerated, it is true that slate constitutions contain much more de- tail than does the Constitution of the United States. This detailed nature of state constitutions has impor- tant consequences for state judiciaries and for the practice of judicial review.

Finally, state bills of rights are often different from the U.S. Bill of Rights. Many state civil rights and liberties provisions are more detailed than are their counterparts in the U.S. Constitution. This is frequently the case with state provisions protecting against an establishment of religion, for example.63 Sometimes the language of state bills of rights ap- pears to go beyond what is required in the U.S. Con-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 11

stitution. Free speech provisions and guarantees of political participation are often of this nature.64 Most state constitutions contain rights provisions for which there are no counterparts in the U.S. Constitution. For example, 40 constitutions guarantee a right to education, and 19 contain an explicit right to be free of gender discrimination.65 Again, these differences have important implications for state courts.

State Courts and State Constitutions The Constitution of the United States requires

that state court judges "be bound by Oath or Affirma- tion, to support this [the U.S.] Constitution."66 In im- plementing this requirement, state constitutions usu- ally require state judges to take a specified oath swearing fidelity to both the U.S. Constitution and the state constitution. For instance, the Pennsylvania Constitution prescribes the following oath for judges: "I do solemnly swear (or affirm) that I will support, obey, and defend the Constitution of the United States and the Constitution of this Commonwealth. . . ."e7 Given that the supremacy clause of the U.S. Constitution provides that "This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance thereof. . . shall be the supreme Law of the Land," state judges, in cases of a conflict between their two loyalties, must give precedence to the U.S. Constitution and law. In fact, the U.S. Constitution makes this requirement explicit. After declaring the Constitution and laws of the United Statcs to be su- preme, it goes on to provide that the "Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Con- stitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary not- withstanding."68 Yet, even with the clear supremacy of the U.S. Constitution, this does not answer the question of whether state judges should look first to the U.S. Constitution or to the constitution of their state when it is claimed that a state action violates both.

Prior to the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment in 1868, state judges, quite naturally, looked to their state constitutions because there was little in the U.S. Constitution to limit state action.60 Later, when the U.S. Supreme Court began to find such protections in the Fourteenth Amendment- first for property rights and then for personal liber- ties-state judges also turned to the U.S. Constitu- tion.70 After 1937, the U.S. Supreme Court held that the Fourteenth Amendment does not limit state eeo- nomic regulation, except in the most unusual situ- ations. State court judges, because they are bound by the Supreme Court's interpretations of the U.S. Constitution, likewise turned from the Fourteenth Amendment as a defense of property rights against state action but, of course, continued to use lhcir state constitutions as property rights werc challcngcd by increasingly active state governments.

Similarly, as the Warren Court expanded the scope of national constitutional protections for per- sonal liberties, state judges also turned to the U.S. Constitution whcn confronted with cases involving personal liberties. In part, this tendency to look to the U.S. Constitution resulted from the nature of the le- gal strategy employed: because federal constitutional rights were so broadly interpreted by the U.S. Su- preme Court, lawyers naturally argued their client's cause on the brrsisof the U.S. Constitution. Statecon- stitutional issucs, when they were raised at all, were often seen as secondary.

Furthermore, state court judges began to inter- pret state constitutional provisions as identical to equivalent national constitutional provisions. For ex- ample, the language of Section 8 of the Pennsylvania Constitution's Declaration of Rights-dealing with searches and seizures-is similar to the language of the Fourth Amendment to the U.S. Constitution; consequently, Pennsylvania judges have tended to in- terpret Section 8 in precisely the same way as federal judges have interpreted the Fourth Amendment. Clearly, Section 8 of the Pennsylvania Constitution could not have been interpreted to deny rights pro- tected by the Fourth Amendment of the U.S. Consti- tution. At the same time, Section 8 could have been interpreted by Pcnnsylvania judges to guarantee rights beyond what might be required by the Fourth Amendment.

This raises thc difficult issue of "floors and ceil- ings." If state judges vicw state constitutional provi- sions as identical lo U.S. constitutional provisions, then interpretations by the U.S. Supreme Court be- come both thc Iloor and the ceiling for the states. However, if state court judges interpret state consti- tutional provisions independently of the way in which the U.S. Supreme Court interprets the U.S. Consti- tution, then U.S. Supreme Court interpretations irn- pose a floor only, and the states are free to develop an independent constitutional law that goes beyond that of the U.S. Supreme Court. At least this is the view of a number of state supreme court justices, including Hans Linde of Orcgon, Stanley Mosk of California, Robert N. C. Nix, .lr., of Pennsylvania, and Robert Utter of Washington.

Interpreting state bills of rights independently of the U.S. Rill ol'Rights also raises once again the prob- lem of uniformity versus diversity. Should American citizens have precisely the same civil rights and liber- ties regardless of where they live? Or should the states continuc to play a role in defining civil rights and libertics? If the latter position is admitted, what should bc thc rolc ol'thc U.S. Supreme Court in set- ting basic standi~rcls for civil rights and liberties? Be- cause the Amcricirn rccdcral system is predicated on a pragmatic and dynamic balancing of uniformity and

12 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

diversity, one should not be surprised to find these difficult considerations arising here.

State Constitutional Law and American Federalism

The development of an independent state con- stitutional law has important implications for Ameri- can federalism, implications that go beyond the issues of personal rights and liberties. For example, an inde- pendent state constitutional law reaffirms the role of the states as laboratories. It has been argued that to- day's issues of civil rights and liberties are cxtraordi- narily complicated, often pitting one personal liberty against another. Even the most ardent civil libertari- ans disagree on how to resolve such issues as free press versus fair trial or the free exercise of religion versus the establishment of religion. These are con- flicts in which society might benefit from experiment- ing with a variety of solutions in different settings without imposing a single uniform national standard. Even beyond issues of civil rights and liberties, ex- perimentation seems a necessity when confronted with such issues as balancing legislative and executive control over bureaucracy or how to achieve equity in educational finance.

In addition, an independent state constitutional law would foster diversity, one of the key values un- derlying federalism itself. One should not assume that uniformity in constitutional doctrine means bet- ter constitutional doctrine. Many contemporary con- stitutional issues admit of a variety of solutions, no one of which is necessarily better than another, only different.

Third, the development of an independent state constitutional law would reinforce the rolc of the states as polities. Earlier in this chapter, it was argucd that the principal role of the states in the American federal system is to make policy for their own citizens in keeping with their own needs and traditions. Con- stitutional policymaking, no less than legislative and executive policymaking in such fields as education, social welfare, and domestic relations, is an attribute of being a polity. This must not be taken to mean that the states are "sovereign," at least in the classic sense of that word. The American states exist within the framework of the Constitution of the United States, whose supremacy clause assures the superiority of constitutionally legitimate national laws. Neverthe- less, no matter how broadly we interpret the powers delegated to the national government, our constitu- tional bargain assures a considerable policymaking role for the states.

Finally, an independent state constitutional law can be supportive of democracy itself. Constitutions address the most fundamental political questions: what public policies are legitimate, how is political conflict managed and organized, and what are the

very purposes of the political community? In the American states, citizens write and approve constitu- tions, ratify amendments through direct participa- tion, and, in most slates, play a role in selecting or re- taining the judges who interpret the constitutions. These matters of constitutional choice are at the very heart of democra~y. Without vital state constitutions and constitutional development, American citizens would be denied any opportunity to participate in this most basic decisionmaking process.

The Organization of this Study This study is organized into four parts. Part I,

which includcs this chapter and the next, explores the role of state constitutions and constitutional law in the American fcdcrnl system and the contemporary opportunities for the development of an independ- ent state constitutional law. Part 11, which includes chapters 3 through 7, explores how state courts have addressed fundamental constitutional issues, includ- ing the organization of state government, civil rights and liberties, equality, criminal procedure, and prop- erty rights. Part 111, chapters 8 and 9, deals with how the development of an independent state constitu- tional law affects selected areas of public policy-in this case workmen's compensation and educational reform. Finally, Part IV, chapter 10, presents the conclusions of the study.

NOTES 1 For other overvicw treatments, see U.S. Advisory Com- mission on Intergovernmental Relations, State Constitic tional Law: Ca.ves and Materials (Washington, DC: ACIR, M- 159, October 1988), and The Question of State Goven~nient (b-lxzbility (Washington, DC: ACIR, A-98, January 1985) pp. 27-63; John Kincaid, ed., "State Con- stitutions in ii Fcderiil Systcm," The Annals of the Ameri- can Acatietny of Political and Social Science 496 (March 1988): enlire issue; "Ncw I)cvelopments in State Consti- tutional Iaw," P~~blirls: 771e Jounial of Federalism 17 (Winter 1987): entire issue; and Bradley D. McGraw, ed., Developmeti~s in Stmte Constitutional Law (St. Paul: West Publishing Co., 1985).

2U.S. Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Rela- tions, Changing Public Attitudes on Governments and T a w , 1988 (Washington, DC: ACIR, S-17,1988), pp. 6-7 and 33-34.

3For a description of the writing and ratification of the Massachusetts Constitution, see Paul C. Reardon, "The Massachusetts Constitution Marks a Milestone," Publius: The Jounral of Federalism 12 (Winter 1982): 45-56. For fuller treatment, see Ronald M. Peters, The Massachusetts Cor~stitution of 1780: A Social Compact (Amhcrsl: University of MassachusettsPress, 1979). The Massachusetts Constitution of 1780 now has 117 amend- ments.

4For a complcte chronology of state constitution writing, see Albert I,. Sturm, "The Development of American State Chnstitutions." Publius: The Journal of Federalism 12 (Wmler 1982): 57-98.

5Sce the comparisons drawn by James Madison and Alexander F-l am llton in Federalist 650 and Federalist f85, in Jacob E. Cookc, ed., The Federalist (Middletown, Con-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 13

necticut: Wesleyan University Press, 1961), pp. 343-347 and 587-595.

6Donald S. Lutz, "The Purposes of American State Con- stitutions," Publius: The Jounlalof Federalism 12 (Winter 1982): 27-44. See also the same author's "The United Statesconstitution as an Incomplete Text,"Anr~alsoftl~e American Academy of Political and Social Science 496 (March 1988): 23-32.

7For a discussion of the American states as "polities," see Daniel J. Elazar and Stephen Schechter, The Role of the Statesas Polities in the American Federal System (Philadel- phia: Center for the Study of Federalism, 1982), esp. pp. 4-19.

8For a discussion of Indian federalism, see D. D. Basu. In- troduction to the Constitiition of India (New Delhi: Pren- t i e Hall of India Private Ltd., 1985).

gFor a discussion of the relationship between national and state constitutional law in Brazil, see Antonio Rulli, Jr., "Federal and State Law in the Brazilian Fcdcral Sys- tem," paper presented at the meeting of the Compara- tive Federalism Research Group, Philadelphia, PA, 1987.

1°Constitution of the United Statcs, Articlc I. Section 10. l1 For a good discussion of this "umpiring function, see

John R. Schmidhauser, The Suprenze Corrrtas Fina1Arl)i- ter of Federal-State Relations (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1958).

12" . . . nor shall private property be taken for public use without just compensation." Amendment V.

13". . . nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the Laws." Amendment XIV.

14"No state shall pass any 'Law impairing the Obligation of Contracts. . . .' " Article I, Section 10.

15"The Citizens of each State shall be entitled to all Privi- leges and Immunities of Citizens in the several States." Article IV, Section 2.

18Congress shall have the power "To regulate Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the Indian Tribes." Article I, Section 8. As early as 1851, the U.S. Supreme Court held that under certain circumstances, this power is exclusive with Congress and, even in the absence of national law, state regulation may still be prohibited, but under other circumstances, state regulation is permissible-giving rise to what has been called "the dormant power of the commerce clause." See Cooley v. Board of Wardens, 53 U.S. 299 (1851). See also Southern Pacific Company v. Arizona, 325 IJ.S. 761 (1945), and Bibb v. Navajo Freight Lines, 359 US. 520 (1959).

17"No State shall, without the Consent of Congrcss, lay any Impost or Duty on Imports or Exports, except where may be absolutely necessary for executing its inspection laws. . . ." Article I, Section 10.

18Beginningwith West Coast Hotel v. Panish, 300 U.S. 399 (1937), the Supreme Court reversed a long string of precedents and began to reject constitutional objections to state economic regulation based on the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. The situation with regard to claims brought under the equal protection clause is somewhat more complicated. For discussion of the latter issue, see Railway Express Agency v. New York, 336 U.S. 106 (1949), and Morey v. Doud, 354 US. 457 (1957).

1gSec Loretto v. Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp., 458 US. 419 (1982), and Nollan v. California Coastal Commission, 107 S.Ct. 3141 (1987). See also Lee P. Symons, "Property Rights and Land Use Regulation: First English and Nollan," Pirblius: Tlze Journal of Fedeml- ism 18 (Summer 1988): 81-96.

20See Southern Pacific Company v. Arizona. 21 See Philadelphia v. New Jersey, 437 U.S. 617 (1978), for

example. 221t was on this point that the U.S. Supreme Court ulti-

mately decidcd the case of Gibbons v. Ogden, 22 US. 1 (1824).

23For two attempts to articulate such standards, see Hines v. Davidowitz, 312 U.S. 52 (1941), and Pennsylvania v. Nelson, 350 1J.S. 497 (1957). See chapter 2 of this report for a fuller treatment.

24See his dissenting opinion in City of Burbank v. Lockheed Air 'I'crminal, Inc., 411 U.S. 624 (1973). See also Puerto Kico Department of Consumer Affairs v. Isla Petrolcum Corporation, 56 U.S.L.W. 4307 (1988).

25See, for examplc. Cartcr v. Carter Coal Company, 298 U.S. 238 (1936).

26National Imguc of Cities v. Usery, 426 U.S. 833 (1976). But see also Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority, 105 S.Ct. 1005 (1985), reversing Usery.

z7Indeed, this was the precise argument of the majority in Garcia.

28This was reaffirmed in Barron v. Baltimore, 32 U.S. 243 (1833).

29One of the earliest cases raising the issue of the impact of the Fourteenth Amendment on the Bill of Rights was the Slaughter House Cases, 83 U.S. 36 (1873). See also Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U.S. 78 (1908), Palko v. Con- necticut, 302 U.S. 3 19 (1937), and especially Adamson v. California, 332 U.S. 46 (1947).

3OGitlow v. New York, 268 US. 652 (1925), in which the Supreme Court "incorporated" freedom of speech among the "liberties" protected by the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

31 See, for example, Camara v. Municipal Court, 387 U.S. 523 (1967). Chime1 v. California, 395 U.S. 752 (1969), Katzv. Unitccl States, 389 US. 347 (1967) and Mirandav. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966).

32Lau v. Nlchols, 414 U.S. 563 (1974). 33See, for example, New York Association for Retarded

Children v. liockcfeller, 356 F.Supp. 752 (1973). 34Holt V. Sarver, 505 F.2d 194 (1974), for example. Also, see

generally, Ellis Katz, "Prisoners' Rights, States' Rights and the I3ayh-Kastenmeier Institutions Bill," Publiiis: Tlze Joirn1al ofl.'ederalism 8 (Winter 1977): 179-198.

35Griswoltl v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965). 36Brown v. Board o f Education, 349 US. 294 (1954). 37Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186 (1962). 38Reed v. Reed, 404 U.S. 71 (1971), for example. 39Douglas v. California, 372 U.S. 353 (1963). 40See Clifford M. Lytle, The Warren Court and Its Critics

(Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1968). 4lThis is one of the principal arguments of John Ely, De-

mocracy and Distnat: A Theory of Jlrdicial Review (Cambridge: Haward University Press, 1980).

42See Malcolm E. Jewell and David M. Olson, American State Political Partics arid Elections (Homewood, Illinois: The Dorsey Press, 1982).

14 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

43See Malcolm E. Jewell, Representation in State Legisla- tures (Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1982).

44See Lany Sabato, Goodbye to Good-Time Charlie: The American Goven~orsl~ip Tmnsfom~ed (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 1983).

45See Mavis Mann Reeves, "Look Again at State Capac- ity," in Robert J. Digler, ed., American Intergoven~mental Relations Today (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Pren- tice-Hall, 1986), pp. 143-159, esp. 153-154.

46See Lany Berkson and Susan Carlton, Court Unification: Histoiy, Politics and Imp~ementation (Washington, DC: Government Printing Office, 1978).

47See Charles Press and Kenneth VerBurg, State and Community Govenlments in the Federal Sy.vtem (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1983), pp. 455-494.

48"Etemally Vigilant" is the motto of the American Civil Liberties Union.

49See New York Times v. Jascalcvich, 439 U.S. 1301 (1978). 50See Widman v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263 (1981). 51The classic discussion is still Louis D. Brandeis, "The

Right to Privacy," Harvard Law Review 4 (1890). See also the discussion in William Cohen and John Kaplan, Con- stitutional Law: Civil Liberty and Individual Rights Pineola, New York: The Foundation Press, 1982), pp. 181-193.

52See Thomas Y. Davies, "A Hard Look at What We Know (and Still Need to Learn) about the 'Costs' of the Exclusionary Rule," American Bar Fozrndation Research Journal (1983): 611-690.

53See Ellis Katz, "Prisoners' Rights, States' Rights." 54See City of Los Angeles v. Manhart, 435 U.S. 202(1978),

for example. 55Millerv. California, 413 U.S.15 (1973), although the US.

Supreme Court seems to have retreated from this posi- tion.

%ee, for example, Stone v. Powell, 428 U.S. 465 (1976). 57See Michigan v. Long, 463 US. 1032 (1983). 58In fact, there is some evidence that state supreme courts

may be just as vigilant about protecting individual liber- ties as is the U.S. Supreme Court. See Craig R. Ducat, Mike1 L. Wyckoff and Victor E. Flango, "Can State Judges Be Trusted to Defend Federal Constitutional Rights?" Paper delivered at the 1988 Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Washing- ton, DC.

59For a fascinating typology of state constitutional tradi- tions, see Daniel J. Elazar, "Principles and Traditions

Underlying State Constitutions," Publius: The Jounlalof Federalism 12 (Winter 1982): 11-26.

"Albert L. Sturm, '"The Development of American State Constitutions." But Sturm does not include the Con- necticut and Khtxle Island charters as constitutions, and his survey was completed before the adoption of the Georgia Constitution of 1982. Therefore, the correct number might be 148 rather than 145. See also the infor- mation regularly provided by the Council of State Gov- ernments in its annual Rook of the States.

e1 Book of he States, 1988-89 (Lexington, KY: Council of State Govcrnmcnts, 1988), p. 18.

"See, for cxiiniple, John J. Harrigan, Politics and Policy in Statesand Cntnmr~ni/ie.s (Ihston: Little Brown and Com- pany, 1984), csp. pp. 19-34.

"SCC G. Alan 'I'arr, "Rcligion under State Constitutions," Annals of thc A~mvican Academy of Political and Social Science 496 (March 1988): 65-75.

e4For exan~ple, Article I, Scction 5 of the Michigan Consti- tution provides: "Ehery person may freely speak, write, express, and publish his views on all subjects, being re- sponsible for the abuse of that right. . . ."

65For example, the Pennsylvania Constitution provides: "The General Assembly shall provide for the mainte- nance and support of a thorough and efficient system of public education to serve the needs of the Common- wealth." (Article 111, Section 14); "The people have a right to clean air, pure water, and to the preservation of the natural, scenic, historic and esthetic values of the en- vironment. . . ." (Article I, Section 27); and "Equality of rights undcr thc law shall not be denied or abridged in the Commonweallh because of the sex of the individ- ual." (Article I, Section 28).

66Constitution of the Unitcd States, Article VI, Section 2. e7Constitution of Pennsylvania, Article VI, Section 3. 68C~nsti tuti~n of the United States, Article VI, Section 2. 69Unfortunately, this is an area that is not studied ade-

quately. But sce David B. Rabban, "The First Amend- ment in its Forgotten Years," Yale Law Journal 90 (Janu- ary 1981): 514-595, and Edward S. Corwin, Liberty against Govenrment (13aton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1948).

701n fact, the process may have worked just the other way, with federal judgcs borrowing the concept of substantive due process from state constitutional developments. It may be that the concept was first articulated in New York in Wynehamer v. People, 13 N.Y. 378 (1856). See Corwin, Liberty against Government. . . .

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 15

16 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 2

Powers of and Restraints on "Our Federalism":

State Authority under the Federal Constitution

In 1971, Justice Hugo Black wrote of "Our Fed- eralism" as "a system in which there is sensitivity to the legitimate interests of both State and National Governments, and in which the National Govern- ment, anxious though it may be to vindicate and pro- tect federal rights and federal interests, always en- deavors to do so in ways that will not unduly interfere with the legitimate activities of the States."l In 1971, however, it was not yet clear that the U.S. Supreme Court had consecrated a new era of greater, though still bounded, federal constitutional support for state regulatory powers. During the past one-and-one-half decades, the U.S. Supreme Court has recast the na- tion's image of the U.S. Constitution and has rede- fined its own authority to interpret the Constitution. These developments should have special meaning for state governments. From the federal judiciary's rec- ognition of constitutionally expansive federal admin- istrative authority in 19372 to the late 1970s, the fed- eral constitutional landscape was not as hospitable to state exercises of broad police and economic regula- tory powers as it is today with the Supreme Court's new solicitude for "Our Federalism."

"Our Federalism" has operated on several fronts in federal constitutional doctrinc. The Burger Court substantially tempered the activist role that the War- ren Court had asserted in expanding individual rights guarantees. In turn, the Rehnquist Court has mar- ginalized the force and reversed the momentum of Warren Court precedents in many areas,3 including criminal procedure,4 constitutional privacy,= and Fourteenth Amendment state action6 and equal pro- tection doctrine^.^ At the same time, the Court has acknowledged the potential for independent state protection of individual liberties under state constitu- tional, statutory, and common law.8 Additionally, al-

though a narrow majority of the Burger Court re- fused to cont i n ~ to enforce substantive restraints on Congress' conirncrce powcrs in the interests of state governmcnts,g the Court may be willing to scrutinize the congressional procedures for enacting commerce legislation that directly burdens the states.10 More- over, the Supreme Court has limited the access of in- dividual rights plaintiffs to the federal courts, in part by strengthening the procedural barriers of stand- ing" and by broadening constitutional preferences for state court powers in the doctrines of adequate and independent state law grounds, state sovereign immunity, abstention, and equitable restraint.12

The Supreme Court's heightened sensitivity to "Our Federalism" yields much ground for activism to states in the development of their own constitutional law. To some extent, state courts have responded to the clarion call for leadership in the field of individual rights protection.13 Yet, vast territories of state con- stitutional law remain to be explored by state legisla- tures, in thcir cconomic and civil liberties policymak- ing, and by statc courts, in their interpretation of the mandates of their own constitutions.l4 Particular op- portunities-and the nature and scope of state authority to exploit thcm-will be examined in the following chapters of this book.

This chaptcr scrves mcrely to sound a warning. In the stir of a much warranted enthusiasm for state constitutional law development, it must be remem- bered that "Our Federalism" embodies restraints on state authority as well as powers. Inherent in coop- erative federalism is an expectation that the federal Constitution will furnish a "floor of security" for the interests of lifc, liberty, and property below which the states cannot fall in ordering their policy priorities through state law. including state constitutional law.

Advisory Commission on intergovernmental Relations 17

Generous as the U.S. Supreme Court has been of late in sanctioning the independent evolution of state constitutional law, its recent construction of several federal constitutional doctrines has not been wholly congruent with this attitude. Sound leadership of the state constitutional law movement depends on care- ful study of the ambiguities in these federal doctrines, which may limit all branches of state government in their lawmaking authority, or affect only the state ju- diciary in its authority to declare state constitutional law.

Brief analyses of the most relevant of these doc- trines follow.15 The first section examines the con- tours of major federal constitutional doctrines that channel the economic and police powers of statc leg- islatures, executives, administrative agencies, and courts. In order of treatment, they include the pre- emption doctrine, the dormant commerce clause doctrine, and the takings clause, and economic due process and equal protection doctrines. The second section describes federal constitutional boundaries on the authority of state courts to interpret state law, including state constitutional law. They involve the adequate and independent state grounds doctrine, and various abstention and equitable restraint doc- trines.16

Restraints on State Economic and Police Regulation

Preemption Doctrine

The preemption doctrine is rooted in the su- premacy clause of the US. Constitution.17 Because federal law is supreme within the realm of its consti- tutional authority, state law that interferes with the operation of federal law or that intrudes in the realm of federal law can be invalidated by the courts. The supremacy clause is the basis on which the federal and state legislatures and judiciaries delineate the spheres of regulatory power that are delegated exclu- sively to the federal government and those spheres of concurrent and supplementary federal and state gov- ernmental activity. Accordingly, the preemption doc- trine is one of the primary constitutional vehicles by which the Constitution defines the profile of "Our Federalism."

The preemption doctrine identifies two general grounds on which federal law can preempt state law, including state constitutional law. First, Congress may preempt an entire regulatory area within its con- stitutional authority and prevent state involvement, regardless of the compatibility of state activity with federal rules and objectives, by establishing its deci- sion to "occupy the field." Second, even where Con- gress has not displaced state activity in a field of regu- lation entirely, state law that is in "actual conflict" with federal law may be preempted.

In using the first ground, the judiciary examines a federal statute to determine whether Congress "in- tended" to occupy the regulatory field. Of course, ex- plicit statutory language may define the extent to which the enactment preempts state law.l8 Even in the absence of such language, however, an intent to occupy the field may be inferred where a scheme of federal regulation is so pervasive as to preclude sup- plementation by the states,lg or where the area is tra- ditionally left to federal control.20

Thejudiciary may find state regulation in "actual conflict" with federal law on a number of bases. Pre- emption most likcly occurs when federal and state laws give rise to conflicting obligations, thus making it impossible for thosc who are subject to regulation to comply with both federal and state rules.21 Even when federal and state laws are not contradictory on their face, a statc regulation may be invalidated if it conflicts with 1 he aims of federal law, and is, thereby, an obstacle to the accomplishment of the full pur- poses and objectives of Congress.22

These standards have not been applied in a uni- form and consistent manner over time. Indeed, in any particular era, the Supreme Court's approach under the preemption doctrine appears to reinforce what- ever theory of federal-state relations holds sway in constitutional interpretation at the time of a deci- ion.^^ Whereas the Court's earlier views of federal- ism were bolstered l y a presumption of federal pree- mption in any subject area regulated by Congress,24 the current judicial view of "cooperative federal- ism"25 may be driving the Court's recent preemption decisions. Since 1973,26 the preemption doctrine has embodied a state-protective presumption: the tradi- tional economic and police powers of the states will not be superscdcd by federal law unless Congress clearly and manifestly establishes its intent to preempt slate law.27

This presumption is evident in both grounds of the preemption doctrine. Federal "occupation of the field" will not likcly bc implicd merely from the exis- tence of a I'cdcral regulatory scheme.28 Rather, fed- eral exclusivity may depend on a clear statement, found in the text or legislative history of a congres- sional enactment, of the national objective to preempt all state regulations of the subject area.29 In the absence of such an express provision, the parame- ters of federal exclusivity may be limited to those dis- crete aspects of an industry that are extensively and comprehensively regulated in the federal s t a t~ te .3~ Similarly, the second ground of "actual conflict" ap- pears to be restricted to cases in which compliance with both statc and federal regulations is a physical impossibility31 (or an "imminent irnpo~sibility"~~), and in which the state regulation directly and sub- stantially frustratcs the purposes of federal law.33

18 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Thus, the current preemption doctrinc gcneral ly accommodates more expansive police and economic regulatory authority in state governments, evcn in subject areas affected by federal law. In summary, the probability that a state constitutional grant of author- ity to state and local governments or the police, and economic measures enacted or enforced under such a grant, will be preempted by federal law decreases with the aggregate of the following variables: the state constitutional grant or administrative measure (1) regulates a subject matter traditionally left to the states, (2) has historic police power objectives con- cerning health, safety, or morals, (3) has objectives that are compatible with or supplemental to the pur- poses for any federal regulation in the subject area, (4) is in a subject area that has not been preempted explicitly by federal law, and (5) affects dimensions of an activity that have not been regulated comprehen- sively by federal law.

Dormant Commerce Clause Doctrine

Federal constitutional powers that lie "dormant" are those that have been granted to the fcdcral gov- ernment but are not currently bcing used. Even in the absence of federal regulation that could preempt the operation of state law, dormant constitutional pow- ers might be enforced by the judiciary to limit state authority. Only one constitutional grant of federal power has given rise to substantial litigation under the concept of dormant powers-the commerce clause.34 The Supreme Court has interpreted the constitutional grant of congressional commerce power to imply corollary restraints on state authority to regulate certain interstate economic transactions that Congress has not attempted to control.35

The dormant commerce clause doctrine essen- tially furthers the federal interest in the national free trade unit: it prevents the states from erecting barri- ers to the movement of goods and services across state lines.36 By challenging state regulations that aim to protect local markets and industries from in- terstate competition, the doctrine curbs sister-state retaliation and economic balkanization.37 On the assumption that congressional "silence" in the face of parochial state legislation does not amount to fed- eral approval of local economic protectionism,36 the judiciary stands in the stead of Congress to keep the channels of interstate commerce free of state- created obstacles.39

The Supreme Court has developed three calego- ries of analysis in dormant commerce clause litiga- tion. First, state economic regulation is suspect if it discriminates against interstate commerce. A scheme is likely to be characterized as discriminatory if, on its face, it treats out-of-state competitors differently than in-state enterprises by imposing greater eco- nomic burdens on the out-of-state interests;40 even a

facially ncutral schcmc may be suspect if, in itsopera- tion, it so sul~stnnti:~lly and disproportionately disfa- vors out-of-state interests as to evidence a clear state purpose to discriminate against interstate com- merce.41 Once idcntified as discriminatory, a state economic regulation typically will be invalidated, un- less the state can demonstrate that the scheme was designed to serve a legitimate purpose other than protection of the economic interests of its own resi- dents, such as the promotion of a significant local safety or health objective.@ Even if the state law pro- motes a non-protcctionist purpose, differing treat- ment for out-of-state goods and ventures must be jus- tified for some reason apart from their state of origin.43 In all probability, a state economic regula- tion found to discriminate against interstate com- merce will run afoul of the commerce clause.44

Although a particular measure may not be dis- criminatory when viewed in isolation because it treats in-state and out-of-state enterprises in an even- handed manner, it may nonetheless adversely affect only the economic interests of multistate businesses when considered in the aggregate of all applicable state regulations that thc businesses must observe. Accordingly, the second category of dormant com- merce clause cascs restrains state economic schemes that subject interstate commercial activities to con- flicting or inconsistent rcgulationsfrom state to state. In such cases, of course, a state regulation favors lo- calized commerce by imposing cumulative burdens on national enterprises. Typically, the judiciary re- quires either a showing of actual conflict among state regulations45 or of direct regulation of extraterrito- rial trade46 to invalidate a state economic regulation on this basis.

The third category of analysis evaluates whether a state rule that is neither discriminatory nor incon- sistent with sistcr-state schemes places economic burdens on interstate commerce that clearly exceed the local bencfits obtained. Under this "balancing" approach, the judiciary assesses the nature and the significance of the state's regulatory interests ascom- pared to the extent of the monetary burdens and eco- nomic inefficiencies imposed on interstate commer- cial transa~tions.~' 'The continuing viability of this approach for enforcement of the commerce clause is in some doubt. 01' late, a significant minority of the Supreme Court ]ins opposed the balancing approach, arguing that the judiciary is institutionally incompe- tent to weigh thc relative benefits and burdens of state econonlic rcgulati0ns.~6 In this regard, judicial skepticism is supported by theoretical arguments that dormant commerce clause analysis requires courts to operate in a quasi-legislative capacity that is explicitly disavowed in other constitutional areas.49

In the last decade, a major "loophole" in dor- mant commerce clause restraints has amplified the

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 19

federal constitutional authority of state governments to favor local economic interests. The "market par- ticipant" exception allows the states to burden inter- state commerce-indeed, to discriminate against out-of-state business concerns in an open and overt manner-provided the state itself has "entered the market" by subsidizing private businesses50 or by op- erating a business as a proprietor.51 The analytic dis- tinction between the state as a "market participant" (i.e., when state activities will not be subject to dor- mant commerce clause restrictions) and the state as a "market regulator" (i.e., when state activities will be amenable to doctrinal restrictions) is not a bright line, however. Should a state exploit its economic clout to discriminate against commercial transactions occur- ring beyond its territorial jurisdiction and outside of the particular market in which it is contracting, its be- havior may be deemed "downstream regulation" rather than market participation.52

Consistent with the state-protective presump- tion in the contemporary preemption doctrine, the current doctrine of the dormant commerce clause promises a broad range of state governmental discre- tion in economic regulation when Congress has not acted to control the field of interstate commerce. Even if the Supreme Court does not totally abandon the balancing approach in dormant commerce clause analysis, its increased deference to state governmen- tal rulemaking in the commercial realm enhances the opportunities for innovative state economic policy under state constitutional and statutory law. In gen- eral, a state constitutional grant of economic regula- tory powers, or a state constitutional restraint on public and private economic transactions, or any leg- islative or administrative measure implementing such powers is likely to survive challenge despite its effects on interstate commerce, provided: (1) it is de- signed to promote traditional police power objec- tives, such as health or safety, rather than the busi- ness interests of its own residents; (2) it treats out-of-state and in-state economic entities even- handedly; and (3) it does not vary from national stan- dards to such an extent that it imposes conflicting ob- ligations or cumulative burdens on multistate businesses.

Takings Clause Doctrine

The Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments of the federal Constitution limit the governmental power of eminent domain9 government may "take" private property, but only for a "public use"; even then, the taking must be accompanied by "just compensation." By conditioning the power of eminent domain on both the demonstration of a public purpose and the government's willingness to pay, the takings clause theoretically promotes several objectives: an expen- diture of public monies should secure a public gain,

and not merely benefit a politically powerful interest group;" moreover, a public good should not be ex- torted from any discrete and identifiable individuals, but financed by the public at large.55

As the Supreme Court has interpreted the tak- ings clause, the legitimacy of a state's exercise of emi- nent domain can be challenged on four grounds: first, the state has "taken" the property, rather than merely regulated its use by private owners and opera- tors; second, the state cannot establish that the prop- erty was taken for a "public use"; third, the state can- not demonstrate that the taking is sufficiently related to the public purpose to be justifiable; fourth, the state has not provided adequate compensation, whether in cash or in kind. As to most of these issues, the takings clause doctrine is both unsettled and opaque.56 Recent dcvclopments in the takings clause, which may have particular impact on state land-use regulation. highlight the importance of un- raveling its tanglctl doctrincs, however.

The first question-whether the state has "taken" or mcrely "regulated" private property-is crucial, for only in the case of a "taking" is the govern- ment required to pay compensation for controlling or burdening the private uses of property. The border between a "taking" and a "regulation" of private property is not marked by any bright and definitive line; nevertheless, it is possible to identify polar posi- tions and characteristic attributes in light of which a state activity can be deemed a "taking" or a "regula- tion."

The classic case of a "taking" is the state's perma- nent and physical occupation of private property.57 Without regard to the importance of the public inter- ests served, or to the severity of the imposition on the landowner's usual and expected functions, a state's permanent trespass and appropriation of property is virtually certain to be found a "taking."58 In opposi- tion, the classic case of a "regulation" of private prop- erty is thc statc's prohibition of a noxious use or nui- sance.59 Of coursc, when the state banishes or controls a “harmful" use of private property, it may be favoring an alternative private use to which sur- rounding property had been or will be committed; traditional police powers have been stretched con- ceptually to include regulatory zoning that benefits a conforming private use, even when the nonconform- ing use was not recognized as a public or private nui- sance at common law.eO

Apart from these polar cases of physical occupa- tion and noxious use, the distinction between a "tak- ing" and a "regulation" has been made on a case-by- case basis,@l with the Supreme Court viewing several variables as relcvanl. Among them, diminution in the value of property, dcstruction of investment-backed expectations, and reciprocity of benefits figure prominently in Supreme Court precedents. The

20 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

more substantial the reduction of the value of the pri- vate property, the more likely it is that a "taking" will be found.62 Similarly, the more severe the interfer- ence with expectations of a reasonable return on pri- vate investment, the more vulnerable a state regula- tion will be to invalidation for uncompensated losses.63 In contrast, when a state regulatory scheme provides a "reciprocity of advantage" by creating par- allel benefits and burdens for all interested parties (for example, in enhancing land value for an alterna- tive activity at the same time that it diminishes land value for the prohibited activity),64 it is less likely to work a compensable "taking."

Despite the judiciary's essentially ad hoc, factual inquiries in distinguishing "takings" and "regula- tions," it is possible to articulate generally the cir- cumstances (apart from the requirements for "public use" and "means-ends fit" to be discussed below) in which a state regulatory scheme may impose uncom- pensated losses without creating a "taking." The state regulation (1) should not impose a permanent and physical occupation of private property; (2) should not destroy any traditionally recognized attribute of the property rights; (3) should not substantially di- minish the commercial value of the property; (4) should not substantially frustrate expectations of a reasonable rate of return on investment; and (5) if at all possible, should secure some reciprocity of advan- tage for the burdened parties.

The second issue in takings clause challenges- whether the state has established a "public use" for the private property-is clearly the least problematic in case doctrine, if only because the Supreme Court has virtually abdicated any serious review of state regulation under this requirement. As early as 1905, the Supreme Court intimated that any use conducive to the public benefit was a "public use" justifying emi- nent domain, whether or not property was actually devoted to use by the public.65 With the erosion of the distinction between public and private purposes under the takings clause, the "just compensation" re- quirement has become the surrogate for an inde- pendent inquiry into the public purpose of a "taking" of private property." In its most recent articulation of the "public use" requirement for eminent domain, the Supreme Court acknowledged that the concept of "public use" is essentially "coterminous with the scope of a sovereign's police powers."67

In contrast, the third issue-whether the state can demonstrate an adequate "means-ends fit" (i.e., whether the statutory scheme is sufficiently related to the alleged public purposes)-lately has been res- urrected as a potential obstacle to uncompensated land-use regulations, and may prove to be an inde- pendent requirement in the future for exercises of eminent domain even when just compcnsation is pro- vided. A narrow majority of the Supreme Court re-

cently required a showing that the particular land-use regulation chosen by the state would closely and sub- stantially further the purposes or objectives for the regulatory schcme.e8 This "standard of precision," of course, far exceeds the burden of proof demanded of the state under the "public use" requirement in emi- nent domain or in review of state economic regula- tion under the due process clause.69 Whether the jus- tices will maintain their hcightened scrutiny of the means-ends fit, ol' course, remains to be seen.

The fourth issue-whether the state has pro- vided "just compcnsation" for a "taking9'-has as- sumed greater importance since the Supreme Court dramatically changcd thc constitutional doctrine of "inverse condcmnation"70 in 1987. After years of un- certainty over the remedial rights of property owners who establish a regulatory "taking,"71 the Supreme Court has declared that a government must compen- sate a property owner for whatever "temporary tak- ing" occurs between enactment and invalidation of an offending regulation, at least when the owner is de- nied "all use" of the property during that period.72 At this point, it is not clear how far-reaching the "tempo- rary takings" doctrine will prove to be. For example, will the damages remedy be limited to temporary de- nial of all ejIective use? What substantial time must pass before a "temporary taking" is likely to be found?73 To what damages will the property owner be entitled-consequential damages, loss of good wi11?74 Ambiguities notwithstanding, it is evident that the "temporary takings" doctrine will be critical for state and local land-use regulators: once the doctrine is extended to zoning cases, government will presumptively be liable for interim damages should land-use restrictions later be deemed compensable "taking~."7~ Moreover, the doctrine is likely to in- crease economic incentives for challenges to adminis- trative rulings that inhibit land development.76

Cloudy and uncertain as the takings clause doc- trine rightly appears, several of its elements have been revitalized. At the very least, this indicates the potential for a more stringent protection of private property rights under the federal Constitution that constrains a state's economic regulatory powers un- der its constitutional and statutory law. Such a signal is paralleled, as well, in the Fourteenth Amendment equal protection doctrine.

Economic Ilue Process and Equal Protection Doctrines

Fourteenth Amendment constraints on state economic regulation also exist under the due process and equal protection cla~ses.~7 Although earlier in this century thc Supreme Court regularly invalidated economic mcasurcs under these clauses,78 the Court's decisions since the late 1930s have demon- stratcd a virtuiil "hands-off'' approach in substantive

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 21

review of state economic regulation.79 Generally, the Court has enforced a rule of "mere rationality": a state or local regulation affecting private economic and social interests will not be stricken if there is any "rational relationship" between the regulatory scheme and a legitimate legislative objective, even a "conceivable" purpose that might have motivated the regulating body.80

In a striking departure from rationality rcvicw, the Supreme Court lately has examined much more carefully the legitimacy of state regulations that dis- criminate against the economic interests of out-of- state enterprises.81 A discriminatory measure en- acted only for the purpose of promoting domcslic business at the expense of out-of-state trade might not survive the Court's heightened standard of re- view.82 This development is remarkable for at least two reasons. First, if it leads to an increased judicial solicitude for private economic interest~,~3 the Court would be abandoning its post-1930s deference to po- litical decisionmaking in areas of socioeconomic pol- icy. Second, unlike its rulings under the dormant commerce clause, judicial enforcement of the equal protection clause would be binding on the Congress as well, restricting its authority under the commerce clause to permit parochial favoritism in state eco- nomic regulation.84 However uncertain the future of equal protection restraints on discriminatory eco- nomic legislation,85 it is apparent that a state regula- tion that disfavors out-of-state commercial ventures is vulnerable to attack, even with the approval of Congress, if it only furthers a "naked preference" for domestic industry.86

Authority for State Judicial Declaration of State Constitutional Law

Adequate and Independent State Grounds Doctrine

Unlike the constitutional provisions described above, which restrain all branches of state govern- ment in their exercise of police and economic regula- tory powers under state constitutions, the doctrines to be examined in this section focus primarily on the federal constitutional authority of the federal judici- ary. These doctrines restrain the federal judicial poweF in the interest of full and effective declara- tion of state law by state courts. Essentially, these doctrines recognize and endorse independent state judicial development of state law, including state constitutional law.

Clearly, the independent and adequate state grounds doctrine is the most important among them. This doctrine vrevents the U.S. Supreme Court from

does not rely conceptually and doctrinally on the fed- eral law ruling (i.e., "independence" of state ground), and when the state court's judgment would stand even after Supreme Court reversal of its federal law holding (i.e., "adequacy" of state ground), the judg- ment is immunized totally from appellate review by the Suprcrne Court.89

At least two ol)jcctives justify the Court's self- imposed restr;~inls on appellate jurisdiction under this doctrine. I:irsl, t he Suprcme Court should avoid unnccessary pronouncements on federal constitu- tional and statutory law. particularly if friction with state substantive policies or state judicial procedural rules might be avoided. Accordingly, the doctrine en- sures the necessity for, and the efficacy of, a federal court ruling on appeal that actually resolves a case or contro~ersy .~~ Second, the Supreme Court should manifest its respect for the state judiciary's role in de- veloping and applying state law, constitutional and nonconstitutional, substantive and procedural. Thus, the doctrine is a gauge of the strength of "Our Feder- alism."

The Supreme Court has invoked the doctrine in both procedural and substantive contexts. In the pro- cedural context, a state high court typically refuses to decide a fedcral law issue because the federal rights claimant has failed to comply with a requirement of state court procedure. In such a case, it is clear that the state procedural ground is "independent" of fed- eral law, and the Supreme Court's inquiry addresses the "adequacy" of the procedural rationale to bar consideration of the federal law claim.91 In the sub- stantive context, however, a state high court judg- mcnt may appcar to rely on both federal and state substiintivc law, and the Supreme Court's inquiry pri- marily ex~lores thc "independence" of the state law grouid:gidid the stale c o k understand state law as the basis for its judgment, or did it refer to state law merely as additional support and illustration of a de- cision controlled by federal law? Discussion will focus on the substantive applications of the doctrine, for it is in this context that the doctrine has evolved into a viable and powerful instrument of "Our Federalism."

For illustration, compare Case 1 and Case 2 in the following example:

Case 1: Astate high court holds that a state stat- ute violates both state and federal con- stitutional guarantees. In its considera- tion of the state law ground, the court finds that the state constitutional stan- dards violated by the statute are differ- ent from those under the federal Con- stitution.g3

reviewing a state high court judgment that ultimately Case 2: A st;~tc high court holds that a state rests on a determination of state law, even though the st;Wlc violatcs both state and federal state court may have erroneously dccidcd an issue of constiluticlncil guarantees. The court federal law.88 When resolution or the state ground rc;tsons that the state and fedcral provi-

22 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

trines, these rules generally apply when a fcdcral dis- trict court is asked to grant injunctive or declaratory relief to prevent alleged violations of federal consti- tutional rights by state executive, administrative or judicial officials in their enforcement of state law.103 In federal court actions against state and local gov- ernments, familiarity of governmental counsel with these rules will maximize the opportunities for state court adjudication of state constitutional law issues.

Pullman Abstention Doctrine. Where adjudica- tion of an unclear and unsettled question of state law would dispose of a substantial and sensitive federal constitutional question, a federal district court must temporarily abstain from exercising jurisdiction in or- der to give the state courts an opportunity to decide the state law issue.

The rule of Pullman abstention104 recognizes that federal courts should exercise their equitable powers so as to avoid the "waste" of an unnecessary and tentative decision on fcdcral constitutional grounds,lOs and to accord due respect for state adju- dication of ambiguous state law issues.106 Abstention is conditioned, however, on real uncertainty in the in- terpretation of a state law; generally, the federal court will not be confident that a bona fide dispute over the meaning or purpose of the state law c& be resolved by construing the text or by relying on defini- tive state court precedents. Even significant ambigu- ity will not trigger abstention, however, unless clarifi- cation of the state law may avoid the need for further consideration of the federal constitutional issue. No- tably, the Supreme Court has not yet required ab- stention in the face of a potential state constitutional challenge, although invalidation of the state law on this basis would clearly moot the federal constitu- tional question.lo7

Abstention in Diversity Actions. A federal dis- trict court may abstain from exercising diversity juris- diction to adjudicate an unclear and unsettled issue of state law where there is the potential for federal in- terference with the operation of state law in a sensi- tive area of state policy.

The Supreme Court has extended the abstention doctrine to federal diversity actions challenging state policies in significant public regulatory fields, such as eminent domain proceedings1°8 and management of essential state industries.109 In these instances, ab- stention often prevents federal intermeddling in the operation of complex and technical administrative schemes involving difficult questions of state 1aw.l l o

Federal district courts are not required to relinquish diversity jurisdiction, however, merely because poli- cies important to the domestic interests of a state are cha1lenged.l l

equitable action for declaratory judgment or injunc- tive relief challenging the federal constitutionality of a s tate law or an official act which is the subject of a pending judicial or administrative proceeding brought by the state against the federal plaintiff.

The Supreme Court's current solicitude for "Our Federalism" first congealed in the crucible of the equitable restraint doctrine.1l2 The intricate web of rules subsumed under this doctrine113 may pro- mote "comity" between federal and state co6rts in several ways. By refusing to intervene in state adjudi- cations in ordcr to explore a federal constitutional question, federal district courts do not disrupt the normal processes of the state judiciary, and do not foreclose their opportunities for independent devel- opment and enforcement of state substantive law,ll4 including state constitutional law. Furthermore, the federal district courts demonstrate confidence in the competence and good faith of the state judiciary to enforce the guaritntccs of the federal Constitu- tion.l15 Whether thc cquitablc restraint doctrine ef- fectively attains its purposcs,ll6 it symbolizes the dedication of contemporary fedcral constitutional law, in a numbcr ol' areas, to the maintenance of "Our Federalism."

Conclusion This overview of eight federal constitutional doc-

trines only sketches the outlines of the greater feder- alist design. At the same time that it restricts state ac- tion, American fcderalism recognizes broad state powers to ordcr public rights and private liberties in economic ventures and political and civil activities. In the efforts of statc government to strike a balance among competing public policy objectives, state con- stitutional law has a central role to play. The poten- tial for state constitutional involvemeni must be un- derstood and the extent of its authority enforced.

Understanding this potential is not, however, an effortless or risk-free task. As the prior discussion should illustrate, successfuI navigation of federal constitutional restraints requires careful study of the rocks and shoals on which the independent develop- ment of state conslitutional law might founder. Reli- ance on any broad-brushcd or abstract concept of in- herent statc sovereignty is unlikely to immunize state action from feclentl limitations. Only a precise identi- fication of the federal constitutional doctrines irnpli- cated by state regulations or judicial rulings, and a de- tailed analysis of the parameters within which state policymaking may safely operate, will ensure the vi- ability of the state constitutional law enterprise.

The warning of Justice Robert Jackson, written for an analysis of "inherent" presidential powers, takes on a differcnt and special meaning in the con-

Equitable Restraint Doctrine. A federal district text of the evolution of state constitutional law: "But court must refrain from exercising jurisdiction in an I have no illusion that any decision by this Court can

24 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

keep power in the hands of [state government] if it is not wise and timely in meeting its problems. . . .If not good law, there was worldly wisdom in the maxim at- tributed to Napoleon that 'The tools belong to the man who can use them.' "117 The federal judiciary has created opportunities for state foresight and assump- tion of responsibility. While nascent, the current movement to integrate state constitutions into the processes of state lawmaking signifies that the prom- ises of "Our Federalism" might be realized.

NOTES

Younger v. Harris, 401 U.S. 37,44-45 (1971). 21n federal constitutional history, the year 1937 is gener- ally regarded as the birthdate of a radical shift in federal judicial thought, which ratified the expansion of federal administrative authority over economic and police power affairs that formerly had fallen within the domain of state law. This movement in constitutional jurispru- dence originated with the Supreme Court's sanction of broad Congressional powers under the commerce clause. See, e.g., National Labor Relations Board v. Jones and Laughlin Steel Corp., 301 U.S. 1 (1937). For accounts of the post-1937 "revolution" in federal consti- tutional doctrine and theory, see Grant Gilmore, The Ages of American Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977); Laurence Tribe, American Constitutional Law (Mineola. New York: Foundation Press. 1988). DD. 297-316,378-3'97; David Skover, " 'Phoenix ~ i s i n ~ ; ' E d Federalism Analysis," Hastings Constittitional Law Quur- terly 13 (1986): 271,281-284.

3See Ronald Collins and David Skover, "The Future of Liberal Legal Scholarship: A Commentary," Micliignn Law Review 87 (October 1989): 1899-239.

4For example, the Burger Court created a "public safety" exception to the Fourth Amendment rules against jnvol- untary confessions in New York v. Quarles, 104 SCt. 2626 (1984), and a "good faith" exception to the exclu- sionary rule in United States v. Leon, 104 S.Ct 3405 (1984). Moreover, after many years in which federal habeas corpus had encompassed claims under the exclu- sionary rule, the Burger Court held in Stone v. Powell, 428 U.S. 465 (1976), that it would not be available to re- view search and seizure decisions reached after full con- sideration in state courts. Excellent analyses of the cur- tailing of constitutional rights for criminal defendants recognized by the Warren Court are provided in Leonard Levy, Against the Law: The Niron Court and Criminal Justice (New York: Harper and Row, 1974); Yale Kamisar, Police Interrogations and Co~lfessions (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1980).

=The right of privacy in sexual relations, recognized for married couples in Griswold v. Connecticut, 38 1 U.S. 479 (1965), and for unmarried heterosexuals in Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438 (1972), was not extended by the Rehnquist Court in Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986) to consenting adult homosexual activity in the pri- vacy of the home. Some scholars consider Bowers to sig- nal the demise of the current doctrine of privacy. See e.g., Daniel 0. Conkle, "The Second Death of Substan- tive Due Process," Indiana Law Jo1r17ml 62 (1987): 1585-94.

61n its notorious "shopping center" cases, the 13urgcr Court compromised the force of the "public function" rationale for the state action doctrine, which had been

used by the Warren Court to protect political speech ac- tivities. See Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551 (1972); Hudgens v. National Labor Railroad Board, 424 U.S. 507 (1976). Of course. this development set the stage for in- dependent slate protection of free speech under state constitutions. Scc chapter 4. In addition, the Rehnquist Court seriously undermined the potential for finding state action in a "symbiotic" economic relationship be- tween the state and a private party in San Francisco Arts and Athletics Inc. v. United States Olympic Committee, 107 S.Ct. 207 1 (1087). For an analysis of the potential un- der state constitutional law for rejecting the Fourteenth Amendment state action doctrine, see David Skover, "The Washington Constitutional 'State Action' Doc- trine: A Fundamental Right to State Action," University of Puget Sound Law Review 8 (1985): 221-82.

7The Burger Court has not materially broadened the categories of "suspect classes" or "fundamental rights," which are especially protected under the equal protec- tion clause, beyond those established by the Warren Court. In addition, the Court imposed a substantial bur- den on civil rights plaintiffs by requiring proof of inten- tional discrimination before an equal protection dis- crimination claim will be upheld. Washington v. Davis, 426 US. 229 (1976). Recently, the Rehnquist Court ex- tended this requirement to hold that a challenge of racial discrimination in a petit jury must be based on proof that the jury members acted with discriminatory purpose in the criminal defendant's own trial. McCleskey v. Kemp, 107 S.Ct. 1756 (1987). , ,

8Pruneyard Shopping Center v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74 (1980). Further discussion of the Pruneyard decision and its import for the evolution of free speech doctrine under state constitutions is found in chapler 4,

gGarcia v. Sat1 Antonio Mctropolitan Transit Authority, 105 S.Ct. 1005 ('1985) (no independent Tenth Amend- ment limitation on Congress' commerce powers), over- ruling National Izague of Cities v. Usery, 426 U.S. 833 (1965).

1°The Garcia decision stressed that judicial limitation of Congress' commerce powers in the interest of the states could be justified only by possible breakdowns in the structural or procedural restraints that protect the states within the national political processes. 105 S.Ct. at 1019-20. This emphasis on judicial review of the national political process invites the adoption of standards to en- sure adequate consideration and weighing of state inter- ests implicated in federal interstate commerce regula- tion. These standards might require a "clear statement" in legislative history that conscious and deliberate atten- tion was given tostate interests in striking the balance in favor of federal commerce regulation. In fact, the Court has already hinted at the viability of such standards for judicial review of federal commerce clause legislation in United States v. I3ass, 404 US. 336 (1971), and has im- posed a stringent "clear statement" rule in challenges to commerce clause legislation under the Eleventh Amendment. See, e.g., Atascadero State Hospital v. Scanlon, 105 S.Ct. 3142,3149-50 (1985). For discussion of judicial review of the national political process under the commerce cli~use. see Skover, " 'Phoenix Rising' and Fcdcralism Analysis."

l 1 Sce, e.g.. Vallcy 170rgc Christian College v. Americans Ilnilctl, 454 IJ.S. 404 (1982Xfcderal taxpayer standing); Allen v. Wright, 104 S.Ct 3315 (1984Xminority class standing).

Advisory Commission on lntergovemmental Relations 25

"For analysis and critique of reccnt dcvclcrpmcnts in thc Eleventh Amendment sovercign ininiunily doctrine, see, e.g., Akhil R. Amar, "Of Sovereignty and Fcder;~l- ism," Yale Law Journal 96 (1987): 1425, and Skovcr, " 'Phoenix Rising' and Federalism Analysis," pp. 298- 303.

13See generally Ronald Collins and Peter Galie, "Models of Post-Incorporation Judicial Review: 1985 Survey of State Constitutional Individual Rights Decisions," Publius: The Journal of Federalism 16 (Summer 1986): 111-140; Collins and Galie, "State Constitutional Cases and Commentaries," National Law Journal (Sept. 29, 1986): p. S 9, col. 2; Collins, Galie, and John Kincaid, "State High Courts, State Constitutions, and Individual Rights Litigation since 1980: A Judicial Survey," Publius: The Journal of Federalism 16 (Summer 1986): 141-163.

14See Collins and Skover, "The Future of Liberal Legal Scholarship," Parts IV-A and IV-B.

15This chapter's analysis of federal constitutional doc- trines often draws on the rulings in US. Supreme Court cases decided in the second half of the 20th century. Such a reliance neither implies that the federal Constitution means only what the Supreme Court interprets it topro- vide nor suggests that the political branchcs of the fcd- era1 government play no role in defining the scope of state power under the Constitution. Indeed, it is impnr- tant not to equate federal constitutional thought cxclu- sively with courts, or to neglect the impact of congres- sional and executive action on the constitutional process. See Collins and Skover, "The Future of Liberal Ixgal Scholarship" (stressing the need for legislative scholar- ship); William N. Eskridge and Phillip P. Frickey, "Legis- lation Scholarship and Pedagogy in the Post-Legal Pro- cess Era," Univemity of Pittsburgh Law Review 48 (1987): 691-73 1, 691,693,709-10,716-19,724-25); Ronald Col- lins and David Skover, "The Senator and the Constitu- tion: An Interview with Omn G. Hatch" (interview and annotations presenting a constitutional "profile" of Senator Hatch). Rather, this chapter's focus on jurispru- dence is a function of necessity. Two of the federal con- stitutional provisions discussed in the first section of the chavter-the suvremacy and commerce clauses-re- str& astate's la6makingunder its own constitution pri- marily by force of Supreme Court interpretations that either presume an absence of congressional action-in the case of the dormant commerce clause doctrine-or take congressional action as a fait accompli-as in the preemption doctrine. The remainder of the first section treats those federal guarantees of individual property rights-the takings clause and the due process and cqual protection clauses-that have been revitalized by rcccnt Supreme Court interpretations to place potentially se- vere constraints on a state's econoniic regulatory powers under its constitutional and statutory law. Finally, all of the doctrines described in the second section of the chapter concern the constitutional power of the federal courts vis-a-vis state judicial and political governmental actors, and derive from Supreme Court constructions of Article I11 of the U.S. Constitution and of congressional grants of jurisdiction.

'6This chapter presents only a partial vision of the re- straints under the U.S. constitution on state lawmaking, including state constitutional law development. Among individual rights and federalism doctrines that are not treated here-the specific limitations on state power in Art. I, 10 (particularly the commerce clause doctrine), the requirements of the privileges and immunities clause

of Art. IV, 2, thc: rcslriclions on state taxation of inter- state comnicrcc. t hc breadth of congressional spending power for the "gcneral welfare," the incorporation of the 1311 of Rights through the Fourteenth Amendment due process clause, the Fourteenth Amendment equal pro- tection clause, and the Art. I11 limits on federal court power (particularly the standing and political question doctrines)-all constrain state authority, to a greater or lesser degree, to regulate economic and sociopolitical in- terests under state constitutional and nonconstitutional law. Of course, even a cursory study of the full body of these doctrines is beyond the scope of this chapter. Three criteria distinguish the doctrines selected for re- view here. First, traditional federal constitutional con- structs for examination of federalism issues have been fashioned through these doctrines, particularly the pre- emvtion and dormant commerce clause doctrines. Sec- ond, several of these doctrines have been especially im- portant in the evolution of the state constitutional law movement, including preemption, independent and adequate state law grounds, abstention and equitable re- straint doctrines. 'Third, recent Supreme Court develop- ments in several of these doctrines, including the dor- mant commerce clause, takings clause and economic equal protection doctrines, have taken unanticipated turns, which may ;ill'cct significantly the exercise of tradi- tional state police powers. primarily with respect to busi- ness and land use rcgulation.

17Article VI, cl. 2 of the U.S. Constitution provides:

This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which sh;~ll bc niadc in Pursuance thereof; and all Treatics madc, or which shall be made, under the Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding.

lBSee, e.g., Jones v. Rath Packing Co., 430 U.S. 519,536-37 (1977) (state labelling regulation held expressly preempted by congressional prohibition of any labeling and packaging requirements in addition to those under federal statutes).

19See, e.g., City of Burbank v. Lockheed Air Terminal, 411 U.S. 624 (1973) (city ordinance regulating aircraft noise conflicted with purposes of Federal AemnarrticsAct to in- sure the efficient utilization of airspace); Amalgamated Association of Street, Electric Railway and Motor Coach Employees of America v. Lockridge, 403 U.S. 274, 296 (1971Xpervasivencss of federal regulation of labor rela- tions precluclcs state wrongful discharge actions requir- ing interpretation of labor contract's union security clause). 'The cxistcnce of a federal agency with broad regulatory powers in a particular subject area is relevant to the issuc of Congressional intent to preempt a field. Scc, e.g., ?'e:~n~stcrs Local 20 v. Morton, 377 U.S. 252 (1964Xstatt: rcstrict~ons on striking activities preempted by national lalnrr regulations). But a federal agency's ex- istence is not dispositive of the issue of federal occupa- tion, particularly when state regulation of an aspect of in- terstate commerce may concern itself with "local" matters. See, e.g., Pacific Gas and Electric Co. v. State Energy Resources Conservation and Development Commission. 461 U.S. 190 (1983) (California statute aimed at the cconomic problems of storing and dispos- ing of nuclear waste is not preempted by extensive fed- eral regulation of the nuclear power industry through the Nuclear Regulatory Commission).

26 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Z0Subject areas committed to congressional regulation un- der U.S. Constitution, Art. I, 8, such as bankruptcy, pat- ent and trademark, admiralty, and immigration, have been found regulatory fields of dominant federal interest in which state activity may be barred. See, e.g., Hines v. Davidowitz, 312 U.S. 52 (1941) (Pennsylvania's Alien Registration Act preempted by federal Alien Registration Act because regulation of aliens and foreign affairs is of primary national concern); Ramah Navajo School Board, Inc. v. Bureau of Revenue, 458 U.S. 832 (regula- tion of Indian educational institutions falls within an area of peculiarly federal interest).

21See, e.g., McDermott v. Wisconsin, 228 US. 115 (1913Xproper labelling of syrup for retail sale under Fed- eral Food and Drugs Act regulations would have violated state statutory requirements for labeling); Southland Corp. v. Keating, 465 U.S. 1 (1984) (California statute nullifying arbitration clauses in contracts in direct con- flict with Federal Arbitration Act).

22See, e.g., Nash v. Florida Industrial Commission 389 US. 235 (1967) (invalidated state unemployment compensa- tion law as applied to deny benefits to applicants bccause they had filed an unfair labor practice charge with the N.LR.B.); City of Burbank v. Lockheed Air Terminal, Inc. It is possible that judicial enforcement of the full pol- icy objectives underlying a congressional regulatory scheme will have the unantici~ated im~ac t of discourae- ingstate constitutional desigk that dhegate economyc and police powers to local governmental units. An inter- esting example of this phenomenon is found in Commu- nity Communications Co., Inc. v. City of Boulder, 455 U.S. 40 (1981), in which the television cable broadcasting regulations of a "home rule" municipality, granted ex- tensive powers of self-government by its state constitu- tion, were held to be subject to the restraints of federal antitrust legislation, as the municipality's economiccon- trols did not enjoy immunity under the "state action" ex- emption.

23For a description of theoretical stages in the Supreme Court's develo~ment of federalism doctrine. as viewed in the context of Congress' interstate commerce powers, see Skover, " 'Phoenix Rising' and Federalism Analysis," pp. 273-91. See also Tribe, American Constitutional Law; Scheiber, "Federalism (History)" and Elazar, "Federal- ism (Theory)," in Leonard W. Levy, Kenneth L Karst, and Dennis J. Mahoney, eds., Encyclopedia of theAmeri- can constihihrtion, Vol. 2 (New York: Macmillan Publish- ing Co., 1986), pp. 697-708 (hereinafter Encyclopedia).

z4Two eras of constitutional federalism-the pre-1930s and the period from 1940 to 1973-were characterized by Supreme Court solicitude for national intcrests under the preemption doctrine, but for different theoretical reasons. Prior to the 1930s. the Su~reme Court's "dual sovereignty" perspective, which Agidly differentiated federal and state spheres of uower, was fortified by apre- sumption of federal preemption in any field that theted- era1 government might constitutionally regulate and did in fact regulate. In contrast, during the Warren Court years, an expansive preemptive scope in any federal scheme that regulated a substantial industry solidified the jurisdiction of nascent federal administrative agen- cies, and secured the primacy of federal control in areas of traditional state economic and police regulation, in- cluding labor law, civil rights, welfare entitlements. and criminal law. For an excellent analysis of changes in the Supreme Court's preemption doctrines in tandem with the Court's evolving concepts of constitutional federal-

ism, see Note, "The Preemption Doctrine: Shifting Per- spectives on Federalism and the Burger Court," Colum- bia Law Review 75 (1975): 623 (surveying common directions in preemption decisions from the early 1900s to 1974).

ZSThe term "cooperative federalism" refers to the notion that national socioeconomic policy is the joint product of federal and state governmental regulation. The main features of cooperative federalism-overlapping of fed- eral and state spheres of economic and police powers, sharing of political responsibilities and financial re- sources, and interdependence of administration-are associated typically with federal grant-in-aid programs. See Edward S. Convin, Constitutional Revolution, Ltd. (Claremont, California: Pomona College, Scripps Col- lege, Claremont College. 1941); Scheiber, "Cooperative Federalism," in 2 lkcyclopedia, p. 503.

26The federal judiciary's contemporary approach in preemption-marked by a protective attitude toward state economic and police regulatory power-was ush- ered in by four Supreme Court decisions in 1973 and 1974: Goldstcin v. California, 412 US. 546 (1973Xstate prohibition of rcprtduction of misappropriated phono- graph records uphcld under narrow construction of Art. I, 8 copyright claust:): Ncw York State Department of So- cial Services v. Jhblino, 413 U.S. 405 (1973XNew York requirement that recipients of federal AFDC benefits accept employn~ent not preempted by federal welfare regulations); Kewanee Oil Co. v. Bicron Corp., 416 U.S. 470 (1974Xfederal patent law does not preempt state trade secret law); Merrill Lynch, Pierce, Fenner and Smith, Inc. v. Ware, 414 US. 117 (1973Xstate statutory directive prohibiting judicial enforcement of arbitration clauses in employee suits for collection of wages not preempted by a Se~vrities Exchange rule of arbitration of any controversy arising from employment termina- tion). The Burger Court's early change of direction in the presumptions underlying the Preemption Doctrine is discussed in Note, "The Preemption Doctrine," 639-51.

Z7In the Supreme Court's most recent preemption deci- sion to date, the Justices unanimously articulated this presumption as follows:

As we have repeatedly stated, "we start with the assumption that the historic police powers of the States were not to be superseded by the Federal Act unless that was the clear and manifest pur- pose of Congress."

Puerto Rico Department of Consumer Affairs v. Isla Pe- troleum Corporation, 56 U.S.L.W. 4307, 4308 (1988), quoting Hillsborough County v. Automated Medical Laboratories, Inc. 471 US. 707, 715 (1985) quoting Jones v. Rath Ikking Co., 525. The state-protective presumption for the constitutional preemption doctrine has been reinforced by recent guidelines For federal executive interpretation of legisla- tive policies that have federalism implications. President Ronald Reagan's Executive Order on Federalism re- quires executive departments and agencies to construe a federal statute to preempt state law only when the stat- ute contains an express preemption provision, when there is compelling evidence of congressional preempt- ive intent, orwhen the exercise of state authority directly conflicts with the exercise of federal authority under the federal statute. See Executive Order 12612, Federal Reg- ister, Vol. 52. No. 210. pp. 41685-688 (October 30, 1987).

28See, e.g., C.T.S. Corp. v. Dynamics C o p . of America, 107 S.Ct. 1637 (1987)Qndiana statute regulating take- overs not preempted by WilliantsAct that governs hostile

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 27

corporate stock tender offers); Wardair Canada, Inc. v. Florida Department of Revenue, 106 S.Ct 2369, 2372 (1986Xstate sales taxation of airline fuel not preempted despite the fact that "agencies charged by Congress with regulatory responsibility over foreign air travel exercise power. . . over licensing, route services, rates and fares, tariffs, safety, and other aspects of air travel"). If Con- gress terminates or substantially reduces regulation of a field, the federal judiciary is not likely to require an ex- press intent to retransfer regulatory authority to the states before finding that Congress has abandoned the field. See Puerto Rico Department of Consumer Affairs v. Isla Petroleum Corp., 4308 (congressional purpose to mandate a freemarket regime in the ficld of petrolcum allocation and pricing and to preempt all state regu lotion of the field cannot be implied merely from thc expiration of a former and comprehensive federal regulatory scheme).

29For example, in C.T.S. Corp., the Court noted that the Williams Act would preempt a variety of state corpora- tion laws authorizing staggered boards of directors and cumulative voting, if it were construed to invalidate any state statute that may limit or delay the free exercise of power after a successful tender offer. The Court re- sponded:

The long-standing prevalence of state regula- tion in this area suggests that, if Congress had in- tended to preempt all state laws that delay the acquisition of voting control following a tender offer, it would have said so explicitly.

30See, e.g., Schneidewind v. ANR Pipeline Co., 56 U.S.L.W. 4249 (1988) (Michigan statute controlling the approval of securities issues by public utilities which dis- tributed natural gas in the state preempted by the Naiu- ml Gas Act). The Court determined that the Michigan statute was designed to protect investors and ratepayers by ensuring "efficient and uninterrupted service at rea- sonable rates." The state's attempt to direct rate setting fell within the aegis of the Natural GasAct (NGA), which had conferred on the Federal Energy Regulatory Com- mission (FERC) exclusive jurisdiction over the rates and facilities of natural gas companies that engaged in the wholesaling of natural gas in interstate commerce. Al- though NGA had not expressly authorized FEKC to regulate the issuance of securities by natural gas compa- nies, the state's pre-issuance review of securities amounted to a regulation in the field of gas wholesales that Congress "had occupied to the exclusion of state law" by "a comprehensive scheme of federal regulation." The Court concluded:

In short, the things [the Michigan statute] is di- rected at . . . are precisely the things over which FERC has comprehensive authority. Of course, every state statute that has some indirect effect on rates and facilities of natural gas companies is not preempted. [The Michigan statute's] effect, however, is not "indirect." In this case we are presented with a state lawwhose central purpose is to regulate matters that Congress intended FERC to regulate. Not only is such regulation the function of the federal regulatory scheme, but the NGA has equipped FERC adequately to address the precise concerns [the Michigan stat- ute] purports to manage.

31 See, e.g., C.T.S. Corp., 1647 (no actual conflict requiring preemption of Indiana takeover regulation, since it is en- tirely possible for entities to comply with both the Intli- ana statute and the CVilliarnsAct; the Indiana slatutc pro-

vides for vesting of voting rights 50 days after commencement of an offer, within the 60-day maximum period Congress established for tender offers); Florida Lime and Avocado Growers v. Paul, 373 U.S. 132, 143 (1963) (California law which regulated the marketing of avocados sold in the state did not actually conflict with federal regulations of Florida avocado production, be- cause joint compliance was not impossible if Florida growers allowed the fruit to mature beyond the earliest picking date permitted by federal regulations).

32See, e.g., Schneidcwind, 4254 (preemption of Michigan natural gas rate regulation supported by the "imminent possibility of collision" bctwcen the state and federal laws, without a tlcn~onstration that the impossibility of dual compliance would I-K: an "inevitable consequence").

33In the absence or a finding that Congress has occupied the reaulatow ficltl, a state law which either serves iden- tical o~siniili~.ohjcctivcs as fcderal law, or furthers a tra- ditional statc purpose which is distinct, yet consonant with federal obiectives, is likely to be sustained as ''SUD- plementary"st~te action. see, e.g., C.T.S. Corp., 1645& (Indiana's protection of shareholders from coercive takeover offers furthers the federal policy of investor protection in the Williams Act); Silkwood v. Ken-McGee Corp., 464 U.S. 238 (1984) (traditional tort remedies, in- cluding compensatory and punitive damages, may be awarded to victims of radiation injuries from nuclear power plants without frustrating the federal purposes to occupy the entire field of nuclear safety concerns under the Atomic Ener~y Act; whatever compensation standard the state might impose, the nuclear licensee remains free to operate under the federal standards for construction and safety and to pay for any injury that results).

34Article I, 8, cl. 3 of the U.S. Constitution provides: [The Congress shall have Power] to regulate Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several States, and with the Indian Tribes.

35This analysis of dormant commerce clause doctrine does not examine the case law particular either to discrimina- tory and cumulatively burdensome state taxing schemes or to intergovernmental tax immunities. For useful dis- cussions of thcsc areas, see Paul J. Hartman, Federal Litnitations on Stirtc. and Local Taxation (Rochester, New York: Lawyers Ctroperative Publishing Co., 1981) 21-2:20,6:l-628; Jerome R. Hellerstein, State Taxation: Cotporatc. Inconw rind Franchise Tar RT. 1 (New York: Warren Gokham and Lamont 1983) Vol. I 4.1-4.16.

36For theoretical analyses of the designs and objectives of the dormant commerce clause doctrine, see, e.g., Earl Maltz, "How Much Regulation Is Too Much-An Ex- amination of Commerce Clause Jurisprudence," George Warlringtotl Law Review 50 (1981): 47 ("free location principle" in dormant commerce clause); Henry P. Monaghan, "Foreword: Constitutional Common Law," Hatvard Law Review 89 (1975): 1, (constitutional com- mon law doctrine based on national free trade philoso- phy); Donald H. Regan, "The Supreme Court and State Protectionism: Making Sense of the Dormant Com- merce Clause," Michigan Law Review 84 (1986): 1091 (primary purpose is prevention of purposeful economic protectionism); MarkV. Tushnet, "Rethinking the Dor- mant Commerce Clause," Wisconsin Law Review (1979): 125 (economic "efficiency" concerns).

37The classic slatcment of the purposes and functions of the Dormant Conimerce Clause Doctrine was articu- lated by Justice Robert Jackson in H. P. Hood and Sons, Inc. v. I>u MonJ, 336 lJ.S. 525,534-39 (1949):

28 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

While the Constitution vests in Congress the power to regulate commerce among the states, it does not say what the state may or may not do in the absence of congressional action. [This] Court has advanced the solidarity and prosperity of this Nation by the meaning it has given to these great silences of the Constitution. . . .[The] principle that our economic unit is the Nation, which alone has the gamut of powers necessary to control the economy, including the vital power of erecting customs barriers against for- eign competition, has as its corollary that the states are not separable economic units. . . . Our system, fostered by the Commerce Clause, is that every farmer and every craftsman shall be encouraged to produce by the certainty that he will have free access to every market in the Na- tion, that no home embargoes will withhold his exports, and no foreign state will by custom du- ties or regulations exclude them. Likewise, every consumer may look to the free competition from every producing area in the Nation to protect him from exploitation by any. Such was the vi- sion of the Founders; such has been the doctrine of this Court which has given it reality.

Woncurring in Duckworth v. Arkansas, 314 U.S. 390, 400 (1941), Justice Robert Jackson explaincd that con- gressional inertia in eliminating state obstructions to in- terstate commerce justified judicial activism under the dormant commerce clause doctrine:

[These] restraints are individually too petty, too diversified, and too local to get the attention of a Congress hard pressed with more urgent mat- ters. [The] sluggishness of government, the mul- titude of matters that clamor for attention, and the relative ease with which men are persuaded to postpone troublesome decisions, all make in- ertia one of the most decisive powers in deter- mining the course of our affairs and frequently give to the established order of things a longevity and vitality much beyond its merits.

In this regard, see also Ernest J. Brown, "The Opcn Economy: Mr. Justice Frankfurter and the Position of the Judiciary," Yale Law Journal 67 (1957): 219, 222 ("Nor has Congress been so idle that such matters could be assured a place on its agenda without competition from other business which might often be deemed more pressing"). Public choice theory may support the role of the judiciary in enforcement of the dormant commerce clause. If the benefits of economic parochialism are con- centrated within a small, easily organized group of state industries, invalidation of state protectionist legislation allocates the burden of overcoming congressional inertia on the interest group that has the most economic incen- tive to seek favorable federal regulation. See, e.g., James Q. Wilson, Tlze Politics of Regulation (New York: Basic Books, 1980), pp. 366-70 (need for a "watchdog" for the public interest in the case of "client politics"); Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods mid the Theory of Groups (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1965), pp. 1-3, 53-65, 125-31 (relatively small groups with concentrated economic interests are more frequently able to mobilize political power than rela- tively large, latent groups with dispersed economic inter- ests).

391n one important sense, judicial enforcement of the dor- mant commerce clause doctrinc against state cconomic regulation differs from constitutional decisions in other

contexts, such as enforcement of the commerce clause against congressional legislation or enforcement of the contract and takings clauses against state legislation. It must be remembered that the restraints of the dormant commerce clause operate in the "silence" of Congress. Coneress mav alwavs dis~lace dormant commerce clause decisons by &irm&tiveiy regulating, either to preempt state regulation of interstate commerce or to authorize state interference wilh interstate commerce. See, e.g., Prudential Insurance Co. v. Benjamin, 328 U.S. 408 (1946) (ICfcCb17utr-l;ergrrsott Act, reserving to the states the power to regulate insurance, allows for discrimina- tory taxes on prcmiums paid to out-of-state insurance firms).

%ee, e.g., City of Philadelphiav. New Jersey, 437 U.S. 617 (1978) (invalidating a New Jersey law which prohibited the importation of solid or liquid waste collected outside the territorial limits of the state); Hughes v. Oklahoma, 441 U.S. 322 (1979) (invalidating an Oklahoma law that barred the export of minnows taken from state waters).

41 See, e.g., Hunt v. Washington Apple Advertising Com- mission, 432 U.S. 333,349-51 (1977)(invalidating a North Carolina statute that prohibited closed containers of ap- ples shipped into or sold in the state to display any grade other than the applicable US. grade or standard). De- spite the evenhanded treatment of local and out-of-state producers on the face of the statute, because North Carolina had no grading requirements at all, the regula- tion exclusively burdened out-of-state producers with strict grading requirements. The Court attached sub- stantial weight to the fact that, by stripping Washington of the competitive advantages it had enjoyed through its rigorous inspection and grading system, the statute ap- peared to serve an intentionally discriminatory purpose.

42Sce, e.g., Maine v. 'Taylor, 106 S.Ct 2440 (1986)(Maine's total ban on the importation of live bait fish, supported by bona fide concerns for the health and safety of the slate's wild fish stock, sustained in the absence of reason- able non~lisc.~.imin;atory alternatives to the discrimina- tion against interstate commerce); Mintzv. Baldwin, 289 U.S. 346 (3933) (upheld New York law requiring all cattle importcd into the state for dairy or breeding purposes to be inspected for Bang's disease).

431n other terms, the state must demonstrate that out-of- state entities are the peculiar source of an evil which the state may legitimately aim to control. Contrast City of Philadelphia (New Jersey's legitimate environmental goals could have been met by a nondiscriminatory regu- lation of the amounts of waste deposited in the state's private landfills, regardless of their state of origin) with Maine v. Taylor (parasites and sea animals that might upset the ecological balance of Maine's unique fisheries were not native to Maine waters, and there existed no satisfactory way to inspect baitfish shipments to screen the harmful conditions).

44A solid majority of the Supreme Court recently affirmed the exacting nature of its review of discriminatory state economic regulation under the commerce clause in Brown-Forman Distillers Corp. v. New York State Liq- uor Authority. 106 S.Ct 2080,2084 (1986):

When a state statute directly regulates or dis- criminates against interstate commerce, or when its effcct is to favor in-state economic interests ovcr out-of-state interests, we have generally struck down the statute without fur- ther inquiry.

45See, e.g., I3ibh v. Navajo Freight lines, Inc., 359 US. 520 (1959) (invalidating Illinois' mudguard regulation as ap-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 29

plied to interstate trucking intlust~y, as the rcgul;ition varied from the uniform requircmcnts of other states without any evident safety advantage and actually con- flicted with the requirements of one state).

46See, e.g., Brown-Forman Distillers Corp. v. New York State Liquor Authority (invalidating New York price iif- firmation law, which required liquor distillers and pro- ducers selling liquor in New York to seek the permission of the liquor authority before lowering prices in other states, because it effectively gave the state agency the power to control prices beyond the state's borders); Edgar v. MITE Corp., 457 U.S. 624,644(1982)(invalidat- ing Illinois' takeover statute that regulated tender offers for multistate corporations if 10 percent of shareholders were state residents; criticizing the statute's extratenito- rial sweep, the majority held that a "state has no legiti- mate interest in protecting nonresident shareholders"); but, compare C.T.S. Corp. (sustaining Indiana's take- over statute regulating only the corporations that the state has chartered).

47The balancing approach in dormant commerce clause doctrine is associated with its most celebrated statement in Pike v. Bruce Church, Inc., 397 U.S. 137,142 (1970Xin- validating Arizona law requiring fruit grown within the state to be packed locally). See also Southern PacificCo. v. Arizona, 325 U.S. 761 (1945) (invalidating Arizona's restrictions on the lengths of railroad trains on the basis that whatever slight or marginal improvements to safety the regulation might accrue could not outweigh the great expense and delay that it imposed on railroad travel by deviating from nationally standard practices); Kassel v. Consolidated Freightways, 450 U.S. 662 (1981Xplurality opinion by J. Powell) (invalidating Iowa limits on the length of trucking "doubles" by balancing state's safety interest against the burden on interstate commerce).

48Among the most forceful opponents of balancing in dor- mant commerce clause cases is Justice Scalia, who ar- gued in concurrence in C.T.S. Corp., 1652-53, that "such an inquiry is ill-suited to the judicial function. . . . I do not know what qualifies us to make . . . the ultimate (and most ineffable) judgment as to whether, given impor- tance level x, and effectiveness level y, the worth of the statute is 'outweighed' by impact on commerce z." This argument largely echoes the position taken by then- As- sociate Justice Rehnquist against balancing state safety considerations against burdens on interstate commerce in transportation regulations. See, e.g., Kassel, 691-93 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting). Importantly, the majority opinion in C.T.S. did not examine the validity of the In- diana takeover statute under balancing analysis before affirming its constitutionality and, in fact, expressed a re- luctance "to second-guess the empirical judgments of lawmakers concerning the utility of legislation," C.T.S, 1651, citing Kassel, 679 (Brennan, J., concumng). Al- though it may be implied that the Court is increasingly willing to dispense with the balancing approach in the dormant commerce clause doctrine, the rejection of this analysis remains to be seen.

4gSee Skover, " 'Phoenix Rising' and Federalism Analy- sis," pp. 295-98 (active judicial intervention in economic regulation under dormant commerce clause doctrine is theoretically and practically inconsistent with the Su- preme Court's reliance on "political safeguards of fcder- alism" in recent commerce clause doctrine); Julian N. Eule, "Laying the Dormant Commerce Clause to Rest," Yale Law Journal 91 (1982): 425 (evaluation of discrimi- natory economic measures under different constitu- tional provisions); Tushnet, "Rethinking the Dormant

Commerce ('lause" (focus of inquiry should be distor- tions in statc poli1ic;il prt~csscs).

50Sce,e.g., I~ughcs v. Alcxanclria Scrap Corp., 426 U.S. 794 (1976) (susta~ning a Maryland program designed to re- duce the number of junked automobiles in the state by establishing a "bounty" on Maryland-licensed junk cars and imposing more stringent documentation require- ments on out-of-state scrap processors than on in-state competitors); White v. Massachusetts Council of Con- struction Employers, Inc., 460 US. 204 (1983) (uphold- ing an order of the mayor of Boston that all construction projects funded by the city must be performed by a work force including one-half bona fide city residents).

51 See, e.g., Reeves v. Stake, 447 U.S. 429 (1980) (upholding the policy o f a state-owned cement plant to favor in-state customers in times of product shortage).

52See South-Central Timber Development v. Wunnicke, 467 U.S. 82 (1984)(invalidating contractual requirement of Alaskapublic corporation that timber sold by the state at preferential prices be processed within the state. for imposition of unconstitutional regulatory conditions downstream in the timber processing market).

53The takings clause of the Fifth Amendment to the US. Constitution, which restricts the eminent domain pow- ers of the federal government, provides: "nor shall pri- vate property be taken for public use, without just com- pensation." Identical limitations on the eminent domain authority of state governments have been enforced through the Fourteenth Amendment due process clause.

"As will become apparent, the Supreme Court's current doctrine on the "public use" requirement understands that this objective-the securing of a public good-is likely to be scrved by the "just compensation" require- ment: that is, public willingness to pay for a transfer of property suggests that some actual public gain underlies the taking.

55Among the most important studies of the history and normative purposes of the takings clause, see generally Bruce Ackerman, Private Property and tile Coristit~rtion (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977); Richard Epstein, Takings: Private Property and tile Power of Enri- nent Domain (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985); Frank I. Michelman, "Property, Utility and Fair- ness: Comments on the Ethical Foundations of 'Just Compensation' Iaw," Harvard Law Review 80 (1967): 1165; Joseph I, Sax, "Taking and the Police Power," Yale Law Journal 74 (1971): 36; Joseph L. Sax, "Takings, Pri- vate Property and Public Rights," Yale Law Jorrmal81 (1971): 149.

5Qhe Supremc Court itself has acknowledged as much, in admitting a lack of determinate rules or standards in the takings clause doctrine. Consider Justice William Bren- nan's statement in the opinion of the Court in Penn Cen- tral Transportation Co. v. New York City, 438 U.S. 104, 124 (1978):

['Tihis Court, quitc simply, has been unable to develop iiny "set Ibrniula" for determiningwhen "justice and Cairncss" require that economic in- juries causctl hy public action be compensated by the govcrnmcnt, rathcr than remain dispro- portionatcly concentrated on a few persons.

57See, e.g., Pumpclly v. Green Ray and Mississippi Canal Co., 80 U.S. 166 (1871) (destruction of private property by government-caused flooding).

58In Lmetto v. Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp., 458 U.S. 419 (1982), the Supreme Court recognized that

30 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

a "taking" generally will be found in the case of a govern- mentally authorized permanent physical occupation of private property. The Court's decision in Loretto invali- dated a New York statute that required landlords to per- mit a cable television company to install cable facilities on rental land and buildings. Compare Federal Commu- nications Commission v. Florida Power Corp., 94 L. Ed. 2d 282 (1987) (upheld federal statute authorizing the FCC to review the rates that utility companies charge ca- ble operators for the use of utility poles, distinguishing Loretto on the basis that nonconfiscatory regulation of rates chargeable for the use of private property devoted to publicuses is not a "taking"). See also United States v. Causby, 328 U.S. 256,261 (1946) (frequent flights imme- diately above a landowner's property constituted a "tak- ing" "as complete as if the United States had entercd upon the surface of the land and taken exclusive posses- sion of it.").

59See, e.g., Northwestern Fertilizing Co. v. Hydc Park, 07 U.S. 659 (1878Xdenying compensation for the banish- ment of a fertilizing company, originally located outside of Chicago city limits, when the area became inhabited); Village of Euclid v. Ambler Realty Co., 272 US. 365,368 (1926Xdenying compensation in enforcement of local zoning ordinance)("a nuisance may be merely a right thing in the wrong place, like a pig in a parlor instead of the barnyard").

Gosee, e.g., Miller v. Schoene, 276 U.S. 272 (1928Xuncom- pensated governmental destruction of red cedar trees in- fected with a rust endangering nearby apple trees analo- gized to the regulatory abatement of a public nuisance at common law); Goldblatt v. Hempstead, 369 U.S. 590 (1962Xupholding as a "safety regulation" a zoning law prohibiting a sand and gravel mining enterprise from ex- cavating below the water table, in part on the basis of in- conclusive evidence of substantial diminution of the property value).

The Supreme Court has acknowledged that the judicial finding of a "taking" of property involves ad hoc decis- ionmaking based on the facts of a particular case. Con- sider Justice William Brennan's statement in the major- ity opinion of Penn Central Transportation Co. v. New York City, 123-24:

[The] question of what constitutes a "taking" for purposes of the Fifth Amendment has proved to be a problem of considerable difficulty. . . .[In- deed,] we have frequently observed that whether a particular restriction will be rendered invalid by the government's failure to pay for any losses proximately caused by it depends largely "upon the particular circumstances [in that] case."

62See, e.g., Pennsylvania Coal Co. v. Mahon, 260 U.S. 393 (1922) (state statute prohibiting underground coal min- ing which might damage surface property, as applied to affect the rights of a private coal company to engage in such miningunder a deed executed by the surface home- owner's predecessor in title, worked a "taking" as it would “destroy previously existing rights of property and contract."). Of course, the Question that is difficult to an- swer is how much diminuhon in value is "too much." Both before and after Pennsylvania Coal Co., the Su- preme Court has indicated a strong reluctance to find a "taking" only on the basis of this variable, at lcast in the absence of total destruction of property rights. See, e.g., Hadachek v. Sebastian, 239 U.S. 394 (1915) (decrease of value from $800,000 to $60,000 sustained as an uncom- pensated regulatory loss); Penn Central, 131 ("[Tlhe de-

cisions sustaining other land-use regulations [reject] the proposition that diminution in property value. standing alone, can establish a "taking"). Indeed, the viability of Pennsylvania Coal Co. itself is in serious question, as the Supreme Court has appeared toundermine its reasoning (although not to reverse its holding) in the recent deci- sion of Keystone Bituminous Coal Association v. DeBenedictis. 107 S.Ct. 1232 (1987) (upholding Pennsyl- vaniastatute that authorized a regulatoryrequirement of maintenance of 50 percent of coal beneath structures as a means of providing surface suu~or t for ~ u b l i c build- ings, privat&residen&s, and cemkteries, on the ground that the act would not interfere unduly with investment- backed expectations).

"In this regard, compare Penn Central, 136 (New York's historic Ii~ndmarks preservation law permits Penn Cen- tral's continued opxation as a railroad terminal contain- ing off~ce spxe and concessions, and thereby "does not interfere wit I1 wliat must hc rcgardcd as Penn Central's primary expectation concerning the use of the parcel [or its abillty] to obtain a 'reasonable return' on its invest- ment") and Kaiser Actna v. United States, 444 U.S. 164 (1979) (federal government's attempt to create a public right of access to a lagoon that had been dredged for use as a private marina waterfront found to destroy the in- vestment-backed expectations of the private lagoon owner).

64See, e.g., Penn Central, 137. The New York landmarks preservation law allowed owners of landmark sites who had not developed their property to the full extent other- wise permitted under zoning laws to transfer their devel- opment rights to contiguous parcels on the same city block. In its determination that the economic impact of the law fell short of a "taking," the Supreme Court took account of the provision of these transferable develop- mental rights as a feature that "enhances the economic position of the landmark owner in one significant re- spect." The Supreme Court's understanding of the "av- erage reciprocity of advantage" appears to have taken an unexpected turn in Keystone Bituminous Coal Associa- tion v. IkBcnedictis (balancing the burdens on coal companies imposed by mine subsidence regulation against the benefits accruing to the companies from re- strictions falling on others in different regulatory schemes). For an insightful critique of this approach, see Epstein, "Takings: Descent and Resurrection," in Philip Ku rland, ed.. 1987 Siprenie Court Review (Chicago: Uni- vcrsity of Chicago Press, 1987), pp. 22-23 ("For Holmes the test of average reciprocity of advantage was really a way of asking whether the parties whose property was taken receivctl compensation in-kind for the loss in ques- tion in the same transaction. . . . Indeed, under Stevens's misdirected rendering of Holmes's test, no restrictions on use ever could be unconstitutional because the state might also right the balance on some future occasion.")

"See Clark v. Nash, 198 U.S. 361 (1905); Strickley v. High- land Boy Gold Mining Co., 200 U.S. 527 (1906).

66See Tribe, American Constitutional Law, 8-5 and 9-2. "Hawaii Housing Authority v. Midkiff, 467 U.S. 229,240

(1984) (Hawaii Land Reform Act served a valid "public use" by employingeminent domain to enable homeown- ers with longterm land leases to purchase the lots on which they 11vcd). In the last three to four decades. the "public use" doctrine has bcen assimilated conceptually wth the "publ~c purpose" and "rational relationshl~" standards ippliedin reviewing regulations of economic interests under the due urocess clause. See. ex.. Berman v. Parker, 348 U.S. 26 (1954). Essentially, the Supreme

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 31

Court has established that, so long as the slate's use of eminent domain is rationally rclatcd to a conccivable public purpose, the "public use" rcquircment is satisfied. See Berman, 17-19 (discussion of "rational rclationship" standard in economic due proccss doctrine). 'l'he rela- tionship between the broad approach to the "public use" doctrine in eminent domain and the due process "public purpose" doctrine is described in Arvo Van Alstyne, "Public Use," 3 Encyclopedia, p. 1494, and Harry N. Scheiber, "Public Purpose Doctrine," 3 Encyclopedia, p. 1489.

68See Nollan v. California Coastal Commission, 107 S.Ct. 3141 (1987) (invalidating state land-use regulation that conditioned the issuance of a permit to rebuild an ocean- front residence on the property owners' grant to the pub- lic of a permanent easement across their beach). The Nollan Court found that the easement condition did not substantially advance the government's alleged pur- poses, including the public's ability to see and gain access to the beach from the streets in front of the home. The Court concluded that, "unless the permit condition serves the same governmental purpose as the develop- ment ban, the building restriction is not a valid regula- tion of land use but 'an out-and-out plan of extortion.' " Nollan, 3 148.

69"It is [by] now commonplace that this Court's review of the rationality of a State's exercise of its police power de- mands only that the State 'could rationally have decided' that the measure adopted might achieve the State's ob- jective." Nollan, 3151 (Brennan, J., dissenting).

70In an "inverse condemnation" action, the private prop- erty owner sues to establish that the government has ef- fectively appropriated his property and must pay for it. If the court finds a "taking," the court will order payment of just compensation. This action is distinct from a man- damus or a declaratory judgment action, in which the private owner merely claims that a governmental regula- tion affecting his property violates his due process rights. Should the court find such a violation, it will merely in- validate the regulation as applied prospectively to the property.

71Typically, state courts had not subjected state or local governments to damages or an inverse condemnation award for a legislative or regulatory action that was found to be a taking; they regarded the invalidation of the regulation as the only proper remedy, leaving the pri- vate landowner with full prospective use of his property. Essentially, the state courts had denied the private owner any compensation for the "temporary taking" of his property that occurred between the effective date of the state or local regulation and the effective date of the judicial invalidation of the regulation. See, e.g., Agins v. Tiburon, 24 Cal. 3d 266,598 P.2d 25 (19792, afl;rnled on other grounds, 447 U.S. 255 (1980).

;*First English Evangelical Lutheran Church of Glcndale v. County of Los Angeles,l07 S.Ct. 2378, 2388 (1987) ("temporary" takings that deny a landowner all use of his property are not different from pcrmanent takings, for which the Constitution clearly requires compensation).

73Ibid., 2389 (indicating that the "temporary taking" doc- trine will not apply in the case of "normal delays in ob- taining building permits, changes in zoning ordinanccs, and the like").

74The First Evangelical Court did not address the valu- ation of the "temporary taking" for purposes of "just compensation." It only indicated that, when such a "tak-

ing" is buntl, ihc owner must bc compensated for the full period.

75Though exploralion of thc question is beyond the scope of this analysis, i t is intcrcsting to ask whether state and local eovcrntnents mav limit somewhat their emosure to crippCng liability for ikterim damages by enac6ng more stringent statutes of limitation on inverse condemnation acti&s challenging land use regulations.

76Professor Richard Epstein makes the point that a broad reading of First English and Nollan would have a com- bined influence that could shift the cost-benefit calcula- tions for land developers who perceive an increased "rate of return" from suits challenging land-use regula- tions. Epstein, "'Takings: Descent and Resurrection," pp. 43-44.

77In pertinent part, Amend. XIV, 1 to the U.S. Constitu- tion provides: or shall any State deprive any person of life,

liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.

78See, e.g., Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905) (in- validating a New York law regulating the hours and wages of biikcry employees as an abridgement of the lib- erty of contract that violated the due process rights of both employees and employers); Adkins v. Children's Hospital, 261 U.S. 525 (1923) (invalidating a law that es- tablished minimum wages for women under due process and equal protection rationales). Between 1899 and 1937, the Supreme Court invalidated state or federal eco- nomic and social regulations under the due process clause, usually coupled with the equal protection clause, in approximately 200 eases. For comprehensive surveys of the Court's rulings in this period, see Benjamin F. Wright, The Growth of American Constitutional Law (New York: Reynal and Hitchcock, 1942), pp. 153-168; Normal Jerome Small, ed., The Coristit~rtion of the United States; Analysis and Interpretation (Washington DC: US. Government Printing Office, 1964)

79Among the most celebrated cases articulating the con- temporary doctrines of economic substantive due proc- ess and equal protection, see, e.g., Williamson v. Lee Op- tical Co.. 348 US. 483 (1955) (sustaining Oklahoma statute that prohibited an optician from fitting or dupli- cating lenses without a prescription from an ophthal- mologist or optometrist, challenged on due process and equal protection grounds); Railway Express Agency v. New York, 336 US. 106 (1949) (sustaining a New York City traffic regulation that banned commercial vehicular advertising, except for the vehicle owner's own prod- ucts).

sosee, e.g., Williamson v. Lee Optical Co., 488 ("It is enough that thcrc is an evil at hand for correction, and that it mighl bc though1 that the particular legislative measure was a riitio11;d way to correct it."); Minnesota v. Clover Ixaf Crea~ncry Co., 449 US. 456,464 (1981)("Al- though partics challenging legislation under the Equal Protection C'lausc niay introduce evidence supporting their claim that i t is irrational, they cannot prevail so long as 'it is evident from all the considerations presented to [the legislature], and those of which we may take judicial notice, that the question is at least debatable.' "). In con- trast to the Warren Court years, the Burger Court era ap- peared occasionally to infuse a little "bite" into the "mere rationality" standard. See, e.g., City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, 105 S.Ct. 3249 (1985)(invalidat- ingunder the equal protection clause the application of a

32 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

municipal zoning ordinance to deny a special permit for the operation of a group home for the mentally re- tarded). Clearly, however, such cases expressed the ex- ception to "mere rationality," rather than the rule, for the Burger Court.

81 See, e.g., Metropolitan Life Insurance Co. v. Ward, 470 U.S. 869 (1985) (invalidating Alabama insurance re y l a - tion that taxed out-of-state companies at a higher rate than domestic companies for the illegitimatc purpose of promoting the business of domestic insurers by penaliz- ing foreign insurers); Williams v. Vermont, 105 SCt. 2465 (1985) (invalidating Vermont autonlobile sales tax scheme that allowed a credit against state use tax for any sales tax paid in another state only if the taxpayer were a Vermont resident at the time the car was purchased).

82In Metropolitan Life Insurance Co., the majority rea- soned:

Alabama's aim to promote domestic industry is purely and completely discriminatory, designed only to favor domestic industry within the State, no matter what the cost to foreign corporations also seeking to do business there. Alabama's purpose. . . constitutes the very sort of parochial discrimination that the Equal Protection Clause was intended toprevent.. . . [Tlhis Court always has held that the Equal Protection Clause for- bids a State to discriminate in favor of its own residents solely by burdening "the residents of other state members of our federation."

83Metropolitan Life Insurance Co. was decided by a nar- row majority of five Justices, with Justice Powell writing the opinion of the Court and Justices O'Connor, Bren- nan, Marshall and Chief Justice Rehnquist in dissent. Of course, Justice Kennedy's arrival on the Court and any changes in the Court's composition in the near future would render any projections regarding a "new era" of constitutional protection for private economic liberty (under the equal protection clause, however, instead of under economic substantive due process) totally specula- tive.

84This point was demonstrated emphatically by the dis- senting Justices in Metropolitan Life Insurance co., who viewed the majority opinion as charting an "ominous course," that "has serious implications for the authority of Congress under the Commerce Clause." Noting that Congress in the McCarran-Ferguson Act had explicitly placed insurance regulation "firmly within the purview of the several States," the dissenters objected to the ma- jority's use of the equal protection clause as an instru- ment of federalism: "Surely the Equal Protection Clause was not intended to supplant the Commerce Clause, foil- ing Congress' decision under its commerce powers to 'af- firmatively permit [some measure] of parochial favorit- ism' when necessary to a healthy federalism." 470 U.S. at 899 (O'Connor, J., dissenting).

851ndeed, soon after Metropolitan Life Insurance Co, was decided, the Court unanimously upheld against chal- lenges under the commerce and equal proteaion clauses the laws of Connecticut and Massachusetts, that limited the creation or acquisition of in-state banks to banking corporations located in the six-state New England re- gion. Northeast Bancorp, Inc. v. Board of Governors of Federal Reserve System, 472 IJS. 159 (1985). The Court found that a federal statute, the Rank I-iolditig ('ot,ipany Act of 1956, itself authorized the individual statcs to balkanize the banking industry. Moreover, the Court deemed the "independence of banking inslitutions" to

be a legitimate state objective to which the laws bore a rational relationship. In concurrence, Justice O'Connor argued that the state schemes in Northeast Bancorp were indistinguishable from that in Metropolitan Life Insurance Co., and suggested that the latter ruling might have confined Metropolitan Life to its peculiar facts. 472 U.S. 178-9 (O'Connor, J., concurring).

86See Sunstein, "Nakcd Prcfcrences and the Constitu- tion," Co/'olrrtd~ia h w Hcview 84 (1984): 1689.

e7Art. II1,2 of the U.S. C~nstilution provides: The judicial Power shall extend to all Cases, in Law and Equ ily. arising under this Constitution, the I ~ w s of' the United States, and Treaties made, or which shall be made, under their Authority.

The text of Art I11 would appear to grant appellate juris- diction to the Supreme Court to review any state court decision involving a question of federal law, regardless of the manner in which the state court resolved the case, and to grant original jurisdiction to inferior federal courts to decide any such case in the first instance. Doc- trinal restraints on such an expansive power have been self-imposed by the Supreme Court and lower federal courts, in their interpretation of Art. I11 and federal statutory grants of jurisdiction.

88As articulatctl concisely by the Supreme Court in Fox Film Corp. v. Mueller, 296 U.S. 207,210 (1935) the inde- pendent and adequate state grounds doctrine embodies "the settled rule that where the judgment of a state court rests upon two grounds, one of which is federal and the other non-federal in character, [Supreme Court] juris- diction fails if the nonfederal ground is independent of the federal ground and adequate to support the judg- ment."

89For example, if a state high court determines that the right of the media to broadcast copies of court tape re- cordings can be upheld under both the First Amend- ment of the IJ.S. Constitution and state constitutional guarantees of spcech and press rights, the U.S. Supreme Court should deny appellate jurisdiction to review the state court's potentially erroneous decision under the First Amendment, provided the state constitutional law holding does not rely substantively on the federal lawde- cision and would sustain the judgment alone if the fed- eral law holding were undermined upon review. See State v. Coe, 101 Wash. 26 364, 679 P.2d 353, 359-62 (1984).

9OIn Herb v. Pitcairn, 324 U.S. 117, 125-26 (1945), Justice Robert Jackson characterized the doctrine as a preven- tative against Supreme Court issuance of "advisoryopin- ions" in violation of the Art. I11 case or controversy re- quirements. Arguably, use of this metaphor is unfortunate. By casting the doctrine as a device to pre- vent "advisory opinions," Justice Jackson raised it to the level of a constitutional justiciability requirement, simi- lar to the standing or political question doctrines. This characterization does not recognize the nature of the re- straint as a sclf-imposed or prudential limitation on the Supreme Court's appellate jurisdiction. For critiques of the constitulional basis for the doctrine, see, e.g., Richard A. Matasar and Gregory S. Bruch, "Procedural Common l a w . Ktleral Jurisdictional Policy, and Aban- donment of the Atlcquale and Independent State Grounds 1)tx:lrinc." (bl'olrrt~~l~iu 1-aw Review 86 (1986): 1291, 13 17-22.

g1 Several well-cstal)l~shctl principles guide Supremecourt review of a statc high court judgment that bars consid-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 33

eration of a federal law claim bccausc of a procedural de- fault:

1) The determinative issue-whether a federal law claim was sufficiently and properly raised in the state courts-is itself ultimatcly a question of the "adequacy" of the state law ground. 13ecause the is- sue implicates the scope of the Supreme Court's own jurisdiction, it presents a federal question as to which the Court is not bound by the state court rul- ing. Street v. New York, 394 U.S. 576,583 (1969).

2) The enforcement of state court procedure at the ex- pense of a hearing of a federal law claim, at the very least, must pass muster under the "fundamental fairness" requirements of the Fourteenth Amend- ment due process clause. Reece v. Georgia, 350 US. 85 (1955).

3) Even if enforcement of a state court procedural rule would meet "fundamental fairness," it will not bar Supreme Court review of a federal claim if the rule were applied with a specific intent to deprive a claimant of his federal rights or if it "unreasonably interfer[ed] with the vindication of such rights." James v. Kentucky, 466 US. 341,348-9 (1984)(state procedural requirement had not been consistently applied in prior cases); Williams v. Georgia, 349 U.S. 375,383 (1955) (state court refusal to exercise discretion deemed "in effect, an avoidance of the federal right").

Although the Supreme Court appeared to expand the scope of its review despite procedural default in Henry v. Mississippi, 379 U.S. 443, 447 (1965) (balancing the im- portance of the claim of federal right against the utility of the state's enforcement of its procedural requirement in the specific case at bar, insofar as it furthers a legitimate state interest), subsequent retrenchment in the Court's standards for federal habeas corpus jurisdiction may have undermined the intellectual supports for Henry's broad approach to the Court's direct appellate review. See, e.g., Stone v. Powell, 428 U.S. 465 (1976) (no habeas corpus relief if state court procedure afforded a "full and fair" opportunity to litigate a federal constitutional claim); Wainwright v. Sykes, 433 US. 72 (1977) (habeas corpus review of state court judgment turning on failure to comply with "contemporaneous-objection" rule barred unless defendant demonstrates "cause" for the procedural defect and resulting "prejudice").

92Assuming the "independence" of a state substantive law basis for a judgment, as long as the basis itself did not vio- late the federal Constitution, it generally would be deemed "adequate."

93See, e.g., State v. Badger, 141 Vt. 430,450 A.2d 336,347 (1982) (claimant's rights sustained independently under Vermont Constitution after determining that thcrc was a corresponding right available under federal law); State v. Coe, 361-62 (first granting relief under state constitu- tional law, and then proceeding to establish fcclcral claims under federal law).

94For classicexamples of state court rulings that automati- cally presume that federal constitutional decisions shape the character and contours of state constitutional law guarantees, see, e.g., Washington v. Fireman's Fund Inc. Co., 708 P.2d 139 (Haw. 1985); State v. Jackson 11, 672 P.2d 255,260 (1983) [discussed and critiqued in Ronald Collins, "Reliance on State Constitutions: The Montana Disaster," T m Law Review 63 (1985): 10951. Both deci- sions sustained the constitutionality of the state laws against challenges by the rights claimants. An insightful

and imaginative account of four conceptual models for the "rcl;itionships" of state and federal constitutional laws is presented in Collins and Galie, "Models of Post- Incorporation Judicial Kcvicw."

95Michigan v. I m g . 463 IJS. 1032 (1983). Prior to Michi- gan v. Long, the Supreme Court had adopted avariety of methods for resolving the issue of the "independence" of a state law ground: (1) dismissal in the case of unclear grounds for decision, see, e.g., Lynch v. New York, 293 U.S. 52 (1934); (2) remand to the state high court for clarification of the grounds for decision, see, e.g., Minne- sota v. National Tea Co., 309 U.S. 551 (1940); (3) exami- nation of state law rulings to discern whether state courts generally used federal law merely to guide application of state law, see, e.g., Texas v. Brown, 460 US. 730 (1983Xplurality opinion). These cases and other similar decisions were cited and characterized as failing impor- tant interests of fcclcralism by the Michigan Court, 1038.

96 Ibid.,l041. 971bid. (emphasis added). 98Laurence Tribe considers this ramification of the Michi-

gan v. Long standard to be central to the autonomy of state law. See Tribe, American Constitrrtio~iaILaw. p. 166.

99Michigan. 1041. Critics of the Michigan v. Long ap- proach have argued, of course, that the balance among federalism intcrests was struck in a manner that accords insufficient rcspect for state court autonomy. Mr. Justice Stevens, in his dissenting opinion in Michigan v. Long, claimed to bc "thoroughly baffled by the Court's sugges- tion that it must stretch its jurisdiction and reverse the judgment of lhc Michigan Supreme Court in order to show 'respec.t for the independence of state courts.' " Michigan, 1072 (5. Stevens, dissenting). See, e.g., Ronald Collins, "Reliance on State Constitutions: Some Ran- dom Thoughts," Mississippi Law Journal 54 (1984): 371, 400-01 (suggesting a "less intrusive presumption" to vin- dicate the autonomy of state judiciaries, such as a rule on unreviewability in the absence of a "plain statement" that state law does not provide the relief sought). Con- trast Martin Redish, "Supreme Court Review of State Court 'Federal' Decisions: A Study in Interactive Feder- alism," Georgia Law Review 19 (1985): 861 (arguing that Michigan v. Long is not "invasive" of state court preroga- tives in any meaningful sense).

'o0An enigmatic ftx)tnote in the Michigan v. Long majority opinion, 1041 n. 6, gives reason for concern over what, indeed, will constitute a sufficient demonstration of a "bona fide separate, adequate, and independent" state law ground:

Thcre may be certain circumstances in which clarification is necessary or desirable, and we will not be foreclosed from taking the appropriate action.

Post-Iang decisions indicate that the Supreme Court may wcll cxcrcisc rcvicw in the face of any ambiguity ovcr the basis o f ;i state high court judgment. Compare Ohio v. Johnson, 467 [J.S. 493 (1984) and Florida v. Myers, 446 US . 380 (1984) (appellate review due to fail- ure to indicate clcarly that dccision was based ultimately on state law) with Uhlcr v. AFLCIO, 468 U.S. 1310 (1984) (California Suprcme Court's prohibition of a bal- lot initiative rested on independent state ground because of state court's detailed analysis of state law).

101 All of the analytic devices described in the text were em- ployed to advantage in Carreras v. City of Anaheim, 768 F.2d 1039 (9th Cir. 1985) (municipal ordinance banning solicitation of religious donations outside publicconven-

34 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

tion center violates California's constitutional guaran- tees of speech liberties). In particular, sce Carreras, 1042-43 (prefatory discussion of the role of state law as first basis for consideration of claims of right), 1042 n.4 (acknowledging rule of avoidance of unnecessary federal constitutional questions), 1044 n.7 (establishing trend of greater protection for expressive activity under state con- stitutional law than under First Amendment), 1043-45 and 1048-50 (analysis of state constitutional precedents alone for governing rules and standards), 1044 n.8 and 9 (ensuring that controlling state constitutional lawprece- dents themselves rested on state law), 1048 11.21 and 1049 n. 24 and 25 (explicitly stating that citation to federal ju- dicial precedents in past state supreme court decisions, and past adoption of analytical frameworks developed by the Supreme Court under the federal constitution, served only to guide independent interpretation of the state constitution). Given its self-conscious, deliberate, and artful use of the full battery of analytic devices, Car- reras stands as an excellent case study and role model for the independent interpretation of state constitutional law. It is interesting to note that a federal appeals court was responsible for such a splendid example of state con- stitutional exegesis.

"J2In this regard, a comparison of two state high court deci- sions may be instructive. Compare State v. Badger (ac- knowledging that separate consideration of Vermont constitutional claims is required and that the state con- stitutional meaning is not identical to federal constitu- tional meaning even for parallel provisions; relying ex- clusively on state court precedents in interpreting state constitutional provisions; providing "plain statement" that judgment rests on state constitutional guarantees) with Patchogue-Medford Congress of Teachers v. Board of Education, 70 N.Y.2d 57,510 N.E.2d 325 (1987) (ex- plicitly acknowledging reliance on both federal and state constitutional law because violation of the former is vio- lation of the latter; interweaving discussion of federal and state constitutional texts and court precedents; ana- lyzing the determinative issues as substantively identical under federal and state constitutional law; providing no "plain statement" that the judgment is grounded on state constitutional law).

103For comprehensive and thoughtful analyses of the ab- stention and equitable restraint doctrines, see H. Fink and M. Tushnet, Federal Jlrrisdiction: Policy and Pmctice, pp. 615638, 655-675, 681-694 (1984); Martin Redish, Federal Jurisdiction: Tensions in the Allocation of Judicial Power (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1980), pp. 233-58, 291-321.

104The Pullman abstention doctrine derives from the rule in Railroad Commission of Texas v. Pullman Co., 312 U.S. 496 (1941) (requiring federal district court absten- tion from decision of Fourteenth Anicndmcnt equal protection claim, to afford thc Tcxas state courls an op- portunity to rule on the state statutory claim of abuse of discretion in the commission's order to segregate opera- tion of railroad sleeping cars).

105A federal ruling on a sensitive fedcral constitutional is- sue might be tentative or "wasteful" in the sense that in- terpretation of an unclear state law by the state courts might well moot the federal constitutional issue. For ex- ample, the Supreme Court understood in Pullman that because the last word on the statutory authority of the railroad commission could issue only from the Texas Su- preme Court, any decision on the constitutionality of the commission's segregation order would be a "tentative answer which may be displaced tomorrow by a state ad-

judication. . . . The reign of law is hardly promoted if an unnecessary ruling of a fcdcral court is thus supplanted by a controllmg tlccision of a state court." Pullman, 500.

106For analysis and critique of the functionsof the Pullman abstention doctrine, see Martha A. Field, "Abstention in Constitutional Cases: The Scope of the Pullman Absten- tion Doctrine," Universig of Pennsylvania Law Review 122 (1974): 1071; Martha A. Field, "The Abstention Doc- trine Today," University of Pennsylvania Law Review 125 (1977): 590.

107Abstention to perniit a state constitutional law attack on a state law is typically deemed improper where the state constitutional provision is virtually identical to the appli- cable federal constitutional provision. See, e.g., Wiscon- sin v. Constantineau, 400 U.S. 433 (1971)(refusing to or- dcr abstention to permit state court scrutiny of state liquor regulation under state constitutional law). Ab- stention in such circumstanceswould be tantamount to a rule of exhaustion of state judicial remedies before bringing a federal action on federal constitutional grounds, a prerequisite which the Supreme Court has not becn willing to impose. See, e.g., Monroe v. Pape, 365 US. 167 (1961).

108Sce, e g , Imisiana Power and Light v. City of Thibodaux, 360 U.S. 25 (1959) (requiring abstention in a diversity action challenging the authority of state mu- nicipalities to condemn utility properties, since the dele- gation of eminent domain powers to localities is a ques- tion "intimatcly involved with the sovereign prerogalive").

lOQSee, e.g.. Burford v. Sun Oil Co., 319 U.S. 315 (1943)(up- held abstention in a challenge to a drilling permit issued under a Texas state scheme creating a complex and co- herent pattern of administrative and judicial decision- making to resolve oil rights issues); Alabama Public Serv- ice Commission v. Southern Railway Co., 341 U.S. 341, 347 (1951) (requiring abstention in a challenge to the commission's order to continue certain local train serv- ice, on the rationale that resolution of the dispute de- pends on the "predominantly local factor of public need for the service rendered.").

11OFor example, in Rurford, 326-27, the Supreme Court ex- plained that the Texas legislature had established a uni- fied state administrative and judicial network to regulate the production of oil and gas, and that state judicial re- view of the commission's orders was speedy and thor- ough. Indeed, to prevent confusion of multiple review of legal issues involving the state scheme, the legislature had provided for concentration of all direct review of the commission's orders in the state districts of one county. The exercise of federal equity jurisdiction in this case would create thc "very 'confusion' which the Texas legis- lature and Suprernc Court fcared might result from re- view by many statc courts or thc Railroad Commission's orders." llurfonl, 327.

111 See, e.g., Zahltxki v. Redhail. 434 U.S. 374(1978)(invali- dating Wisconsin statute that required court permission for remamag or a statc rcsident under legal obligation to provide child support). The Supreme Court distin- guished Burforcl v. Sun Oil on the basis that "this case does not involve complex issues of state law, resolution of which would be 'disruptive of state efforts to establish a coherent policy with respect to a matter of substantial public concern.' " Burford, 380. Importantly, the state statute in Zablocki implicated a substantial question of federal constitutional law, on which resdution of the case ultimately turned. Professor Martin Redish argues that abstention from the exercise of diversity jurisdiction

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 35

should be restricted to controversies in which (1) the regulatorypolicy is "of significant and special concern to the state"; (2) the administrative scheme is, "in fact, de- tailed and complex"; and (3) any substantial and trouble- some federal question "cannot be resolved without re- quiring the federal court to immerse itself in the technicalities of the state scheme." Redish, Federal J~rris- diction, pp. 246,259. But see Kaiser Steel Corp. v. W.S. Ranch Co., 391 U.S. 593 (1968) (diversity suit for tres- pass, involving no complex regulatory or administrative scheme).

112Mr. Justice Hugo Black first used the term "Our Federal- ism" in the celebrated case of Younger v. Harris, 401 U.S. 37 (1971), to announce the principle of "comity" be- tween federal and state courts on which the Court has relied in formulating the rules of the equitable restraint doctrine.

"3In summary, the equitable restraint doctrine yields the followine, rules:

~t ihe time a litigant initiates a federal proceeding to challenge state action as unconstitutional, if the litigant is a defendant in a pending or ongoing state criminal proceeding, and if the federal litigant can raise the constitutional claims in the state proceed- ing, ordinarily the litigant will not be able to obtain federal injunctive or declaratory relief. Younger v. Harris, 401 U.S. 37 (1971) (federal in- junctive relief against state criminal prosecution); Samuels v. Mackell, 401 US. 66 (1971) (fetlcral declaratory relief against criminal statutc cnforccd in pending prosecution). A federal district court may grant declaratory or in- junctive relief against unconstitulional state action if the federal litigant does not become a defendant in a state criminal prosecution concerning the same issues before proceedings of substance on the mer- its have begun in the federal action. Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452 (1974) (federal declaratory relief where genuine threat of enforce- ment of unconstitutional state statute demon- strated); Doran v. Salem Inn, Inc., 422 U.S. 922 (1975) (preliminary injunctive relief to preserve status quo pending declaratory judgment); Hicks v. Miranda, 422 U.S. 332 (1975) ("proceedings of sub- stance" restriction). At the time a litigant initiates a federal proceeding to challenge state action as unconstitutional, if the litigant is a defendant in a pending state civil suit brought by state officials to enforce important state policies, and if the federal constitutional claims may be raised and litigated fully in the state pro- ceeding, ordinarily the litigant will not be able to obtain federal injunctive or declaratory relief. Huffman v. Pursue, 420 U.S. 592 (1975) ("quasi- criminal" nuisance abatement action); Juidice v.

Vail, 430 1J.S. 327 (1977) (civil contempt proceed- ing to effcctuate a state damage judgment); Trainor v. Hernandez, 431 US. 434 (1977) (state civil action to recoup welfare payments obtained by fraud); Moore v. Sims, 442 U.S. 415 (1979) (extending equi- table restraint to federal issues between the parties that are not directly implicated in the pending state civil proceeding).

4) The rulcs above do not apply if the pending or on- going state proceeding has been initiated in bad faith or as part of a program of harassment, or if a federal litigant's constitutional claim concerns the procedural fairness of the very state proceeding in which constitutional claims would otherwise be brought. Dombrowski v. Pfister, 380 US. 479 (1965) (excep- tion for had faith and harassment); Gibson v. Ber- ryhill, 41 1 1J.S. 564 (1973) (bias on state board of optometry); Trainor v. Hernandez, (appropriate forum in which to challenge unconstitutional state action must be available in state court system). But see Ohio Civil Rights Commission v. Dayton Chris- tian Schools, 477 U.S. 619 (1986) (no exception to equitable restraint principles for federal due proc- ess challenge to the jurisdiction of the administra- tive tribunal).

"4In Trainor v. Hcrnandcz, 445-56, the Supreme Court recognized that the exercise of federal equitable jurisdic- tion at the time that a statc civil enforcement suit was pending wou Id

. . . confront thc Statc with a choice of engaging in duplicdtive lil igation, thereby risking a tempo- rary federal injunction, or of interrupting its en- forcement proceedings pending decision of the federal court at some unknown time in the fu- ture. It would also foreclose the opportunity of the state court to construe the challenged statute in the face of the actual federal constitutional challenges that would also be pending for deci- sion before it, a privilege not wholly shared by the federal courts.

"=The Supreme Court has articulated forcefully its pur- pose to avoid the "unseemly failure to give effect to the principle that state courts have the solemn responsibil- ity, equally with the federal courts 'to guard, enforce, and protect every right granted or secured by the Constitu- tion of the IJnited States.' " Steffel v. Thompson, 415 US, at 460-61.

"BFor a persuasive critique of the contradictory bases for the equitable restraint doctrine, see Redish, Fedeml Jir- risdiction, pp. 298-307.

"7Youngstown Shect and Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579,654 (1952) (Jackson, J., concurring) (original refer- ence to "powcr in the hands of Congress").

36 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 3

Government Structure

In the American federal system, there are few national requirements governing the structure and relationship of state government institutions. States are not even directly required to have constitutions. Some thought was given to a "model" state constitu- tion that would have been mandated by the Conti- nental Congress early in 1776, but the idea was dropped without being considered serious1y.l Article IV, Section 4 of the U.S. Constitution does provide that "the United States shall guarantee to every State in this Union a Republican Form of govern- ment.. . ."2In 1912, however, when the argument was made that Oregon's constitutional provision for the passage of legislation by popular initiative violated the requirement of a "republican" (government by elected representatives) government, the U.S. Su- preme Court reaffirmed its long-held position that this issue constitutes a nonjusticiable political ques- tion left to congressional enf~rcement.~ Congress, of course, may require the inclusion of provisions in a state constitution as a condition to the admission of new states4

In addition, the federal Constitution does pro- vide a few limitations on the exercise of state power, for example, to regulate commerce and coin money. Most of these restrictions on state power were, in part, direct responses to perceived abuses perpe- trated by the powerful, and relatively unchecked, state legislatures during the decade before adoption of the federal Constitution.

Finally, the Fourteenth Amendment and its judi- cial interpretation for more than a half a century have imposed a range of restrictions on states with respect to various individual rights and liberties. Beyond these limits, however, the American states remain free to devise and change governmental institutions and arrangements as their citizens see fit. As Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes said:

under State Constitutions We shall assume that when, as here, a state Constitution sees fit to unite legislative and judicial powers in a single hand, there is nothing to hinder so far as the Constitution of the United Slates is concerned.5

Thus, with respect to governmental structure, a state remains free to, in the famous words of Justice Louis Brandeis, "scrve as a laboratory"6 for what Holmes referred to as "social experiments . . . in the insulated chambers afforded by the several states."7

The American statcs have played this role of ex- perimenting with govcrnmcntal structure and rela- tionships sincc thc heginning of the Union. Thomas Paine, defending I'ennsylvania's 1776 constitution, which featured a unicamcral legislature, weak execu- tive, and virtually no chccks and balances, wrote in 1778:

It is in the interest of all the States, that the constitution of each should be somewhat di- versified from each other. We are a people founded upon experiments, and. . . have the happy opportunity of trying variety in order to discover the best. . . .8

One very good example of the states' experi- ments with government structure can be seen in the area of thc "legislative veto." States put in place mechanisms by which legislatures could, short of en- acting a law, disapprove of administrative agency ac- tions. The separation of powers problems with this approach were dcbated in the state courts, with the nearly unanimous conclusion that such mechanisms could not be permitted. Thcn the people in various states rcjccted proposed state constitutional amend- ments that would have permitted the practice. Most of this activity prcdated the resolution of similar problems in the I'cderal government.9

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 37

Despite the permitted diversity with respect to governmental structure, there are many identifiable patterns and similarities among the statc govern- ments. As Frank P. Grad observed: "In spite of their enormous diversity, it is probably safe to say that the similarities between government structure in differ- ent states are considerably greater than their differ- ences. . . ."lo

The Function of State Constitutions Regarding Governmental Structure

At the outset, it must be recognized that the po- litical and legal functions of state constitutions are very different from those of the federal Constitution. The U.S. Constitution creates and defines a govern- ment of limited, enumerated, delegated powers. The federal government must point to some explicit or implied grant of power to authorize it to act. There- fore, many of the key questions regarding judicial in- terpretation of federal power under the Constitution concern implied powers. The state governments, by contrast, are based on a very different fundamental conception of government. State govcrnmcnts, par- ticularly the legislative branch, exercise all residual or plenary powers of sovereign governments, cxcept in situations where they are expressly or irnpliedly limited by the state or federal constitutions, or by valid congressional legislation or fedcral administra- tive action. It is sometimes said that state govern- ments exercise power similar to that possessed by the British Parliament. Therefore, many of the impor- tant issues for judicial interpretation of state power under state constitutions concern implied limita- tions.

In the words of the Supreme Court of Kansas:

It is fundamental that our state constitution limits rather than confers powers. Where the constitutionality of a statute is involved, the question presented is, therefore, not whether the act is authorized by the constitu- tion, but whether it is prohibited thereby."

According to the Supreme Court of Illinois, "All leg- islative power is vested in the General Assembly. . . . Every subject within the scope of civil government which is not within . . . constitutional limitations may be acted on by it."'*

The function of state constitutions, not surpris- ingly, dictates their form. Generally speaking, be- cause of the necessity to enunciate specific limita- tions on otherwise virtually unlimited governmental power, state constitutions contain much more detail with resuect to the structure and operations of gov-

a range of ways that is unfamiliar in the federal gov- ernment.

Further, bccause state constitutions are easier to amend than the Scdcral Constitution, they have accu- mulated many limiting details reflecting the concerns of citizens during the various eras of American his- tory. For example, evidence of the periods of distrust of the legislature, the Industrial Revolution, the Pro- gressive Movement, Jacksonian democracy, the set- tling of the West, bankruptcy in public finance, con- cern for efficient management, and many other matters can be seen clearly in any modern state con- stitution.

Finally, the state constitutions include numerous mechanisms for direct popular involvement in gov- ernmental decisions that have no analog in the fed- eral Constitution. Amendments or revisions of state constitutions themselves must be ratified by the vot- ers before they can take effect. Beyond this funda- mental point, however, direct citizen involvement in such governmental decisions as issuing bonds, levying certain taxes, and even, in some states, approving gambling operations, is often required by state con- stitutions. Statcs with initiative and referendum pro- visions in their constitutions obviously permit direct popular participation in lhc lawmaking process itself. Also, many stiites permit citizen litigation over gov- ernmental matters by authorizing a wide range of tax- payer actions. Nonc of these examples of popular participation in governmental decisions are present in the U.S.Constitution.

State Constitutions and Separation of Powers

James Madison noted in The Federalist, No. 37, that "no skill in the science of government" has been able conclusively to define legislative, executive, and judicial power. As a result, "[Q]uestions daily oc- cur. . . which puzzle the greatest adepts in political science." Matters have remained just as unsettled in the state constitutions in the 200 years since Madison wrote those words.

Many state constitutions, by contrast to the fed- eral Constitution, contain explicit textual statements of the doctrine of separation of powers. For example, Article 11, Section 3 of the Florida Constitution pro- vides:

The powers of the state government shall be dividcd inlo legislative, executive, and judi- cial branches. No person belonging to one branch shall excrcise any powers appertain- ing to either of the other branches unless ex- pressly proviclcd herein.

ernmenf. For example, state conktutions contain These sorts of statcments date from the earliest state long articles on taxation and finance, two of the most constitutions in 1776.13They express two related con- important functions of any government. These provi- cerns: that thepowers of government should be sepa- sions restrict state government taxing and spending in rated; and that thepersons who exercise these powers

38 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

should be separate individuals. It has always been true, however, that the state constitutions, likc the U.S. Constitution, do not provide for a sharp separa- tion of powers; instead, they include a number of blended powers. For example, it is generally con- ceded that the governor's veto, although assigned to the chief executive officer, is actually a legislative power.

An important question must be asked about the impact of placing explicit statements of the separa- tion of powers doctrine in state constitutions. Should these explicit statements have an impact on judicial determination of separation of powers controversies so as to yield results different from those obtaining under the federal Constitution, where the doctrine is merely inferred from that document's creation of three branches? Courts in Florida have concluded that with respect to delegations of power to adminis- trative agencies a more strict separation of powers is required because of the explicit textual statement in the state constitution.14 New Jersey courts, by con- trast, despite the presence in that state's constitution of a provision virtually identical to Florida9s,1s reach the opposite conclusion:

There is no indication that our State Constitution was intended, with respect to the delegation of legislative power, to depart from the basic concept of distribution o f the powers of government embodied in the Fed- eral Constitution. It seems evident that in this regard the design spellcd out in our State Constitution would be implied in con- stitutions which are not explicit in this re- gard. . . . We have heretofore said our State Constitution is "no more restrictive" in this respect than the Federal Constitution. . . . Indeed in our State the judiciary has ac- cepted delegations of legislative power which probably exceed federal experience.16

Generally speaking, however, state courts seem to enforce the separation of powers doctrine, at least in the area of delegations of legislative authority to agencies, more strictly than is the case with separa- tion of powers doctrine in the federal government."

The State Legislative Branch

State legislatures are, historically, the fountainhead of representative government in this country. A number of them have their roots in colonial times, and substantially an- tedate the creation of our Nation and our Federal Government. In fact, the first for- mal stirrings of American political inde- pendence are to be found, in large part, in the views and actions of several of the colo- nial legislative bodies.

Chief Justice Earl Warren18

Despite the legal and political changes that have occurred since 1776, resulting in the types of limita- tions on the state legislative branch described below, state legislatures remain extraordinarily powerful. They are the local point of policymaking in state gov- ernment. The prevailing view is illustrated by the Su- preme Court of Illinois:

Under traditional constitutional theory, the basic sovereign power of the State re- sides in the legislature. Therefore, there is no need to grant power to the legislature. All that needs to be done is to pass such limita- tions as are desired on the legislature's oth- erwise unlimited power.19

Limitations on Legislative Power

A commentator observed in 1892 that "one of the most marked features of all recent State constitu- tions is the distrust shown of the legislature."20 The transition from early state constitutions granting un- fettered legislative power to the more recent consti- tutions restricting legislative power reflects one of the most important themes in state constitutional law. The cleiirly established pattern during the founding decade of 1776-1787 was a gradual transi- tion from lcgislalive dominance, or "omnipotence," to an increased rolc for thc executive and judicial branches21 Thc new exccutive and judicial powers operated as a check on rccognizcd legislative power rather than a sharing of lcgislative power.

In 1776 and the years immediately following, virtually all of the newly independent constitution- makers' trust was placed in the legislative branch, al- beit usually in two houses. It was generally felt that, under the newly flourishing ideas of republicanism, representatives in government should be like the citi- zens themselves and mirror as closely as possible the makeup of the population.22 The idea of professional politicians or representatives had not yet developed. Rather, the virtuous members of society would serve, on a rotating basis, for short terms, representing small districts, and honor instructions from their con- stituents. As Gordon Wood has observed, at this time, "a tyranny l y the people was theoretically in- conceivable."23

The legislative branch had been identified with the people themselves and was viewed as a safeguard against exccutive abuses rather than a possible source of abuses itself. Under these circumstances, the 3776 brand of legislative supremacy, although not supported unanimously, was not surprising. Effective checks on this legislative power were not viewed by many as necessary because, aRer so many years of abuses by the Ilritish, the newly independent Ameri- cans did not foresee that "the people," as repre- sented in the legislature, would also commit abuses.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 39

This philosophy soon began to change, however, clusio czlterius (the expression of one is the as experience under the new legislative supremacy exclusion of another).26 proved to be less than satisfactory. The range of highly visible legislative abuses, such as suspension of debts, seizure of the property of Loyalists, generous authorization of paper money, and legislative inter- ference with the executive and judicial branches, be- gan to raise concerns. Increased executive veto power came to be viewed as not inconsistent with popular sovereignty but, rather, as a necessary mechanism to limit legislative power. In this way, even within revo- lutionary republican rhetoric, with its absence of reli- ance on a hierarchial social structure that had justi- fied "balanced government," the case could be made for checks on the misuse of power by government of- ficials.Z4 In Gordon Wood's words, "The Americans' inveterate suspicion and jealousy of political power, once concentrated almost exclusively on the Crown and its agents, was transferred to various statc legisla- tures."25

The transition in American history has been from relatively unfettered legislative powcr to a more evenly balanced distribution of governmental powers among the branches. In addition, the legislative arli- cles of modern state constitutions reflect two impor- tant characteristics: (1) the insertion of specific "con- stitutional legislation" into state constitutional texts, thereby supplanting legislative prerogatives and sometimes leading to a limitation of legislative alter- natives through judicially discovered "negative irnpli- cations" and (2) the insertion into state constitutions of detailed procedural requirements that the legisla- ture must follow in the enactment of statutory law.

Negative Implication

Many state constitutions include provisions that could be relegated to statutory law. When these pro- visions mandate legislative actions or grant authority to a legislature vested with plenary power, courts can transform these apparent grants of power into limita- tions on legislative power. As Frank Grad noted:

It must be emphasized that very nearly everything that may be included in a state constitution operates as a restriction on the legislature, for both commands and prohibi- tions directed to other branches of the gov- ernment or even to the individual citizen will operate to invalidate inconsistent legisla- tion. . . . In constitutional theory state gov- ernment is a government of plenary powers, except as limited by the state and federal constitutions. . . . In order to give effect to such special authorizations, however, courts have often given them the full effect of nega- tive implications, relying sometimes on the canon of construction expressio unius est ex-

For these reasons, many apparent grants of authority become, through judicial interpretation, limits on legislative power. This can be a hidden dimension of state constitutional language, which, when inter- preted by state courts, can transform grants into lim- its. For example, many state constitutions contain fairly explicit provisions on legislative compensation which, of course, would be within the legislative power even in the absence of such constitutional pro- visions. If the legislature seeks, by statute, to provide some other form of compensation, it is often argued that the constitutional provision contains an implied limitation on lcgislative authority in the area of com- pensation.27

Procedural Limitations on the Enactment of Statutes

The legislative articlcs of virtually all state con- stitutions contain a wide range of limitations on state legislative processes. Gcncrally, these procedural limitations did not appear in the first state constitu- tions. Instead, thcy were adopted throughout the 19th century in response to perceived abuses of legis- lative powers. Last-minute consideration of impor- tant measures; logrolling; mixing substantive provi- sions in omnibus bills; low visibility and hasty enactment of important, and sometimes corrupt, leg- islation; and the attachment of unrelated provisions to bills in the amendment process-to name a few of these abuses-led to the adoption of constitutional provisions restricting the legislative process. These Lnstitutional provisions seek generally to require a more open and deliberative state legislative process, one that addresses the merits of legislative proposals in an orderly and deliberative manner.

Familiar examples of state constitutional limita- tions on the legislature include requirements that a bill contain a title disclosing its content and include only matters on a "single subject";28 that all bills be referred to comrnittee;29 that the vote on a bill be re- flected in the legislature's journal;30 that no bill be al- tered during its passage through either house so as to change its original p~rpose ;~ ' and that appropria- tions bills contain provisions on no other subject.32 These procedural restrictions must be distinguished from the comlnon substantive limits on state legisla- tion, such as those prohibiting statutes limiting wrongful death recoveries33 or mandating a certain type of civil service system,34 and from the general limits contained in state bills of rights.

Such procedural requirements for enacting stat- utes provoke criticism on a number of grounds. rang- ing from the claim that the requirements "have caused considerable damage through invalidation of noncomplying laws on technical grounds,"35 to the

40 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

assertion "that an argument bascd on the onc sul?jcct rule is often the argument of a despcratc advocate who lacks a sufficiently sound and persuasive onc."36 Judicial precedents add little certainty to thc applica- tion of the generally worded title and single-subject requirements.

Despite such criticism, the limitations on state legislative procedure survived the wave of state con- stitutional revision that occurred during the middle of the 20th century. Therefore, because these limits have, in effect, been readopted in contemporary state constitutions, they reflect policies relating to the na- ture of the deliberative process in state legislatures. Further, they represent an important limit on legisla- tive authority and illustrate the lasting result of ear- lier public disillusionment with legislative abuses.

Although the procedural limits outlined above are usually discussed as if they were all of the same quality, there are important differences. Some provi- sions require the legislature to act affirmatively, while others prohibit certain acts. A violation of cer- tain restrictions, such as title and single-subject pro- visions, can be seen from examining the text of the fi- nal legislative enactment. By contrast, a violation of other restrictions, such as the prohibition of a bill be- ing altered on its passage through either house so as to change its original purpose, will not be reflected on the face of the final legislative enactment. Conse- quently, a search for this type of violation requires an examination of the procedure leading to the enact- ment.

State courts have developed a surprisingly wide range of approaches to enforcing restrictions on leg- islative procedure under circumstances where an act on its face does not violate procedural limitations. Some courts will not "go behind" an enrolled bill, duly signed by legislative officers, to consider evi- dence of violation of legislative procedure provisions in state constitutions. Other courts will scrutinize the official legislative journals but not other evidence. Still other courts will consider any relevant evidence of such state constitutional violations. Even within single jurisdictions, one can detect inconsistent doc- trines and a lack of continuity over time. These widely varying judicial doctrines reflect what are essentially volitical decisions, made in the context of adiudicat- hg actual controversies, concerning the extcit of ju- dicial enforcement of state constitutional norms. On rare occasions, these procedural provisions may in- validate a statute. More importantly, such restric- tions make the state legislative process significantly different from, and more rigidly slructurcd than, the congressional legislative process.37

Direct Legislation

cation of public clissat isfriclion with state legislatures. Initiat ives enablc t t ~ c publ ic to bypass unresponsive statc legislatures, and rcfercnda provide a check on the effect of unpopular statutes. 'I'hese devices are more sophisticated than thc earlier procedural re- strictions, most of which reflected general disap- proval of legislative actions. The initiative allows the people to take direct action when the legislature re- fuses to act. The referendum enables the people to target specific enactments rather than depend on the indirect deterrence of procedural restrictions.

Although state constitutions contained specific provisions requiring a referendum on such questions as assumption of debts and changes in the constitu- tional text. the people of South Dakota began the process of taking back, or reserving to themselves, a measure of gcneral legislative power in a constitu- tional amendment approved in 1898. Now, 21 states provide for thc statutory initiative, and 25 provide for the referendum.38 One observer predicted that "[tlhe more direct legislation you have. . . the greater the body of judge-made law.'Qg This view raises inter- esting and complex questions of political philosophy, especially today when many major public issues are resolved at the ballot box.40 Legal questions also arise with regard to initiated statutes: (1) Can they be amended or rcpcalcd by the legislature? (generally yes, unless the stale constitution provides to the con- trary); (2) Can lhey be vetoed by the governor? (gen- erally no); (3) Do the title and single-subject limita- tions apply? (generally yes); (4) How should courts interpret such statutes? (according to the under- standing of the ordinary, intelligent voter).

The State Executive Branch Public distrust of the executive branch, as re-

flected in the early state constitutions, historically has been inversely related to public distrust of the legislative branch. The executive branch began in dis- favor,'+' but has gained more power and authority over the centuries. State constitutions have been amended gradually to bring gubernatorial powers closer to those assigned to the President under the federal Constilution, including longer terms of office (all but two states now have four-year gubernatorial terms) and stronger budgetary authority.

Constitutional Dulies and Agencies Although thc cxccu t ivc branch's main responsi-

bility is usually Ihotlght of as the faithful execution of the laws, state constitutions directly assign numerous functions to governors and cxecutive branch officials and agencies. I:or cxitmplc, constitutions often assign the powcr of executive clemency to the governor, thereby insulating the exercise of that from legislative or judicial interference. -

The initiative and referendum movement that The people in many states have created execu- emerged at the turn of this century was another indi- tive agencies through "constitutional legislation."

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 41

The status of such constitutional agencies or offices in relation to the legislature can be very different from statutorily created executive agencies or offices. For example, the Florida Supreme Court invalidated a statute prohibiting hunting on Sundays on the ground that it conflicted with an atlministrutive rule of the constitutionally establishcd Gamc and Fish <'om- mission. The rule provided for a one-month hunting season that included Sundays.42

Most state constitutions also provide for the statewide election of executivc officials other than the governor. Therefore, such officials as attorncys general, secretaries of state, commissioners of educa- tion, state treasurers, and others, in states where such offices are constitutionally created, develop their own constitutional and political base or power, neces- sarily detracting from centralized gubernatorial power. In Florida, where the governor shares power with six elected executive officials ("the cabinet"), proposals to streamline the system are extremely

The Veto Power

In 1776, the exercise of a veto by the executive was generally thought to be "aristocratic," and too much like the exercise of the veto by the royal colo- nial governors. That view began to change, however, as it was recognized that there needed to be some ex- ecutive check on legislative power. Now, the gover- nors of all states except North Carolina have the power to veto enactments of the legislature.

The gubernatorial "negative voice" in legisla- tion, however, was basically an "all-or-nothing" power. The veto power was, therefore, even more broadly expanded with the advent, around the turn of the century, of the item veto over specific line items in appropriations bills.44 Some states go beyond the item veto and permit governors to reduce such line items without vetoing them.45 President Ronald Reagan suggested that the President be authorized to exercise an item veto similar to that of governors;46 thus, the item veto has become a subject of national debate.47 Gubernatorial exercise of the item veto, originally intended to prevent legislative "logroll- ing," presents a range of complex issues. For exam- ple, what constitutes an "item" in an appropriations bill? May a governor veto language or restrictions without vetoing the appropriation itself? What con- stitutes an appropriations bill? These and other re- lated questions have resulted in a relatively large vol- ume of recent l i t i g a t i ~ n . ~ ~

Executive Orders

A recent series of cases concerning cthics and conflicts of interest addressed thc extent ol' gubcrna- torial authority to make policy through cxccutivc or- ders. Several governors promulgated financial disclo-

sure requirements and conflict-of-interest guidelines by executive order which, in the absence of clear leg- islative authority, were challenged as being beyond the executive power. In the leading case, Rapp v. Carey,49 the New York Court of Appeals invalidated the executive order:

The crux of thc case is the principle that the Governor has only thoscpowers delegated to him by the constitution and the statutes.. . . Under our system of distribution of power with checks and balances, the purposes of the executive order, however desirable, may be achieved only through proper means.

Based on the proposition that the executive branch may exercise only thosepowers delegated to it by the constitution or statute, the question of implied pow- ers is often crucial. This consideration may be con- trasted with the importance of implied limitations on the legislative branch.

The State Judicial Branch Statc constitutions govern the judicial branch in

many respccts. They have been the vehicles for streamlining and unifying state court systems. State constitutions usually set forth in some detail the juris- diction of most state courts. Finally, the method of se- lection and tenure of state judges is controlled by the state contstitulion.

Statc suprcme courts serve a number of impor- tant functions within state government and the legal systcm. Most familiar is their role in common law de- velopment and statutory and constitutional interpre- tation, functions performed in the context of adjudi- cating cases. Interestingly, state supreme courts developed the concept of judicial review of the con- stitutionality of statutes well before Marbury v. Madison.50 Most studies of state courts focus on their adjudicatory function in deciding cases. A major fo- cus of the study of state constitutional law, however, should be on the nonadjudicatory functions (outside the decision of cases) of state supreme courts.

Rules of Practice and Procedure Supreme courts in many states have constitu-

tional authority to promulgate rules of practice and procedure for the courts. Although this power is ex- plicitly granted now in many constitutions, earlier commentators regarded it as an inherent judicial power.51 Exercise of the rulemaking power reaches such crucial areas of lawyers' work as discovery and class actions. This grant of power to the courts serves as a limitation on legislative authority. Therefore, statutes that inwdc thc proccdural realm may be in- validated by thc courts.

'I'hc rclntionship between statutes and court rules varics from statc to statc, but common issues arise. For example, in thc famous case of Winberry v.

42 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Salisbury,52 the New Jersey Supreme Courl hcld lhat the New Jersey Constitution53 prohibits the lcgisla- ture from statutorily overriding court rules. Othcr states resolve this issue by rcfercnce to the specific constitutional language involved. For example, Florida's constitution provides: "These rules may be repealed by general law enacted by two-thirds vote of the membership of each house of the legis la t~re ."~

The distinction between practice and procedure is easier to define than to apply. For example, does the following formulation apply to the law of evi- dence? "[Slubstantive law creates, defines, adopts and regulates rights, while procedural law prescribes the method of enforcing those rights."55 When the Florida legislature passed a comprehensive statutory evidence code, the Florida Supreme Court resolvcd the potential conflict by adopting the evidence code as a court rule.56 The Colorado Supreme Court avoided a possible conflict between its rulemaking authority and a rape shield statute by holding that the statute would stand because there was no conflicting court rule on the subject.57Taking a different view of its relationship to the legislature, the New Jersey Su- preme Court has intimated that because it can make substantive law in common law adjudications there is no need for the court to limit itself strictly to practice and procedure in its rulemaking capacity.58

Regulation of the Practice of Law

Another power initially claimed to be inherent in the judiciary relates to the admission and discipline of attorneys.59 Many state constitutions now expressly confer this power on the courts and, again, as a grant of judicial authority, this power serves as a limitation on the legislature. Surprisingly, to many people, state legislatures may not pass statutes concerning the ad- mission and discipline of lawyers. A recent series of cases in Pennsylvania held that the state ethics act could not be applied to lawyers.60 "Sunset" legisla- tion applying to statutes regulating professions may not apply to the practice of law.

Through the exercise of their power to regulate the bar, courts have promulgated the modern student practice rules that form the basis for clinical legal education.61 The New Jersey Supreme Court utilized the power to place limits on attorneys' fccs for tort cases,62 and most courts are now grappling wilh law- yer advertising and specialization. Thc Florida Su- preme Court, now followed by many othcrs. used the power to regulate the practice of law to initiate an in- novative program that permits lawycrs to place funds entrusted to them in interest-bearing accounts and to use the revenues for various public service pr0jects.6~

Inherent Powers of the Courts

In recent years, particularly with respect to bud- getary matters, state courts have been asserting that:

. . . thc Judiciiiry must possess the inherent powcr to tlcterrnine and compel payment of those sums of lnoncy which are reasonable and ncccssary to carry out its mandated re- sponsibilities, and its powers and duties to administer Justice, if it is to be in reality a co- equal, independent Branch of our Govern- ment.e4

This claim of inherent powers raises important ques- tions of political theory. However, the issue of whether the branches of state government exercise delegated or inherent powers islargely academic. Be- cause state constitutions provide that all legislative power resides in the legislature, the important task is to define the legislative power, not to quibble over whether that power is inherent or delegated. State constitutions similarly place the judicial power in the judiciary; consequently, rather than debating whether a court's power is inherent, the inquiry should focus on whether the claimed power is prop- erly and necessarily a judicial function.

Advisory Opinions Eleven state constitutions authorize or require

state supreme courts to render advisory opinions to various governmental officials." States differ, of course, as to which officers may request opinions and when thcy may do so. The courts tend to construe strictly their authority and obligations under these provisions.66 Interesting questions may arise as to the precedential value of advisory opinions. After all, ad- visory opinions are not adjudications of actual contro- versies, and are not exercises of the traditional "judi- cial power." According to the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts:

It has been uniformly and many times held that such opinions, although necessarily the result of judicial examination and delibera- tion, are advisory in nature, given by the jus- tices as individuals in their capacity as consti- tutional advisors of the other departments of government and without the aid of argu- ments, are not adjudications by the court, and do not fall within the doctrine of stare decisis. 67

There secms to be cvidcnce that, in the context of ad- visory opinions, courts do not accord the same pre- sumption of corrcclncss to the actions of the other branches that they do in adjudicating cases. The advi- sory opinion can bc vicwcd as an important safety valve standing in Lhc way of unconstitutional actions.

The Position and Function of the State Judiciary in Adjudication

In addition to these nonadjudicatory functions of state supreme courts, the state courts differ signifi- cantly from federal courts even with respect to adju-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 43

dication. The typical state court system occupies a dif- ferent institutional position and performs a different judicial function from its federal counterpart. The typical state constitution also differs from its federal counterpart in many ways. Consequently, state court judicial review of state statutes or executive actions is, or should be, qualitatively different from the federal court judicial review of the same statutes or actions. First, as noted earlier, beginning soon after inde- pendence, the balance of power between state lcgis- latures and judiciaries has been gradually shifting, in- creasing executive (as discussed earlier) and judicial authority at the expense of legislative authority. In addition, the wide range of detailed restrictions on state governments contained in state constitutions is enforceable by state courts, bringing them into a much more detailed involvement in the workings of the other branches. For all these reasons, statc courts are often deeply involved in the state's ongoing poli- cymaking processes (constitutional and nonconstitu- t i~nal ) .~* Although the extent of this involvement may vary from state to ~ t a t e , ~ g such judicial involve- ment nevertheless reflects a very different institu- tional position from that occupied by the federal courts.

Second, the typical state court's judicial function is different from the federal court's. For example, state courts have traditionally performed much non- constitutional lawmaking. As Justice Hans A. Linde observed:

When a state court alters the law of prod- ucts liability, abolishes sovereign or charita- ble tort immunity, redefines the insanity defense, or restricts the range of self- exculpation in contracts of adhesion, its ac- tion is rarely attacked as "undemocratic." Nor is this judicial role peculiar to matters of common law subject to legislative rcvcrsal. The accepted dominance of courts in statc law extends to their "antimajoritarian" rolc in review of their coordinate political branches in state and local governments.70

Federal courts, although they certainly have far- reaching powers to enforce federal law, have been denied this general lawmaking power since 1938, when, in Erie Railroad v. Tompkins,71 the US. Su- preme Court declared that federal courts do not have the power to make common law decisions binding on states.

As discussed earlier, most state supreme courts promulgate law through rulemaking powers. They also exercise various "inherent powers," usually at the expense of the legislative branch. Once thought to be legislative in nature, these powers have dc- volved on state judiciaries during this century.

Many state supreme courts do not face the same overwhelming caseload pressures and jurisdictional restrictions as does the U.S. Supreme Court. Some state courts even have "reach down" provisions72 that enable them to obtain jurisdiction quickly over state constitutional conflicts requiring early resolution. Therefore, state courts are able to approach state constitutional analysis on a narrower, more incre- mental basis than the U.S. Supreme Court, which la- bors under intense pressure for broader, more sweeping pronouncements.

Finally, state courts may be viewed as closer to state affairs and as arguably more accountable to state citizens than federal courts. Many state consti- tutions provide for an elected judiciary, or periodic review of appointed judges. Standing and jus- ticiability barriers are usually lower in the state courts. Furthermore, in certain areas, such as crimi- nal procedure, state trial judges are more experi- enced than fcdcral judgcs in the problems of admini- stering U.S. Suprcme Court formulations on a daily basis. Many stale judges now view their roles as some- times requiring controversial constitutional rulings.

Judicial Review By contrast to the federal Constitution, the text

of a state constitution may provide explicitly for state judicial review of legislative and executive action. For example, Article I, Section 2, paragraph 5 of the Georgia Constitution provides: "Legislative Acts in violation of this Constitution or the Constitution of the United States are void, and the judiciary shall so declare them."The North Dakota Constitution, how- ever, imposes a voting rule on judicial review: "The supreme court shall not declare a legislative enact- ment unconstitutional unless at least four of the [five] members of the court so decide" (Article VI, Section 4).

Contrary lo the federal experience, most judici- ary provisions of state constitutions have been re- vised and ratified in this ccntury without a serious struggle over the cxercisc of judicial review. As indi- cated earlier, judicial rcvicw existed in the states prior to thc fedcriil Constitution and the landmark Marbury v. Mudison dccision in 1803, in which Chief Justice John Marshall established the doctrine of ju- dicial review for the U.S. Supreme Court. The fact that state constitutions are so much more easily amended than is the federal Constitution has led to at least some support for an increased level of judicial scrutiny of statutes because "mistakes" can be more easily corrected by the electorate.73

Imal Government and State Constitutions

Local governments have a very wide range of powers and responsibilities in the American govern-

44 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

mental system. Actually, the existence of local gov- ernments predates national independence and the formation of the states. It is surprising, therefore, to note that the first state constitutions were virtually si- lent on the question of local governments and their powers. As one commentator noted, the early state constitutions did not separate "powers vertically (state-local) as well as horizontally (executive-legisla- tive-judicial)."74 This absence of "constitutional le- gitimacy"75 for local governments caused a number of problems in developing legal and political justifica- tions for their ongoing existence and exercise of pow- ers. These justifications varied, until finally, by the 1860s, the famous "Dillon's Rule" of local govern- ment subordination to the state legislature gained ac- ceptance:

Municipal corporations owe their origin to, and derive their powers and rights wholly from, the legislature. It breathes into them the breath of life, without which they cannot exist. As it creates, so it may destroy. If it may destroy, it may abridge and contr01.~"

This dependent status of local governments, par- ticularly of large cities, became more and more unsat- isfactory as cities and their problems grew, while rural-dominated state legislatures tended to give in- sufficient attention to urban problems. Local leaders began to argue for their own powers, which they could utilize to address local problems without con- stantly seeking authority from a sometimes distant and unconcerned state legislature. These local con- cerns led to the home rule movement, a major com- ponent of which involved state constitutional amend- ments granting semi-autonomous powers to local governments.77 The forms of these amendments have followed several different models, have evolved over time,78 and have generated much litigation ovcr the question of whether an area of concern can I)e dealt with by local government rather than by the state legislature.79 For example, the well-known Vil- lage of Morton Grove gun control case in Illinois turned on, among other things, the home rule power to regulate firearms.aO

In addition to home rule, many other areas of lo- cal government are directly affected by state constitu- tions. Taxation and finance, for example, including the tax limitation movement of the 1970s, are treated in detail in state constit~tions.~' The recent move- ment to require state funding to enable local govern- ments to carry out state-imposed "mandates" has re- sulted in constitutional amendments in seven states (and statutory provisions in seven other slates) re- quiring such legislative funding, although those rulcs are not always effective.82 Finally, there appears to be a significant trend in the judicial interpretation of state constitutions that recognizes "localism'? as a

state constitutional value, at least in litigation over exclusionary zoning and school finance.83

Conclusion The evolution of the treatment of government

structure in state constitutions reflects, to a great ex- tent, the progressing understanding of American government. As citizens came to understand the need for expanded executive power and the dangers of unfettered legislative authority, the legislative- executive balance was adjusted. As the need for judi- cial independence, court unification, and additional, intermediate courts was felt, state constitutions were amended to accommodate these needs. Calls by local government 1e;ldet-s for increased powers were, al- beit slowly, recognized by constitutional home rule provisions.

The picture of state constitutions as governmen- tal straitjackets, or inhibitors of change, has been changing. There has been movement toward what Daniel J. Elazar calls the "managerial pattern" of state constitutions, characterized by "conciseness, broad grants of powers to the state executive branch, and relatively few structural restrictions on the legis- lature."84

Still, however, state constitutions contain many costly restrictions on the way state and local govern- ments operate, if not on how they are structured. This is particularly true in the area of taxation and finance. It must be remembered, in the words of Frank P. Grad:

The least we may demand of our state consti- tutions is that they interpose no obstacle to the necessary exercise of state powers in re- sponse to state residents' real needs and ac- tive demands for service.85

NOTES 1 Willi Paul Aclams. 7he Fitst Anierican Constit~ctionr Re- prrblicun Idedop cind /he Making of the State Constitu- tions in the Kcw~l~rtionary Era (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina I'rcss, 198I1), pp. 55-56.

2William M. Wiccck, Tile Gnurantee Clause of the United States Consti~ntion (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1972).

3~acific States Telephone and Telegraph Co. v. Oregon, 223 U.S. 118 (1912).

4See Coyle v. Smith, 221 U.S. 559 (1911). See also Peter S. Onuf, "New State Equality: The Ambiguous History of a Constitutional Principle," Publius: The Journal of Feder- alism 16 (Fall 1986): 53-69.

5Prentice v. Atlantic Coast Line Railroad, 211 U.S. 210, 255 (1908).

6New State Icc Co. v. Liebmann, 285 U.S. 262,311 (1932) (13randcis. J.. disscnting).

7'I'ruax v. (hrrigan, 257 U.S. 312,344 (1921) (Holmes. J., disscnting)

8Pennsylvariiu Packet. December, 1778, The Coniplete Wtititrgs of '/%omas Puine, ed. Philip S. Foner, 2 Vols. (New York: Citaclel Press, 1969), 2:281.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 45

9See L. Harold Levinson, "The Decline of the Legislative Veto: FederalIState Comparisons and Interactions," Publius: The Journalof Federalism 17 (Winter 1987): 115.

loFrank P. Grad, "The State Constitution: It's Function and Form in Our Time," Virginia Law Review 54 (June 1968): 941.

11 State ex rel. Schneider v. Kennedy, 225 Kan. 13, 587 P 2nd 844,850. (1978)

12The Italia Shipping Corp. v. Nelson, 323 Ill. 427, 439 (1926).

13Robert F. Williams, "Evolving State Legislative and Ex- ecutive Power in the Founding Decade," Annals of h e American Academy of Political and Social Science 496 (March 1988): 43. See also John V. Orth, "Separate and Distinct: Separation of Powers in North Carolina," Notth Carolina Law Review 62 (October, 1983): 1.

14Askew v. Cross Key Waterways, 372 So. 2d 913,924 (Fla. 1978); Robert W. Martin Jr., "Legislative Delegations of Power and Judicial Review-Preventing Judicial Impo- tence," Florida State Universi~ Law Review 8 (Winter 1980): 51.

15New Jersey Constitution. Article 111, Section 1. 16Brown v. Heymann, 297 A 2d 572, 576-77 (NJ, 1972);

Martin, "Legislative Delegations," p. 51 n. 41. 17Frank E. Cooper, State Administrative Law, 2 vols. (Indi-

anapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965), 1:31. 18Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533,564 (1964). 1QClient Follow-Up Co. v. Hynes, 390 N.E. 26 847,849 (Ill.

1979). 20Amasa M. Eaton,"Recent State Constitutions," Haward

Law Review 6 (October 1892): 109. 21 Gordon S.Wood, The Creation of the American Republic,

1776-1 787 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1969), p. 452.

22See also Rodney 0. Davis, "The People in Miniature': The Illinois General Assembly, 1818-1848," Illinois His- torical Journal 81 (Summer 1988): 95-108.

23 Wood, Creation of the American Republic, p. 62. 24Peter S. Onuf, "State Politics and Ideological Transfor-

mation: Gordon S. Wood's Republican Revolution," William and Mary Quarterly, 3rd ser. 44 (July 1987): 614.

25 Wood, Creation of the American Republic, p 409. 2"rad, "The State Constitution," 964-966. 27For a case avoiding this negative implication problem,

see Eberle v. Nielson, 78 Idaho 572,306 P.2d 1083 (1957). 28Millard H. Ruud, "No Law Shall Embrace More than

One Subject," Minnesota Law Review 42 (January 1958): 389.

29See, e.g., Pennsylvania Constitution, Article 111, Section 2.

Sosee, e.g., Ohio Constitution, Article 11, Section 9. 31 See, e.g., Pennsylvania Constitution, Article 111, Section

1. 32See, e.g., Florida Constitution, Article 111, Section 12. 33Grad, "The State Constitution," p. 955 n. 92. 341bid., pp. 961-62. 35Ibid., p. 963. 36Ruud, "No Law Shall Embracc," p. 447. 37Robert F. Williams, "State Constitutional Limits on

Legislative Procedure: Legislative Compliance and Jutli-

cia1 Enforcement," Publirrs: The Journal of Federalism 17 (Winter 1987): 91.

38David Maglcby, Direct Legislation: Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (Baltimore: John Hop- kins liniversi ty Press, 1984), pp. 38-40.

39Georgc Iefcoe and Barney Allison, "The Legal Aspects of Proposition 13: 'l'hc Aniador Valley Case," Southern California LLW &view 53 (November 1979): 172.

40Sce Richard Ilril'k~ult, "Distrust of Democracy," Terar Law Review 63 (MarchIApril 1985): 1347 (reviewing Magleby, Direct 1.rgislatioti).

41 "The Americans, in short, made of the gubernatorial magistrate a new kind of creature, a very pale reflection indeed of his regal ancestor. This change in the gover- nor's position meant the effectual elimination of the magistracy's major responsibility for ruling the soci- ety-a remarkable and abrupt departure from the Eng- lish constitutional tradition." Wood, Creation of the American Republic, p. 136. See also pp. 132-43.

42Whitehead v. Rogers, 223 So2d 330 (Fla. 1969). Compare Bums v.Butscher, 187 So. 26 594 (Fla. 1966) with District School Board v. Askew, 278 So. 2d 272,275 (Fla. 1973) ("constitutional officers").

43See Jon C. Moyle, "Why We Should Abolish Florida's Elected Cabinet," Florida State Univetsity Law Review 6 (Summer 1978): 591; Malcolm B. Johnson, "Why We Should Keep Florida's Elected Cabinet," p. 603.

44See generally Ada E. Bechman, "The Item Veto Power of the Executive," Temple Law Quarterly 31 (Fall 1957): 27; Arthur J. Harrington, "The Propriety of the Nega- tive-The Governor's Partial Veto Authority," Mar- quette Law Review 60 (Spring 1977): 865.

451nterestingly. this notion of gubernatorial reduction of appropriation items, as opposed to absolute veto, seems to stem from Pennsylvania's judicial interpretation in Commonwealth v. Barnett, 199 Pa. 161,48 A 976 (1901) of its provision lo permit such reductions. Virtually all other courts that hiwe considered the issue have rejected this interpretation. See. e.g., Wood v. State Administra- tion Board 255 Mich. 220 238 N.W. 16 (19311 Mills v. Porter, 69 Mont. 325, 222 P 428 (1924):A nbmber of states, however, have amended their constitutions to authorize gubernatorial reduction. See generally Note, "Item Veto, Reduction of Items, Elimination of Items Included in a General Sum," Southern California Law Review 12 (March 1939): 321.

46NewYork Times, October 25, 1981. Not surprisingly, this suggestion came from a former governor of California, a state where governors may reduce items. The idea is not new. See for example, Note, "Separation of Powers: Con- gressional Riders and the Veto Power," Universily of Michigan Journal of'Law Reform 6 (NO. 3 1973): 735.

47Louis Fisher and Neal Devins, "How Successfully Can the States' Itcm Veto Be Transferred to the President?" Georgetown Law Journal 75 (October 1986): 159. See also House Conimlttce on Rules, Item Veto: State Eyerience and its Application to the Federal Situation, 99th Con- gress, 2nd Session (Committee Print 1986), and U.S. Ad- visory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations, Fiscal Discipline in the Federal System: National Reform and the Erpe~ierice of the States (Washington, DC: ACIR, 1987).

48Scc, for cx;~niplc. Ilrown v. Fircstonc, 382 So. 26 654(Fla. 1080); Sli~tc IT rc:l Scgo v. K~rkpatrick. 86 N.M. 359,524 P.W 975 (1974): Ki~rchcr v. Kcan, 97 N.J. 483. 479 A.2d 403 (1984); State ex rcl. Klcc~ka v. Conta, 82 W.S. 2d 679, 364 N. W. 2d 530 ( 1978).

46 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

4944N.Y. 2d at 166-67,375 N.E. W at 750-51,404 N.Y.S.21 at 570. See also Buettell v. Walkcr, 59 I11 2d 146,319 N.E. 2d 502 (1974) (purpose of executive order appears to be to formulate a new legal requircnicnt rather than to cxe- cute an existing one); Shapp v. Butera, 22 1%. Commw. 229 348 A.2d 910 (1975) (governor has only those powers delegated by constitution or statute, or which may be im- plied from the nature of the duties imposed on him.) See generally Martin v. Chandler, 318 S.W. 2d 40 (Ky. 1958); Opinion of the Justices, 118 N.H. 582, 392 A.2d 125 (1978); Richard E. Faboriti, "Executive Power under the New Illinois Constitution: Field Revisited," Joi~n Mar- shall Journal of Practice and Procedure 6 (Spring 1973): 235; Note, "Gubernatorial Executive Orders as Devices for Administrative Discretion and Control," Iowa Law Review 50 (Fall 1964): 78.

SoEdward S. Corwin, "The Progress of Constitutional The- ory between the Declaration of Indepenclcnce and the Meeting of the Philadelphia Convention," Anlerican Historical Review 30 (April 1925): 521; William E. Nelson, "The Eighteenth Century Background of John Mar- shall's Constitutional Jurisprudence," Michigan Law Re- view 76 (May 1978): 893.

51See Roscoe Pound, "The Rulemaking Power of the Courts," American Bar Association J o ~ ~ n a l 12 (Septem- ber 1926): 599; John Henry Wigmore, "All Ixgislative Rules for Judiciary Procedure are Void Constitution- ally," Illinois Law Review 23 (November 1928): 276.

525 N.J. 244474 A.2d 406 (1950). 53The New Jersey Constitution provides: "The Supreme

Court shall make rules governing the administration of all courts in the State and subject to law, the practice and procedure in all such courts." New Jersey Constitution, Article 6, Section 2, paragraph 3 (emphasis added).

54Florida Constitution, Article 5, Section 2(a). Issues for judicial interpretation still remain. See, e.g., Carter v. Sparkman, 335 So. 2d 802,808 (Fla. 1976), cert. denied, 429 U.S. 1041 (1977) (repeal by implication not permit- ted): In re Clarification of Florida Rules of Practice and Procedure, 281 So. 2d 204 (Fla. 1973) (legislature may re- peal but not amend rules).

55In re Florida Rules of Criminal Procedure, 272 So. 2d 65 (Fla. 1973).

56See in re Florida Evidence Code, 376 So. 2d 1161 (Fla. 1979); In re Florida Evidence Code, 372 So. 2d 1369 (Fla. 1979).

57People v. McKenna, 196 Colo. 367,585 P. 275 (1978). See also Knight v. City of Margate, 86 NJ 374, 386-98, 431 A2d 833, 839-45 (1981) (distinguishing the existence of judicial rulemaking power from its exercise).

58Busik v. Levine, 63 NJ 351,307 A.2d 571 (1973). The constitutional grant of rulemaking power iis to practice and procedure is simply a grant of power; it would be a mistake to fincl in that grant restrictions upon judicial tcchniclues for the cx- ercise of that power, and still a largcr mistake to suppose that the grant of that power implicdly deprives the judiciary of flcxibility in the area called "substantive" law.

Id. at 363, 307, A.2d at 577. The difference, of course, between the two "techniques" of exercising judicial power was that the New Jersey Su- preme Court had held that the legislature could not over- rule court rules, although the legislature could ovenule substantive law decisions.

5QScc Petition of tlic Florida State Bar Ass'n, 40 S. 2d 902, 905-06 (Fa. 1940) and cases cited therein. See also Board of Overseers of the Bar v. ILC, 422 A.2d 998, 1002 (Me. 1980).

"See Wajert v. Slatc Ethics Commission, 491 Pa. 255,420 A.2d 439 (1980); Uallou v. State Ethics Commission, 56 Pa. Commw. 240,424 A.2d 983 (1981); Kremer v. State Ethics Commission, 56 Pa. Commw. 160,424 A.2d 968 (1981)(judges). ContraKnight v. City of Margate, 86N.J. 374, 431 A.2d 833 (1981). See generally Joseph D. Robertson and John W. Buehler, "The Separation of Powers and the Regulation of the Practice of Law in Oregon," Willametie Law Journal 13 (No. 2 1977): 273.

61See for example, Art XVIII, Integration Rule of the Florida Bar, as amended, cited in Attorney General and Others to Amend Article XVIII of the Integration Rule of the Florida Ilar. 339 So. 2d 646 (Fla. 1976).

62Sce American 'I'rial Lawyers Association v. New Jersey Supreme Court, 66 N.J. 258,330 A.2d 350 (1974).

63See generally In re Interest on Trust Accounts, 402 So. W 389 (Fla. 1981). The program is discussed in Com- ment, "A Source of Revenue for the Improvement of Le- gal Services, Part I," St. Mary's Law Jounlal 10 (No. 3 1978): 539; "Part 11," St. Mary's Law Jountal 11 (No. 1 1979): 113.

64Commonwcnlth ex re1 Caroll v. Tate, 442 Pa. 45,52,274 A.W 193, 197 (1971). See also Comment, "State Court Assertion of I1owcr to Determine and Demand Its Own Budget," Uuivemity of Pennsylvania Law Review 120 (June 1972): 1187. For a more recent example of the Pennsylvania C~ourt's thinking, see Beckert v. Warren, 439 A.2d 638 (Pa. 3!)81). See generally Geoffrey C. Haz- ard, Jr., Martin B. McNamara and Irwin F. Sentilles, 111, "Court Finance and Unitary Budgeting," Yale Law Jour- nal 81 (June 1972) 1286: Note. "Judicial Financial ~ u t o n o m ~ and ~nhdrent Power," ome ell ~ a w Review 57 (July 1972): 975. W e e generally Comment, "The State Advisory Opin- ion in Perspective," Fordham Law Review 44 (October 1975): 81.

66See In re House Resolution No 12, 88 Colo. 569, 298 (1931; In re Opinion of the Justices, 314 Mass. 767. 49 N.E. 2d 252 (1943).

67Commonwealth v. Welosky, 276 Mass. 398, 400, 177 N.E.656,658 (1931). The court continued:

When the same questions are raised in litigation, the justices then composing the court are bound sedulously to guard against any influence flow- ing from the previous consideration, to examine the subject anew in the light of arguments pre- sented by parties without reliance upon the views theretofore expressed, and to give the case the most painstaking and impartial study and de- terminat~on that an adequate appreciation ofju- dicial duty C ; I ~ inipcl.

Thc New I 1a1npshi1.c Supreme Court "caution[ed] that the op~nion is not ;t judicial clccision. . . ." In re Opinion of the Justices, 82 N.H. 561,575,138 A. 284,291 (1927). The Florida Constitution provides for "interested per- sons to bc heard on the qucstions presented." Florida Constitution, Art. IV, Section l(c).

68Henry Robert Glick. Supreme Cowts in State Politics (New York: Basic Books, 1971), p. 5: "State supreme courts are not simply duplications of the national court at a lower level of the judicial hierarchy. Instead, they are distinctive institutions which are integral parts of state political and legal systems." See also Herbert Jacob and

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 47

Kenneth N. Vines, Politics in the American States: A Comparative Analysis, 3d ed. (Boston: Little Brown and Co., 1976), p. 246: "I[t] becomes apparent that the state courts make significant policies in many of the same sub- stantive areas in the other organs of government."

69Glick, Supreme Courts, p. 151; Henry Robert Glick and Kenneth N. Vines, State Court Systems (1973). See gener- ally, G. Alan Tarr and Mary Cornelia Porter, State Su- preme Courts in State and Nation (New Haven: Yale Uni- versity Press, 1988).

70Hans A. Linde, "Judges, Critics, and the Realist Tradi- tion," Yale Law Journal 82(1972): 248. See also Lawrence Baum and Bradley C. Canon, "State Supreme Courts as Activists: New Doctrines in the Law of Torts," in Mary Cornelia Porter and G. Alan Tarr, State Supreme Courts: Policymakers in the Federal System (Westport. Connecti- cut: Greenwood Press, 1982), p.83. The "legitimacy" of such common-law decisions is sometimes attacked as in- vading the province of the legislature. See generally Ralph F. Bischoff, "The Dynamics of Tort Law: Court or Legislature?" Vermont Law Review 4 (Spring 1979): 35. State supreme courts also pursue policy initiatives out- side their formal judicial role in the adversary process, including direct and indirect contact with legislators. See Henry Robert Glick, "Policy-Making and State Supreme Courts: The Judiciary as an Interest Group," Law and Society Review 5 (November 1970): 271.

71 304 U.S. 64 (1938). 72See, for example, Arthur J. England, Jr., Eleanor

Mitchell Hunter, and Richard C. Williams, Jr., "Consti- tutional Jurisdiction of the Supreme Court of Florida: 1980 Reform," University of Florida Law Review 32 (Win- ter 1980): 193-96; Arthur J. England, Jr. and Richard C. Williams, "Florida Appellate Reform One Year Later," Florida State University Law Review 9 (Spring 1981): 250-53.

73Commonwealth v. O'Neal, 369 Mass. 242, 275, 339 N.E.2d 676,694 (1975). For the contrary view, see State v. Baker, 81 N.J. 99, 115-26,405 A.2d 368,375-81 (1979).

74James E. Herget, "The Missing Power of Local Govern- ment: A Divergence between Text and Practice in Our Early State Constitutions," Virginia Law Review 62 (June 1976): 1001.

75Ibid.

76Clinton v. Cedar Rapids and Missouri River Railroad, 24 Iowa 455 (1868), quoted in Michael E. Libonati, "Inter- governmental Relations in State Constitutional Law: A Historical Overview," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 496 (March 1988): 113.

77Jefferson I3. Forclham, "Foreword: Local Government in the I ~ r g e r Scheme of Things," Vanderbilt Law Review 8 (June 1955): 668-71.

78Kenneth Vanlandingham, "Constitutional Municipal Home Rule since the AMA (NLC) Model," William and Mary Law Review 17 (Fall 1975): 1.

%ee, for example. City of Miami Beach v. Fleetwood Ho- tel, Inc., 261 So. 2d 801 (Fla. 1972) (rent control); City of Miami Beach v. Forte Towers. Inc., 305 So. 26 764 (Fla. 1974) (same).

8oKalodimos v. Village of Morton Grove, 103 Ill. 2d 483, 474 N.E. W 266 (1984).

81 David M. Roscnberger, "Historical Perspective on Con- stitutional 1,irnitation of Property Taxes in Michigan," Wayne Low l k v i ~ w 24 (March 1978): 939; M. David Gel- fand, "Seeking Iocal Government Fiscal Integrity through Dcbt Ceilings, Tax Limitations, and Expendi- ture Limits: The New York Fiscal Crisis, the Taxpayers' Revolt, and Beyond," Minnesota Law Review 63 (1979): 545.

82U.S. General Accounting Office, Legislative Mandates: State @eriettces Offer Insights for Federal Action (Wash- ington, DC: GAO, September 1988); Libonati, "Inter- governmental Relations," p. 116; Durant v. State Board of Education, 424 Mich. 364, 381 N.W. 2d 622 (1985); Boone County Court v. State, 631 S.W. 2d 321 (Mo. 1982).

83Richard Briffault, "Localism in State Constitutional Law," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 496 (March 1988): 117.

BeDaniel J. Elazar, "The Principles and Traditions Under- lying State Constitutions," Publius: TheJoumal of Feder- alism 12 (Winter 1982): 22.

85Grad, "Thc State Constitution," p. 939.

48 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 4

The States and Civil Liberties Most Americans today view the protection of

civil liberties primarily as the responsibility of the U.S. Supreme Court, and they look to its rulings in- terpreting the federal Bill of Rights and the Four- teenth Amendment to discover the scope of individ- ual rights. Yet this identification of civil liberties with the federal Constitution and the U.S. Supreme Court is a relatively recent development in American his- tory. For most of the nation's history, the federal Bill of Rights was understood to protect solely against federal infringements on rights.' State law-as found in state bills of rights, state statutes, and the common law-served as the primary guarantor of individual liberties.

The dramatic shift in the relative roles played l y state law and federal law in protecting rights began in the early 20th century. In 1925 the U.S. Suprcme Court ruled that the First Amcndmcnt's ban on abridgements of freedom of speech by thc fcdcral government is applicable to the states by the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amcndmcnt.2 Over the next 50 years, the Supreme Court conlinucd its gradual process of selectively extending federal con- stitutional protection on a case-by-case basis against state violations of various other guarantees of the U.S. Bill of Rights.3 During the 1960s, this process, usually referred to as "selective incorporation," ac- celerated significantly, as the Supreme Court incor- porated most of the Bill of Rights' criminal justice guarantees.4

Selective incorporation influenced both the fo- rums in which civil liberties claims were advanced and the forms that those claims took. By ruling that the federal Constitution prohibited state violations of rights, the Supreme Court multiplied its opportuni- ties to address civil liberties issues. At the same time, the perception that federal forums were more sympa- thetic to rights claimants-a perception that often- times was quite accurate-diverted cases from state courts, thereby retarding the development of a state constitutional jurisprudence. Even when civil liber- ties issues arose in state tribunals, attorneys typically ignored state bills of rights or treated statc and fcd- era1 provisions as interchangeable, relying on the

U.S. Supreme Court for doctrine and legal prece- dent. The predictable result was the domination of civil liberties law by the federal judiciary.

Early in the 1970s, this domination was chal- lenged by a few state courts that began to rely on state bills of rights to rcsolve civil liberties issues.5 Since then, this devcloprnent, known as the "new judicial federalism," has bccome a nationwide phenome- non.6 State judges from all sections of the country have reported significant increases in litigation under state bills of rights.7 Scholars have identified some 400 cases sincc 1970 in which state high courts have either granted greater rights protection under their state constitutions than was granted by the U.S. Su- preme Court under the federal Constitution or have based their decisions affirming rights solely on their state constitulions.8

The crncrgcncc of lhc ncw judicial federalism raiscs ancw thc yucstion of what part state law can and should play in tlclincating and protecting rights. To answer this qucst ion, wc review in this chapter the debate over thc role to be assigned to statelaw in pro- tecting civil libertics. Next, to assess the contribution of state law in protecting rights, we consider how state law has dealt with selected aspects of the free- doms of speech, press, and religion. Clearly, no set of three issues can be fully representative. However, because the rights at stake in these three areas are so fundamental, our survey of state efforts to protect them furnishes some indication of the role currently played by state civil liberties 1aw.Q Equally important, our analysis of these issues illustrates the opportuni- ties that thc statcs have to contribute to the protec- tion of civil libcrties, the array of legal weapons at their disposal for this purpose, and the use that the statcs have made of these weapons.

A State Civil Liberties Law? Thc basic question to be addressed is whether

thc statcs should play any part in defining and pro- tecting rights. Opponents of state involvement have insistcd that thc protection of rights is properly a fed- eral rcsponsibil ity because all Americans should en- joy thc same rights, rather than having their rightsde-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 49

termined by accidents of geography (i.e., by where they live). In addition, they have suggested, whatever the theoretical arguments in favor of state involve- ment, the unhappy record of the states throughout American history in failing to safeguard rights justi- fies lodging this responsibility in thc fedcral govern- ment.

Undeniably, these arguments for an interstate uniformity of rights and for the protection of those rights by the national government have considerable force. However, they are hardly the whole story. There are important reasons rooted in American constitutional history and constitutional theory, as well as in the nature of American federalism, for state participation in defining and protecting rights.

Before elaborating those reasons, however, one might note the implications of the argument for an interstate uniformity in rights. That argument, ifgen- eralized, would justify the elimination of virtually all policymaking by the states. For if one's rights should not depend on "accidents of geography," neither pre- sumably should the availability of any other impor- tant benefit or service provided by government. How- ever, Americans have long accepted some state autonomy and a degree of diversity in the provision of benefits and services because we belicvc that. on bal- ance, the system of federalism that pcrmits such autonomy and diversity is a good system.10 'This, of course, hardly proves that there should be interstate differences in rights. Although we wclcome divcrsity in some matters, in others we have opted for national uniformity. Nonetheless, it does suggest that the mere fact of interstate diversity is not, in and of itself, a sufficient argument against participation in protect- ing rights.

The broader argument in favor of state participa- tion in defining and protecting rights begins with the recognition that such involvement is no innovation but rather an established feature of American consti- tutiona1ism.l Even before the adoption of the fed- eral Constitution, several states had assumed this re- sponsibility by prefacing their constitutions with bills of rights. Other states inserted protections for rights in the body of their charters. As initially proposed, the federal Constitution largely left the task of pro- tecting rights in state hands, since it did not include a bill of rights. Even when Antifederalist complaints led to the addition of a bill of rights, the First Con- gress made clear that state declarations of rights could and should continue to provide protection by reject- ing a proposal that guaranteed various rights against state infringement. Since then, all 50 states have in- cluded bills of rights in their constitutions and also have acted to secure rights through statutes and judi- cial rulings. Although the Fourteenth Amendment to the U.S. Constitution was designed to augment fed- eral power to prevent state violations of rights, the amendment was meant to supplement, rather than to preempt, state protections. Thus, as a matter of con- stitutional design, the states have from the outset

becn encouragccl to participate in defining and secur- ing rights, and throughout the nation's history they have donc so.

Yet in encouraging the states to define and pro- tect rights, the nation almost inevitably committed it- self to an interstatc diversity in rights. Even at the time the federal Constitution was adopted, there were important differences in the rights enjoying constitutional protection in the various states.12 Al- though one might have expected the adoption of the federal Bill of Rights to promote interstate uniform- ity by providing a model for emulation, in fact this has not occurred. In some instances, the states have looked to the fedcral Constitution for direction: for example, 33 states have adopted constitutional provi- sions that parallel the Second Amendment by tying the right to bear arms to the need for a "well-regu- lated militia."l3 But more frequently the states have looked to their sister states rather than to the na- tional government for guidance: 30 states, for exam- ple, have modeled constitutional protections on the Virginia Constitution's declaration that "all men are born equally free and independent."l4 Moreover, whereas the fcdcral Constitution has been amended only infrcqucntly to secure rights beyond those con- taincd in lhc llill of Rights, the states have not hesi- tated to amend thcir constilutions to recognize new rights or to extend protcction against new threats to rights. Between 1968 and 1976, for example, 16 states adopted constitutional guarantees of gender equal- ity.15 Finally, as Table 1 demonstrates, several states have adopted protections for rights that lack any ana- logue in the U.S. Constitution.

Table I Examples of Distinctive

State Constitutional Protections

Right States

The right to privacy 10 states: 8 as part of protection against unreasonable search and seizure 2 as free-standing protections

A right to pure water Bans or limits on imprisonment for debt The right to a legal remedy for injury The right to safe schools Prohibition against undue harshness

The right to fish

Prohibition against sex discrimination

Pennsylvania

39 states

36 states California

7 states California, Rhode Island

19 states

50 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

The diversity of rights protected by the various states and the addition of new protections by consti- tutional amendment suggest that the states have often been responsive to their citizens' demands for the protection of rights not secured by the federal Constitution. In addition, the states' inventiveness in discovering rights, as well as the willingness of states to seek guidance from their sister states, underlines a major advantage of permitting states to contribute to the definition and protection of rights. Requiring a uniformity in rights from state to state would prevent the states from performing their historic function as incubators of political change. If uniformity is re- quired, it will necessarily mean adherence to the "lowest common denominator" that is acceptable na- tionally.16 If, however, each state is permitted to pur- sue its own course, within the limits imposed by the federal Constitution, then the states' experiments can contribute to our national understanding of rights. Indeed, American history confirms the impor- tance of state leadership in the recognition and pro- tection of rights. See Table 2.

Yet, ultimately, the fear remains that if each state can follow its own path, basic rights might b

Table 2 Selected State Initiatives in Protecting Rights

Press Shield Laws: 18 states enacted press shield laws prior to the U.S. Supreme Court's dccision in Bmnzburg v. Hayes (1972), which rejected claims that the First Amendment prolccts reporlcrs from having to divulge their sources. After the Suprcme Court's decision, another seven states extended protection to reporters.

Right to Counsel: 35 states provided counsel to indigent defendants in felony cases prior to the U.S. Su- preme Court imposing the requirement on the states in Gideon v. Wainwright (1963). The Wiscon- sin Supreme Court imposed the requirement in Carpenter v. Dane (1850), over a century before Gideon.

Exclusionary Rule: The exclusionary rule bars the use of illegally seized evidence in criminal prosecutions. The Iowa Supreme Court adopted the exclusionary rule in State v. Sheridan (1903), 11 years before the US. Supreme Court in Weeks v. United States (1914) imposed the rule in federal prosecutions. By the time the U.S. Supreme Court imposed the rule as a requirement in state prosecutions, 23 states had adopted the exclusionary rule as a matter of state law.

Equal Pay Provisions: Equal pay provisions forbid wage discrimination on the basis of sex. Before Congress enacted an equal pay law in 1963, 19 states had en- acted similar laws.

Fair Housing Legislation: Fair housing legislation pro- hibits discrimination on the basis of race i n thc sale or rental of housing. Before Congress enacted a Fair housing law in 1968, 17 states had enacted similar laws.

jeopardized. Admittedly, there is some historical warrant for this concern. But this concern is less justi- fied in the contemporary political and legal context. As noted in chapter 1, judicial decisions, federal leg- islation, and intrastate political developments have all combined to make state political systems more representative than in the past. Partially as a result of this, instances of blatant suppression of minority rights arc rare. Thc civil liberties agenda in the states instcad tends to be rather different. The states today are more likely to bc called on to establish the proper balance when rights seem in conflict-for example, when press claims of freedom of access to pretrial proceedings collide with the right to privacy or the right to a fair trial.17 Or states may be asked to bal- ance the competing claims of equality and local autonomy, as in school finance or zoning litigation.18 Thus, the civil liberties issues that the states are ad- dressing today seldom involve whether basic rights should be protected. At the same time, the complex- ity of these new issues underlines the advantage of al- lowing various political and judicial bodies in a multi- plicity of jurisdictions to contribute their thoughts on how these issues should be resolved.

Finally, it should be remembered that the incor- poration of various guarantees of the U.S. Bill of Rights and the passage of federal civil liberties legis- lation have, in effect, established a "floor" of basic rights that anno t be infringed. This has not ended state expcrimcntation, nor was it meant to. However, the existence of this "floor" has had the effect of channeling stales' cxpcrimcnts in the direction of ex- panding and sal'cguarding, rather than violating, rights. Thus, statc involvcmcnt in defining and secur- ing rights should not jeopardize fundamental rights.

Freedom of Speech under State Constitutions

Every state bill of rights guarantees the freedoms of speech and of the press.lg During the 19th century, moreover, state rulings interpreting these provisions provided the main body of judicial doctrine on free- dom of expression.20 However, when the U.S. Su- preme Court began to address First Amendment is- sues during the early 20th century, doctrinal debate on the Court quickly detached itself from the body of state cases, pursuing arguments and directions unan- ticipated by thc state courts. Over time the U.S. Su- preme Court developed an impressive body of case law, and its decisions spawned a vast scholarly litera- ture. Thus, in the early 1970s, when state courts be- gan once again to address speech and press questions undcr thcir state constitutions, they confronted a well dcvelopcd and highly sophisticated body of legal doctrine.

In such circumstances, one would expect state courts to rcly heavily on federal law and precedent rathcr than to chart their own independent constitu-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 51

tional course. This has occurred. Yet even where fed- eral law predominates, state law can make important contributions where (1) the national government has left issues to the states for resolution, (2) the national government has failed to provide adequate protec- tion for rights, andlor (3) distinctive state constitu- tional provisions afford protection beyond that avail- able under the federal Constitution.

Private Abridgements of Free Speech

By its very terms, the First Amendment protects the freedom of speech only against congressional abridgement. As a result of incorporation, the fcd- era1 Constitution is now understood to prohibit state infringements on First Amendment rights; howcver, private limitations of expression remain outside its purview.2' The U.S. Supremc Court has rccognixcd that in certain limited circumstances, narncly, whcn private entities are performing public functions, thcy too are engaged in "state action" and are thus subject to federal constitutional constraints.22 Nonethclcss, the U.S. Supreme Court has read this "public func- tion" exception narrowly. In particular, it has con- cluded that although privately owned shopping cen- ters may resemble traditional downtown shopping areas, this does not mean that they are performing a "public function." As a result, shopping center own- ers do not violate the First Amendment when they re- strict or forbid speech on their premises.23

The U.S. Supreme Court's rulings, however, are not the final word on the subject. Although the U.S. Constitution does not secure a right to speak on pri- vate property, neither does it accord property owners a right to exclude speakers. Rather, it allows the states-through their statutory, constitutional, and common law- to define the scope of property rights and to regulate the use of private property in the pub- lic interest.24 Put differently, the states remain free to balance, as they see fit, the competing claims of speakers seeking access and of property owners seek- ing to restrict speech on their property.

In striking this balance, the states must dcter- mine whether their constitutional protcctions for free speech are directly applicable to private restric- tions on speech. Despite variations, what is striking about state guarantees is that many do not merely echo the First Amendment's ban on governmental infringements on the freedom of speech. The Michi- gan Constitution, for example, states: "Every person may freely speak, write, express and publish his views on all subjects, being responsible for the abuse of such right; and no law shall be enacted to restrain or abridge the liberty of speech or of the press."25 Whereas, the second clause of this provision, likc the First Amendment, bars governmental intcrfcrence with the freedom of speech, the first does not men- tion government. Instead, it announces a positive

right of free speech, albeit one subject to regulation to prevent abuse. In determining the scope of speech rights under state law, then, the states must consider whether this affirmative right of free speech extends beyond the prohibition of governmental infringe- ments on the right to speak-that is. beyond state ac- tion-and requires that speakers be accorded access to private property to convey their messages. In reaching this determination, however, the states must also take account of state constitutional protec- tions for property rights and, more specifically, of constitutional requirements that they neither take nor damage property without compensation.26

Within thc past decade, several states have ad- dressed directly the issue of speech rights on private property. 'l'hc scniinal case is Robins v. Pruneyard Shopping Cetrfvr ( 1 979). in which the California Su- preme Court upllcld Robins' right to collect signa- tures in a privately owncd shopping center for a peti- tion protesting the Unitcd Nations' anti-Zionism reso1utionP"l'hc California high court noted that the federal due process clause does not preclude the states from regulating the uses of private property in the public interest. It also asserted that the affirma- tive endorsement of freedom of speech in the state constitution signals a strong public interest that can, at least in some circumstances, override the claims of property owners. More specifically, the court ob- served that Robins' solicitation of signatures for his petition neither interfered with the normal business operations of the mall nor diluted property rights. It concluded therefore that he was entitled to protec- tion under the state constitution.

When the U.S. Supreme Court unanimously up- held the California court's ruling in Pruneyard, simi- lar cases were filed in several other states.28 Because the affirmativc recognition of speech rights in state constitutions is accompanied typically by an "abuse" limitation, the courts in these states-like the Cali- fornia court in Pruneyard-have had to consider whether speakers had interfered with the legitimate claims of propcrty owners. This necessarily required state judges to devclop standards for applying the dis- tinctive state guarantees. Some courts made impres- sive strides in this endeavor. For example, in over- turning the trespass conviction of a member of the United States Labor Party who distributed leaflets on the campus of Princeton University without permis- sion, the New Jersey Supreme Court in New Jersey v. Schmid (1980) considered carefully both the nature of the private property on which Schmid intruded and the extent to which Schmid's expression interfered with-or, as in this case, promoted-the purposes to which the property was dedicated. Similarly, in up- holding an environmental group's right to collect sig- natures and demonstrate in a shopping mall, the plu- rality opinion for the Washington Supreme Court

52 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

noted that the right depended on whether "state law confers such a right and . . . its exercise does not un- reasonably interfere with the constitutional rights of the owner."29

However, not all state jurists have concludcd that their constitutions afford speakers a right tocon- vey their messages on private property. Several of the decisions extending protection against private abridg- ment of speech have provoked sharp disscnts from justices who found a "state action" rcquircmcnt im- plicit in the state's bill of rights. Sincc 1984, courls in Connecticut, Michigan, and New York have all cn- dorsed the dissenters' position.30 Moreover, even those states that have extended constilutionnl pro- tection against private restrictions on specch have found it difficult to strike a balance between the rights of speakers and those of property owners.31

Yet, the fact that one encounters interstate- and even intrastate-disagreements about the inter- pretation and application of state constitutional pro- visions is hardly surprising. Rather, it would be surprising if every state, having recognized that its constitution affords independent protection for rights, interpreted its constitutional guarantees in ex- actly the same way. Moreover, the diversity of inter- pretation that results from our system of federalism should be viewed as a strength rather than a weak- ness. This diversity encourages an interstate dialogue about the scope of individual liberties that can pro- mote thoughtful, informed decisions.32 As state judges consider in new contexts the meaning of their state's distinctive constitutional guarantees-for example, the "abuse" limitations on the freedom of speech found in several state constitutions-and begin to develop a state jurisprudence of free speech, they will undoubtedly benefit from the exchange of views with their colleagues on other courts that is promoted by state protection of civil liberties.33

Freedom of the Press under State Constitutions

In general, witnesses must answer all pertinent questions put to them during grand jury investiga- tions andlor trials: those who fail to do so may be pun- ished for contempt. However, exceptions to this re- quirement have been recognized, when its enforcement would imperil certain confidential rela- tionships, such as those between doctor and patient or between priest and parishioner. Journalists have contended that the relationship between reporters and their confidential news sources warrants similar protection. They insist that because confidential sources often are willing to provide information only if their identities can remain secret, compclling rc- porters to name their sources and/or testiljl aboul Lhc information they receivc impcdcs the gnlhcring of news and its transmission to thc pul~lic. Wh:~tcvcr the

validity of this claim, it has not prompted creation of a federal testimonial privilege for reporters. In 1972, the U.S. Supreme Court concluded that the First Amendment does not protect journalists who refuse either to testify or to divulge their sources to grand ju- ries. Subsequent efforts in Congress to enact a press shield law have also proved unavailing34

Perhaps bccause state courts handle the vast ma- jority of criminal cases, thc states had begun to ad- dress thc issue ol'a tcstimonial privilege for reporters long bcl'orc il cmcrpxl on thc fcdcral political and le- gal agcndus.35 In 1896, Maryland enacted the na- tion's first press shicld law, granting a limited testi- monial immunity to rcportcrs. A series of highly publicized dispulcs during the 1930s prompted re- newed attention to the issue of testimonial immunity, leading ten additional states to adopt shield laws. During the 1960s and early 1970s, seven more states passed shield laws, in part in response to complaints about the increased issuance of subpoenas to report- ers. Finally, when the U.S. Supreme Court ruled that the First Amendment does not excuse reporters from testifying, seven more states responded by extending protection to reporters.

This is not to say that the states have adopted uniform policies on reportorial privilege. Not all states accord a testimonial privilege to journalists, and even those that do still differ over who is entitled to the privilege and over what the privilege entails. Some states, such as California, have protected re- porters against contempt citations but not against charges of obslruction of justice or against directed verdicts in libel cases. Other states, among them Ari- zona and Ohio, authorize reporters to withhold only the namcs of sourccs, whereas others, such as Dela- ware and Michigan, allow reporters to protect both their sources and the information they receive. Fi- nally, some stales afford protection only to profes- sional journalists connected with the formal news media, but others extend protection to free1ance;s and other persons engaged in news gathering or re- search.

Even within individual states, significant changes have occurred over time in the protection afforded to reporters. In several states, the scope of press privi- leges has emerged through interaction between the legislature and thc courts, with legislators responding to narrowing constructions of press shield laws by ex- tending broader protection. For example, on three separate occasions, the New Jersey legislature amended the state's shield law in response to judicial rulings that had construed it narrowly.36 After Cali- fornia's courts repeatedly had narrowed the scope of the statc's shicld law, the citizens responded by amending the California Constitution to give consti- tutional prolcction to rcportcrs' testimonial privi- legc.37

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 53

Our survey of state responses to claims of rcpor- torial privilege leads to three general observations. First, by the time civil liberties issucs cmcrgc a s part of the nation's political and legal agendas, ol'lcntimcs (as was the case with press shicld laws) the statcs had addressed the issues and confrontcd the difficult task of defining the scope of those libcrtics. This, in turn, suggests that the federal government can-and should-profit from the example and experience of the states.38 Again, this underlines how the nation's federal system promotes a beneficial dialogue on civil liberties issues.

Second, the willingness of state legislatures to enact press shield laws and to repudiate narrowing ju- dicial constructions of them confirms that state statu- tory law, as well as state constitutional law, can pro- vide important safeguards for civil liberties.

Finally, the recent flurry of cases involving the state constitutional right of reporters to gain access to pretrial hearings suggests that both state legislatures and state courts will continue to be involved in ad- dressing the right of journalists to obtain information controlled by government.39

Church and State in the States The Constitutional Context

The absence of federal law has afforded states the opportunity to define rights on private property and to protect the confidentiality of reporters' sources. However, the role of state civil libcrtics law is not merely interstitial. The states can pursue an in- dependent legal course and make a substantial con- tribution even when there is a body of federal law bearing on an issue. A prime example of such state in- dependence is to be found in the constitutional law of church and state.40

Prior to the Supreme Court's incorporation of the establishment clause in 1947, the states had pri- mary responsibility for regulating the relationship be- tween church and state. Incorporation inaugurated a new era of federal judicial involvement and doctrinal development. Yet, this increased federal activity has not diminished the importance of state constitutional guarantees. Although both federal and state charters enforce some degree of separation between church and state, state bills of rights typically have avoided the apparent vagueness of the First Amendmcnl's ban on laws "respecting an establishment of rclig- ion." Instead, most state constitutions contain spe-

'1 Ion- cific and detailed provisions governing the rcl 1' ship between church and statc. Thcsc provisions, when considered in light of the controversies that cn- gendered them, amply justify an independent state jurisprudence.

Generally speaking, state constitution-making on church and state has occurred in two phases. The first phase commenced after independence, when

the original states had to determine whether to main- tain thcir existing religious establishments. Although most did not immediately eliminate their establish- ments, indcpcnder~cc triggcrcd a movement toward disestablishrncnt, best exemplified by the famous campaign for rcligious libcrty in Virginia. This move- ment found expression in carly state constitutional provisions guaranteeing freedom of conscience and prohibiting prcference to any religious sect. None of the states subsequently admitted to the Union cre- ated a religious establishment, and by the 1830s intra- state pressures, as well as the federal example, led the original states to eliminate the last vestiges of their official establishments. As those states adopted new constitutions or amended their old one, they used the occasion to remove outdated provisions rec- ognizing religious establishments from their funda- mental law.

Despite the climination of official establish- ments, many states continued to provide unofficial support to Protestant Christianity, particularly in the public schools. As long as the nation's population re- mained relatively homogeneous religiously, this sup- port produced little controversy. However, the immi- gration to America of large numbers of Roman Catholics, who objected to this "Protestantizing" of public education, prompted a second phase of state constitution-making. In response to Catholic de- mands for statc funding of their schools and for the elimination of Protestant religious practices in public schools, several states strengthened their constitu- tional bans on aid to religious institutions and their mandates that school funds be expended only for public schools. Other states responded to the contro- versy by adding similar provisions to their constitu- tions. Finally, several states that were settled later or that escaped sectarian conflict over public education nonetheless borrowed the strict constitutional lan- guage of their sister states. As a result, long before the federal courts addressed the issue, most state constitutions had recorded a considered constitu- tional judgment on aid to religious institutions. In fact, their emphatic and detailed prohibitions of such aid appear to justify a separationist reading that may yield results different from those obtained under the First Amendment.

Aid to Parochial Schools Given the specificity of these state constitutional

prohibitions, it is hardly surprising that few cases have arisen involving direct aid to religious schools and that state courts havc consistently struck down such aid as unconstilulional.41 State cases since World War I t have focuscd instead on indirect aid to religious schools and thcir students. such as the pro- vision of transportation or tcxtbooks to children at- tending parochial schools. While the US. Supreme Court has ruled that such programs do not violate the First Arnendment,42 the states have divided over

54 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

their constitutionality. In part, this division reflects textual differences among state constitutions. For ex- ample, after their high courts had invalidated pro- grams authorizing the transportation of students to parochial schools, Wisconsin and New York adopted constitutional amendments expressly permitting their reinstitution.43 On the other hand, the Alaska Supreme Court concluded that, given Alaska's em- phatic constitutional ban on aid to religious institu- tions, the failure to include a clause permitting incli- rect aid implied that such aid was impermi~siblc.~~

In part, however, interstate disagreements on the constitutionality of indirect aid can be traced to whether state judges are willing to read state consti- tutional provisions as independent judgments on the permissibility of aid to religious institutions. Gener- ally speaking, those state courts that have invalidated programs of indirect aid have displayed a greater sen- sitivity to the distinctive language in state constitu- tions and to the historical experiences that produced it. Gamey v. State Department of Education, which in- volved the constitutionality of Nebraska's textbook- loan law, can serve as a model of independent consti- tutional analysis.45 Eschewing the U.S. Supreme Court's doctrinal formulations, the Nebraska Su- preme Court focused instead on the state's constitu- tional prohibition of any "appropriation in aid of any sectarian institution or any educational institution not owned and controlled by the state."The clarity of this language, the court insisted, made interpretation unnecessary, and its broad sweep admitted of no ex- ceptions. Moreover, the records of the convention that drafted the provision confirmed that a major aim was to devise a precise prohibition that would prevent sectarian conflict over the funding of church-related schools. The Nebraska Supreme Court therefore ruled the law unconstitutional.

Other state courts have likewise emphasized the distinctive language of their state constitutions in jus- tifying development of an independent constitutional position. The California Supreme Court, for exam- ple, concluded that the state constitution's ban on cx- penditures for "any sectarian purpose" was designed to prevent the state from providing bcnc fits to scctar- ian schools that furthered their educational purpose. On that basis, the court invalidatcd a textbook loan program.46 Similarly, the Idaho Supreme Court, in striking down a state law authorizing the transporta- tion of students to nonpublic schools, reasoned that the uncompromising prohibitory language in the Idaho Constitution was purposely included to place even greater restrictions on government than that found in the First Amendment.47 Finally, the Massa- chusetts high court, noting that a challenged textbook loan program aided sectarian schools in carrying out their essential educational function, held that it vio- lated a state constitutional amendment, adopted fol-

lowing its 1913 decision, which ruled out the "use" of money for maintaining or aiding sectarian schools.48 If the U.S. Supreme Court adopts a more accom- modationist stance on aid to religious institutions, as has been predicted, it can be expected that state courts will be called on increasingly to determine whether such aid violates the state constitution.

Conclusion Our survey o f how state law has helped to define

and protect civil lilmties, although hardly exhaus- tive, permits some general observations. First, state involvement in protecting rights is nothing new. It was the states that first devised bills of rights, and it was the states that had primary responsibility for de- fining and protecting rights for over a century after the nation was created. Thus, the "new judicialfeder- alism" and the recent upsurge of interest in state civil liberties law should be heralded not as an innovation, but as thc rediscovery of a traditional aspect of American fedcral ism.

Second, throughout the nation's history, the statcs have utilized a variety of legal means to safe- guard rights. Anwng the most familiar of these are state bills of rights, which have been employed to complement, supplement, and extend the protec- tions available under the U.S. Constitution. How- ever, other state constitutional provisions-for ex- ample, education clauses banning sectarian influences in publicly funded schools-also have served to safeguard civil liberties. So, too, have state statutes, such as those protecting reporters' confi- dential sources. Finally, state courts have invoked the common law and their own rulemaking authority to secure individual rights.49Thus, our examples under- score the variety of state initiatives on behalf of rights.

Third, as the struggle for religious liberty in Vir- ginia illustrates, these initiatives-constitutional, legislative, and judicial-have served not only to pro- tect rights within the borders of the state but also to provide impetus and guidance for efforts by other states and the national govcrnment to secure rights. This coincides with the pattern of cooperative activity that has characterized many aspects of American fed- eralism throughout the nation's history.

Having said this, the fact remains that contempo- rary state el'lorls to safeguard civil liberties occur in the context of a federal system in which the federal courts have assumed a major role in protecting rights. This heavy federal influence underlines the crucial importance of the legal relationship between federal and state law-and particularly between federal and state bills of rights. It is well established that state constitutional rulings resting on "independent and adequate state grounds" are exempt from federal ju- dicial scrutiny.50

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 55

When, then, is it appropriate to interpret state bills of rights independently? Some jurists-most no- tably, Justice Hans Linde of the Oregon Supreme Court-have concluded that the correct answer is al- ways.51 It is their contention that the logic of our fcd- era1 system requires that state judges look first to the law of their own state in deciding cases and then to federal law only when a case cannot be resolved on state grounds. Even jurists who have not endorscd this "state law first" position have recognized that, when state law diverges from federal law, it must be given independent effect.52 A moment's reflection suggests that such divergence is likely to occur fre- quently.

As we have noted earlier, many state constitu- tional provisions, such as state guarantees of privacy and prohibitions on undue harshness in punishment, have no federal constitutional analogucs.53 Thus, if states are to remain faithful to their law, they must seek the meaning of those guarantees independently.

Furthermore, whereas federal constitutional guarantees secure rights only against governmental infringement, state guarantees may protect rights against private infringement as well. In some in- stances, state constitutions do so e~pressly.5~ In oth- ers, as our discussion of state free speech provisions has shown, the state guarantees do not specify to whom their constitutional strictures are addressed. Although some state courts have been influenced by federal constitutional doctrine to read a "state ac- tion" requirement into these constitutional guaran- tees, many scholars and jurists have challenged this practice as unwarranted. Indeed, some scholars have insisted that in the absence of express language to the contrary, state guarantees should be read to rcach private as well as governmental action.55 Whatever the validity of this contention, fidelity to state consti- tutions demands that the scope of stalc protcclion be determined not by reference to federal conslitutional doctrine, but rather by independent analysis of state guarantees.

In addition, as our discussion of statc provisions on church and state has shown, even state provisions that restrict only governmental action and have some sort of federal analogue often differ from their fed- eral counterparts in language and/or historical ori- gins. In such circumstances, sensitivity to the federa1 character of the American polity should caution against assuming too readily that state protections are merely functional equivalents of federal constitu- tional guarantees.

Finally, even when the text of state and federal constitutional provisions are identical, this docs not mean that state officials-be they judges, cxecutivcs, or legislators-are obliged to accept thc U.S. Su- preme Court's interpretation of the fcdcral guaran- tee as authoritative, foreclosing independent inter-

pretation of the state provision. Federal precedent may be persuasive, but it is not authoritative; state of- ficials have an obligation to seek the best possible in- terpretation of thcir own constitutions. In fact, some scholars have argued that state courts should avoid taking thcir cucs from U.S. Supreme Court rulings because the institutional positions of the state and federal courts arc quite dissimilar.56 As the nation's highcst court, thc U.S. Supreme Court is constrained by considerations of federalism and the separation of powcrs that may prevent it from according full pro- tection to rights. Fkcause state courts do not operate under such constraints, it is argued, they should feel free to go beyond federal rulings that seem to under- protect civil lihcrtics. In the next two chapters, which deal with statc constitutional protections of the rights of criminal del'cndants and of equality, we shall see how they have done so.

NOTES

'This was established authoritatively in Baron v. Balti- more, 32 U.S. (7 Peters) 243 (1833).

2Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 653 (1925) and Stromberg v. California. 283 U.S. 359(1931), marked the first invali- dation of a state law on federal free speech grounds, and Nearv. Minnesota, 283 U.S. 697 (1931), the first invalida- tion of a state law as an infringement of the federal free- dom of the press.

3For an overview, see Richard C. Cortner, The Supreme Court and the Secorid Bill of Rights (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1981).

4Relevant cases include: Robinson v. California, 370 US. 660 (1962) (cruel and unusual punishment); Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335 (1963)(right to counsel); Mur- phy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964) (self- incrimination); Pointer v. Texas, 380 US. 400 (1965) (confrontation of witnesses); Kopfer v. North Carolina, 386 US. 213 (1967) (speedy trial); Duncan v. Louisiana, 391 US. 145 (1968) (trial by jury); and Benton v. Mary- land, 392 1J.S. 784 (1969) (double jeopardy).

5For an overview o f lhcse early cases, see Donald E. Wilkcs. Jr., "'l'llc Ncw I+dcralism in Criminal Proce- dure: State Court Ihasion of the Burger Court," Ken- tucky Law Jol1rrial62 (1974): 421-451.

6For a bibliography of thc literature on the new judicial federalism and ;I listing of judicial rulings, see Ronald K.L. Collins and Peter J. Galie, "State Constitutional Rights Decisions,"National Law Journal 11 August 1986. Since December 1987, the Association of State Attor- neys General has published a monthly survey of develop- ments in state constitutional law. See also John Kincaid, "State Court Protections of Individual Rights under State Constitutions: The New Judicial Federalism," The Jo~irnal of State Government 61 (September/October 1988): 163-169.

'Ronald K.L. Collins, Peter J. Galie, and John Kineaid, "State High Courts, State Constitutions, and Individual Rights Litigation since 1980: A Judicial Survey," Pllblirrs: 71ie Jorrr~ial oj'lederalisrn 16 (Summer 1986): 141-162.

*Collins and Galic, "State Constitutional Rights Deci- sions."

gFor furthcr discussion of the protection of rights under state constitutions, see chapters 5 and 6.

56 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

10For a recent elaboration of the justifications for federal- ism, see Daniel J. Elazar, &ploring Federalism (Tus- caloosa: University of Alabama Press, 1987), chapter 3.

1 It follows that if states have concurrent responsibility for defining and protecting rights, state officials have a con- stitutional obligation to honor and enforce this body of state law, even though doing so may lead to diffcrcnt definitions of rights from state to state.

12Whereas some state constitutions, such as Virginia's and Pennsylvania's, were prefaced by eloquent declarations of individual rights, others-for example, New Jer- sey's-had no bill of rights at all. Even those states that adopted bills of rights differed in what was protected. Compare, for example, the treatment of religion under the Massachusetts and Virginia constitutions. For a more general treatment of early state constitutional guarantees, see William E. Nelson and Robert C. %I- mer, Liberty and Community (New York: Oceana, 1987).

13For an overview of state provisions, see Robcrt Dowlut and Janet A. Knoff, "State Constitutions and the Right to Keep and Bear Arms," Oklahoma City University Law Review 7 (Summer 1982): 177-241.

14See Ronald K.L Collins, "Bills and Declarations of Rights Digest," in The American Bench, 3rd ed. (Sacra- mento: Reginald Bishop Forster and Associates, 1985), pp. 2491-2493.

15For a listing and discussion, see chapter 6. 16The U.S. Supreme Court candidly adniittcd as much in

San Antonio Independent School 1)istrict v. Ih~lrigucz. 411 U.S. 1 (1973). More generally, see Robcrt F. Wil- liams, "In the Supreme Court's Shadow: hgitimacy of State Rejection of Supreme Court Reasoning and Re- sult," South Carolina Law Review 35 (Spring 1984): 353-404, and Lawrence G. Sager, "Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms," Haward Law Review 91 (April 1978): 1212-1264.

17For discussion of how state courts have dealt with this is- sue under their state constitutions, see G. Alan Tarr, "State Constitutions and First Amendment Rights," in Stanley Friedelbaum, ed., Human Rights in the States (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1988).

18Representative cases include Serrano v. Priest, 487 P.2d 1241 (Cal. 1971) and Southern Burlington County NAACP v. Township of Mount Laurel, 336 A.2d 713 (N.J. 1975).

lgFor an overview of these provisions, see Collins, pp. 25022505.

20For background on state rulings on the freedoins of speech and of the press prior to incorporation, see David B. Rabban, "The First Amendment in Its Forgotten Years," Yale Law Journal90 (January 1981): 514-595, arid Margaret A. Blanchard, "Filling in the Void: Speech and Press in State Courts Prior to Gitlow," in Bill F. Chamb- erlin and Charlene J. Brown, eds., The FirstAmendment Reconsidered (New York: Longman, 1982).

21 This focus on governmental infringements on rights is characteristic of the federal Constitution-only the Thirteenth Amendment directly forbids private viola- tions of individual rights.

22Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U.S. 501 (1946). 23Lloyd Corporation v. Tanner, 407 US. 551 (1972) and

Hudgens v. National Labor Relations Board, 424 U.S. 507 (1976), overruling Amalgamated Food Employees Union v. Logan Valley Plaza, 391 U.S. 308 (1968).

24This underli~ics the important point that the states, in ex- ercising their traditional legal responsibilities, often make decisions that affect civil liberties.

25Michigan Constitution, Art. I, sec. 5. Other state consti- tutional provisions. such as those relating to access to the ballot, may also be relevant in specificcases. See Batchel- dcr v. Allicd Storcs International, 445 N.E.2d 590 (Mass. 1983).

260n the importance assigned to property rights by state constitution-makers, see, for example, the Arkansas Declaration of Rights, Art. 11, Sec. 22: "The right of property is before and higher than any constitutional sanction." On the need to compensate property owners, see, for example, Illinois Constitution, Art. I. Sec. 15: "Private property shall not be taken or damaged forpub- lic use without just compensation as provided by law." See generally chapter 7 of this study.

2'592 P.2d 341 (Cal. 1979). 28Cases decidcd shortly after the ruling in Pruneyard

Shopping Center v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74 (1980), include: State v. Schmid, 423 A.2d 615 W.J. 1980): Common- wealth of Pennsylvania v, Tate, 432A.2d 1382 (Pa. 1981): State v. Felmet, 273 S.E.2d 708 (N.C. 1981); Alderwood Associates v. Washington Environmental Council, 635 P.2d 108 (Wash. 1981); and Batchelder v. Allied Stores International, 445 N.E.2d 590 (Mass. 1983).

2Q635 P.2d at 1 12. 30Cologne v. WCS~~WIIIS Associates, 409 A.2d 1201 (Conn.

1984); Wootllancl v. Michigan Citizens Lobby, 378 N.W.2tl 337 (Mich. 1985): and Shad Alliance v. Smith Haven Miill, 498 N.Y.S.W 99m.Y. 1985). One court that initially endowd a right of free speech on private prop- erty appears to be reconsidering its position: Western Pennsylvanie Stxii~list Workers 1982 Campaign v. Con- necticut General life Insurance Co., 515 A.2d 1331 (Pa. 1986).

31 See Brown v. Davis, 495 A.2d 900 (N.J. Sup. Ct. 1984), and Jacobs v. Major, 390 N.2d 86 (Wis. App.1986). For possible solutions to these difficulties, see Martin B. Marguilies, "Westfarms' Unquiet Shade," University of Bridgeport Law Review 7 (1986): 1-45; and Sanford Levin- son, "Freedom of Speech and the Right of Access to Pri- vate Property under State Constitutional Law," in Brad- ley D. McGraw, ed., Developments in State Constitutional Law (St. Paul: West Publishing Co., 1985).

32For discussion of this dialogue, see G. Alan Tarr and Mary Cornelia Porter, State Supreme Courrs in State and Nation (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1988) chap- ter 1.

33For a ruling that suggests a possible new direction for state constitutional law dealing with freedom of expres- sion, see Oregon v. Henry, 732 P.2d 9 (Ore. 1987).

34Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665 (1972). An analysis of congressional failure to pass a shield law is found in Maurice Van Gerpen, Privileged Communication and the Ptws (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1979), chapter 7.

35Backgro~nd on slate shield laws and their interpretation can be found in Gcroen, Privileged Communication; Ar- thur B. Hanson, An AnalysisofState Newsnten's Privilege Ixgislation and (hses Arising Tliereunder (Washington, UC: 1972): and "Comment, The Newsman's Privilege af- ter B r a z h r ~ The Case for a Federal Shield Law," U. C. L.A. Law Review 24 (October 1976): 160-192.

36Following judicial rulings in State v. Donovan, 30 A.2d 421 (Sup. Ct. 1943) and Brogan v. Passaic Daily News,

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 57

123 A.2d 473 (N.J. 1956), the New Jersey legislature amended the state's shield law to extend coverage, N.J. Stat. Ann. Sec 2A: 84A-21 (West 1976) (cnactctl 1960). After In re Bridge, 295 A.2d 3 (App. Div.), ccrtif. dcnicd, 299 A.2d 78 (1972), cert. denictl. 410 IJ.S. 90 1 (1073), the legislature again amended the shicld law, 1977 N.J. l ~ w s 1027. Finally, responding to In rc Farbcr, 394 A.W 330, cert. denied, 439 U.S. 997 (1978), the New Jersey Iegkla- ture in 1980 further extended the protcction arrordcd re- porters, N.J. Stat. Ann. Sec. 2Z84A-21.1 to 21.9 (Wcst Supp. 1983-1984).

37California Constitution, Art. I Sec. 2(b), adopted in re- sponse to Fan. v. Superior Court, 99 Rptr. 342 (Ct. App. 1971), cert. denied, 409 U.S. 1011 (1972) and Rosato v. Superior Court, 124 Cal. Rptr. 427 (Ct. App. 1975), cert. denied, 427 U.S. 912 (1976). The New Mexico Supreme Court invalidated the state's shield law as a legislative in- vasion of the judiciary's authority to establish rules of evidence. See Ammerman v. Hubbard Broadcasting, Inc., 551 P.2d 1354 (N.M. 1976).

38Some federal judges have acknowledged their dcbt to state tribunals. See, for example, William J. Drennan, Jr., "Some Aspects of Federalism," New York Univetsity Law Review 39 (1964): 947.

39Relevant cases include: KFGO Radio, Inc. v. Rothe, 298, N.W.2d 505 (N.D. 1980), and State ex rel. Oregonian Publishing Co. v. Deiz, 613 P.2d 23 (Ore. 1980).

40For a more detailed treatment of the historical back- ground of state provisions on church and state, see G. Alan Tan., "Religion under State Constitutions," Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 498 (March 1988): 65-75.

41 See, for example, Harfst v. Hoegen, 163 S.W.W 609 (Mo. 1942), and Berghorn v. School District, 260 S.W.W 573 (Mo. 1953). The sole instance of a state ruling permitting direct aid-Opinion of the Justices, 102 N.E. 464 (Mass. 1913)-prompted a constitutional amendment prohibit- ing aid: Massachusetts Constitution Amend., Art. 46, Sec. 2.

420n bus transportation, see Everson v. Board of Educa- tion, 330 U.S. 1 (1947), and on the loaning of textbooks, see Board of Education v. Allen, 392 U.S. 236 (1968).

43Reynolds v. Nusbaum, 115 N.W.2d 761 (Wisc. 1962), re- versed by amendment, Wisconsin constitution, Art. I, Sec. 21: and Judd v. Board of Education, 15 N.E.2d 576 (N.Y. 1938), reversed by amendment, New YorkConsti- tution, Art. XI, Sec. 4.

44Matthew v. Quinton, 362 P.2d 932 (Alas. 1961). 45Gaffney v. State Department of Education, 220 N.W.2d

550 (Neb. 1974).

46California Tcachcrs Association v. Riles, 632 P.2d 953 (Cal. 1981).

47Epcldi v. Egclking, 488 P.2d 860 (Ida. 1971). 48Dbmni v. Scllool Comniittcc of Springfield, 379 N.E.2d

578 (Mass. 1978). 49For thc comlnori law as a source of rights, see, for exam-

ple, State v. %*l;~nowicz, 55 A. 743 (E and A 1903), in which the Ncw Jcrsey Supreme Court recognized a common-law right against sclf-incrimination, a position that it has confirnicd in more recent cases, such as State v. Fary, 117 A.2d 499 (N.J. 1955) and State v. Hartley, 511 A.2d 80 (N.J. 1986). For judicial rulemaking as a source of rights, see People v. Jackson, 217 N.W.2d 22, 27-28 (Mich. 1974), in which the Michigan Supreme Court es- tablished a suspect's right to counsel, absent extraordi- nary circumstances, during identification procedures.

5OFor discussion of this doctrine, see Stewart G. Pollock, "Adequate and Independent State Grounds as a Means of Balancing the Relationship between State and Fed- eral Courts," Texas Law Review 63 (1985): 977-94.

5lHans A. Iinde, "Without 'Due Process': Unconstitu- tional Law in Oregon," Oregon Law Review 49 (1970): 125-87; and State v. Kennedy, 66 P.2d 1316 (Ore. 1983).

52See, for example, Stewart G. Pollock, "State Constitu- tions as Separate Sources of Fundamental Rights," Rut- gets Law Review 35 (Summer 1983): 707-722, and State v. Hunt, 450 A.2d 952,965-67 (N.J. 1982).

S3For an example of state constitutional protection of pri- vacy rights, sce Alaska Constitution, Art. I, Sec. 22: "the right of the pcoplc to privacy is recognized and shall not be infringed." The importance of these state privacy guarantees was underscored by the U.S. Supreme Court in Katz v. IJnited States, 389 U.S. 342, (1967): "The pro- tection of a person's general right to privacy.. . is.. . left largely to the law of the individual states." For an exam- ple of state constitutional protection against excessively harsh punishment, see, for example, Rhode Island Con- stitution, Art. I, Scc 14: "[N]o act of severity which is not necessary to secure an accused person shall be permit- ted."

54See, for example, Montana Constitution, Art. 11, Sec. 4: "Neither the state nor any person, firm, corporation, or institution shall discriminate against any person in the exercise of his civil or political rights on account o f . . . religious ideas."

55See David M. Skover, "The Washington Constitutional 'State Action' Doctrine: A Fundamental Right to State Action," University of Puget Soiu~d Law Review 8 (Winter 1985): 221-282.

5"ee Williams. "In the Supreme Court's Shadow," and Sager, "Fair Measure."

58 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 5

Equality under State Constitutions State governments are responsible for undcrtak-

ing or administering most governmental activities that directly affect individual citizens. In undcrtaking these activities, they are constantly confronted with the task of determining what distinctions between persons are legitimate and what distinctions violate constitutional mandates of equality. Under thc fed- eral Constitution, there is only one generally applica- ble requirement of equality that binds the actions of states. This is the equal protection clause of the Four- teenth Amendment, adopted in 1868, which provides that: "No state shall. . . deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws." State constitutions, in contrast, contain many different equality provisions, aimed at a range of different but related problems. Although the Fourteenth Amend- ment equality requirement is well known and exten- sively analyzed, the state provisions have not received careful attention.'

James Madison contended that in a large, geo- graphically and politically diverse nation, there would be less likelihood of oppression of minorities because of the need for continued coalition, political accom- modation, and compromise.2 Madison wrote in The Federalist:

The smaller the society, the fewer prob- ably will be the distinct parties and interests composing it; the fewer the distinct parties and interests, the more frequently will a ma- jority be found of the same party; and thc smaller the number of individuals compos- ing a majority, and the smaller the compass within which they are placed, the more easily will they concert and execute their plans of oppression. Extend the sphere, and you take in greater variety of parties and interests; you make it less probable that a majority of the whole will have a common motive to in- vade the rights of other citizens; or if such a common motive exists, it will be more diffi- cult for all who feel it to discover their own strength, and to act in unison with each other.3

Madison'sconcerns seem to have been proven gener- ally true. As responses, state constitutional provi- sions have aimcd a1 a number of demonstrated prob- lems relating to equality over the years.

Most statc constitutions do not contain an ex- plicit "equal protcction" clause.4 They do, however, contain a variety of equality provisions. In some states, broad guarantees of individual rights have been interpreted to require equal protection of the laws in general.5 Further, most states have generally applicable provisions prohibiting special and local laws, grants of special privileges, or discrimination against citizens in the exercise of civil rights or on the basis of sex. Finally, many state provisions guarantee equality in specific or limited instances-from requir- ing "uniform" or "thorough and efficient" public schools to requiring uniformity in taxation.

Virtually all ol' these state constitutional provi- sions differ significantly from the federal guarantee of equal protection. They were drafted differently, adopted at different times, and reflect the diverse concerns about equality that surfaced during the vari- ous eras of state constitutional revision. For example, the broad guarantees of individual rights found in many state constitutions are intended to secure an equality of rights before the law for all persons. The bans on special laws and local laws, however, focus on the substance of the law, seeking to ensure equality (understood as uniformity of treatment) by requiring that laws bc of general applicability. The same con- cern that all citizens be treated uniformly underlies the constitutional prohibitions of special privileges, which protect the general public against preferential treatment for a small group, and the requirement of uniformity in taxation. Conversely, state bans on dis- crimination on the basis of gender, religion, or race reflect the more familiar concern to protect members of minority groups from majority tyranny. Finally, constitutional requirements of "uniform" or "thor- ough and efficient" public schools reflect a concern that the state avoid fhvoritism in the provision of es- sential state services.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 59

The First State Constitutions Rights. Even though many of these provisions seem

A few early state constitutions contained lan- guage similar to the classic language of equality in the Declaration of Independence. Section 1 of the Vir- ginia Bill of Rights, written by Gcorgc Mason and adopted a month before the Dcclaration of lndc- pendence, provided:

That all men are by nature equally free and independent, and have certain inherent rights, of which, when they cnlcr into a slatc of society, they cannot by any compact de- prive or divest their posterity; namely, the enjoyment of life and liberty, with the means of acquiring and possessing property, and pursuing and obtaining happiness and safety."

Although only Pennsylvania7 and Massachu- setts8 initially included broad provisions, like that of Virginia,s many states now have similarly worded provisions.10 Notions of equality, however, perrne- ated the first state constitutions with respect to gov- ernmental structure, even if not with respect to indi- vidual rights.l Pennsylvania's "liberal" constitution of 1776 probably pushed equality of consent as far as any of the first state constitutions by providing for a unicameral legislature, with no executive veto.12 Of course, most states still denied the franchise to blacks, women, and those who did not own property.

Several of the early state constitutions contained another type of general equality provision intended to prohibit grants similar to royal privilcges. Section IV of the 1776 Virginia Bill of Rights, for example, provides that "no man, or set of men, is entitled to cx- clusive or separate emoluments or privilcges from the community, but in consideration of public serv- ices."l3

It is important to remember the historical con- text in which the first state constitutions were written. Contrary to the view prevailing today-that constitu- tional protections exist to be enforced by the courtsl4-concepts of judicial review were still in their infancy in the late 18th century.l5 In other words, judicial enforcement of bill of rights provi- sions was probably far from their framers' minds. Thus, in many ways, these early provisions, some- times referred to only as "principles of govern- ment,"l6 can be viewed as descriptive rather than normative. Moreover, one must question the draf- ters' overall commitment to equality because slavery and formal inequality in political participation were allowed to continue, as they were undcr thc U.S. Constitution as well.

Despite these early bcginnings, much of thc modem judicial doctrine of equality undcr statc con- stitutions has its textual basis17 in such state conslitu- tional provisions as Section 1 of the Virginia Rill of

only to dcclarc pol&cal truths, they have been inter- preted to limit state actions.18 At the same time, gen- eral provisions that do not expressly mandate equal- ity, such as Ncw Jersey's Article I, paragraph I, have been intcrprctcd to guarantee equal protection of the law gcn~rally.~~' l 'hc New Jcrsey provision, for ex- ample, scrvctl as the basis for the state Supreme Court's dccision rcjccting thc US. Supreme Court's equal protection analysis in Harris v. McRae20 and in- validating slntc rcslrictions on Medicaid funding for abortion.21

Most state courts, however, have not developed doctrine independcnt of the federal equal protection clause undcr these kinds of equality provisions.22 In- stead, they seem content not to read into such provi- sions anything other than what the U.S. Supreme Court has read into the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

Other Generally Applicable Equality Provisions in State Constitutions

Jacksonian Equality Provisions The wave of constitutional revision in the 1820s

did not focus on the generally applicable equality provisions contained in the first state constitutions.23 Instead, equality issues centered around extending the right to vote to blacks and nonfreeholders and re- apportioning legislative representation.24

Later in the century, many states amended their constitutions to curb the granting of "special" or "ex- clusivc" privileges. In doing so, voters were reacting to a series of abusesby the relatively unfettered state legislatures, many of which were granting special privileges to powcrful economic interests.25 These provisions were modeled after provisions adopted earlier in other states, such as Section IV of the Vir- ginia Bill of Rights.26 For example, Article I, Section 20 of the 1859 Oregon Constitution, which was pat- terned after Indiana's 1851 Constitution,27 provides: "No law shall be passed granting to any citizen or class of citizens privileges or immunities which, upon the same terms, shall not equally belong to all citi- zens."28 These provisions commonly are found in state bills of rights-not in the legislative articles. They reflect the Jacksonian opposition to favoritism and special treatment for the powerful.29

Although these provisions may overlap some- what with federal equal protection doctrine, closer scrutiny revcals significant differences. As Justice Hans Lindc of the Oregon Supreme Court has noted, Oregon's Article I, Section 20 and the federal equal protcction c la~~sc "were placed in different constitu- tions at difl'ercnt lirncs by different men to enact dif- fcrcnt historic conccrns into constitutional policy."30 Justicc Bctty I<ohcrts of the same court has noted further:

60 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Article I, Section 20, of the Oregon Constitution has been said to be the "an- tithesis" of the equal protection clause of the fourteenth amendment. . . . While the four- teenth amendment forbids curtailment of rights belonging to a particular group or indi- vidual, Article I, Section 20, prevents thc cn- largement of rights. . . . Therc is an hislorical basis for this distinction. The Hcconstruction Congress, which adopted the h u rlccn t I1 amendment in 1868, was conccrncd with dis- crimination against disfavored groups or in- dividuals, specifically, former slavcs. . . . When Article I, Section 20, was adoptcd as a part of the Oregon Constitution nine years earlier, in 1859, the concern of its drafters was with favoritism and the granting of spe- cial privileges for a select few.31

A provision like Oregon's, then, does not seek equal protection of the laws at all. Instead, it prohibitslcgis- lative discrimination in favor of a minority.

These provisions may differ in other ways from the federal equal protection clause. Justice L.inde suggests that Oregon's provision can cover individu- als in addition to classes of people,32 and that it may not apply to corporations or nonresidents.33 More- over, the specific reference to the "passage of laws" may preclude its application to executive action. A similar provision prohibiting grants of "exclusive privileges" was instrumental in the North Carolina Supreme Court's decision invalidating that state's hospital certificate-of-need ~tatute.3~

Prohibitions on Special and Local Laws

Closely related to the provisions prohibiting grants of special or exclusive privileges are prohibi- tions on "special" and "local" laws.35 These provi- sions, found in the legislative articles of state consti- tutions, contain either general or detailed limits on the objects of legislation.3~pecial laws are those that apply to specified persons or a limited number of persons-for example an act granting a divorce or a corporate charter. Local laws are those that apply to specified or a limited number of localities-for exam- ple an act providing criminal penalties for conduct in only one county.37 One variety of local law is the "population act" or law which classifies cities accord- ing to population. Many states permit this sort of leg- islation if the basis for the classification can bc re- garded as rational. In addition, notice requirements usually are included for those subjects that may be dealt with by local laws, giving residents of localities to be affected at least constructive notice of the Iegis- lature's intended action.

Though intended in part to curb Icgislative abuses, these proscriptions on special and loc;~l laws reflect a concern for equal treatment under the law. In 1972 the Illinois Suprcmc Court held that lllc state's no-fault automobile insurance act violated Ar-

ticle IV, Section 13 of the Illinois Constitution, which provides that "[tlhe General Assembly shall pass no special or local law when a general law is or can be made appl i~able ."~~ The statute required only own- ers of "privatc passenger automobiles" to purchase no-fault insurance, but imposed substantial limita- tions on tort rccovcries of persons injured by any type of motor vchiclc. In dislinguishing Illinois' "equal protcction" clir~~sc,:'~ which had been added in 1970,40 J uslicc Wa l lcr V. Schacfer observed:

While thcsc two provisions of the 1970 con- stitution cover much of the same terrain, thcy arc not duplicates, as the commentary to Scclion 13 of Article IV points out: "In many cases, the protection provided by Sec- tion 13 is also provided by the equal protec- tion clause of Article I, Section 2."41

He concluded that Article IV, Section 13 imposed a clear constitutional duty on the courts to determine whether a gencral law "is or can be made applicable," and that "in this case that question must receive an affirmative answer." The constitutionally infirm por- tions of the statute were therefore invalidated.

Prohibitions on special and local laws have broad application, but thcy do appear limited to the legisla- tures, and therefore not to cover executive action. As with other state equality provisions, many state courts interprct special laws provisions by applying federal equal protcction analysis.

Discrimination in the Exercise of Civil Rights In thc mid-20th century, a number of state con-

stitutions wcrc amended to include provisions pro- hibiting discrimination in the exercise of civil rights. Pennsylvania, for example, added a provision in 1967 which directs that "[nleither the Commonwealth nor any political subdivisions thereof shall deny to any person the enjoyment of any civil right, nor discrimi- nate against any person in the exercise of any civil ~-ight."~2 Similar provisions in other states typically limit the proscription to discrimination on the basis of race, color, or national origin.43

These antidiscrimination provisions are products of the civil rights movement of the late 1950s and the 1960s. In this respect, they are a good example of state constitutional amendments that "did not di- rect, but mcrely recorded, the currents of social change."44 So far, they have not been treated by the state courts as proclaiming any important new consti- tutional principle.

The express proscription of discrimination against persons in the exercise of their civil rights, in addition to prohibiting the denial of rights, provides a strong textual basis for extending such protection be- yond fcdcral equal protcction doctrine. For example, in Harris v. M(~Ruc~ ,~5 thc U.S. Supreme Court held that restrict ions on Medicaid funding for abortions did not vtol:~tc (tic. I'cdcral equal protection clause.46 The Court conclutlcd that a mere failure to fund the

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 61

exercise of the federal constitutional right lo choose abortion did not unconstitutionally i)urdcn or limit the exercise of that right.47 Failurc to fund was held neither to deny the right, nor to impose an "unconsti- tutional condition"48 on its excrcisc.

A state provision, such as Pcnnsylvania's, how- ever, provides a different argument concerning such policies. For example, the right to choose to have an abortion is a clearly established constitutional, or "civil" right based on the US. Supreme Court's 1973 decision.49 So too is the right to bear children, under Supreme Court decisions.50 It has been argued, therefore, that a state legislature in a state with a pro- vision such as Pennsylvania's that provides funding only for child-birth, while excluding abortion from the Medicaid program, violates the state constitu- tion.51

State constitutional provisions prohibiting dis- crimination in the exercise of civil rights may become increasingly important as state governments expand from regulation into the provision of services.52 When state governments primarily regulated con- duct, prohibiting them from denying persons' civil rights was, if adequately enforced,53 an effective limit. States did not have the leverage of attaching "unconstitutional conditions" to the provision of services; therefore, they could not as easily favor one right over another. When the state acts as a service provider, however, as it does in such programs as Medicaid, it has the opportunity, in Laurence Tribc's words, "to achieve with carrots what [it] is forbiddcn to achieve with ~ticks."5~ Thus, to prevent states from illicitly discouraging citizens' exercise of their rights, states have adopted provisions prohibiting discrimi- nation against persons in the exercise of their civil rights.

Specific and Limited Equality Provisions

Although many states have interpreted generally applicable bill of rights provisions so as to guarantee equality under the law, other provisions, not usually found in bills of rights, expressly require equality in specific and limited instances. When applicable, these provisions offer state courts sound textual bases for invalidating state actions. At the same time, these provisions warrant extending equality guaran- tees beyond those of federal equal protection doc- trine. These provisions also allow courts to avoid some of the problems of basing decisions on gcncrally applicable equality provisions.

InRobinson v. Cahi11,55for cxamplc, thc New Jcr- sey Supreme Court held unconstitutional thc statc's school financing scheme under a provision in the New Jersey Constitution requiring a "thorough and efficient" education.56 The provision was added to New Jersey's Constitution in 1875, partly to reflect public concern over equality in education.=7 After criticizing the U.S. Supreme Court's approach to fed- eral equal protection cases,58 the New Jersey court

explained why it chosc not to base itsdecision on state "cqual protccl ion" doctrinc:

We hesitate to turn this case upon the State equal protcction clause. The reason is that thc equal protcction clause may be un- managcablc il' i t is callcd to supply categori- cal answers in the vast area of human needs, choosing those which must be met and a sin- gle basis upon which the State must act. . . . [W]e stress how difficult it would be to find an objective basis to say the equal protection clause selccts education and demands inflex- ible statewide uniformity in expenditure. Surely no need is more basic than food and lodging. . . . Essential also are police and fire protection, iN to which the sums spent per rcsidcnt vary with local decision. Nor are water and sundry public health services available throughout the State on a uniform dollar basis.59

Thus, thc New Jersey court used the state's thorough and cfficicnt education provision as a more "specific and limitcd" basis for its equality decision, justifying its limitation to the field of education and ensuring that its holding could not be expanded beyond educa- tion.

In addition to the education provisions, most statcs have uniformity in taxation provisions that pro- vide specific grounds for enforcing equality.60 Tax uniformity provisions require that once a legislative decision is made to tax a type of property or income, everything subject to the tax must be treated uni- formly. The legislature may, however, make a deci- sion not to tax a type of property, thereby exempting it.61 It is important to note, though, that while these provisions may be limited in focus, they can be far- reaching in effect. The primary effect of tax uniform- ity provisions is to mandate equality in property taxa- tion.62 Such provisions go well beyond the restrictions of the federal equal protection clause.63 Moreover, not all jurisdictions limit their uniformity provision to property taxes. As the Pennsylvania Su- preme Court noted:

[Tlhe constitutional standard of uniformity also possesses widespread and far-reaching application. While some other jurisdictions adhere to the view that uniformity applies only to propcrty taxes, our particular consti- tutional manclatc that "[all1 taxes shall be uniform . . ." is quite clear, and it is settled that this mandalc applics to all species of taxcs.64

Case Study: Gender Equality in the States

During the 1960s, gender equality emerged as a salient political issue, prompting responses from both the statcs and federal government.65 For the states, this involvement was nothing new: historically,

62 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

it had been state law-constitutional, statutory, and common law-that defined the political and civil rights and the legal capacities of women. State law had, for instance, governed contractual relations, regulating the capacity of married women to enter into contracts without their husbands' consent. It had defined property rights, including the right of mar- ried women to hold property in their own name. It had regulated domestic relations, including such mat- ters as divorce, alimony, child support, and child cus- tody. It had also established police power regulations that affected women's opportunities to seek and ob- tain employment .66

Although federal law and judicial rulings have assumed an increasing importance, state law contin- ues to play a major role in defining the legal status of women. However, constitutional changes have dra- matically altered the substance of that law. This sec- tion documents some of those changes in order to show how state law can contribute-and has contrib- uted-to promoting equality.

State Constitutional Guarantees Today, in some fashion or another, 19 state con-

stitutions expressly bar gender discriminati~n.~~ Some state guarantees long antedated federal in- volvement in securing women's rights. As early as the 1890s, for example, the Wyoming and Utah Constitu- tions mandated equal enjoyment of civil, political, and religious rights and privileges for all men and women. In its 1947 constitution, New Jersey modified its traditional recognition of natural rights, inserting gender-neutral language in order to ensure gender equality.68 Most states, however, adopted their con- stitutional bans on gender discrimination between 1968 and 1976, a period roughly coincident with the proposal of the federal Equal Rights Amendment (ERA) and its submission to the states for ratifica- tion.

Given the timing of their adoption, it is not sur- prising that many of the "little ERAS," as they are sometimes called, resemble the proposcd fcdcral model. However, several have distinctive clcments. Montana's, for example, extends broadcr pl-olcclion, expressly barring gender discrimination by private parties as well as by government. Several others omit a "state action" requirement, allhough the guaran- tees usually have been interpreted to apply only against governmental infringements on equality.69 California's guarantee is more focused than was the proposed federal ERA, mandating merely that the right to engage in a profession shall not be denied on the basis of gender. Louisiana's ERA is more tolerant of gender classifications, prohibiting gender distinc- tions only if they are arbitrary, capricious, or unrea- sonable.

In interpreting state guarantees of gender equal- ity, state courts have generally looked for direction to the U.S. Supreme Court's interpretations of the equal protection clause and to commentaries on the

(unratified) federal Equal Rights Amendment. How- ever, instead of promoting doctrinal uniformity among the states, this practice has merely duplicated on an interstate basis the complexities of the U.S. Su- preme Court's equal protection jurisprudence. Thus, the Illinois Supreme Court, among others, has inter- preted its constitution to require "strict scrutiny" of gender classifications, the same standard used by fed- eral courts in determining the validity of racial classi- fications.70 Some state courts, however, have adopted a less rigorous standard. The Utah Supreme Court, for instance, has endorsed the U.S. Supreme Court's "rational relationship" test, upholding gen- der distinctions as long as they are reasonably related to the achievement of avalid state aim.71 In contrast, some courts-among them, the Washington, Mary- land, and I'cnnsylvnnia supreme courts-have read their constitutions as imposing the same absolute ban on gender discrimination that was sought in the fed- eral FIRA.72

Although the level and focus of litigation under these provisions have varied from state to state. some general patterns have emerged. First, a number of constitutional challenges have come from male liti- gants who insisted that state laws or judicial rulings imposed unequal burdens on them. The conflict over child support has been particularly intense. In ad- dressing this issue, courts in Washington, Texas, and Pennsylvania have concluded that child support is a responsibility of both parents. However, mathemati- cally equal contributions from both parents have not been required, and in considering child support judges have recognized that nonmonetary as well as monetary contributions may be relevant.73 Second, men have challenged state laws and practices that al- legedly penalize them or deny them benefits solely on the basis of their sex. Illustrative of such challenges are the constitutional attacks on the "tender years doctrine," under which wives are granted a prefer- ence in contested custody cases involving young chil- dren.74 Third, defendants have asked courts to strike down criminal stalules, such as rape laws, that have used gcndcr-bnscd language in defining crimes. State courls, however, I w c gcncrally refused to allow de- fendants to usc state ERAS as a shield from criminal liability.75 Fourth. in scvcral instances, women have invoked state constitutional guarantees successfully against outmoded common-law rules, such as the prohibition on wives' recovering damages for negli- gent loss of c0nsortium.~6 Finally, women have in- voked state constitutional guarantees to challenge denials of access or opportunities, most notably in several cases involving restrictions on their participa- tion on athletic teams.77

What is most striking about the litigation under state ERAS, howcver, is its infrequency. Whereas one might have expected that the adoption of new state constitutionnl guarantees during the 1970s would have produced a flurry of challenges to state

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 63

laws and practices, in fact, during the decade no state supreme court heard as many gender equality cases as did the U S . Supreme Court. In part, the paucity of litigation under state constitutional provisions re- flects the preference of litigants for federal forums and federal law, particularly in such areas as job dis- crimination. In part, however, it also testifies to the efforts of other branches of state government to vin- dicate the constitutional commitment to equal rights. State attorneys general have issued numerous opin- ions providing guidance on the meaning of these con- stitutional guarantees, thus reducing the need for re- course to the courts.78 Even more important, state legislatures have taken the initiative in reforming state law to conform to constitutional requirements.

Legislative Implementation

When 14 states adopted "little ERAS" between 1968 and 1976, they committed themselves to eradi- cating gender discrimination and securing increased opportunities for women. In some states-for exam- ple, Connecticut-this constitutional commitment was reflected in an impressive body of Icgislation pro- moting gender justice.79 In othcrs, adoption ol' the "little ERA" provided the impctus for s t ;~tc Icgislo- tures and state attorneys general to eliminate gcnder discrimination. New Mexico's experience in imple- menting its ERA illustrates the crucial role that state legislatures have played in conforming state law to constitutional mandates.80 After ratification of the amendment in November 1972, the New Mexico leg- islature appointed an Equal Rights Committee to oversee its implementation. This committee, with the assistance of special committees established by the New Mexico state bar association, reviewed the en- tire New Mexico code to identify provisions inconsis- tent with the amendment and recommended statu- tory reforms needed to eliminate gender bias from New Mexico law. The New Mexico legislature acted quickly on most of these recommendations, approv- ing changes in 26 statutes and two amendments dur- ing its first session following ratification of the consti- tutional ban on gender discrimination.

What occurred in New Mexico has occurred in other states as well. Several states-among them, Alaska, Texas, and Washington-have undertaken a comprehensive review and revision of their codes to bring them into conformity with constitutional requirements. Some, such as Connecticut, have es- tablished permanent commissions to monitor com- pliance with constitutional mandates. Othcrs, such as Hawaii, have sought to ensure gender equality through piecemeal reform of their law. Even states, such as Virginia, that have not mounted a compre- hensive reform effort have modified their law to eliminate glaring inequities.81 In sum, then, the legis- lative, executive, and judicial branches of state gov-

ernments have all played an important role in pro- moting and safeguarding gender equality.

Conclusion The states, through provisions included in their

constitutional texts and through statutes, attorney general opinions and judicial decisions, have ad- dressed a range of equality concerns over the years since 1776. State law, in fact, contains a much broader range of provisions concerning equality than is found in federal law. A combination, however, of the states' earlier unwillingness to enforce these provisions ag- gressively and the highly visible initiatives under fed- eral law since the 1950s, has led to an almost instinc- tive tendency to look to the federal government to deal with equality issues. As James Madison warned, threats to equality may be more likely to arise within the states, justilying a renewed interest in, and con- cern with the enforcement of, state law provisions on equality.

NOTES For a particularly noteworthy exception, see Susan P. Fino, Vie Hole of State Srprenze Courts in the New Judicial Federalim (Wcstport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1987).

*SCC generally Nok, "A Miidisonian Interpretation of Equal I'rotcction I)octrinc," Yale Law Journal 91 (1982): 1403 (contcntling that fcdcral equal protection doctrine should be cnforcctl more strictly against states than the fcdcral government); sce also Gordon S. Wood, Tlie Creatiorz of [lie An~ericarz Republic, 1776-1 787 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1969), pp. 504-506 (suggesting that Madison saw Congress as less likely to succumb to the majoritarian democratic "ex- cesses" exhibited by state legislatures).

3The Federalist No. 10, p. 135 (J. Madison) (B. Wright, Ed. 1961). Madison added in The Fedemlist No. 51: "In the extended republic of the United States and among the great variety of interests, parties, and sects which it em- braces, a coalition of a majority of the whole society could seldom take place on any other principles than those of justice and the general good," p. 359.

4Sidney Z. Karasik, "Equal Protection of the Law under the Federal and Illinois Constitutions," DePaul Law Re- view 30 (1981): 270 11.33 ("Illinois was only the eighth state to include an equal protection clause in itsconstitu- tion.")

=New Jersey's "equal protection" doctrine, for example, is based on a provision that states: "All persons are by na- ture free and indcpendent, and have natural and unal- icnablc rights, among which are those enjoying and de- fending life and liberty, of acquiring, possessing, and protecting property, and of pursuing and obtaining safcty and happiness." New Jersey Constitution, Art. I, para. 1 (1947); see. for example, Right to Choose v. Byrne, 91 N.J. 287,303-05,450 A.2d 925,933-34 (1982).

6Virginia Constitution, Bill of Rights 1 (1776). 7Pcnnsylvania Constitution, Art. I, 1 (1776). 8Massachusetts Constitution, Pt. I, Art. I (1780). 9See Willi Paul Adams, The First Anierican Constit~~tions: Republican Ideology and the Making of the State Coiistitrr- [ions in tlie Revolrrtior~aty Era (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1980), p. 176.

64 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

'Osee e.g., New Jersey Constitution, Art. I, para I (1844). "See generally Ronald J. Peters, Jr., The Massackrisetts

Constitution of 1780: A Social Compact (Amherst: Uni- versity of Massachusetts Press, 1978), p. 190 (discussing these two facets of political equality).

12See J. Paul Selsam, The Pennsylvania Constitution of 1776: A Study in Revolutionary Democracy (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1936); Richard A. Ryerson,"Republican Theory and Partisan Reality in Revolutionary Pennsylvania: Toward a New View of the PennsylvaniaConstitutionalist Party", in Sovereign States in an Age of Uncertainly, Ronald Hoffman and Peter J. Albert, eds. (Charlottesville: University Press of Vir- ginia, 1981), p. 94.

13Virginia Constitution, Bill of Rights 4 (1776). For a simi- larprovision, see Massachusetts Constitution, Pt. 1, Art. VI (1780).

14On the nature of "constitutions" in thc revolutionary era, see Cecelia M. Kenyon, "Constitutionalism in Hcvo- lutionary America," in Roland J. I'cnnock and John W. Chapman, eds., Nomos XV;. Cori.~/i/r/tiorwlisr~t (Ncw York: New York University Press. 1979), pp. 86-92.

'=See William E. Nelson, "The Eighteenth Century nack- ground of John Marshall's Constitutional Jurispru- dence," Michigan Law Review 76 (1978): 937; William E. Nelson, "Changing Conceptions of Judicial Review: The Evolution of Constitutional Theory in the States, 1790-1860," Univemily of Pennsylvania Law Review 120 (1972): 1168.

16Frank P. Grad, "The State Bill of Rights," in V. Ranney, ed., Con-Con: Issues fir the Illinois Constitutional Con- vention (Urbana: Institute of Government and Public Affairs, University of Illinois, 1970), p. 34. But see Kenyon, "Constitutionalism," pp. 96-99 ("natural law" concepts, though largely ideological, were thought to be enforceable through "public opinion, elections. . . [and] revolution").

170n the role of textual basis in judicial interpretation of state constitutions, see Hans A. Linde, "Without 'Due Process': Unconstitutional Law in Oregon," Oregot1 Law Review 49 (1970): 131

l8See, for example, Henry v. Bauder, 213 Kan. 751, 518 P.2d 362 (1974). There, the Kansas Supreme Court ob- served: "While. . . [the equality] provisions of our Bill of Rights declare a political truth, they are given much the same effect as the clauses of the Fourteenth Amend- ment." 75243,518 P.2d at 365; see also State v. Currens, 111 Wis. 431,434-3587 N. W. 561,562 (1901) (although phrased like the Declaration of Independence, "life, lib- erty, and the pursuit of happiness" provision judicially enforceable); Winters v. Myers, 92 Kan. 414,420-25,140 P. 1033,1036-37 (1914) (noting that constitutional provi- sions declare political truths and legislation may not "trench upon the political truths which they affirm").

lgPeper v. Princeton University Board of Trustees, 77N.J. 5579,389 A.2d 465,477 (1978). New Jersey's constitu- tional provision is quoted in footnote 5.

20448 U.S. 297 (1980) (upholding termination of funds for abortion in the Medicaid program). See generally Robert F. Williams, "In the Supreme Court's Shadow Legitimacy of State Rejection of Supreme Court Rea- soning and Result," South Carolina Law Review 35 (1984): 364-365.

21 Right to Choose v. Byrne, 91 N.J. 287,305,450 A.W 925, 934 (1982).

22See, for example, Ilaase v. Sawicki, 20 Wis. 2d 308,311 n.2, 121 N.W.2d 876,878 n.2 (1963).

23See generally Merrill Peterson, Democracy, Liberty, and Pmpeq: The State Constitutional Conventions of the 1820s (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1966) (discussion of the Massachusetts, New York, and Virginia conven- tions).

24Ibid., pp. 59, 214, 377.24.6 25See James Willard Hurst, The Gmwth ofAmerican Law:

The Law Makers (Boston: Little Brown & Co., 1950), pp. 241-42; William F. Swindler, "Minimum Standards of Constitutional Justice: Federal Floor and State Ceiling," Missouri Law Review 49 (1984): 2; A.J. Thomas, Jr., and Ann Van Wynen Thomas, "The Texas Constitution of 1876," Taus Law Review 35 (1959): 907.

28See note 13 and accompanying text. The concern of the newer provisions was with legislative rather than royal favoritism. Sw I ,intle, "Without 'Due Process,' " p. 141.

27Scc Lintlc. "Without ' Ihc Process,' " p. 141. As to the "copying" or "hor~wving" of state constitutional provi- sions during westward expansion, see Robert F. Wil- liams, "State Constitutional Law Processes," William and Mary I,aw Itcview 24 (1983): 174 n.14,

280regon Conslitution, Art. I, 20 (1859). 29Historian Rush Welter observed: "Hence the whole

thrust of Jacksonian thought was in the first instance negative, an effort to eliminate institutions and practices that an earlier generation had more or less taken for granted. The "aristocracy" that Jacksonians complained of consisted of selective access to power, prosperity, or influence. At bottom it was apolitical rather than a social or economic concept: in Jacksonian eyes, an "aristocrat" was someone who was empowered by law to affect the economic and social welfare of his contemporaries, or who enjoyed legal privileges that he could turn to his own account in an otherwise competitive economy." Rush Welter, The Mind ofAmerica: 1820-1860 (New York: Co- lumbia University Press, 1975), pp. 77-78 (footnote omit- ted). As lo "Jacksonian Democracy," see R. Lawrence Hachey, "Jacksonian Democracy and the Wisconsin Constitution," Manquette Law Review 62 (1979): 485.

30Linde, "Without 'Due Process,' " p. 141. For a listing of similar stale provisions, see p. 182 n.43. For opinions by Justice Linde on Art. I, 20, see State v. Freeland, 295 Or. 367,667 P.2d509.512-16 (1983); State v. Clark, 291 Or. 231,2364,630 P.2d 810,814-18 (1981).

31 Hewitt v. State Accident Insurance Fund Corp., 294 Or. 33,42.(,53 P.W 970,975 (1982); see also Behrns v. Buake, 89 S.D. 96,100,229 N.W.2d 86,89 (1975X"more stringent constitutional standard" than fourteenth amendment); Comment, kVillarnelte Law Journal 19 (1983): 757 (dis- cussing Hewilt).

32See State v. Freeland, 667 P.2d 509,512 (1983); State v. Clark, 291 Or. 231,237-38,630 P.2d 810,814-15 (1981).

33Linde, "Without 'Due Process,' " p. 142 notes 53 and 54. 34See In re Aston Park Hosp., Inc., 282 N.C. 542, 193

S.E.2d 729 (1973); Comment, "Hospital Regulation after Aston Park: Substantive Due Process in North Caro- lina," Nodl Carolina Law Review 52 (1974): 763.

35See James Quale Dealey, Growth ofAmerican State Con- stitutions from 1776 to the Er7d of the Year 1914 (New York: DaCapo Press. 1972, 1915 reprint) pp. 224-26; Hurst, The G ~ o ~ r ~ l i ofAmericari Law, pp. 241-42; Thomas and Thomas. "'l'hc 'Texas Constitution," 915.

3%ee, for example, Florida Constitution, Art. 111, ll(aX1) (1968); Pennsylvania Constitution, Art.111, 32

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 65

37See generally City of Louisville v. Klusmeyer, 324 S. W.2d 831. 833-34 (Ky. 1959) (noting that both territorially and substantively "special" statutes are permissible in certain cases). The Tennessee Constitution's "law of the land" provision, Tennessee Constitution, Art. XI, 8 (1796) has been interpreted to allow statutes to be restricted to cer- tain counties by population classification only when "the classification is based upon reason, is natural and not ar- bitrary or capricious." State ex re1 Hamby v. Cummings, 166 Tenn. (2 Beeler) 460,463,63 S.W.2d. 515,516 (1933).

38111inois Constitution, Art. IV, 13 (1970); see Grace v. Howlett, 51 111. 2d 478, 283 N.E.2d 474 (1974). Illinois' "special laws" provision declares further that "whether a general law is or can be made applicable shall be a matter for judicial determination." Illinois Constitution, Art. IV, 13 (1970). On judicial enforcement of this type of provision, see Truax-Traer Coal Co. v. Compensation Commissioner, 123 W. Va. 621, 626-27, 17 S.E.2d 330, 334 (1941); Thomas F. Green, Jr., "A Malapropian Pro- vision of State Constitutions," Washington University Law Quarterly 24 (1939): 359; Frank E. Horack, "Special Legislation: Another Twilight Zone,"Zndiana Law Jour- nal 12 (1936): 110-21.

39Illinois Constitution, Art. I, 2 provides: "No person shall. . . be denied the equal protection of the laws."

40See Karasik, "Equal Protection," pp. 270-74. 41 Grace v. Howlett, 51 Ill. 2d 478,487 283 N.E.2d 474,479

(1974). 42Pennsylvania Constitution, Art. I26 (1967); cf. New York

Constitution, Art. I. 11 (1938) (earlier version of this type of provision). For discussion of similar provisions in other state constitutions, see Albert L. Sturm, "The De- velopment of American State Constitutions," 1'11blir~s: The Joumal of Federalistn 12 (1982): 87-88; Albert L Sturm and Kaye M. Wright, "Civil 1,ihcrtics in 1lcvisc:il State Constitutions," in Stephen L. Wasby, cd.. ('ivill~ib- erties: Policy and Policy Making (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976). pp. 182-83.

43See, for example, New Jersey Constitution, Art. I, para 5 (1947).

44See Hurst, The Growth ofAmerican Law, p. 246. See gen- erally Charles Press, "Assessing the Policy and Opera- tional Implications of State Constitutional Change," Publius: The Joumal of Federalism 12 (1982): 108-11 (dis- cussing the politics of constitutional revision).

45448 US. 297 (1980). 46This was a Fifth Amendment equal protection case deal-

ing with a federal statute. The companion case, Williams v. Zbaraz, 448 US. 358 (1980), applied identical analysis to a state statute under the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

47Williams v. Zbaraz, 315-17. 48Ibid., 317 n.19. 49Roe v. Wade, 410 US. 113 (1973). 50Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438,453 (1972); Skinner v.

Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942). 51 This argument, which contends that such federal consti-

tutional rights constitute "civil rights" under the state constitutional provision, was rejected in Fischer v. De- partment of Public Welfare, 509 Pa. 282, 502 A. 2d 114 (1985).

52See generally Frank P. Grad, "The State Constitution: Its Function and Form in Our Time," Virginia Law He- view 54 (1968): 929-939 (describing the shifting functions of state governments).

53 Of course, many states did not enforce even these earlier provisions in the area of, for example, racial discrimina- tion.

54Iaurence 11. Tribe, American Constitutional Law (Mineola, New York: Foundation Press, 1978) 15-10, p. 933 n.77. For a complete discussion of unconstitutional conditions, see Seth Kreimer, "Allocational Sanctions: The I'roblcm of Negative Rights in a Positive State," U~iivemity of t'ennsylvatiia Law Review 132 (1984): 1293.

55 62 N. J. 473,s 13,303 A.2d 273,294, cert. denied, 414 U.S. 976 (1973).

56New Jersey Constitution, Art. VIII, 4, para 1 (1947); see Gershon M. Katner, "A New Legal Duty for Urban Pub- lic Schools: Effective Education in Basic Skills," T a m Law Review 63 (1985): 815 n. 144; Paul L. Trachtenberg, "Reforming School Finance through State Constitu- tions: Robinson v. Cahill Points the Way," Rutgets Law Review 27 (1974): 415-28.

57See Cahill, 62 N.J. 501-10,303 A.2d 287-92. For a deci- sion dealing with equality of educational opportunity for handicapped students under New Jersey's "thorough and efficient" provision, see Levine v. State Department of Institutions and Agencies, 84 N.J. 234,418 A.2d 229 (1980); see also In re G.H., 218 N.W.2d 441, 446 (N.D. 1974) (holding that failure to provide free education to handicapped children violates North Dakota Constitu- tion's education and equality provisions).

58The New Jersey court said: "In passing we note briefly the reason why we are not prepared to accept that con- cept for State constitutional purposes. We have no diffi- culty with the thought that a discrimination which may have an invidious base is "suspect" and will be examined closcly. And i f a discrimination of that kind is found, the inquiry may well cnd, for it is not likely that a State inter- est could suslain such a discrimination. But we have not found hclplul thc conccpt of a "fundamental" right." Cahill, 62 N.J. 491, 302 A.W 282.

SgIbid., 62 N.J. at 492.495-96,303 A.2d at 283,284. In fact, New Jersey has no "equal protection" clause in its consti- tution. The genctxl state constitutional doctrines of equality arise from New Jersey Constitution, Art. 1,para. 1 (1947). See supra note 5.

60See generally Michael M. Bernard, Constitutions, Taxa- tion and Land Policy, 2 vols. (Lexington, Massachusetts: D.C. Heath, Lexington Books, 1979, 1980) (abstracting tax provisions from the federal and all state constitu- tions); Wade J. Newhouse, Constitutional Uniformity and Equality in State Tauation, 2nd ed. (Buffalo: William S. Hein Co., 1984) (analysis of state tax uniformity and equality provisions, organized into nine prototypical clauses); William LA Matthews, Jr., "The Function of Constitutional I'rovisions Requiring Uniformity in Taxation," Kenlrrchy Law Jounial38 (1949): 31 (d' ISCUSS- ing the development and application of state tax uni- formity provisions); David A. Myers, "Open Space Taxa- tion and State Constitutions," Vanderbilt Law Review 33 (1980): 837 (differential taxation of farm, timber, and open space land tends "both to countermand and to re- inforce the iclcal that absolute equality in state taxation can be attained").

61 See, for example, Gottlieb v. City of Milwaukee, 33 Wis. 2d 408, 147 N. W. 2d 633 (1967).

62Sw Note, "lnccpi~lity in Property Tax Assessments: New (lures for a n Old Ill." Haward Law Review 75 (1962): 1377-80: Note, "'l'hc Road to Uniformity in Real Estate l'axat ion: Valuation and Appeal," University ofPeririsyl- vania l,aw Kcvirw 124 (1976): 1447.

66 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

63See Lenhausen v. Lake Shorc Auto Parts Co., 410 U.S. 356, 359 (1973); Allied Stores, Inc. v. Ilowcrs, 358 US. 522, 526 (1959); Nashville, Chattanooga. and St. I m i s Railway v. Browning, 310 U.S. 362,368 (1940) (referring to the "narrow and sometimes cramping provision of. . . state uniformity clauses").

64Amidon v. Kane 444 Pa. 38,47,279 A.2d 53,58 (1971).

65Federal initiatives include passage of the Equal Pay Act of 1963 (57 U.S.C. 206 [1976]), the Civil RiglztsActof 1964 (42 U.S.C. 2000e [I976 and Supp. I11 1979]), and Title IX of the Education Act Amendments of 1972 (20 U.S.C. 1681 [1976]) as well as Reed v. Reed 404 U.S. 71 (1971) and subsequent judicial rulings under the equal protec- tion clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. State initia- tives include not only the constitutional guarantees of gender equality discussed below but also statutory re- forms and judicial decisions demonstrating a commit- ment to securing gender equality even in the absence of express constitutional mandates. See, for example, Sailer Inn v. Kirby, 485 P.2d 529 (Cal. 1971).

66For a thorough overview of the changes in state law, see Barbara A. Brown, Ann E. Freedman, Harriet N. Katz, and Alice M. Price, Women's Rightsand the Law: Tile I I ~ pact of the ERA on State Laws (New York: Praeger, 1977).

67Alaska Constitution, Art. I, 3 (1972); California Consti- tution, Art. I, 8 (19 ); Colorado Constitution, Art. 11,29 (1972); Connecticut Constitution, Art. I 20 (1974); Ha- waii Constitution, Art. 1, 3, and Art. I, 5 (1972); Illinois Constitution, Art. I, 18 (1971); Louisiana Constitution, Art. I, 3 (1974); Maryland Constitution, Art. 46 (1972); Massachusetts Constitution, Part First, Art. I (1976); Montana Constitution, Art. II,4 (1973); New Hampshire Constitution, Part First, Art. 2 (1975); New Jersey Con- stitution, Art. I, para. l(1947); New Mexico Constitution, Art. 11, 18 (1973); Pennsylvania Constitution, Art. I, 28 (1971); Texas Constitution, Art. I, 3a (1972); Utah Con- stitution, Art. IV, l(1896); Virginia Constitution, Art. I, 11 (1971); Washington Constitution, Art. 31, s 1 and 2 (1972); and Wyoming Constitution, Art. VI, 1, and Art. I, 3 (1890). Litigation and legislative action under these provisions through 1980 are surveyed in NOW Legal De- fense and Education Fund, ERA Impact Project (unpub- lished. 19811

68The revised provision substituted "persons" for "men." The aim of securing equal rights through this change is documented in "Note: Rediscovering the New Jersey E.R.A.: The Key to Successful Sex Discrimination Liti- gation," Rutgem Law Review 17 (Winter 1986): 253.

GgSee, for example, McLean v. First N.W. Industries of America, Inc., 600 P.2d 1927 (Wash. 1979). and Junior Football Association v. Gaudct, 546 S.W.217 1 (Tcx. <'w. App. 1976).

70See, for example, People v. Ellis, 311 N.E.W 98 (111. 1974). For a contrary view, see Hartrord Accident and Indemnity v. Insurance Commissioner, 482A.241542(Pa. 1984).

71Salt Lake City v. Wilson, 148 P. 1104 (Ut. 1915), and Stanton v. Stanton, 517 P.2d 1010 (Ut. 1974).

72Consortium is defined as the "[c]onjugal fellomhip of husband and wife, and right of each to the company, so- ciety, cooperation, affection, and aid of the other in every conjugal relation." (Black's Law Dictionary, 5th ed. [St. Paul: West Publishing Co., 19791, p. 280) Tradition- ally, under common law a husband could recover for negligence leading to an impairment or loss of the wn-

sortium of his spouse, but a wife could not. Darrin v. Gould, 540 1'.2rl 885 (Wash. 1975); Rand v. Rand, 374 A.2d 900 (Md. 1977); and Hopkins v. Blanco, 320 A.2d 139 (Pa. 1974).

73Henderson v. Henderson, 327 A.2d. 60 (Pa. 1974); Smith v. Smith, 534 P.2d 1033 (Wash. 1975); Cooper v. Cooper, 513 S.W.2d 229 (Tex. Civ. App. 1973); Friedman v. Fried- man, 521 S.W.2d I l l (Tex. Civ. App. 1975); and Krempv. Kremp, 590 S.W.2d 229 (Tex. Civ.App. 1979).

74The relevant cases, in both "little ERA" and "non- ERA" states, are surveyed and analyzed in G. Alan Tarr and Mary Cornelia Porter, "Gender Equality and Judi- cial Federalism: The Role of State Appellate Courts," Hastings Coiistitirtional Law Quarterly 9 (Summer 1982): 942-950 and 963-973, Tables E-H.

75See, for example, People v. Barger, 550 P.2d 1281 (Col. 1976); Finley v. State, 527 S.W.2d 553 (Tex. Crim. App. 1975); and Brooks v. State, 330 A.2d 670 (Md. 1975).

76Sce, for example, Tlopkins v. Blanco, 302 A.2d 855 (Pa. 1973); Whittlcsey v. Miller, 572 S.W.2d 665 (Tex. Civ. App. 1978); and 1-andgrens v. Whitney's Inc., 614 P.2d 1272 (Wash. 1980). For discussion of state elimination of the discriminatory common-law ban on recovery, see Tarr and Porter, "Gender Equality," pp. 937-942.

~ ~ S C C , for exi~~l ip l~ , Packel v. Pennsylvania Interscholastic Athletic Association, 334 A.2d 839 (Pa. 1975), and Dar- rin v. Gould. 540 P.2d 885 (Wash. 1975).

78For example, whereas in Texas the right of married women to revert to their birth names on official records was confirmed by judicial decision, in Maryland and Pennsylvania the issue was resolved by opinions issued by the states' attorneys general. For Texas, see In re Erickson, 547 S.W. 2d 357 (Tex. Civ. App. 1977); for Maryland, see 57 Opinions of the Attorney General 234 (11/30/72), cited in NOW Legal Defense and Education Fund, ERA Impact Project: Summary-Maryland State ERA Experience, pp. 7-8; and for Pennsylvania, see Offi- cial Opinion No. 62, Opinions of the Attorney General 172 (8/20/73), cited in NOW Legal Defense and Educa- tion Fund, ERA Impact Project: Summary-Pennsylvania State ERA Experience, pp. 11-12.

79Connecticut prohibited gender discrimination by private employers in 1967 and by public employers in 1969 (Con- necticut Gen. Stats. 4-61,31-12, and 53-35 [I979 Rev.]). A year prior to the adoption of the state ERA in 1973, the state had made gender neutral all laws concerning di- vorce, marriage, alimony, division of property, custody, and child support (Connecticut Gen. Stat. 46b-40 et seq. [I979 Kcv.1). It sliould be noted that many states that did not adopt consl~lutional prohibitions on gender dis- crimin;~licm Iioncll~clcss acted to remove discriminatory provisio~is Croni their laws. See Brown et al., Women's Higizts and (Ire Law, chapter 3.

8OThis account of New Mexico's reform effort is based on NOW Lrgi~lI)efcnse and Education Fund, ERA Impact Project: Siinzmaty-New Mexico State ERA Experience, pp.8-13.

8lFor example, two months after the Virginia Supreme Court in Archer v. Mayes, 194 S.E.2d 707 (Va. 1973), up- held an automaticexemption from jury duty offered only to women, the Virginia Legislature replaced the statute with one offering an exemption to anyone who is respon- sible for the care o f a child or a handicapped adult (Vir- ginia Code 8.01-341.1 [Rep. Vol. 1977).

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 67

68 Advisory Commlssion on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 6

The States and Criminal Procedure Rights protections for defendants in criminal

cases represent another area where state courts have become very active in recent years. State courts are often holding that a defendant is afforded more pro- tection under a section of a state constitution than the U.S. Supreme Court has granted through its in- terpretation of the corresponding provision in the U.S. Bill of Rights. This development has resulted, in part, from the changes in the substance of U.S. Su- preme Court decisions. Under Chief Justices Warren Burger and William Rehnquist, the Court has slowed the expansion of criminal defendant rights and, in some areas, narrowed the protections granted to the defendant under the U.S. Constitution by the War- ren Court.'

Because of the Supreme Court's post-Wnrrcn approach to defendant rights, the slate courts are taking initiatives in this field. Justice William Bren- nan approves of these state initiatives. He finds that "state courts no less than federal are and ought to be the guardians of our liberties."2 In the past, when de- fendants' rights were federalized, the states had no reason to consider their own state constitutions. However, the BurgerIRehnquist Court does not in- terpret these rights as expansively as did the previous Court.

This chapter will demonstrate that, despite sev- eral problems, state courts have turned to their own constitutions to guarantee more protection than the Supreme Court's interpretation of the U.S. Constitu- tion grants to the defendant. State courts may and do interpret their constitutions independently of the federal Constitution. State constitutions are not mir- rors of the federal Constitution; they have their own language and history, which shape state court inter- pretation.

In order to avoid Supreme Court review and pos- sible reversal, state courts must make a plain statc- ment that their decision is based on an independent and adequate state ground and note that whilc fcd- era1 law may persuade the court it does not compcl the result. This chapter focuses on the exclusionary

rule of the Fourth Amendment to the U.S. Constitu- tion. This rule has become central to the American criminal justice system. This rule is also important for federalism because, even if a state court is able to use state grounds as the basis of its decision, a federal court may still be able to use the evidence that was suppressed in the state court. The U.S. Supreme Court has hcld that successive prosecutions in state and federal courts are not violative of the double jeopardy clause of the Fifth Amendment.

The defendant can attempt to stop the federal court from using evidence that is impermissible un- der the state constitution even if he or she cannot avoid the federal prosecution. The state court might be able to enjoin the state official, who obtained the evidence in violation of state rules, from testifying or handing thc cvidcnce over to the federal prosecutor. The state court might be able to prohibit the intro- duction of cvidcnce from a federal official who vio- lated the state constitution through the "reverse sil- ver platter doctrine." In addition, the defendant can make his or her argument to the federal court. If the state court is hesitant to act, the federal judge may rule that the federal officials should not receive evi- dence that a state official obtained in violation of state law. The federal court can also decide to pro- hibit state officials from using evidence seized con- trary to state law in the federal prosecution.

State Courts and Constitutions Several commentators assert that the states

should take the initiative in the area of constitutional rights. Ronald Collins, for example, maintains that the states musl take responsibility to protect individ- ual rights in order to revitalize federalism.3 For Jus- tice William Rrennan, the federal courts are still pri- marily rcsponsiblc for protecting individual rights, but thc s t a m should take the role of expanding pro- tections bcyond Scclcral guarantees4 He believes that Jamcs Madison would have approved and welcomed the increase in the reach of state constitutional law.5 Perhaps, as onc commentator suggests, the state rule

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 69

should simply act as an alternative to federal law be- cause the states are as able as the federal courts to formulate workable rules for the application of the standard formulated by the Supreme Court.6

However, some observers argue that the state courts should not interpret their constitutions in a manner different than the Supreme Court's under- standing of the U.S. Constitution. As Chief Justice Burger stated in Florida v. Casal,

. . . when state courts interpret state law to require more than the Federal Constitution requires, the citizens of the state must be aware that they have the power to amend state law [by referendum in that case] to en- sure rational law enforcement.?

Problems may arise, like those in the pre-Mapp era before the exclusionary rule was applied to the states uniformly. Two rules of law will exist in each state; one federal and the other state. More cases may arise due to this lack of uniformity between states and the federal government. However, since each state has unique interests, complctc uniformity may not be required or desirablc.8

Further, there is a custom of looking to federal law for the protection of the defendant. Because courts are accustomed to federal rules, the state judges usually defer to the Supreme Court's inter- pretation. However, such deference is not necessarily appropriate. Although the U.S. Supreme Court re- ceives the most attention, state courts have often guaranteed particular protections to defendants be- fore the Supreme Court has done s0.Q

Another problem that can arise is confusion about which rule of law, state or federal, must be fol- lowed in a case. Nonuniformity causes difficulties in instructing law enforcement officers in their duties. In many states, the law enforcement officers may find that their duties change when the state court decides to interpret the state constitution more narrowly than the federal Constitution, which had been fol- lowed before.

However, state courts are no longer performing any service when they interpret their state constitu- tions as equal to the federal Constitution because the Fourteenth Amendment applies most of the protec- tions of the U.S. Constitution to the states. State courts must use the state constitutions as documents granting more protections to the criminal defendant in order to make a contribution to the 1aw.lOThe state court must make an independent determination in each case.l l

The state courts' practice of deciding issues on the basis of state constitutional law before reaching federal law is useful for several reasons. First, the state court will avoid adjudication of federal constitu- tional questions unless it is necessary.12 Second, state

courts are better suited to decide state than federal questions. 'Third, state adjudication on state grounds takes some pressure off the heavy Supreme Court docket becausc the Court cannot decide state law is- sues.13 Fourth, the state court can make its decisions based on the character of the state where it sits. The state can grant benefits to a state defendant due to the capabilities of the state, such as counsel on ap- peal, while the Supreme Court must be sure that all states can afford to enact this provision.14 The states are free to experiment15 and determine the best pro- cedures and laws for their unique circumstances.

Thus, although the state court's use of its own constitution may cause some problems, these prob- lems do not outweigh the benefits. No other body can so easily and efficiently protect rights owed to the de- fendant under state law. Because many state courts are becoming active,l6 it is now the duty of attorneys in each state to raise and brief the issues based on state constitutions. Local practitioners have an obli- gation to raise the issue that the state court can grant broader protection under its own constitution, so that the client and future defendants can receive the benefits of thosc rights. Yet, as the Vermont court stated in Stutp v. Jcwett, the state court should not "use its state constitution chiefly to evade the impact of the decisions of the U.S. Supreme Court. Our de- cisions must be principled, not result oriented.""

State Use of Their Own Constitution

In the first appeal after Michigan v. Long's- Colorado v. NunezlQ-the U.S. Supreme Court dis- missed the case as improvidently granted because it rested on independent and adequate state law grounds. The state court20 decided that the Colorado Constitution grants a trial court discretion to disclose the identity of informants when there is a reasonable factual basis to question the informant's statements, even though the U.S. Supreme Court did not hold that the federal Constitution requires this disclo- sure.21 Thus, the Supreme Court, in dismissing Nunez, permilled the state court to go beyond what was necessary under the U.S. Constitution.

In a concurrence, Justice John Paul Stevens criti- cized Justice White's opinion. White agreed that the Court had no jurisdiction, but he proceeded with a lengthy advisory opinion. For Stevens, White's opin- ion simply demonstrated the Court's tendency to in- volve itself in state court proceedings and encourage litigants to file writs of certiorari. A party may hope for adviscmcnt 1)y some of the justices, even if the state decision is based on state grounds.22

In Turner v. Cify of Lawton,23 the Oklahoma court held that its constitution does not permit the intro- duction of evidence in a civil case that would be im- permissible in a criminal case, although the federal Constitution may allow such civil use.24 For the U.S.

70 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Although the Suprcme Court should rcspcct state jurisdiction because of both thc inability of the Court to construe state law and the rcspcct duc to state courts in a federal system, thc Court will prc- sume that it has jurisdiction. To avoid federal review, the state court must include a "plain statement" that the state court is basing its decision on independent and adequate state grounds. Federal precedents are used only as guidance and do not compel the deci- sion.48

The Vermont court in State v. Jewett49 instructed local practitioners to rely on state law rather than on federal law. The court warned that in order to avoid federal jurisdiction, the states should not use fcdcral cases that compel the result. A state court may use federal decisions only for their persuasive value, like decisions from other states.50 If the state court opin- ion relies too heavily on federal precedent, the U.S. Supreme Court in review might find that it has juris- diction, even though the state court plainly states that its decision is based on independent and adequate state grounds.

The U.S. Supreme Court may hold that the state court's reliance on federal precedent in a particular case is misguided and, therefore, reverse the decision if the state's use of independent and adequate state grounds is not clear. In Florida v. Meyers,51 the appel- late state court reversed the trial court conviction po- tentially on two grounds.52 The first was a restriction on cross examination under state law, which was not challenged on appeal. The second was the use of evi- dence obtained in an automobile search.53

In the U.S. Supreme Court's summarypercuriam opinion, the issue of independent and adequate state grounds is addressed in a footnote. The Court finds that the state court made no "clear indication" that the issue of cross examination was an adequate ground for reversal, independent of the suppression of the evidence obtained in an automobile search.54 Over the strong dissent of Justice Stevens, the Court held that the search of the automobile was proper un- der the Fourth Amendment and reversed the state

Stevens asserted that the Court should not have granted certiorari. He noted that sincc 1981 the Court had summarily reversed lower court decisions upholding constitutional rights 19 timcs. Slcvcns stressed that the Court should be "ever mindful of its primary role as the protector of the citizcn and not the warden or the prosecutor."56 Thcrcfore, states must base their decisions clearly on statc constitu- tional grounds to protect state defendants. If federal law is used, the Supreme Court is likely to reverse the decision, possibly with only a summary proceeding.

Similarly, in Massachusetts v. U p t ~ n , ~ ~ the Su- preme Court, in another per curiam opinion, found that the court in the Commonwealth misunderstood

thc definition of probable cause, which the Court ar- ticulated in Illinois v. Gates.S8 Gates set out a flexible "totality of thc circumstanccs" test that overruled the two-prongcd Aguilur-Syinelli test. The U.S. Supreme Court overrulcd the judgment of the state court.

Justice Stevens, this time in a concurrence, agreed with the reversal because the state court did not express whether the warrant was valid and sup- ported by probable cause under the Massachusetts Constitution. He suggested that if Massachusetts were to find thc warrant under state law to be in viola- tion of its constitution on remand, then the first opin- ion, in which the court incorrectly pursued federal law, was worthless and insufficient.59 This was pre- cisely what occurred in that case.

The state should look to state law and the state constitution bcforc it turns to the U.S. Constitution. According to thc Ninth Amendment, rights are re- taincd by the pcoplc of the state and are protected by the state constitution. The state court must guard the liberties of thc citizens of the state and may exceed the rights grantcd under the U.S. Constitution.60

Many statc courts are able to grant the defendant grcatcr protcctions than the U.S. Supreme Court's interpretation of the U.S. Constitution on remand by explicitly relying on a state ground to obtain a differ- ent result. In Commonwealth v. Upton,61 for example, the Massachusctts Supreme Judicial Court decided that its constitution exceeded the protection of the defendant granted by the Fourth Amendment prob- able cause standard. The court stated that: "The Con- stitution of the Commonwealth preceded and is inde- pendent of the Constitution of the United States."62 The two constitutions have different language, and the courts have found different results and under- standings of constitutional doctrine under the two documents.

The Massachusetts Court has realized in the past that it may protect the defendant more thoroughly under the state than the federal Constitution.63 It held that the Aguilar-Spinelli test sets a clear and comprehensible standard, encourages careful work by the police, and reduces the number of unreason- able searches in Massachusetts. The court decided that this stand;trd should be maintained in the Com- monwcalth iintl is rcquircd by the Constitution of Massach~sclls.6~

In Stute v. Neville," the South Dakota Supreme Court held that it could suppress, under the state constitution, cvidcnce of a potentially intoxicated driver's rcfusal to take a blood alcohol test. Although the U.S. Supreme Court has decided that refusal is admissible under the Fifth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution,66 the state, acting as the final arbiter of the state constitution, can grant the defendant more rights than the U.S. Constitution. The court deter- mined that thc federal cases did not control its deter-

72 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

mination. The words of the state constitution con- cerning the privilege against self-incrimination are different and broader than the words in the Fifth Amendment."The refusal to submit to the test is not an admissible physical act, but is a communication that must be p r ~ t e c t e d . ~ ~ The court, therefore, sup- pressed the evidence.

In addressing state laws and constitutions, how- ever, state courts must be careful. They should use federal precedent explicitly only for its persuasive value and state plainly that they are relying on aspects of their own state constitution rather than the U.S. Constitution.

Nevertheless, even if the state court specifically states that it is using the state constitution, the U.S. Supreme Court may find that the ground is not com- pletely adequate or independent and, therefore, re- verse the decision. In a large number of cascs in which state courts have protected a defendant's rights more fully than the Court's interpretation of the U.S. Constitution, the Supreme Court has re- versed in per curiam opinions. However, the Su- preme Court may be forced to accept state court in- terpretations of their own constitutions if there is a plain statement, as required by Michigan v. Long, and if there is no real reliance on a federal precedent that requires the decision.

If the state court fails to rely solely on state law in its first opinion, the state court may reverse the deci- sion on remand from the U.S. Supreme Court by re- lying explicitly on independent and adequate state grounds. In response to this action, the Supreme Court has reversed some cases that had protected the defendant without remand to the state court.69 Therefore, if a state court wishes to have its ruling stand, the state should rely on its own constitution in the first place, not only to avoid repetitious litigation, but also to avoid the problem in Gates.

State and Federal Prosecutions Even if a state court bases its decisions on state

constitutional grounds that are adequate and inde- pendent of the U.S. Constitution, thc fcdcral courts in the state may still use the evidence that is sup- pressed in the state court under the less restrictive federal rule. In two cases decided on the same day, the Supreme Court, in Bartkus v. Illinois70 and Abbate v. United States,71 did not deny the state and federal governments the power to prosecute the same act.

In Bartkus, the defendant was tried and acquitted in federal district court. Then the federal agents gave the evidence to the officials of the state of Illinois, who proceeded to convict the defendant for the same acts under a state statute.72 As the U.S. Supreme Court stated in Moore v. Illinois, "the same act mayhc an offence or transgression of the laws of both"73 the state and federal sovereigns. The Court held that the

double jeopardy clause of the Fifth Amendment did not preclude the second prosecution by the state.74 Under Bartkus, successive state and federal prosecu- tions are not in violation of the Fifth Amendment.75

In another case, Abbate v. United States,76 the state of Illinois prosecuted and convicted a defendant for violation of a state statute. Then, the federal dis- trict court in Mississippi prosecuted the defendant for a violation of a federal statute for the same acts.77 This situation is the opposite of that in Bartkus. The Supreme Court rclied on United States v. Lanza,78 which held that the state conviction did not preclude the second fcderal suit. The Court recognized that if the state prosecution barred federal prosecutions for the same acts, "federal law enforcement must neces- sarily be hindered."79 This is particularly dangerous whcn the defendant's behavior impinges on the fed- eral intercst more than that of the state.

These two cases illustrate that the Supreme Court will uphold prosecution of the same act in the courts of difl'crent sovereigns. Thus, if the state court were to hear the case of the defendant and make its decision based on independent and adequate state grounds, the federal court may still hear the case un- der a federal statute. According to Abbate and Lanza, after the state court granted the defendant protec- tion greater than the safeguards in the U.S. Constitu- tion, the federal court can try the same defendant for the same acts and convict him by using the evidence that was not permissible in state court.

However, the Court in Bartkus noted that many states have statutes that bar a second prosecution af- ter the defendant has been tried by a separate sover- eign for the same actions.80 State and federal officials may decide that the statutes under which the defen- dant is prosecuted are so similar that a second suit is not warranted or necessary, even though it is not pro- hibited. The fcdcral government may decide that the federal statutc is so much like the statute that the statc uscd to prosccule the dcfendant that the fed- eral suit should 11ot proceed. Perhaps the expense of the second trial should not be incurred because the defendant is being punished by the state or has re- ceived an acquittal after a fair trial. The defendant could argue this point to the federal prosecutor and to the federal judge as grounds for dismissal.

Federal prosecutors have adopted this policy pursuant to the case of Petite v. United Srates.81 In re- sponse to Bartkus and Abbate, the U.S. Department of Justice adopted a policy that "a federal trial follow- ing a state prosecution for the same act or acts is barred unless the reasons are compelling."@ In Rinaldi, the U.S. Supreme Court enforced the Justice Department's policy that bars the second prosecu- tion. Thc Suprcmc Court dismissed the federal in- dictment and Icft the state conviction and sentence intact.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 73

Under this policy as enforced by the courts, a de- fendant who is first tried in a state court may be able to avoid a federal suit where the evidence, which would be precluded under the more protective state constitution, could be used. The defendant can argue that the Justice Department policy does not allow the second prosecution and that the court must enforce this policy. The problem is that the Justice Depart- ment can change its policy. The court cannot require the department to keep this policy. If the department abandons its policy, a defendant may again be faced with two indictments and trials.

A majority of the present U.S. Supreme Court would appear to limit the protections granted to de- fendants in criminal cases. This has led the Court to admit evidence to convict defendants who were pro- tected by a state court that did not specify its reliance on state law. The Supreme Court has even decided cases without remand in order to avoid state reversal under state law. There is reason to believe that the U.S. Supreme Court will continue to permit federal courts to grant less protection to defendants in sec- ond prosecutions. The lower courts can take many cases which the Supreme Court as a single body can- not hear.

As recently as 1985, the Supreme Court held that the double jeopardy clause does not bar a second prosecution of a defendant for the same acts in a court with a different sovereign than the first. Heath v. Alabama approved two prosecutions for the same acts in different states.83 The Court did not question the fact that consecutive state and fedcral suits are permissible. A defendant must arguc that thc secoricl suit should not take place on thc grounds ol' respect for the state court, efficiency, and thc wisdom of the doctrine that a defendant should not be twice con- victed for the same crime. However, it is doubtful that the federal court is prohibited from hearing the suit.

Avoiding Federal Use of Evidence

State Courts

If a defendant and the state cannot avoid federal prosecution, then federal officials may be unable to use the evidence that was inadmissible under the state constitution. In Rea v. United States,84 the Su- preme Court permitted the federal courts to issue in- junctions against federal agents to prevent them from giving evidence to the state officials. The Court ap- proved of the action of the district court in enjoining a federal official because the relief was not against any state activity, but only against a federal agent who abused his authority. As the Court said, "to enjoin the federal agent from testifying is merely to enforce the federal rules against those owing obcdience to them."85 It was unimportant that the state might con-

done the prwcdure prohibited by the federal rule. The federal agent could not be allowed to flout the rules that he had the duty to follow.86

Similarly, perhaps the state courtscould limit the activity of state agents. The state courts might be per- mittcd to stop state agents from testifying or giving evidcnce to federal agents who could use this evi- dencc in federal court. The fact that the procedure used by the state agent was proper under federal con- stitutional law would be irrelevant. The state court would simply be enforcing its own constitutional rules against thc state agents who were bound to fol- low these rules. If the states could not enforce their rules on statc agents, these agents could act as they pleased and violate constitutional rights of the defen- dants. The defendants would have no remedy.

In his dissent in Rea, Justice Harlan voiced his concern that a federal "injunction [against federal of- ficials] will operate quite as effectively . . . to stultify the state prosecution as if it had been issued directly against New Mexico or its officials."87 Even if the state enjoined only the activities of the state official, the injunction would, in effect, work against the fed- eral suit. The state court would be able to prevent the prosecution of the federal case. This would awaken the concerns about enabling the sovereign with the greater interest in the case to hold the trial, even if the officers of the other sovereign discovered the evi- dence.

This problcm is exacerbated when it is the state enjoining state officials and interfering with federal prosecutions. 'l'hc state court could nullify federal law, which must hc suprcmc to state law.88 A state's nullification of a fcdcral prosecution would turn the supremacy doctrinc on its head: the state could often control the fcdcral court by refusing to turn over pro- bative evidcncc.

In Wilson v. Schnettler,89 the U.S. Supreme Court reflected this concern for violation of a sovereign's power when it refused to enjoin the use of evidence illegally seized by federal officers in state court. After the defendant was indicted in an Illinois state court for possessing narcotics under a state statute, he filed a suit in the federal district court to impound the drugs and enjoin their use in the state trial. The de- fendant argued that the injunction should issue against the fcdcral officials who seized the narcotics and who would be called to testify in the state's case. The defendant failed in the Supreme Court as well as the lower fcdcral courts.

The dccision was based on the rationale that courts of one sovereign must avoid interference with the courts of the other sovereign. Otherwise, embar- rassing and threatcning conflicts between state and fcdcral courts would occur. If each court decided to enjoin the othcr's proceedings, litigants would be left without a rcmcdy.gOThere would be no finality in the

74 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

judgment of the first sovereign, which could be re- versed in a new trial by the other.91

These ideas, voiced in Wilson, were applied in the later case of Younger v. Harris.92That case held that a federal court cannot enjoin an ongoing state criminal proceeding unless there is bad faith, harassment, or some other unusual circumstances.93 Similarly, if the federal court begins its proceeding, the state court should not interfere, particularly because of federal supremacy. If the federal proceeding has not yet started, the defendant can argue that enjoining the federal officials is not forbidden and is appropriate.

However, there could occur a race to the court house between the defendant going to state court and the federal prosecutor going to federal court. In the federal system, however, the state court's supervisory power over the conduct of state officials with respect to violations of state laws might be more important than any inconveniences to the federal prosecutor. The vindication of a state constitutional right of ex- clusion of evidence outweighs the federal court's right to hear evidence obtained in violation of state law. One piece of evidence is not likely to cause the federal prosecutor to drop the suit.

The state court should have supcrvisory powers over state officials so as to ensure that thc ol'ficcrs clo not flout state constitutional law. In City of 1.os~Irigc- les v. Lyons, the U.S. Supreme Court statcd that the states "may permit their courts to use injunctions to oversee the conduct of law enforcement authorities on a continuing basis."" Thus, a state court should have no hesitation in supervising state personnel when that is clearly appropriate.

The state court can also attempt to enjoin a fed- eral official against violation of state laws. There are many limitations on the power of state courts over federal officials. In Tarble's Case, the Supreme Court determined that the state court could not inquire about the validity of the enlistment of soldiers into the militar~.~5 Further, in McClung v. Silliman,QQhe Court determined that state courts could not issue a writ of mandamus against federal officials. Although the U.S. Supreme Court has never ruled explicitly that a state court could not enjoin a federal official, the Court would probably not allow such an action. The Supreme Court is likely to find that if the federal official obtained the evidence, the state court should not interfere with the federal court's jurisdiction.

The defendant could argue that the state court should be able to enjoin its officials, and even federal officials, from acting contrary to the rule enacted by the state courts. The federal officials should follow the state law while they are in the state, if the state law is more protective than the federal law. This would encourage state officers to act in accordance with state law.

However, this law would probably be too strin- gent for the federal officials. Federal officers would have to behave differently in each state, and there

would be no uniform rules. Further, the state law is not suprcmc; the federal law overrules conflicting statc laws. The federal government and officials are not bound by statc laws.

The del'cndant may be able to enforce exclusion of thc evidence obtained legally by federal agents, but which is contrary to the state exclusionary rule in the state court. The state can follow the theory be- hind Elkins v. United States97 and eliminate the "re- verse silver platter" problem that arises in such a situ- ation. Given that Elkins held that evidence obtained by state officers in violation of the U.S. Constitution is inadmissible in the federal courts, evidence ob- tained by federal officers in violation of the state con- stitution should not be admitted in the state court. It would be internally inconsistent for the state court to use different rules depending on whether the officers are state or federal.

If a search is unreasonable and, therefore, vio- lates the state constitution, the products should not be admitted in the state court, regardless of the ac- tors. The victim of the search is harmed equally by state or federal officers. Although federal officers are not usually required to follow state law, the state court should not admit evidence that was obtained in violation of the constitutional rights of its citizens. The fedcral ol'l'iccrs arc not harmed because they probably will I)c iil>lc to use the evidence in federal court. 'l'hc stale clocs not interfere with federal law enforcement or federal courts.

Federal Courts

If the state court is hesitant to interfere with the actions of the federal court by enjoining its state per- sonnel, the defendant can argue to the federal court that it should refuse to admit the evidence. The fed- eral court could make an evidentiary ruling that the federal officials cannot receive evidence that a state officer obtained in violation of state law. Federal courts should not encourage state officers to violate their state laws. Further, the federal court may en- hance this policy prohibiting the federal officers from admitting evidence which they obtained by a knowing violation of the state law where they are working.

A defendant could request an injunction against the state official in federal court to prohibit a handing over of illegally obtained evidence. Because the state actor acted in violation of the state constitution, the official should lose immunity from suit in federal court under Ex Parte Young.98 The state officials must obcy the U.S. Constitution; violations of neither one should be tolerated. The federal court should enjoin the state officcrs on state constitutional grounds.

However, this position has not been accepted by the U.S. Suprcnic Court. In Pennhurst State School and Hospitul v. Hulrlerman,99 the Court refused to en- join a statc official for violation of state laws. Only the state court has power over state officials. Therefore, the lower federal courts will probably not enjoin the state officer in deference to Pennhurst.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 75

In United States v. Chavez-Vernaza,loO the federal court refused to encourage the state officers to follow carefully the state constitutional rules announced by state courts. In that case, Chavez wanted discovery of the manner in which state officials obtained evidence against him to determine if their activities violated state law. He claimed that if the evidence was seized in violation of state constitutional law, comity de- manded that the federal court suppress it. The appel- late court did not agree.

The Oregon court held that evidence is admissi- ble in a federal court under federal standards. Fol- lowing state law would hamper federal law enforce- ment by suppressing probative evidence.101 However, the state constitutional rule would not hamper federal law enforcement significantly. Obvi- ously, a state would not adopt a rule that would bc im- possible for its own law enforccmcnt pcrsonncl to up- hold. If the rule did not harm thc statc courl's enforcement of the law, it is unlikely that a Scclcral court in the state would find it unworkablc.

For the Chavez court, uniformity among fcdcral courts is more important than respect for thc statcs. Although uniformity is a vital consideration, it does not outweigh the Constitution. A court would never assert that law enforcement officers could uniformly violate the U.S. Constitution. Federal courts should not sanction the violation of a state constitution by state officers. Uniform enforcement by the federal court of rules for federal agents will be maintained, while the state constitution is also upheld if the fed- eral court suppresses the evidence.

Finally, the Chavez court asserted that if the state desires to discipline its officers, other means are available as sanctions.102 However, although other sanctions exist, none seem to be as effective as the ex- clusionary rule. In dissent, Judge Harry Pregerson recognized that the federal court should defer to the state exclusionary rule because otherwise the state officers would be able to violate state constitutional law with impunity.103 In United States v. Henderson,l04 the federal court reasoned correctly that the deter- rence of a state exclusionary rule would be lessened if the state officer were permitted to introduce the evi- dence in a federal proceeding.

In Elkins v. United States,l05 the Supreme Court supported this policy of encouraging adherence to state law. The majority recognized that it must ex- clude the evidence in order to avoid conflict between state and federal courts. "When a federal court sit- ting in an exclusionary state admits evidence lawlessly seized by state agents, it not only frustrates state pol- icy, but frustrates that policy in a particularly inap- propriate and ironic way."106 In dissent, Justice Felix Frankfurter agreed that state law is frustrated if the federal court does not suppress the illegally seizcd

evidence. Thus the entire Court agreed that this evi- dence cannot be admitted.

Justice Frankfurter also asserted that the federal courts should not interfere with beneficial state pro- cedures that assist the defendant by limiting the ex- clusion of evidence to the minimum in the U.S. Con- stitution. The state court cannot effectively discipline state officers for violations of state laws that are more protective than the U.S. Constitution. Frankfurter would hold that proper respect for the states de- mands that thc state courts decide whether the evi- dence is admissible and that federal courts abide by this decision. This doctrine would be particularly ap- plicable in a casewhere the state is more protective of the defendant under its constitution than the U.S. Constitution as interpreted by the U.S. Supreme Court.

Conclusion Statc courts, pcrhaps with the help of federal

courts, must try to cnsure the state constitutional rights of statc citizens. Many states are now granting defendants many rights that the Supreme Court has not found in thc U.S. Constitution. The California courts were oncc the leaders of the crusade to have the state courts become the chief guardians of the lib- erties of defendants. However, the court's goals were thwarted when the citizens of the state voted in a ref- erendum that the California Constitution is identical in meaning to the United States Constitution as in- terpreted by the U.S. Supreme Court.107

New Jersey, New York, and Connecticut are leading the eastern states in broad interpretation of their state constitutions. These states and many oth- ers are interpreting their constitutions beneficially for the defcndant. Several western states, such as Alaska, Oregon, and Washington, are also leading in state constitutional interpretation.108 Many states, however, have just begun to look toward their own constitutions, or have not yet attempted to use their own constitutions more broadly than the U.S. Consti- tution.109

NOTES

Sce Ronald K.L. Collins, "Reliance on State Constitu- tions: Some Random Thoughts," in Recent Develop- rnerlts in Stule CortstitutionalLaw (St. Paul: West Publish- ing Co., 1985). p. 13.

2Williani Brennan, "Guardians of Our Liberties-State Courts No Lcss than Federal," Judges Journal (Fall 1976): 83.

3Collins, p. 17. 4"Developments, The Interpretation of State Constitu- tional Rights," Harvard Law Review 95 (1982): 1329.

SBrennan, p. 103. suNote, Statc Constitutional Guarantees as Adequate State Ground: Supreme Court Review and Problems of Federalism," Amc.ricari C~iniirial Law Review 13 (Spring 1976) 737.

7462 US. 637 (1983).

76 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

8 William Greenhalgh, "Independent and Adequate State Grounds: The Long and the Short of It," in Recent Devel- opments in State Cotzstitlitional Law, p. 36.

QCollins, p. 17. Collins notes that the Iowa Supreme Court upheld an exclusionary rule in State v. Sheridan, 96 N.W. 73) (1903) before the federal decision in Weeks v. United States, 232 U.S. 383 (1914) and appointed counsel in Car- penter v. Dane County, 9 Wisc. 274 (1859) prior to the federal determination in Gideon v. Wainright, 372 U.S. 335 (1963).

1O"Project Report, Toward an Activist Role for State Dills of Rights," Harvard Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Re- view 8 (1973): 284.

1 Ibid., p. 285. '%id., p. 288. 13Ibid., p. 289. 14Ibid., p. 290. 'SIbid., p. 292. 'estate v. Jewett, 146 Vt. 221, 500 A.2d 233 (Vt. 1985).

Since 1970,250 cases have held that state constitutions are broader than their federal constitutional counter- parts.

17Ibid., p. 235. 18463 U.S. 1032 (1983). lg465 U.S. 324 (1984). 20658 P.2d 879 (Colo. 1983). 21 Roviaro v. United States, 353 U.S. 53 (1957). 22465 U.S. 329. 23733 P.2d 375 (Okla. 1987). z4Ibid., p. 381. See United State v. Janis, 428 US. 433

(1976). 25Ibid., p. 378. The exclusionary rule was incorporated in

Hess v. State, 84 Okla. 73, 202 P. 310 (Okla. 1921). 26367 U.S. 643 (1961). 27733 P.2d 379. 28 127 N.H. 286,499 A.2d 977 (N.H. 1985). 29499 A.2d 981. 30Delaware v. Prouse, 440 U.S. 648 (1979). The Supreme

Court has yet to grant a writ on this question presented. 31 706 P.2d 317 (Alas. 1985). 32462 U.S. 213 (1983). 33Aguilar v. Texas, 378 U.S. 108 (1964); Spinelli v. Unitcd

States, 393 U.S. 410 (1969). The two-prong test consists of veracity or reliability and basis of knowledge.

34462 U.S. 213. 35 105 N.J. 95,519 A.2d 820 (N.J. 1987). 36468 U.S. 897 (1984). 37519 A.2d 857. SeIbid., 849. 3gIbid., 856. 401bid., 854. 41 Ibid., 856. 42468 U.S. 928. 43519 A.2d 857. 44463 U.S. 1032. 45Greenhalgh, p. 21. Under this new rule, the Supreme

Court will hear the state case if it was based on both state and federal grounds, but the state court increased the protection of the federal right. There is no reason why

the Supreme Court needs to hear a case if the federal right has bcen protected because there is no danger that the federal intercst will be lost.

46463 U.S. 1042. 471bid., 1038, n.4. 481bid., 1041. 49500 A.2d 233. SOIbid., p. 238. 51 466 U.S. 380 (1984). 52432 So.2197 (Ha. 1983). 53466 US. 381. 541hid., 381-82. 55111itl., 382. Although Stcvcns' opinion is a dissent, it did

havc an clkct; pcr curiam reversals occurred less fre- quently sincc tic pointed out the Court's action.

56Ibid., 387. Iktwccn the 1981 and the 1983 term, the Court dcciclctl 19 cases in summary fashion in favor of the wardcn or m;~rshall reversing a decision which up- held a constitutional right (p. 386).

57466 U.S. 727 (1984). 58462 U.S. 213. 5QSee note 61. 60466 U.S. 738. 61 394 Mass. 363,476 N.E.2d 548 (Mass. 1985). @Ibid., 555. 63Ibid. 64Ibid.,556. 65346 N.W.W 425 (S.D. 1984). 66South Dakota v. Neville, 459 US. 553 (1983). G7346 N.W.2d 328. 68Ibid., 429. 69Gates, 462 U.S. 213; Oregon v. Has, 420 US. 714(1975). 70359 U.S. 121 (1959). 7l359 U.S. 187 (1959). 72Bartkus, 359 U.S. 122. 7355 U.S. (14 How.) 13,20 (1852). "Ibid., 124. At the time the Fourteenth Amendment was

not understtxxl to incorporate the first eight amend- ments.

75Ibid., 132. 76359 US. 187. 771bid., 189. 78260 U.S. 377 (1922). 7QIbid., 195. 80359 US. 138. 8' 361 US. 529 (1960). 82Rinaldi v. United States 434 U.S. 22, n.5 (1977). 83474 US. 82 (1985). 84350 U.S. 214 (1955). 85Ibid., 217. 861bid., 218. e71bid., 219. 88United States Constitution, Articlc VI:

This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States. . . shall be the supreme Law of the Land: and thc Jutlgcs in every State shall be bound thcrcby, any Thing in the Constitution or laws of any Statc lo the Contrary notwthstanding.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 77

89365 U.S. 381 (1960). gobid., 384 n.4. 91 Ibid., 385. 92401 U.S. 37 (1971). 93Ibid., 54. 94461 U.S. 95, 113 (1983). 9580 US. (13 Wall.) 397 (1872). 96 19 US. (6 Wheat.) 598 (1821). 97364 U.S. 206 (1959). 98209 U.S. 123 (1908). A state official who violatcs the Con-

stitution loses all immunity. 99465 U.S. 89 (1984).

10084.4 F.2d 1368 (9th Cir, 1987). '01 Ibid., 1374. 102Ibid. lo31bid., 1378. '04721 F.W 1220 (9th Sir. 1983). lo5364 US. 206 (1950). loGIbid., 221. 107111 rc I ~ n c c , 37 (M.3d 873,694 P.2d 744,210 Cal. Rptr.

631 (Cal. 1985). Sce appendix. 08See appendix.

log See appendix.

78 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Appendix

Cases since Michigan v. Long in Which a State Court Has Granted the Defendant More Protections Than the Supreme Court Finds within the U.S. Constitution.

Alabama Ex Parte Lynn, 477 So.2d 1385 (1985)

Sixth Amendment: cross-examination

Bradley v. State, 494 So.2d 772 (1986) Dissent Due Process: pretrial discovery

Alaska Reeves v. State, 599 P.2d 727 (1970)

Fourth Amendment: inventory search

Stephen v. State, 711 P.2d 1156 (1985) Fifth Amendment: custodial interrogation

Best v. Municipality ofAnchorage, 712 P.2d 892 (1985) Fourth Amendment: standing for suppression of evidence

State v. Jones, 706 P.2d 317 (1985) Fourth Amendment: probable cause standard

Arizona State v. Adult, 724 P.2d 525 (1986)

Fourth Amendment: exigent circumstances, in- evitable discovery

Kunzler v. Pima County Superior Court, 744 P.2d 669 (1987) Concur

Sixth Amendment: right to counsel

State v. Powers, 742 P.2d 792 (1987) Right to trial by jury

California People v. Ramos, 689 P.2d 430 (1984)

Due Process: jury instructions

In re Lance, 694 P.2d 744 (1985) Fourth Amendment: no vicarious exclusionary rule

In re William Misener, 698 P.2d 637 (1985) Fifth Amendment: self-incrimination

Williams v. People, 709 P.2d 1287 (1985) Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

People v. May, 748 P.2d 307 (1988)

Fourth Amendment: follow Lance and Proposi- tion 8

Colorado State v. Nunez, 658 P.2d 879 (1983)

Due Proccss: disclosure of informants

State v. Deitchman, 695 P.2d 1146 (1985) Concur Fourth Amendment: good faith exception exists

People v. Drake, 748 P.2d 1237 (1988) Concur and Dissent

Fourth Amendment: list examples

Connecticut State v. Cohane, 479 A.2d 763 (1984)

Fifth Amendment: self-incrimination

State v. Simms, 518 A.2d 35 (1986) Grand jury implied use of state law

State v. Janbek, 529 A.2d 1245 (1987) Due Process: exclude from witness room

State v. Hufford, 533 A.2d 1199 (1987) Sixth Amendment: confrontation

State v. Stoddard, 206 Conn. 157 (1988) Sixth Amendment: right to counsel

Georgia State v. Luck, 312 S.E.2d 791 (1984)

Fourl ti A~iicndrncnt: warrant requirement

Williams v. Ne~<rorne, 334 S.E.2d 171 (1985) Dissent Indigent right to psychiatrist

Hawaii State v. Kalanu, 520 P.2d 51 (1974)

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

Idaho Bates v. State, 679 P.2d 672 (1984) State v. Ankney, 704 P.2d 333 (1985) Dissent

Due Proccss: seizure of driver's license

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 79

Illinois People v. Singleton, 1988 Lexis 27

Fourteenth Amendment: Due Process

Indiana Miller v. State, 517 N.E.2d 64 (1987)

Sixth Amendment: Confrontation Clause

Maryland Hillard v. State, 406 A.2d 415 (1979)

Fifth Amendment: voluntariness; follow Mary- land nonconstitutional law

Massachusetts Commonwealth v. Ford, 476 N.E.2d 560 (1985)

Fourth Amendment: inventory search

Commonwealth v. Upton, 476 N.E.2d 548 (1985) Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

Michigan State v. Chapman, 387 N.W.2d 835 (1986)

Fourth Amendment: curtilage

Paramount Corporation v. Miskins, 344 N.W.2d 788 (1986)

Fifth Amendment: self-incrimination

Minnesota State v. Fuller, 374 N.W.2d 722 (1985) Dissent

Sixth Amendment: double jeopardy

Missouri State v. Brown, 708 S.W.2d 140 (1984) Concur and Dissent

Fourth Amendment: exclusionary rule

Montana State v. Solis, 693 P.2d 518 (1984)

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

State v. Johnson, 719 P.2d 1248 (1986) Sixth Amendment: right to counsel

Nebraska State v. Havlat, 385 N.W.2d 436 (1986) Dissent

Fourth Amendment: open fields

State v. Hinton, 415 N.W.2d 138 (1987) Fourth Amendment: exclusionary rule

New Hampshire State v. Koppel, 499 A.2d 977 (1985)

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

State v. Mercier, 509 A.2d 1246 (1986) Fifth Amendment: self-incrimination

New Jersey Grand Jury Proceedings of Joseph Guarino, 516 A.2d 1063 (1986)

Fifth Amendment: self-incrimination

State v. Gilmore, 511 A.2d 1150 (1986) Jury selection

State v. Ramseur, 524 A.2d 188 (1987) Dissent Eighth Amendment: death penalty

State v. Fritz, 519 A.2d 336 (1987) Sixth Amendment: right to counsel

State v. Novembrino, 519 A.2d 820 (1987) Fourth Amendment: exclusionary rule

New York People v. P.J. 14dc0, 501 N.E.2d 556 (1986)

Fourth Amcntlrnent: scarch and seizure

People v. C'lri.ss, 404 N.E.2d 444 (1986) Fourth A~ncndment: search and seizure

People v. Bigclow, 488 N.E.2d 451 (1985) Fourth A~ncnclrnent: exclusionary rule

People v. Alvarez, 51 5 N.E.2d 898 (1987) Fourteenth Amendment: due process

North Carolina State v. Lachat, 343 S.E.2d 872 (1986)

Fifth Amendment: double jeopardy

Jackson v. Housing Authority of the City of High Point, 364 S.E.2d 416 (1988)

Jury selection

Oklahoma Turner v. City of Lawton, 733 P.2d 375 (1987)

Fourth Amendment: exclusionary rule

Oregon State v. Magee, 744.2d 250 (1987)

Fifth Amendment: Miranda

Rhode Island State v. VonBulow, 475 A.2d 205 (1984)

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

South Dakota State v. Neville, 346 N.W.2d 425 (1984)

Fifth Amendment: self-incrimination

State v. Auen, 342 N.W.2d 236 (1984) Dissent Jury trial

Texas Sanchez v. State, 707 S.W.2d 575 (1986)

Fifth Amendment: Miranda

Wilkerson v. State, 726 S.W.2d 542 (1986) Dissent Sixth Amendment: assistance of counsel

Utah State v. Ashe, 745 P.2d 1255 (1987) Dissent

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

Vermont State v. Jewett, 500 A.2d 233 (1985)

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

80 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

State v. Ballou, 535 A.2d 1280 (1987) Fourth Amendment: probable cause

State v. Wood, 536 A.2d 902 (1987) Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

Washington State v. Jackson, 688 P.2d 136 (1984)

Fourth Amendment: probablc cause State v. Chrisman, 676 P.2d 419 (1984)

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

State v. Stroud, 720 P.2d 436 (1986) Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

State v. Gunwall, 720 P.2d 808 (1986) Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

State v. Box, 745 P.2d 23 (1987) Dissent Fourteenth Amendment: due process

West Virginia State v. Wyer. 320 S.E.2d 92 (1984) Dissent

Sixth Amcndmcnt: right to counsel

Wisconsin State v. Rodgerx. 340 N.W.2d 453 (1984) Dissent

Fourth Amendment: search and seizure

Wyoming Long v. State, 745 P.2d 547 (1987)

Sixth Amendment: right to counsel

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 81

82 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 7

State Courts and Economic Rights This chapter examines the role of state courts in

protecting economic rights. Since the U.S. Supreme Court has decided to expend its constitutional energy on other issues, the protection of property rights from unwarranted state regulation rests essentially with state supreme courts. The correctness and effec- tiveness of this state court activism are legitimate and important concerns for all those interested in pro- moting an effective and balanced role for the state ju- diciaries in our constitutional system. The chapter will examine the argumentsfor and against state judi- cial activism in protecting economic rights, and the standards by which such activism can be judged. It will be argued that critics of this area of judicial activism assume too frequently the relevance of the federal experience and generalize their conclusions to the states without fully appreciating the significant dif- ference found in the state constitutional traditions. We conclude by suggesting that it is necessary not only for judges but also for legislators and citizens to work together to strike a proper balance between a judiciary that does too much and one that does too lit- tle.

State constitutions are a mine of numcrous, unique, and detailed provisions conccrncd with t he protection of property rights. At least 34 state consti- tutions contain open court or right to acccss provi- sions for which there is no national cquivalenl.' These open court provisions can be found in the ear- liest constitutions as well as in ones adopted in the 20th century.2These provisions were included in con- stitutions to ensure that state legislatures would not tamper with common law remedies available to citi- zens and that states would not impose unreasonable financial conditions for access to the courts.3

A number of state constitutions also contain antimonopoly and antiperpetuities clauses for which one finds no national equivalents. These provisions also appeared in the earliest state constitutions and were adopted by other states in the 19th and 20th centuries.4 The earlier antimonopoly provisions were aimed exclusively at public monopolies. These origi-

nated in thc common law rule against perpetuities and the granting of exclusive franchises or licenses by the state, but they were also aimed at prohibiting ex- cessive rcgulalions on busines~.~ Provisions adopted after the Civil War were written in such a way as to make them applicable to privately created monopo- lies as well.6

Finally, the constitutions of half the states con- tain taking clauses, which unlike the federal taking clause contain the phrase property shall not be taken "or damaged" for public use without just compensa- tion.' The addition of the "or damaged" phrase was aimed at providing more protection than the federal equivalent, especially against legalized nuisances, which, generally, have not been interpreted as a "tak- ing" by federal courts.8 These exemplify but do not exhaust the variety of property provisions found in state constitutions.

One of the most controversial areas of state court activism in this era of the new judicial federal- ism is in the use of state due process, equal protec- tion, and right-to-remedy clauses to strike down state and local economic regulations interfering with prop- erty intercsts.'l%c movemcnt togrant greater protec- tion to individuirl rights on state constitutional grounds than the U.S. Supreme Court has granted under the federal Constitution has met generally with favorable rcsponses.0 However, when it comes to economic rights, the reaction has been less than enthusiastic.10 This tepid response is understandable given the association of protecting economic rights with a period of the U.S. Supreme Court's history known as the Lochner era, in which, it is claimed, the Court adopted a laissez faire economic philosophy, striking down economic regulation in the name of free enterprise and property rights."

This is not, however, without its ironies. The "new" judicial fcdcralism is not "new" in the area of economic rights. State supreme courts relied on vari- ous provisions of their respective constitutions to protect such rights well before the Supreme Court discovered substantive due process, and they have

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 83

continued to do so. These courts are major determi- nants of the extent to which property rights are given protection in the United States, and with regard to many areas of economic concern, state courts are the only judicial forums in which these issues are given a serious hearing. In part this is the result of the Su- preme Court's decision to play little or no role in po- licing economic regulations, at least insofar as due process and equal protection challenges are con- cerned. As Lawrence Sager puts it:

With extraordinary generality and finality federal courts have ceased to find in the Constitution any basis for intervening in the decisions of governmental entities to tax or regulate economic affairs12

Justice William Brennan spoke for the Court of the last half century when he noted the wide latitude granted by the Court "to a valid exercise of the state's police power even if it results in severe violations of property rights."l3

As pointed out in chapter 1, three clauses of the U.S. Constitution have been used by the federal courts to protect property rights: (1) the taking clause of the Fifth Amendment, (2) the contract clause, and (3) the due process clauses of the Fifth and Four- teenth Amendments. Nearly all state constitutions contain similar provisions.14 This chapter concen- trates primarily on the use of due process, equal pro- tection, and right-to-remedy clauses by state high courts to review regulations that raise questions of property rights. This focus has four rationalcs: (1) the bulk of state court activity has been and continues to be focused on due process and equal protection as grounds for protecting property rights; (2) most states have incorporated the taking limitation into their due process clauses, thus making it difficult to distinguish the two limitations;l5 (3) when applying the taking or contract clauses, state courts generally have followed the federal precedents, which involve a balancing of private loss against public gain;le (4) the U.S. Su- preme Court has remained active in applying the tak- ing and contract clauses, deciding at least 18 major cases in the last ten years.17

State Courts and Economic Rights in the 19th Century

Substantive due process, the idea that legislation must not be arbitrary (i.e., it must have a real and sub- stantial relationship to a legitimate state interest), arose first among state courts-a fact that was influ- ential in its adoption by the U.S. Supreme Court.18 Edward S. Corwin, after analyzing state and federal cases prior to the Civil War, credits Wynehamer v. State of New Yorklg as the beacon case whose doctrine "less than 20 years from the time of its rendition . . . was far on the way to being assimilated into the ac- cepted constitutional law of the country."20 There were numerous other cases, enough to allow the con-

clusion that the development of substantive due process was as much a function of state judges inter- preting state constitutions as it was the creation of federal judges.21

The adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment (1868) did not give immediate impetus to the devel- opment of economic due process as far as the Su- preme Court was concerned, but state courts were quick to add it to their constitutional arsenals. Exem- plary in this respect is the case of In Re Jacobs (1885).22 The New York legislature had prohibited the manufacturing or preparation of tobacco in tene- ments in citics of 500,000 or more in population. The New York Court of Appeals voided the law as a de- privation of liberty without due process of law. In do- ing so, the court wrote:

Liberty, in its broad sense as understood in this country, means the right, not only of freedom from actual servitude, imprison- ment or restraint, but the right of one to use his faculties in all lawful ways, to live and work where he will, to earn his livelihood in any lawful callings, and to pursue any lawful trade or avocation. All laws, therefore, which impair or trammel these rights, which limit one in his choice of a trade or profes- sion, or confine him to work or live in a speci- fied locality, or exclude him from his own house, or restrain his otherwise lawful move- ments (except as such laws may be passed in the exercise by the legislature of the police powcr . . .) are infringements on his funda- mental rights of liberty, which are under constilutional protection.23 This vicw is one that survived the 19th century

among many statc courts and remains an important principle guiding their decisions in this area. New York was not alone. Between 1885 and 1894, ten states adopted the same general approach. Bernard Siegan has suggested that the U.S. Supreme Court decision in Allegeyer v. Louisiana, in which the liberty of contract was constitutionalized, thus beginning the era of substantive due process, was not unexpected "because the federal judiciary was in fact following trends established in many states."24 Protection of property and economic rights was not foisted on the country by the judiciary: doctrines of vested rights and economic due process were developed out of a commitment to protecting property and economic liberties that are part of the constitutional and politi- cal tradition of the United States.25

State Court Activity and Economic Rights, 1897-1987

The hcyday of federal substantive due process, roughly 1897 to 1937. has been well studied.26The re- action to substantive due process as it was interpreted in Lochner and its progeny was so intense that the U.S. Supreme Court has, for all intents and purposes,

84 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

abandoned any serious review of the kind of eco- nomic regulation that had been the prime target of the doctrine. Oliver Wendell Holmes' stinging dis- sent to Lochner became the definitive understanding of Lochner. Holmes' view, that Lochner was no more than an attempt to read into the Constitution a par- ticular economic philosophy derived from Adam Smith and, more immediately, Herbert Spencer, be- came the dominant view among academic commenta- tors as well as judges. In its place emerged a view that the due process clause, as far as economic regulation is concerned, means what its words suggest, namely, procedural but not substantive protection against government action.27 While the U.S. Supreme Court has revived the general notion of substantive due process, and has recently indicated that it may be- come more solicitous of property rights, thcrc has been no attempt to revive substantive due proccss a s a basis for stricter review of economic and social rcgu- lation.28

What follows is a look at the extent to which state courts adopted a similar doctrine, how rigorously they

applied it and in what areas, and the extent to which the state courts followed the U.S. Supreme Court in rejecting substantive due process. To get some idea of state court involvement in protecting economic rights, an examination was made of eight studies that collected cases in this area.29 Added to the cases noted therein were decisions collected from lists pro- vided by state courts themselves. Finally, to the above were added =ses collected since 1980 from the re- gional reporters. A total of 391 cases were discovered using this method. Although this figure by no means represents all the cases decided by state high courts in this area, it is believed that it is representative of the activity of state courts in the period from 1897 to 1987.30

During thc pcriod of 1897-1937, state courts definitely emphasized substantive due process, with 70 percent of thc cases being decided on this basis (see Table I) . This figure increased to 81 percent during the ncxt pcriod, 1938-1968, but dropped significantly to 18 percent during 1969-1987. The emphasis on equal protection decreased slightly

Table 1 State Supreme Court Activity and Economic Rights, 1897-1 987

Local Regulations1 Judicial Anti- Miscellaneous Remedy Competitive Totals

(%) (No.) (%) (No.) (%) (No.) ( ) (No.)

1897-1 937 Substantive Due Process 75.0 15 50.0 1 66.7 10 70.3 26 Equal Protection 15.0 3 50.0 1 13.3 2 16.2 6 Substantive Due Process/

Equal Protection Combined 10.0 2 0.0 0 20.0 3 13.5 5 Total 100.0 20 100.0 2 100.0 15 100.0 37

1938-1 968 Substantive Due Process 71.1 27 0.0 0 85.6 143 81.0 170

Equal Protection 18.4 7 60.0 3 7.8 13 11.0 23 Substantive Due Process1

Equal Protection Combined 7.9 3 20.0 1 4.2 7 5.2 11 Miscellaneous 2.6 1 20.0 1 2.4 4 2.9 6 Total 100.0 38 100.0 5 100.0 167 100.0 210

1969-1 987 Substantive Due Process 25.8 8 5.1 4 48.0 12 17.9 24 Equal Protection 48.4 15 55.1 43 24.0 6 47.8 64 Substantive Due ProessJ

Equal Protection Combined 9.7 3 5.1 4 24.0 6 9.7 13 Miscellaneous* 16.1 5 34.6 27 4.0 1 24.6 33 Total 100.0 31 100.0 78 lnn.0 25 100.0 134

- - -

Total Number of Cases 23.4 89 22.3 85 54.3 207 100.0 381 *Most of the cases in this category are open court or right-to-remedy provisions of state constitutions.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 85

from 16 percent during 1897-1937 to 11 percent dur- statutes of limitation which would make suit impossi- ing 1938-1968, but then increased dramatically to 48 ble when those minors reached legal age37 and con- percent during 1969-1987. An increase in state legis- sumers from attempts by legislatures to arbitrarily lative activity involving social and economic regula- limit entry into professions, fix prices, or otherwise tion may account for part of the shift, but does not lessen competition.38 seem to be the primary factor. Decisions as far back as the end of the 19th century decided on due process Standards of Review. 1970-1988 grounds would today almost certainly be decided on equal protection grounds.31 The discrediting of due process as a basis for examining social and economic regulation, as well as the rise of equality as a constitu- tional value, have combined to make judges and scholars feel more comfortable with equal protection analysis, even though the outcomes are the same.32

A second significant aspect of the data is the exis- tence of a consistent philosophy governing this judi- cial activism that persists throughout thc pcriods in question. Fifty-three percent of all t hc caws exam- ined fell into the anticompctitivc category. State court judges struck down measures that cit hcr overtly or covertly tended to create monopoly and/or inter- fere with the operation of the markctplacc. In dcci- sion after decision, judges concludcd that the rcal as opposed to the ostensible purpose of the legislation in question was anticompetitive. In doing so, the judges were being true to what one scholar has dem- onstrated was one of the historically valid purposes of the due process clause, namely, protection against monopoly.33

The most recent period, 1969-1987, reveals a de- velopment of some promise in the use of open court or right-to-remedy clauses contained in most state constitutions. These clauses typically take the form of guaranteeing that all courts shall be open, and that all persons shall have a remedy for injuries suffered to their persons, property, or reputation. In conjunction with equal protection clauses, they have been used to strike down guest statutes (which preclude liability for nonpaying passengers in private vehicles), stat- utes of repose (which preclude liability), caps on mal- practice awards, and similar measures. The U.S. Su- preme Court has not addressed any of these issues directly. Assuming that at least some of these statutes are open to legitimate challenge, the only available forums for those challenges have been the state judi- ciaries. In fact, the single most striking dcvclopment among state supreme courts in protecting economic rights since 1980 has been the increasing use of these right-to-remedy clauses, frequently in conjunction with equal protection clauses, to strike down a variety of legislative schemes.34

The protection of economic rights extends be- yond the confines of the business world and involves a variety of groups and interests. These range from widows of workmen denied access to courts for claims to compensation35 to suppliers of materials denied a special exemption from liability granted to archi- tects.36 These decisions have protected minors from

The most rcccnt period of state court activity re- veals important shifts in the ground for as well as the standards of review. The 144 cases examined during this period came from 44 states, with the largest num- bers concentrated in Ohio (12), Alabama (12), Geor- gia (8), California (8), New Hampshire (5), and Texas (5). Fifty-six percent of these cases involved some kind of limitation on liability, whether product liabil- ity, guest statutcs, or limitations on plaintiffs in suits involving thc mctlical profession. In the majority of thcsc cases, the cnactmcnts were struck down on right-to-rcmccly andlor equal protection grounds, suggesting that slate court activism is most likely to be triggercd whcn legislatures tamper with tradi- tional common law rcmedies for injuries without pro- viding alternative relief.

The movement toward stricter liability in torts and the rise of product liability claims coupled with a perceived medical malpractice crisis, galvanized a va- riety of groups to seek relief before state legislatures. The result was legislation placing limitations on li- ability in a variety of areas, but especially in the health professions. State courts have not been unani- mous in their responses to this legislation. With the exception of the guest statutes where state courts have struck down almost all of those remaining on the books, state courts have sustained a variety of limita- tions on liabilit~.~Q The statutes upheld, in most cases, have becn less drastic with respect to remedies left for plaintiff^.^^ Prominent examples of state courts that have upheld such legislation are Califor- nia and Indiana. The California Medical Injury Com- pensation Act of 1975 was challenged in four differ- ent suits, all of which the California Supreme Court sustained by using a rational basis test.41 A similar act adopted in Indiana was also upheld.42

Equal Protection. In applying equal protection clauses, state courts have resorted to a variety of ap- proaches, running li-om rational relationship to strict scrutiny, and in at least two cases, a standard alto- gether different from the three-tiered federal analy- sis.43

Some of the state courts that claim to be applying the rational relationship test are actually requiring a more demanding standard of review. In Whitworth v. B y n ~ r n , ~ ~ the Texas high court dcclared that the state's guest stalutc had no rational relationship to any legitimate statc interest. Applying the same test. the U.S. Suprcrnc Court upheld similar legislation.45 In Ketcham v. Kings County Medical Service,4Vhe

86 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Washington court held an optometrist rcimhursc- rnent scheme to be void on a rational rclationship standard, while the dissenters had no problem com- ing up with facts to sustain the classification.

Other courts have applied a means-scrutiny or middle-tier standard.47 The significance of this stan- dard can be seen in the case of Tabler v. Wallace. In the face of some imaginative "reasonable bases" pro- vided by the attorneys for the state, the Kentucky court responded by arguing that the state equal pro- tection clause requires there to be a "substantial and justifiable reason apparent from the legislative his- tory, statute or some other authoritative source," and that "reasons that could exist without anything of a positive nature to suggest that they did exist do not suffice."48

Another approach used by state judiciaries is to combine equal protection analysis with some other provision of their constitution. The most common combination is with due process and/or right-to-rem- edy clauses. In the cases combining equal protection and due process, the result looks very much like a substantive due process test.49 In Benson v. North Da- kota Workmen's Compensation Bureau:o the North Dakota high court demanded a close correspondence between statutory classification and legislative goals. In Henderson Clay Products, Inc. v. Edgar Woods and Associates, Inc., the fusion of equal protection and due process is equally clear. The Court held that the statute was an "unreasonable and arbitrary legislative classification. . . ."51 This fusion of equal protection and due process results in an intermediate level of re- view under the mantle of the more "respectable" equal protection clause.52

Equal protection was combined most frequently with the right-to-remedy clauses of state constitu- tions. This combination almost always resulted in having the remedy clauses being declared fundamen- tal rights, thus triggering strict scrutiny.53 Other com- binations were also found. In Maryland State Board of Barber Examiners v. Kuhn,54 equal protection was combined with the right to pursue a lawful occupa- tion as guaranteed by Article 23 of the state's Decla- ration of Rights.

Due Process. Under the due process clauscs, similar patterns emerged, though with vaguer stan- dards. Although some decisions rcstcd on a rational relationship test, most appear to have involved closer scrutiny than would be undertaken by federal courts.55 Afew clung to an approach that gocs back to the 19th century. Georgia continues to rely on sub- stantive due process of the Lochner variety. "The right to contract . . . and agree on price is a property right protected by the due process clause of our Con- stitution, and unless it is a business affected with the public interest, the General Assembly is without any

authority to al)ritlgc that right."56 Aware of its rela- tive isolation, the Georgia court noted that this was its position "no matter what other states or the Su- preme Court of the United States may or may not have decided."57

More typical is Louis Finocchiaro Inc. v. Nebraska Liquor Control. Here the court required a "clear, real and substantial connection between the assumed purpose of the enactment and the actual provisions thereof."58 Unlike the federal rational relationship test, these states have required that the rationale be spelled out explicitly; any conceivable rationale that might be adduced will not suffice. These "pure" sub- stantive due process cases are relatively rare in con- temporary state constitutional law. Aside from a few scattered cases elsewhere, they are concentrated in the South.

As with the equal protection cases, due process is occasionally linked with other provisions of state con- stitutions. In In re Certificate of Need for Aston Park, Inc.,59 the North Carolina court linked due process analysis with the constitutional prohibitions against monopolies and perpetuities; in Nelson v. fiusen,60 due process was coupled with the open court provi- sion of the Texas Constitution; and in Magna, Inc, v. Catrania,61 due process was connected with the ex- plicit provisions rcgarding property rights found in the Alabama Constitution. Such uses of state due process clauses to protect property rights find sup- port in the numerous and explicit references to prop- erty found in most state constitutions.

There are some cases that do not rely on equal protection or due process in any way. Most of these cases are based on right-to-remedy or open court pro- visions,62 while still others resort to contract clausess3 or guarantees for workers' compensation for injury or dcath.e4 Finally, at least two states, Lou- isiana and New Jersey, have rejected not only the re- sults of various U.S. Supreme Court decisions based on equal protection but also the federal multiple- tier analysis itself. Both states have adopted what ap- pear to them to be more fluid and protective ap- proaches.65

State courts have resorted to a variety of combi- nations ol'stntc constitutional provisions and avariety of tests in rcvicwing lcgislation.66 This is not surpris- ing. States and their judiciaries are by law and history independent and diverse entities. Moreover, given the generally discredited history of the protection of economic rights, especially through the use of sub- stantive due process, it is understandable that state judges who believe that their constitution, and their position in the federal system, give them a role to play in protecting economic rights, are groping for a sound basis for this role. The search has involved plotting a

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 87

course between the rigidities of Lochnerism and ab- dication.

Judge Michael Zimmerman of the Utah Su- preme Court provides clear evidence of this search. In sustaining legislation against attacks based on due process or equal protection, he noted the long tradi- tion among state courts toward more careful scrutiny of legislative classifications underlying economic regulations. "We do not purport today to settle de- finitively the question of the degree of congruence between the standard of review [required by state provisions as opposed to federal equal protection] but our past decisions . . . demonstrate that in the area of economic regulations, the standard of scru- tiny [under the relevant state provisions] will always meet or exceed that mandated by the Fourteenth Amendment. . . ."67 This cautious seeking for that delicate balance augurs well for the future of state constitutional protection of property rights.

State Courts and Economic Rights: Constitutional Charge or

Reactionary Residue? State supreme courts continue to rely on their

due process, equal protection and, increasingly, their right-to-remedy clauses to grant greater protection to economic rights than would be forthcoming from the federal judiciary. All but three states have refused to follow the lead of the U.S. Supreme Court in its re- jection of substantive due process and equal protec- tion in the area of economic regulation.68 There is no doubt about the continued solicitude for economic rights on the part of state supreme courts; however, there are doubts about the justifications for that ac- tivism. Seven arguments have been put forth in oppo- sition to judicial activism in this area. Some apply only to the use of substantive due process, but most apply to any attempt by courts to scrutinize economic and social regulations, though there does seem to be lcss opposition to the use of the equal protection and right-to-remedy clauses to protect economic rights.

Argument 1: The Distorted History Argument

This view is based on a reading of the due process clause as exclusively procedural. The claim is that substantive due process had very little pre-Civil War basis; substantive due process was essentially the in- vention of the judiciary in its ideologically based de- termination to protect property interests. This posi- tion seemed so obvious to Leonard Levy that he could write, in introducing Walton Hamilton's famous arti- cle on the "Path of Due Process of Law," that what the U.S. Supreme Court did was a "miraculous tran- substantiation of process into substance and human rights into vested rights. . . .The accomplishment was bizarre, haphazard, and ~nplanned."~g

It has been noted that early in the 19th century state courts had construed their due process clauses so as to provide substantive protection to property rights. Was there any justification for these states to do so? Or putting the question a bit differently: if those who insist that there is no indication whatso- ever that the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment meant to provide for substantive due process, is that evidence conclusive insofar as the state due process and law-of-the-land clauses are concerned? In the most recent work on the history of the due process and law-of-the-land clauses, Frank Strong shows that articles 39 and 52 of the Magna Carta were meant to provide "a substantive ban on invasion of ancient rights of personal liberty and feudal pr~perty."~O It was Edward Coke who successfully fused the law-of- the-land provision of the Magna Carta with due proc- ess of law and, in doing so, provided an historical basis for a substantive content to the due process clause that would be handed down to the colonists in the New World. Strong shows that government-granted monopolies and expropriation by public conversion were regarded as denials of due process. Due process was the-ancient enemy of monopoly, a shieldagainst publicly granted monopolies but, at the same time, a sword bolstering state power to deal effectively with private mon~pol ies .~~

Strong concludes his analysis of due process by asserting that the inherited content of substantive due process embraces two core meanings: antiex- propriation of property interest and antimonopoly in economic e n t e r p r i ~ e . ~ ~ He contends, therefore, that the perversions of due process occurred, not with reading into the clause a substantive content, but with Allegeyer v. Louisiana and Lochner v. New York.

The substantive due process the Court now unanimously embraces was of an utterly dif- ferent order from that espoused by Bradley and Ficld. They had stood for opposition to monopoly, a position with deep historical roots in I h c Process increasingly articulated as espousal of freedom of trade. The essence of freedom ol' trade was the general right of all to cngagc in the common callings free from constrictions or prohibitions on entry. In severing this right from its tie with anti- monopoly the Court in one sentence cata- pulted into an uncharted domain in which substantive due process could become the obstacle to endless instances of legal, eco- nomic and social reform.73

The reading of liberty of contract into the due process clausc was not consistent with the historic meaning of substantive due process. The reaction of the U.S. Supreme Court and scholars to this perver- sion was to read out of the clause any substantive con-

88 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

tent, thus throwing the proverbial baby out with the bath water. The notion of due process historically has been not only a shield against arbitrary expropriation and monopolies, but also a sword enabling the state to destroy or regulate private monopolies. Whether or not this revisionist history provides sufficient rea- son for the U.S. Supreme Court to re-enter the arena, it is certainly relevant to any argument about the appropriateness of state supreme courts so doing.

Argument 2: The Superior Importance of Personal Rights

The dichotomization of property versus personal rights, with the attendant elevation of the latter over the former, though well entrenched in the literature and court doctrine, has not gone unchallenged. Judge Learned Hand once said: "Just why property it- self was not a personal right nobody took time to ex- plain. . . ."74 The consequencc ofthc prcmaturc, not to say immodest, embracing of this dichotomy has been the creation of philosophical and practical diffi- culties which have come to light after a half-century of experience. Judge James Oakes of the Second Cir- cuit noted one of these difficulties:

If property rights are personal rights as the procedural cases say they are [referring to Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254 (1970); Fuentes v. Shevin, 407 U.S. 67 (1972); and Matthews v. Eldridge, 424 U.S. 319 (1976)l why should they not have substantive protec- tion like other personal rights?75

Recently, Leonard Levy questioned why the right to a livelihood was not included in the right to liberty and the pursuit of happiness.76 He challenged the dichotomy between personal and property rights as well as the adequacy of protection granted under the rational relationship test.77

Beyond these philosophical objections, a num- ber of practical difficulties arise from this separation. In many of the areas in which state supreme courts have been active, the distinction breaks down. In some cases, privacy and autonomy concerns are inex- tricably interwoven with property rights. How a fam- ily or group wishes to use a dwelling involves the use of property as one sees fit as well as matters of per- sonal autonomy and privacy.78 Cases involving work- ers' compensation are matters that concern one's livelihood, safety, and future well being. In still other areas, one set of property rights is pitted against an- other, as in the debate over limits on damages in medical malpractice suits. Why is it considered a property question deserving of more deference from the courts when a legislature singles out one profes- sional group for protection from liability and not oth- ers, especially when the basis for the classification ap- pears dubious?

Whatever remains viable in the distinction between personal and property rights, it cannot, without additional arguments, determine that all property rights are less important than all personal rights. We may want to say that some kinds of prop- erty rights are less important than others, but it would be difficult to sustain the position that all personal rights are more important than property rights, even supposing we can make the distinction-a supposi- tion which is itself problematic. The intertwining of economic and personal considerations in the cases coming before state high courts is extensive enough to make this distinction of little value for judges de- ciding cases in this area.

Argument 3: Lack of Textual Basis

Leonard I .cvy summarizes the textual basis argu- ment succinctly in responding to the arguments by Robcrl McCloskcy for protecting economic rights.

The problcm. rather, is that the Constitution quite explicitly protects religious liberty, but radiates Prom the vague contours of due process no visible protection to bartend- ers-nor riverboat pilots, oculists, nor any other occupation.79 To the extent there is force to this argument, it

applies to the U.S. Constitution. The same argument cannot be made with regard to state constitutions. In addition to a due process clause found in almost every state constitution, a majority of the state constitu- tions explicitly protect the "inalienable right of ac- quiring, possessing and protecting property."80 Some states explicitly grant the judiciary review power any time a taking for public purposes is an issue.8' The clauses in state constitutions concerning the protec- tion of property are more numerous and more ex- plicit than in the U.S. Constitution. For example, Colorado's Constitution, in addition to the due proc- ess clause, contains nine other provisions dealing with the protection of property in one form or an- other.82 By virtue of their quantity and explicitness, property rights under state constitutional law cannot be placed in a subordinate position to personal rights, at least not on textual grounds.

Argument 4: Conservation of Judicial Resources

This argument is made most forcefully by Robert McCl0skey.~3 The U.S. Supreme Court, he argues, has all it can do to handle the delicate and intractable problems involved in protecting and promoting po- litical and civil liberties. Since the Court cannot do everything, it best serves our constitutional order by concentrating on the protection of personal rights.

To the exlent that this argument has force, that force is attenuated if not completely dissipated in state constitutional history. Indeed, to the extent that

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 89

it is accepted by the U.S. Supreme Court so as to es- chew any role in policing economic regulations, then to that extent a stronger case can be made for state ju- diciaries to provide a forum in which redress may be obtained. Levy, while rejecting any role for the U.S. Supreme Court, suggests that "the remedy may prop- erly lie with state courts and state constitutional law."84

Argument 5: Lack of Judicial Competence

This argument, applied to the fcdcral courts by a number of scholars, has also been applicd to the stale judiciaries. However, this transfcr is questionable. State courts may well be in a better position to assess and judge local conditions and problems than is the U.S. Supreme Court. State court decisions do not en- compass national issues or problems, and the scope of their decisionmaking is limited to individual states. The Supreme Court of Pennsylvania put the argu- ment most effectively when it wrote:

This difference [between federal and state constitutional law] represents a sound devel- opment, one which takes into account the fact that state courts may be in a better posi- tion to review local economic legislation than the Supreme Court, since their prece- dents are not of national authority, may bet- ter adapt their decisions to local economic conditions and needs. . . . And where an in- dustry is of basic importance to the economy of the state or territory, extraordinary regu- lations may be necessary and proper.85

It may be that the U.S. Supreme Court ought not to spend time on, and lacks the expertise to adjudge, antiscalping ordinances in Indiana, but this cannot be said with the same degree of persuasiveness about state courts. James Kirby, in addressing this issue, wrote: "State courts. . . do not appear to have thrust themselves into unmanageable situations. Review of an economic regulation may well be simpler than an apportionment case, a voting rights case, or a product liability appeal."86

to the constitutional traditions of the states. By con- stitutional choice, state voters have granted explicit protection to property rights, recognized a right-to- remedy, and in many cases specifically empowered the judiciary to exercise judicial review.88 The tradi- tion is one of limited government rather than major- ity rule.89 To argue the character of judicial review is to insist that one tradition be favored over the other or, alternatively, that these constituent choices are wrong ones.90

Of course. none of these responses to the argu- mcntsagainst jutliciiil activism are meant to be defini- tive rcfutalions. What they are meant to suggest is that the arguments against judicial activism apply with less force whcn the arena is shifted from thefed- era1 to the stalc judiciaries.

Argument 7: Lack of Workable Standards for Review

In spite of the fact that arguments noted above against judicial activism are attenuated at the state level, there remains a final objection, namely, that the contours of the various state constitutional clauses in question are so undefined as to enable, and perhaps require, judges to read a particular economic philosophy into the clauses, one at variance with, but no more legitimate than, the one adopted by the leg- islature.91

A first response to this charge is to note that in state constitutions many of the clauses protecting property rights are as specific as the specific provi- sions in the national Bill of Rights, and others are no less vague than the most important clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment. This argument becomes even more strained in the face of the U.S. Supreme Court's adoption of substantive due process to pro- tect personal rights.

A corollary to this argument is that when state judges apply the more general or vague phrases of their constitutions to protect economic rights, they have adopted more conservative social and economic theories, thus placing a stranglehold on attempts by the people to deal with their social and economic problems.92 However, there is evidence that when

Argument 6: state courts resorted to substantive due process dur- Anti-Democratic Character of Judicial Review ing the Progressive era (1890-1910) to strike down

economic reform legislation, no consistent phiIoso- One of the most serious objections to judicial ac- phy or theory governed the cases decided during that

tivism is that it conflicts with the basic assumptions of pe,50d.93 ~ ~ l ~ i ~ Urofsky's study of state courts and a self-governing polity. This argument applies even p,otective legislation during this era concluded that more strongly when courts are dealing with Protect- "with few exceptions, state courts moved consistently ing economic rights rather than rights that involve the towards approval of a wide range of reform legisla- political process itself. Judicial activism involves tion. . . . Progressives, although occasionally delayed judges deeply and directly in the political Process, in court, were not blocked there."g4 State courts bal- and preempts larger and larger areas of policy from anced legal doctrines of contract and police power decision by the people or their elected representa- and, in most instances, deferred to legislative judg- tives.87 Federal judges are not elected, and they serve ment in policy matters.95 A study of more recent deci- for life. This argument must be recast whcn applicd sions in thc same area concluded: "On balance, most

90 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

of the economic legislation which state courts have invalidated during the past 25 years is arbitrary. . . ."Q6

Judges should not be allowed to substitute per- sonal prejudice or their own economic philosophies for that of the legislatures: the public ought to have the right to adopt economic and social policies through their elected representatives. Ncvcrthclcss, the legislature is not the people, and the policies adopted by legislators cannot be automatically equated with the will of the people. In thc American tradition, the existence of a constitution means that courts are expected to protect the people from their legislatures when those legislatures act in arbitrary ways. Some balance must be struck between the com- petingvalues involved. With the U.S. Supreme Court unable or unwilling to play any role, state courts need to develop workable standards of review that will en- able them to hold the competing interests in a crea- tive balance. There are a number of approaches or criteria that could provide the guidance to enable state supreme courts to steer a course between the Scylla of judicial abdication and the Charybdis of judi- cial arrogance.97

Conclusion

Although the problems and policy responses will change-from legislative attempts to hold railroads strictly liable in tort actions involving injury to live- stock to attempts to limit court remedies for victims of medical malpractice-the importance of having a judicial forum in which constitutional challenges can be heard is readily apparent. The tests to be used and the extent of judicial activity are legitimate matters for dispute; what is not disputable is the need for some judicial forum in which constitutional chal- lenges can be heard. The U.S. Supreme Court's deci- sion to deny hearings on these questions provides both opportunity and obligation for state courts to play an important role in protecting economic rights and, in doing so, to make a signal contribution to American constitutionalism.

NOTES

Note, "Right of Access to Civil Courts under State Con- stitutional Law: An Impediment or Receptacle of Im- portant Substantive and Procedural Rights?" Rutgets Law Journal 13 (Winter 1982): 399.

2Maryland Constitution, 1776, Art. 41 Declaration of Rights; Massachusetts Constitution, 1780, Pt. I, Art. IX; Oklahoma Constitution, 1907, Art. IT, Scc. 6; Arizona Constitution, 1910, Art. 11, Sec. 2.

3Pioneer Telephone and Telcgl-sph Co. v. Slate, 1.38 p. 1033 (OK 1914); Note "Right of Acccss," p. 436.

4For example, Maryland Constitution, 1776. Art. 42 Dcc- laration of Rights; North Carolina Constitution, 1776. Art. I, Sec. 23; Arizona Constitution, Art. 11. Sccs. 9, 19; Oklahoma Constitution, 1907, Art. 11, Sec. 26.

5State v. Harris 6 S.E.2d 854 (1940); Grempler v. Multiple Listing Bureau of Hartford Co., Inc., 226 A.D.2d 1 (1970).

6For exarnplc, Gcorgia Constitution, 1877, Art. IV, 2; Texas Constitution, 1869, Art. I, 18; Wyoming Constitu- tion, 1889, Art. I , 30. Frank R. Strong, Substantive Due Pmcessof Law: A 1)ichotomy of Sense and Nonsense (Dur- ham: North Carolina Academic Press, 1986), pp. 69-70.

7Richard F. Kahlc, Jr., ed., W7zy Hawaii? Constitutional Convention Stutlics, Vol. 2 (Honolulu: Legislative Ref- erence Bureau, 1978): 53.

BSee, for example, Mosher v. City of Boulder, Colorado 225 F. Supp. (1964): 32,35 (protection available for dam- ages under state constitutional "or damage" provision which would not be available under federal law).

QSee, for example, A. E. Dick Howard, "State Courts and Constitutional Rights in the Day of the Burger Court," Virginia Law Review 62 (1976): 873; Bradley McGraw, ed., Developments in State Constitutional Law (St. Paul: West Publishing Co., 1985); and the collection of articles in "New Developments in State Constitutional Law," Publius: The Journal of Federalism 17 (Winter 1987).

'Osee Hans Iinde, "Due Process of Lawmaking," Nebraska Law Review 55 (1976): 197,237. Helen Garfield, "Privacy Abortion and Judicial Review: Haunted by the Ghost of Lochner," Washington Law Review 61 (1986): 293,300-02. James C. Kirby, Jr., relates the resistance he encoun- tered at the National Conference of Chief Justices at Williamsburg, in his 1984 article "Expansive Judicial Re- view of Economic Regulations Under State Constitu- tions," in Developments in State Constitutional Law, pp. 118-119. Herman Schwartz, "Property Rights and the Constitution: Will the Ugly Duckling Become a Swan?" The American UnivetsiQ Law Review 37 (Fall 1987): 9.

"This view, generally accepted by commentators, is in need of correction. Mary Cornelia Porter, "That Com- merce Shall 13e Free: A New Look at the Old Laissez Faire Court," in Philip Kurland, ed. The Suprune Court Review 1976 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977), pp. 135-159, has begun that correction.

l2Lawrence Sager, "Property Rights and the Constitu- tion," in J. Roland Pennock and John Chapman, eds., Property NornosXYII (New York: New York University, 1980): p. 380. Perhaps with not so much finality, the Court has granted review in and sometimes struck down legislation on the grounds of the taking and contract clauses of the Constitution. See note 17.

13U.S. Trust Co. v. New Jersey, 431 US. 1,61(1977). [Em- phasis added] Brennan's own position represents the ex- treme of this deferential attitude. Thus he wrote: "any claim based on due process has no merit." Allied Struc- tural Steel Co. v. Spannaus, 438 U.S. 234,262 (1978).

14Forty state constitutions contain the equivalent of the federal impairment of contract clause; nearly half con- tain taking clauses. These taking clauses go beyond their federal counterpart in that they require compensation not only when property is taken but also when it is "dam- aged." Nearly all contain due process clauses or the equivalent. 1n addition, 37 state constitutions contain right-to-rcmctly clauses. For a convenient compilation of statc bills ol'riglits. sec Ronald Collins, "Bills and Dec- I;iralions ol' Kights 1)igcsts." in The American Bench. 3rd ccl. ((lalifornia: 1t.13. ltoster and Assoc., 1985), 2522-2533.

15For a list of statcs doing so. sce, Note. "Balancing Private Ioss against I'uldic Gain to Test for a Violation of Due Process or a Taking without Just Compensation." Wash-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 91

ington Law Review 54 (1979): 324-327. Not all states have merged their analysis. See Huttig v. City of Richmond Heights, 372 S.W.2d 833 (Mo. 1963); Rockville Fuel and Feed Co. v. Gaithersburg, 291 A.2d 672 (Md. 1972); State v. Vestal, 195 S.E.2d 297 (N.C. 1973); Agins v. City of Tiburon, 598 P.2d 25 (Cal. 1979).

'BNote, "Balancing Private Loss. . .," p. 327ff.

l7The taking clause cases sustained are: Penn Central Transportation Co, et al. v. New York City et al., 438 U.S. 104 (1978); Andrus v. Allard, 444 US. 51 (1979); Hawai- ian Housing Authority v. Midkiff, 476 U.S. 229 (1984); Connolly v. Pension Benefit Guarantee Corp., 106 S.Ct. 1018 (1986); Federal Communications Commission v. Florida Power Corporation, 107 S.Ct 1107 (1986); Bowen v. Gilliard, 107 S.Ct 3008 (1987); U.S. v. Cherokee Nation of Oklahoma, 107 SCt. 1487 (1987); cases struck down: Kaiser Aetna v. US., 444 US. 164 (1979); Webb's Fabulous Pharmacies Inc. v. Beckwith, 449 U.S. 155 (1980); Loretto v. Teleprompter Manhattan CATV Corp., 458 U.S. 419 (1982); Nollan v. California Coastal Commission, 107 S.Ct. 3141 (1987); Hodel v. Ir- ving, 107 S.Ct. 2076 (1987); First English Evangelical Tu- theran Church v. Los Angeles County, 107 S.Ct 2378 (1987). The contract clause cases sustained arc: Exxon Corp. v. Eagerton, 462 U.S. 176 (1983); Encrgy Kcscrvc Group v. Kansas Power and Light Co., 459 US. 400 (1983); Keystone Bituminous Coal Association v. DeBenedictis, 107 S.Ct 1272 (1987); cases struck down: Allied Structural Steel Co. v. Spannaus, 438 U.S. 234 (1978); U.S. Trust Co. v. New Jersey, 438 U.S. l(1977). In some cases, two or three of the relevant clauses are in- volved. Keystone Bituminous Coal upheld legislation against a taking and contract clause challenge. Pennellv. San Jose, 99 L.Ed.2d 75 (1988), upheld a rent control or- dinance against challenges based on the taking, contract, and due process clauses.

18In its initial appearance, substantive due process was as- sociated with protection of property rights against eco- nomic regulation. More recently it has been resurrected to protect certain privacy interests and the right to abor- tion. Edward S. Corwin, "Due Process of Law before the Civil War," as reprinted in A.T. Mason and G. Garvey, eds., American Constitutional History (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1964); Benjamin Twiss, Lawyers and the Constitution: How Laissez Faire Came to the Supreme Court (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1942).

1913 N.Y. 378 (1856).

20Liberty against Government (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1948), pp. 114-115.

21See e.g. Taylor v. Porter, 4 Hill 140 (N.Y. 1843); In Re Dorsey, 7 Porter 293 (1883).

2298 N.Y. 98 (1885). 23Ibid., 106-107. 24 Bernard Siegan, Economic Liberties and the Constitution

(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), pp. 58-59. 25Ibid., pp. 27-40 provides a history of this commitment. 26Laurence Tribe, American Constitutional Law (New

York: Foundation Press, 1978), pp. 421-455 provides a summary overview; c.f. Siegan, pp. 110-155.

27The view that the due process clause has only a proce- dural content is put forth in its boldest form by John Ely, Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980), pp. 14-21, and Hans Linde, "Due Process of Lawmaking."

28Sce, for example, First English Evangelical Lutheran Church of Glendale v. Los Angeles County, 107 S.Ct. 2378 (1987) (property owners must be compensated when use of their land is restricted even temporarily).

2gThe studies used are as follows: Monrad Paulsen, "The Persistence of Substantive Due Process in the States," Minnesota Law Review 34 (1950): 91; Note, "State Views on Economic Due Process: 1937-1953," CoZumbia Law Review 53 (1953): 827; John A. Hoskins and David A. Katz, "Substantive Due Process in the States Revisited," Ohio State Law Jorrn~al18 (1957): 384; Robert Carpenter, "Economic Due Process and the State Courts," North- west University Law Review 53 (1979): 226; Note, "State Economic Substantive Due Process: A Proposed Ap- proach," Yale Law Journal 88 (1979): 1487; Note, "Counter Revolution in State Constitutional Law," Stanford University Law Review 15 (1963): 309; James C. Kirby, Jr., "Expansive Judicial Review of Economic Regulation under State Constitutions," in Developments in State Constitutional Law, pp. 94-145.

30Generally, these articles exclude cases regarding public utilities rates, the validity of state taxation, and zoning. I have followed this exclusionary policy to keep the added cases consistent with those found in the studies. One ma- jor caveat: most ol' the rcsearch done on state courts and econon~ic rcgul;hons has focused on the 1937-1987 pe- riod with a fcw (lone on the period between 1890-1910. The results prescnted in the charts probably under- represent the activity which took place between 1910 and 1937. However, the disproportionate number of cases af- ter 1937 also represents state court reaction to increasing activity on the part of state legislatures, and the fact that the Supreme Court generally refused to review or strike down social and economic legislation passed by the states after 1937.

31 Bailey v. People, 60 N.E. 98 (Ill. 1901) is typical of a large number of cases. In Bailey, the Illinois Court struck down a statute that limited the number of people a lodg- ing housekeeper may sleep in one room while exempting keepers of inns, hotels, and boarding houses from that limit. The court reasoned on equal protection terms, and the case clearly involves invidious or irrational classifica- tion questions, but the court struck the statute down on substantive due process grounds, 99.

32Philip B. Kurland, Politics, tlte Constitution and the War- ren Court (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), especially chapter 4, "Egalitarianism and the Warren Court," and Alexander Bickel, The Supreme Court and the Idea of Progress (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1970), pp. 103ff. For a similar point in another context, see Peter Weston, "The Empty Idea of Equality," Har- vard Law Review 95 (1982): 538.

33Strong, Substantive Due Process of Law, pp. 14-25,47-67. 34The importance of these clauses has been recognized by

commentators. See David Schuman, "Oregon's Remedy Guarantee," O q o n Law Review 65 (1986): 35; Com- ment, "State Constitutions' Remedy Guarantee Provi- sions Provide More than Mere 'Lip Service' to Render- ing Justice," University of Toledo Law Review 16 (1985): 585; Note, "Medical Malpractice Statute of Repose: An Unconstitutional Denial of Access to Courts," Nebmska Law Review 63 (1984): 150.

35Alvardo v. Industrial Comission of Arizona, 716 P.2d 18 (Ariz. 1986).

36Henderson Clay Products Inc. v. Edgar Wood and Asso- ciates Inc., 451 A.W 174 (N.H. 1982).

37Mominee v. Shcrbarth 503 N.E.2d 717 (Ohio, 1986).

92 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

38For example, Batton-Jackson Oil Co. Tnc. v. Rccvcs, 340 S.E.2d 16 (Ga. 1986); Finocchiaro v. Nebraska 1,iquor Control, 351 N.W.2d 701 (Ncb. 1984): San Antonio Kc- tail Grocers v. Lafferty, 297 S.W.21 813 ('l'cx. 1057); Vaughan v. State Board of Embalmers ctc. 82 S.E.216 18 (Va. 1954).

390f the 33 states adopting gucst statutes, 11 repcalcd them; of the remaining 22,17 were declared unconstitu- tional by state high courts. For a list of state court deci- sions sustaining a variety of enactments aimed at reliev- ing the medical malpractice crisis, see American Bank and Trust Co. v. Community Hospital, 683 P.2d 670,677 (Cal. 1984).

40For an elaborate attempt to distinguish legitimate caps on liability from unconstitutional ones, see former Chief Justice Rose Bird's dissent in American Bank and Trust Co. v. Community Hospital, 683 P.2d 670, 687ff (Cal. 1985).

41 The cases are: Barme v. Wood, 689 P.2d 445 (Cal. 1984); American Bank and Trust Co. v. Community Hospital, 683 P.2d 670 (Cal. 1984); Fein v. Perminente Medical Group, 695 P.2d 665 (Cal. 1985); Roa v. Lodi Medical Group, Inc., 695 P.2d 164 (Cal. 1985).

@Johnson v. St. Vincent Hospital, Inc., 404 N.E.2d 585 (Ind. 1980). The court in rejecting challenges based on due process, equal protection, open court, and trial by jury provisions claimed to be applying a "fair and sub- stantial relationship" test, yet simultaneously claimed that "considerable deference is to be accorded to the leg- islature" and that the burden of proof of unconstitution- ality is on the "attacker" of the law, 591, 600. It is not clear whether the two are compatible, but the case illus- trates the variety of combinations of tests and standards found in state court decisions in this area.

43Example~ of legislation struck down on rational relation- ship test are: Dunbar v. Hoffman, 468 P.2d 742 (Colo. 1970); Kinney v. Kaiser Aluminum and Chemical C o p , 322 N.E.2d 880 (Ohio, 1975); Cotrill v. Cotrill Sodding Service, 744 P.2d 895 (Mont. 1987). The two cases with different standards are Sibley v. Board of Supervisors, 477 S.2d 1094 (La. 1985); and Greenberg v. Kimmelman, 494 A.2d 294 (N.J. 1985). Some states, e.g., New York, did not register any significant activity. Two reasons: states like New York have adopted a more deferential standard of review when social and economic regula- tions are involved; the New York legislature has not been active in limiting liability for special groups such as physicians or with regard to product liability. The case of Colton v. Riccobono, 496 N.E.2d 670 (N.Y. 1986) is illus- trative. The Court of Appeals upheld a requirement that a medical malpractice panel hear, evaluate, and recom- mend on the question of liability. In the teeth of aright- to-remedy provision (Art. I, Sec. 16), the court sustained the statute because the legislation bore a rational rela- tionship to the need to provide quality health care, and the plaintiff did have other remeclics.

44 699 S. W.2d 194 (Tex. 1985) 45Silver v. Silver, 280 U.S. 117 (1929); Carlcr v. Har-

tenstein, 401 US. 901 (1970) (cert. dcnied). 46502 P.2d 1197 (Wash. 1972). A Ncw York Appcllatc

Court had no difficulty sustaining similar Icgislation. United Medical Services, Inc. v. Holz, 4 App. Div. 2d 1017 (N.Y. 1957). In some cases, as in Shibuya v. Archi- tects Hawaii Ltd., 647 P.2d 276 (Ha. 1982), state courts have used a rational relationship test but required under

that test "a fair and substantial relationship to theobject of the legisl:rtion" (288). ' k n s o n v. North Ilakota Workmen's Compensation Bu- rcau, 283 N.W.2cl (N.1). 1979); Carson v. Maurer, 424 A.W 825 (N. I I. 1980); Tabler v. Wallace, 704 S.W.2d 179 (Ky. 1986). The 1J.S. Suprcme Court has developed three levels of scrutiny when applying the equal protection clause. Strict scruliny has been applied to certain suspect categories, such as race and national origin. Minimum scrutiny requires that the legislation further a legitimate state interest and that there be a rational relationship be- tween the classification and its purpose. Means or mod- erate scrutiny involves "almost suspect" categories such as sex. The level of scrutinv here is not as rieorous as the first tier but more deman&ng than the thi;d tier. For a clear elaboration of these terms in more depth see Andrea Bonnicksen, Civil Rights and Civil Liberties (Palo Alto: Mayfield Publishing Co., 1982), pp. 150-165.

48704 S.W.2d 179, 186-187. 49Peter Weston, in "The Empty Idea of Equality. . .," ar-

gues in a more theoretical vein that standards of review, whether rational relationship or strict scrutiny, have meaning not by virtue of any equality component but "because the state is obliged to have rational and legiti- mate reasons for every way in which it treats people. Whatever merit rationality review has must ultimately derive not from notions of equality but from notions of substantive due process," p. 577.

50283 N.W.2d 96,99. 5' 451 A.2d 174, 175 (N.H. 1982). 520ther examples of this fusion are: Arneson v. Olson, 270

N.W.2d 125 (N.D. 1978); Jones v. State Board of Medi- cine, 555 P.W 399 (Idaho, 1976); Gutierrez v. Glaser Crandall Co., 202 N.W.2d 786 (Mich. 1972).

53Cases applying strict scrutiny include: Kluger v. White, 281 S.2d 1 (Ha. 1973); Dangaard v. Baltic Cooperative Supply Association, 349 N.W.2d 419 (S.D. 1984); White v. State, 661 P.2d 1272(Mont. 1983); Kenyon v. Hammer, 688 P.2d 961 (Ariz. 1984). Cases not involving strict scru- tiny include: Hansen v. Williams County, 389 N.W.2d 319 (N.D. 1986), wherein the court wrote, "Right to re- cover for personal injuries is an important substantive right. . . triggering an intermediate scrutiny" (325).

54312 A.2d 216 (Md. 1973). 55For example, Application of Martin, 504 P.2d 14 (Nev.

1972). 56Batton-Jackson Oil Co. Inc. v. Reeves, 340 S.E.2d 16,18

(Ga. 1986). 57Strickland v. Ports Petroleum Co. Inc., 353 S.E.2d 17,18

(Ga. 1987). s8351 N.W.2d 701, 704 (Neb. 1984). See also, Maryland

Board of Pharmacyv. Sav-A-Lot, Inc., 311A.U 242(Md. 1973); Treants Enterprises v. Onslow County, 360 S.E.2d 783 (N.C. 1987); People ex. rel. Oreutt v. Instantwhip Denver, Tnc., 490 P.2d 940 (Colo. 1971). Legislation struckclown in Orcult was similar to that sustained by the Suprcmc Court i n U.S. v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144 (1938).

59 193 S.E.W 729 (N.C. 1973). 60678 S.W.21 9 18 ('l'ex. 1984). 61 512 S.2d 9 12 (Ah. 1987). 62These inclutlc S:u v. Votteler, 648 S.W.2d 661 (Tex.

1983); Jackson v. Mannesmann Damage Corp., 435 S.2d 725 (Ala. 1983); Barrio v. San Manuel Division Hospitals Magma Copper, 692 P.2d 280 (Ariz. 1984); Strahler v. St.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 93

Luke's Hospital, 706 S.W.2d 7 (Mo. 1986); Hardy v. Ver- Meulan, 512 N.E.2d 626 (Ohio, 1987).

63Akers v. Baldwin, 736 S.W.2d 294 (Ky. 1987). 64Alvaradi v. Industrial Commission of Arizona, 716 P.2d

18 (Ariz. 1986). A fair number of the cases examined are based on more than two constitutional provisions. In Wright v. Central DuPage Hospital Association, 347 N.E.2d 736 (Ill. 1976), and Health v. Sears Roebuck, Inc., 464 A.2d 288 (N.H. 1983) equal protection, due process, and right-to-remedy clauses were involved. In Georgia Franchise Practices Commission v. Massey Fer- guson, Inc., 262 S.E.2d 106 (Ga. 1979), the statute in question was found to contravene four separate provi- sions of the Georgia Constitution.

65See Sibley v. Board of Supervisors of Louisiana State University, 477 S.2d 1094 (La. 1985); Greenberg v. Kim- melman, 494 A.2d 294 (N.J. 1985).

661t should be noted that in a large majority of the cases under examination, state and federal constitutional pro- visions are cited as the basis for the decision. This means that these cases in all likelihood would not meet the "plain statement" requirement of Michigan v. Long, 473 U.S. 1032 (1983). In that case, the Supreme Court re- quired state courts wishing to base their decisions on state law, thus insulating them from federal review, to make aplain statement to the effect. This failure was due in large part to the lack of any clear-cut standard from the Supreme Court for insulating decisions from review. Although Michigan v. Long provided such a standard, state courts are only gradually developing an awareness of this requirement. The significance of these decisions is not diminished by this failure, as the Supreme Court turns down petitions for review of these cases nearly all of the time.

67Mountain Fuel Supply Co. v. Salt Lake City Corpora- tion, P.2d (Utah, 1988). Slip opinion, p. 9.

68See Note, "State Views on Economic Due Process," p. 827; Kirby reports that 35 states have specifically refused to follow the lead of the Supreme Court. "Judicial Re- view of Economic Regulations," pp. 109, 122.

69Leonard Levy, ed., American Constitutional Law Histori- cal Essays (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1966), pp. 129. Cf. Mary Cornelia Porter, "That Commerce Shall Be Free," pp. 135-159.

70Strong, Substantive Due Process of Law, p. 7. 71 Ibid., p. 14. 72Ibid., p. 72. 73Ibid., p. 91. 74Learned Hand, "Chief Justice Stonc's Conception of thc

Judicial Function," Colurnbia Law Review 46 (1946): 696, 698. William Blackstone considered property rights as among the most important of the civil liberties possesscd by individuals. Commentaries on the Laws o f England I1 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979; orig. pub- lished 1765-1769), p. 2.

75James L. Oakes, " 'Property Rights' in Constitutional Analysis Today," Wmhington Law Review 56 (1981): 583, 622.

76Leonard Levy, "Property as a Human Right," Constitu- tional Commentary 5 (Winter 1988): 169.

771bid., pp. 171, 184. 78For example, Charter Township of Deltav. Dinolfo, 251

N.W.2d 831 (Mich., 1984) (ordinance preventing com- munitarian Christians from living in dwelling because

they were not a family voided); Lopez v. Fitzgerald, 390 N.E.2d 835 (Ill. 1979) (right to privacy prevented disclo- sure of building inspector's reports to tenant groups con- cerned with their dwellings); Mountain States etc. v. De- partment of Public Service Regulations, 634 P.2d 181 (Mont. 1981) (right to privacy protects corporate utility from revealing confidential trade records). Cf. The Su- preme Court's uncomfortableness with the dichotomy between privacy and property rights in Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494 (1977). For discussion of these "hybrid" privacy/autonomy property cases, see Susan Fino, "Remnants of the Past: Economic Due Process in the States," in Stanley Friedelbaum, ed., Hu- man Rights in the States (Westport: Greenwood Press, 19881 145-162.

79Levy, Anierican Coristitutiotial Law, p. 157. soColorado Constitution 11. 3. See also Alabama I, 35;

Alaska I, 1; Arkansas II,22; Idaho I, 1; Illinois I, 1; Iowa I, 1; Louisiana I, 4; Massachusetts I, 1; Missouri I, 2; Mon- tana I, 3; Nebraska I, 1; Nevada I, 1; North Dakota I, 1; New Hampshire Part I, Art. 2; New Jersey I, para. 1; New Mexico II,4; North Carolina I, 1; Ohio I, 1; Oklahoma 11, 2; Pennsylvania I, 1; South Dakota VI, 1; Utah I, 1; Ver- mont Ch. I, Art. 1; Virginia I, 1; West Virginia II1,l; Cali- fornia I, 1. For example, Arizona 11, 17; Mississippi, Art. 111, 17. At least half of the states add to their just compensation clauses for property "taken," the phrase "or damaged," e.g., Nebraska I, 21; Hawaii I, 20; Missouri I, 26; Texas I, 27; Virginia I, 11. Finally, 34 states have right-to-remedy or open court clauses which generally read like the Idaho constitutional provision: "courts of justice shall be open to every person and a speedy remedy afforded for every injury of person, property or character." I, 18.

82Colorado Constitution 11, 3, 6, 7, 9, 11, 13, 14, 15, 27. 83R~ber t McCloskey, "Economic Due Process and the Su-

preme Court: An Exhumation and Reburial," in Levy, American Coristilrttiorial Law, pp. 185-187. A variation on this argument is found in Jesse Choper, Jrrdicial Review and the National Political Process: A Frrrictional Recorisid- eration of the Role of the Slipreme Court (Chicago: Univer- sity of Chicago Press, 1980).

84Levy, American Constitutional Law, p. 157. 85Pennsylvania State Board of Pharmacy v. Pastor, 272

A.2d 487 (Pa. 1971), 300. EeKirby, "Expansive Judicial Review," p. 120. 87For statement of the antidemocratic character of the ju-

diciary, especially in the area of economic rights, see Paulsen, "The I'cnistence of Substantive Due Process," p. 118; Hoskins and Katz, "Substantive Due Process in the Statcs Kcvisitcd," pp. 400-401.

88These three combine to weaken any argument against an activist rolc f o r the court based on the separation of powers.

89There is a majoritarian tradition in the states. It is most readily apparent in their willingness to change their fun- damental law and the majoritarian character of many of the procedures for revising those documents. Between 1970 and 1979, states adopted a total of 976 amendments to their constitutions. Note, "Developments in the Law. . . ," p. 1354. n. 106. Seventeen states even allow amendments by initiative. David Magleby, Direct Legis- lation: Voting on Ballot Propositions in the United States (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press, 1984). p. 36.

901t has been suggcsted that judicial review at the state level might play the role of safeguarding the interests of

94 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

majorities, i.e., majoritarian review, and that state courts are applying such review in the area of economic regula- tion without providing this justification. Note, "Develop- ments in the Law. . .," pp. 1498-1502. This novel sugges- tion only underscores the need to examine and evaluate the tradition of state constitutionalism on its own terms.

glPaulsen, "The Persistence of Due Process," p. 117; Schwartz, "Property Rights and the Constitution," pp. 36-38.

g2 Ibid.

93Lawrence Friedman, "Freedom of Contract and Occu- pational Licensing 1890-1910: A Legal and Social Study," California Law Review 53 (1965): 487,525.

94Melvin Urofsky, "State Courts and Protective Legisla- tive during the Progressive Era: A Reevaluation," Jortr- nal of American Histoy 72 (1985): 63, 64. Mary Porter

suggests a similar pattern at the national level, "That Commerce Shall Be Free," pp. 141-143.

g51bid., p. 91. gWote, "Counter Revolution," p. 330. See also Heather-

ington, "State Economic Regulation," pp. 250-251; and Note, "State Economic Substantive Due Process," p. 1510.

97Among those who have proposed standards that may serve as guidance for the judiciary are: Siegan, Economic Liberties and the Co~istitution, pp. 322-331; Gerald Gun- ther, "The Supreme Court 1971 Term, Foreword: In Search of Evolving Doctrine on a Changing Court: A Model for a Newer Equal Protection," Haward Law Re- view 86 (1972): 1, 20 ff.; Note, "State Substantive Eco- nomic Due Process: A Proposed Approach," pp. 1504-1510; Strong, Srrbstantive Due Pmcess of Law, pp. 79-80, 94, 205-2117, 297-299; Kirby, "Judicial Review of Economic Relations," pp. 118-122.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 95

96 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

State Supreme courts and Workers' Compensation:

Diffusion of New Ideas Change and the As preceding chapters demonstrate, the dcvcl-

opment of an independent state constitutional law, in particular the protection of individual rights and l i b erties, sometimes depends on the willingness of courts to resuscitate guarantees that have lain dor- mant for long periods of time. If courts are to look to- ward fundamental state charters, they must, for the most part, be prodded by counsel. This, of course, de- pends on counsel's awareness that state constitutions contain protections that are not in the federal Consti- tution, and that may serve client interests and/or may help attain desired policy objectives. State guaran- tees for a quality education, clean air and water, pri- vacy, equality of the sexes, and access to courts are il- lustrative. Further, as the preceding chapters indicate, when individual state courts explicate and vitalize state constitutions, they often provide prece- dent, guidance, and encouragement for courts in sis- ter states.

This chapter, focusing on the intentional tort ex- ception to the exclusive remedy requirement of work- ers' compensation statutes, examines the manner in which a particular doctrinal change has been adopted and dispersed, and speculates about the reasons for its initial acceptance. Since the intentional tort ex- ception has been adopted by only a few, but widely varying kinds of state supreme courts, an in-depth look at the characteristics of these courts is possible. The growth of the intentional tort exception demon- strates that judicial creativity and eagerness to re- spond to what is regarded in some quarters as a major social problem depends on a variety of idiosyncratic factors. Thus, as we look toward state courts to de- velop state law, we should ask what impels a court to- ward assuming a leadership role, and what causes other courts to follow, to lag behind, or to be indiffer- ent to change. The development of state constitu- tional law, however widely heralded, is still in its in-

fancy. State courts bear a large responsibility for its continued growth, and an understanding of what makes thcsc instiltitions respond to change is essen- tial for those who would persuade courts to take the fundamental charlers of their states seriously.

Workers' Compensation: Problems and Proposals for Change

Almost two decades ago, Congress, pursuant to the passage of the Occupational Safety and Health Act (OSHA), established a National Commission on State Workmen's Compensation Laws. The commis- sion was mandated to conduct an examination of the workers' compensation systems of the 50 states and make recommendations for change. It was the view of the Congress that serious questions had been raised concerning the fairness and adequacy of workmen's compensation laws. Many of the problems could be traced to the growth of the economy, the changing nature of the labor force, increases in medical knowl- edge, changes in the hazards associated with various types of employment, new technologies creating new risks to health and safety, and increases in the general level of wages and the cost of living.'

In 1972, the commission issued a wide-ranging report consisting of 84 recommendations that cov- ered the appropriate scope of the compensation sys- tem, and the system's medical care, rehabilitation, safety, and effective delivery objectives. In all of these areas, the commission concluded that "state workmen's compensation laws in general are inade- quate and inequitable."Z Although the commission duly noted the efforts made by some states to im- prove compensation systems, it had few illusions about the possibilities for change. Legislatures are not only bewildered by the system's complexities and the array of proposals for change but also are well aware that other issues command more interest and

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 97

demand more attention. Interest groups represent- ing employers, unions, and insurance companies have exercised effective vetoes over many proposals for change. Business and industry have raised the specter of large-scale departures from states that, from employer perspectives, provide "excessive" em- ployee benefits and protections. Taken together, "deficiencies in workmen's compensation in many states result from lack of leadership, undcrstanding, and interest."3 Indeed, following a spatc of activity engendered by the report, proposals for changcs in state compensation systems were rclegatcd to the back burner. In response to the report, no doubt, and to state legislative inertia, a National Workers' Com- pensation Act was introduced in Congress. Although not enacted into law, the possibility of federal action, either as supplementary to or in lieu of state law, can- not be dismissed as a possibility.4

Of particular concern, and an objective of the workers' compensation system, is the protection of workers' health and safety.5 However, as the system developed, it was charged that some employers found it more economical to compensate for employee acci- dents and deaths than to provide safety measures. As Representative Philip Burton noted when OSHA was debated in the U.S. House of Representatives:

With today's low level of workmen's com- pensation, preventive measures for better health and safety are often the employer's most expensive and uneconomic choice. To- day's workmen's compensation laws. . . offer an economic incentive to many corporations to forbear from preventive expenditures be- cause they have concluded that the cost of employee death and injury (potentially higher Workmen's Compensation Health Insurance Premiums, etc. . .) are often less than the costs of accident prevention.6

While federal and state legislation have been de- signed to protect worker health and safety, thus over- coming this particular shortcoming of the state work- er's compensation systems, enforcement, due to personnel shortages, has been inadequate.7 An alter- native means of reaching the goal has been thein- stitution of suits by injured employees against em- ployers who fail to maintain a safe workplace.

Workers' Compensation and the Courts: An Overview

The nation's first workers' compensation statute, enacted in 1910 by the New York legislature, was al- most immediately invalidated on constitutional grounds by the state's highest court.8 The judicial re- sponse was not surprising. With the onset of the In- dustrial Revolution, American courts, promulgating the "unholy trinity" of employer dcfcnscs-assump-

tion of risk, contributory negligence, and the fellow servant rule-either denied recovery to the vast ma- jority of injured workers who brought suits, or ap- proved awards so small as to be virtually worthless.9

While the judiciary, it has been asserted, was mo- tivated by a desire to keep down employer costs, thereby fostering industrial development, some courts provided legislatures with an impetus for re- form. Employer defenses, Wisconsin's chief justice noted, wcrc "archaic and unfitted to modern indus- trial conditions," a sentiment that reflected growing national consensus. Furthermore, once employers understood that a scheduled compensation system would not only reduce the financial uncertainties sur- rounding the common law system but also mitigate labor unrest, resistance to reform ceased.10

Workers' compensation statutes vary from state to state, but all share similar objectives and charac- teristics. The expenses arising from industrial acci- dents are borne by insured employers who calculate them into production costs that are then passed on to the consumer. ("The cost of the product should bear the blood of the workman."ll) The question of the employer's negligence or lack thereof is irrelevant. Equally irrelevant is the employee's responsibility for his or her injury. Automatic entitlement to and the assumption of liability for the payment of benefits carry with them the forfeiture of rights-the employ- ees' to sue at common law and the employer's to as- sert common law defenses. It is on this compromise, this quid pro quo, that the workers' compensation system is based.

Workers' compensation laws and their admini- stration, while preferable to common law recovery practices, are often regarded by employees as some- what less than satisfactory. Complaints typically fo- cus on low compensation rates, underestimates of de- grees of impairment, delayed payments, and failure to recompense at all. In addition, and most signifi- cant, the lowering or removal of many of the tradi- tional barriers to recovery for a wide variety of inju- ries have highlighted the great difference between jury determined awards and workers' compensa- tion benefits. For example, about one-half of all product liability suits are based on work-related inju- ries. As a result, workers are now turning to the com- mon law to circumvent the limitations of statutorvl administrative compensation systems.12

Among the judicial responses to employee com- pensation problems have been rulings carving out ex- ceptions to the exclusivity rule that allowed workers to recover more from their employers than the statutorily prescribed benefits. Commonly employed exceptions have been the dual capacity and dual in- jury doctrines, considered by some commentators as adjuncts to or surrogates for the intentional tort ex- ception. Thus. injurcd employees have been allowed

98 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

to sue an employer if the employer acts in some ca- pacity that is additional to the employer-employee relationship, and may recover for a second injury that is independent of the original, work-related injury. While the exceptions are understood, thcy have ly no means been accepted in all jurisdictions.13

In creating exceptions to the exclusivity require- ments, courts have engaged in statutory intcrpreta- tion, and have exercised their common law function. To date, exclusivity requirements that have immu- nized employers from suit have not been challenged on state constitutional grounds. However, in one state, Alabama, other immunity provisions of work- ers' compensation statutes were invalidated on the basis of a state constitutional guarantee. This sug- gests a potential use for state constitutions, and, spe- cifically, the Alabama high court has thereby sug- gested another approach for plaintiffs' lawyers seeking favorable judgments for their clients in work- ers' compensation disputes.

The Exclusivity Requirement and State Constitutional Law

Constitutional challenges to the exclusivity re- quirement are rare and are even more rarely sus- tained.14 The basis for these suits has been the right of access to courts provisions contained in most state constitutions, but not in the federal Constitution. Section 13 of the first article of the Alabama Consti- tution is typical, providing in part, that "Every per- son, for any injury done him in his lands, goods, per- son, or reputation shall have a remedy by due process of law." For many years in Alabama and elsewhere, these right-to-remedy clauses were invoked, but without much success. However, in the past 20 years, as their potential has been recognized, suc- cessful challenges to long-standing and arguably out- moded statutes have been mounted, and methodolo- gies for principled constitutional interpretation have been advocated.15 The Alabama high court is among those that have devoted considerable time and en- ergy to reconciling the provisions of the constitution's open court provision with the legislature's un- doubted right, in keeping with valid public policy ob- jectives, to immunize certain groups andlor individu- als from suit.16

When the Alabama legislature amended the state workers' compensation law to immunizeco- employees from suit, the plaintiff's bar determined that the time was ripe to make some practical use of Section 13. In Grantham v. Denke (1978). thc court agreed with the plaintiff's argument that while the employer's immunity was an exchange for his as- sumption of liability, there was no such voluntary ac- commodation among co-employees. Put differently, deprivation of a common law right to sue for injury without the provision of an alternative recourse vio-

lated the state constitutional guarantee of right to re- dress. As an Alabama Justice explained:

The amended language [of the statute] de- nies a job-rclalcd injured employee the right to sue his negligent co-employee and for this he gains thc right to negligently inflict an on- the-job injury to his fellow employee without risk of suit.17

Two years later, in Fireman's Fund American In- surance Co., the court extended Grantham to invali- date the legislative grant of immunity to supervisory employees, corporate officers, and workers' compen- sation carriers. Here, severe and extensive burns sus- tained by the workers were due to the failure of the employer to provide for proper safety measures, to warn of dangerous working conditions, and to inspect the premises. As summarized by the court:

The workmen testify that they were fur- nished with materials that they were to use by their superiors and they had to work with those materials and in that dangerous envi- ronment or quit work. If they refused to ap- ply the scuff bands and screws in the demon- strated fashion, they could have been fired for insubordination. There was dispute whether or not the federally required sign indicating that employees could refuse to work with anything they felt would endanger them was posted before the fire.18

The employee injuries were, of course, compen- sable. However, the majority of the court argued that this did not absolve the tortfeasors who failed to carry out their prescribed andlor voluntarily assumed re- sponsibilities.

Only where the employer, except for em- ployer immunity, owes a duty of due care, the breach of which causes injury, and this duty is delegated by the employer to the co- employee defendant, or voluntarily assumed by him and the defendant breaches this duty through personal fault, can liability be im- posed. . . . As in any negligence claim, the breach consists in the defendant's duty to discharge the delegated or assumed obliga- tion with the degree of care required of a person of ordinary prudence under the same or similar circumstances.~~

A concurring justice, troubled by the implica- tions of the case as it pertained to precedent, consti- tutional explication, and legislativeljudicial relations, summarized her vicw of the ultimate role of Section 13 in our system of government.

It docs not nicrcly prohibit the legislature from abolishing already accrued rights of ac- tion, nor does it immutably enshrine the

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 99

common law beyond the reach of legislative attempts to adapt it to our evolving society and economy. It does prohibit governmental action which is arbitrary and capricious, while allowing the legislature much latitude in drafting laws. But most importantly, it sets up a dual system of review which acts as a cautionary brake when change in the com- mon law is contemplated. In effect, Section 13 says that the rights enjoyed by individuals at the common law are of such fundamental importance in our legal systems, that they must be changed, if at all, only after careful consideration by both legislatures and courts.20

In the broadest terms, Fireman's Fund establishes the principles that a state constitution may be of- fended by a workers' compensation system that bars suits for the sort of negligence that, under the com- mon law, constitutes tortious behavior. Further, the case suggests that open court provisions of state con- stitutions, and by implication due process guarantees, may provide grounds for suits against employers who knowingly harm employees, the quid pro quo of the compensation system notwithstanding. Finally, al- though the issue was not before the court, Alabama's compensation benefits are "meager not only when compared to civil verdicts, but even when compared to Workmen's Compensation Laws." Thus the court, albeit indirectly, addressed what is regarded as one of the major problems of the compensation system, and aided, as have other courts, employee attempts "to circumvent the statutory scheme and bring their claims in tort.'Q1

The Alabama high court's rulings in Grantham and Fireman's Fund were criticized on the grounds that they constituted piecemeal tinkering with a com- prehensive legislative scheme, that they created more problems than they purported to solve, that they violated precedent and precepts of judicial def- erence to the legislative branches in matters of estab- lishing public policy, and that the majority had en- gaged in unwarranted judicial activism. Similar charges have been directed to state and lcdcral courts for many years in a variety of contexts. How- ever, it has been only recently that the Alabama Su- preme Court has been visible enough to draw fire. Fifteen years earlier, the court would not have been so bold. The court's reputation was one of conserva- tism in the common law, of extreme deference to the political branches of government, and with a docket badly in arrears.

Beginning in the 1970s, however, the court un- derwent a dramatic transformation. A hard fought battle for judicial reform culminated in the institu- tion of a modem, and model, state court system,

streamlined rulcs of procedure, and the election of (currently U.S. Senator) Howell Heflin, who led the reform movement, to the chief justiceship. Within only a few years, the court's personnel all but totally changed, the docket became current, and a "new" court consciously assumed an unprecedented role within the state.

The Alabama experience indicates that a variety of factors may explain a court's assumption of an ac- tivist stance regarding the state constitution. Simi- larly, a variety of factors may explain, in a general sense, state high court assertiveness in making public policy and, specifically, state court intervention in workers' compensation systems.

State Supreme Court Policymaking State supreme courts historically have played a

significant policymaking role within their respective states. To the extent that their rulings provide prece- dent for other state courts as well as federal courts, decisions of individual courts have national import. In some respects, state high court policymaking has been in response to major and often controversial problems that the other branches of state govern- ment have failed to address, such as inequitable methods of financing public schools, restrictive zon- ing, and the rights of patients to make decisions about the continuation of life-support systems. In most re- spects, however, judicial policymaking has been di- rected toward more routine though equally salient matters, such as the application of automobile guest statutes, fair trade laws, tenantllandlord relations, and criminal and family law.

It is in developing the common law, however, that state supreme courts make particularly impor- tant contributions to state and national public policy. Abrogation of the doctrines of sovereign, charitable and spousal immunity, and the development of such doctrines as product liability and comparative negli- gence that provide greater consumer protection, are indicative of judicial willingness to abandon out- moded precedent and to anticipate legislative initia- tives.

Common law doctrines initiated in one state will almost ccrtainly, in time, be adopted by courts in other states. The pace of adoption, however, has been uneven. Ikpending on particular historical eras, some courts lead, some follow willingly, and others follow with some hesitancy or reluctance. Other state courts will, for periods of time, either ig- nore or reject changes taking place elsewhere. Some courts may welcome change in particular areas of tort law, but not in others. Some restraintist courts may become activist and vice versa. However, while some courts either resist change or have had few occasions to address the new legal developments, no state has been immune from the "tort law revolution" that

100 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

commenced after the Second World War and contin- ues unabated to this day.22

Exactly what factors motivate individual courts to adopt plaintiff-oriented claims, to follow decisional trends established in other jurisdictions, or to hold, in the classically restraintist manner, that change should emanate from legislatures rather than courts, is not clear. However, recent scholarship provides some clues as to why state high courts may look to the rulings of other courts in reaching a decision.

Peter Harris, for example, concluded that state high courts typically look beyond their borders when confronting novel legal problems or when contem- plating legal change. However, in attempting to ac- count for the directions in which a state supreme court looks, and why, Harris could discover no major patterns of intercourt citation.Z3

Providing a complementary perspective, Greg- ory Caldeira's research reveals that the most fre- quently cited courts shared various characteristics, such as reputations for professionalism, the size of their caseloads, and the societal diversity of their states. As pertains to the adoption of tort law innova- tions initiated elsewhere, Caldeira's observation that judges "cited most often in most jurisdictions have a decidedly liberal cast" is useful. Nor is this surprising, because the more liberal courts "demonstrated a will- ingness to move away from the status quo. Announc- ing a change in precedent naturally causes more com- ment and controversy than does a confirmation of past practice^."^^

Caldeira and other political scientists, Lawrence Baum and Bradley Canon, have, in separate studies, identified courts that enjoy the most prestigious reputations and have categorized courts according to the parts they played in initialing and adopling changes in the law of torts, and havc sough1 to dis- cover overall national patterns for the adoption of plaintiff-oriented innovations.25 The third study re- vealed that the adoption of tort law innovations fol- lowed no consistent patterns. Although some courts were generally more innovative than others, no single court or set of courts either claimed national leader- ship in all tort law reforms or invariably lagged be- hind. Canon and Baum concluded that because of the reactive position of the judiciary (as contrasted with the initiatory role of legislatures and administrative agencies), the pattern of change, reflecting litigant demands, has been purely "idiosyncratic," "embrac- ing," as Caldeira added, "an appreciable amount of

perhaps to lead the charge, but unwilling to bring up the rear.

Taken together, the studies paint a picture of the many-faceted and shifting leadership roles of state supreme courts. Other studies and surveys, such as those directed to the development of "the new judi- cial federalism," are similarly ins t r~c t ive .~~ Only a handful of judiciaries, designated as "lighthouse" high courts, have rather consistently relied on state constitutions in order to extend greater protections to civil rights and liberties than those guaranteed by the post-Warren Court's interpretation of the fed- eral Constitution. Others have been activist in some areas, but not in others. Most continue to defer to fedcral preccdcnt on most questions.

In sum, whilc state supreme courts that have ex- ercised influence and/or have been deemed prestig- ious have bcen identified, leadership by particular state high courts is not a constant. It changes accord- ing to a variety of factors. Activism in one area, such as the law of torts, does not necessarily translate into activism in another area, such as the development of state civil liberties. Indeed, variations exist within particular areas. The New Jersey high court's con- cern for privacy rights and its interest in effecting in- stitutional change, for example, is not matched by a concomitant concern for defendants' rights. The Wis- consin Supreme Court, while willing to reverse its own past tort dccisions, has been unwilling to accept several innovative doctrines initiated elsewhere. Fi- nally, activism and/or the assumption of a leadership role in one or more areas of the law does not appar- ently enhance a court's reputation among courts in other states or coincide with assumptions about the roles and function of different state courts. As Canon and Baum notcd in relation to their ranking of inno- vative tort law courts:

It is not surprising that states such as Minne- sota and ('alifornia rank high, because they have reputations for progressivism and in- novativcncss. . . . But the rankings of many states do not comport very well with conven- tional wisdom about innovativeness-either in general or as it relates to judicial doc- trines. It is almost shocking to see Texas, Kentucky and Louisiana among the top ten and Massachusetts near the bottom.28

The Intentional Tort Doctrine: The Case Law

serendipity."26 Interestingly, the two Canon and The intentional tort exception is based on the Baum studies indicate that a state high court'soverall premise that the workers' compensation laws do not propensity to tort law activism does not perfectly cor- give employers the right to abuse workers intention- respond with its general propensity to innovative- ally, and if they do, they may not avoid full tort dam- ness. Thus, while a state court may be generally activ- ages. The problcm, of course, is the meaning of "in- ist, it may not always be adventuresome-hesitant tent," and the extent to which intent may be

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 101

separated from negligence that, however heinous, does not provide a cause of action.29 Almost unani- mously, the case law has held that workers' compen- sation statutes preclude common law suits when inju- ries are caused by the employer's willful, gross, wanton, deliberate, or reckless misconduct, when the alleged misconduct includes knowingly permitting a hazardous work condition to exist, knowingly order- ing the plaintiff to perform an extremely dangerous job, willfully failing to provide a safe workplace, and willfully and unlawfully violating safety laws.30 As Ar- thur Larson states in his treatise on workers' compen- sation:

The most remarkable feature of the doctrine that "intent means intent" is the way it has survived virtually intact in spite of the most determined onslaughts in dozens of jurisdic- tions. In the rare instances of its breakdown, the doctrine has usually been restored either legislatively or judicially.3'

The first "rare instance" of the breakdown of the "intent means intent" dogma occurred in 1978 when the West Virginia Supreme Court of Appeals held in Mandolidis v. Elkin Industries that the employer's "willful, wanton and reckless misconduct" constitutes an intentional tort for which the common law affords a remedy. Three cases were consolidated in Man- dolidis. In the first, the employee suffered severe hand injuries while using a power table saw that lacked a safety guard. The failure to provide the safety device was in violation of state and federal law, the employer had been forbidden to use the machin- ery in question until federal standards had been com- plied with, and, despite earlier accidents, the em- ployer did not provide the requisitc guards, and cven threatened todismiss employccs who refused to work at the unsafe machines. The othcr two actions wcre brought by representatives of decedent cmployecs. The complaints also raised the matter of the employ- er's noncompliance with safety laws.

The West Virginia compensation law provides that employers are liable if injury arises from their "deliberate intent." The case law, however, drew a line between deliberate intent and gross negligence, holding that employers were immune from suit ab- sent proof of "specific intent" to injure an employee. Absent that proof, the injury would be attributed to negligence, and the employer would retain statutory immunity. Through the years, a number of bills were proposed in the state legislature that would have pro- vided for a more lenient standard, such as a showing of willful, wanton, and reckless employer miscon- duct. All failed of passage. The high court's adoption of precisely this standard in Mandolidis thus might be viewed as an end-play around the legislature-a posi- tion taken by that body when, after similar successful

suits resulted in substantial awards, it directly nulli- fied the court's unprecedented construction of the statute's deliberate intent exception.32

Two years later, in Johns-Manville Products Corp. v. Contra Costa Superior Court, the California Su- preme Court hcld that an employee could bring suit against an employer who had fraudulently concealed from the plaintiff and his doctors that the plaintiff's illness was related to asbestos exposure. It was charged that as a result of the defendant's miscon- duct, the appropriate treatment was not admini- stered to the employee, who continued to work under conditions detrimental to his health. The ruling. while "heraldcd as providing important rights for t c i injured worker," was narrow in scope. The court held that since thc initial injuries arising from the conceal- ment of workplace hazards were foreseeable, the em- ployer could bc sucd only for an aggravation of injury by deceit, which was not foreseeable. In other words, the ruling did not create an exception to the exclusive remedy requirement that would, in effect, penalize employers for exposing employees to toxic sub- stances that employees would not be aware existed in the work environment. Subsequently, the California legislature amended the compensation act to encom- pass the Johns-Manville holding.33

Following Johns-Manvile, the question of the employer's liability for failing to provide a safe workplace was addressed directly in a pathbreaking ruling of the Ohio Supreme Court. Blankenship v. Cincinnati Milacron Chemicals (1982) involved a suit brought by employees who alleged that they had been exposed, during the course of employment, to various chemicals that made them "sick, poisoned, and chemically intoxicated, causing them pain, discom- fort and cmotionnl distress which [would] continue for the indefinite future. . . causing suffering and per- manent disability." It was further alleged that the chemical company knew of and did nothing to rectify the conditions, failed to warn its employees of the ex- posure to hazardous substances, and failed to report, as requircd by law, the hazardous working conditions to the appropriate public agencies. Such actions and omissions, according to the complaint, were "inten- tional, malicious, and in willful and wanton disregard of [the employer's] duty to protect the health of its employees."34 It was argued that employer knowl- edge of the hazard and awareness that employees were contracting an occupational disease constituted an intentional tort and not an injury incurred within the meaning of the exclusivity provision of the com- pensation law. The court agreed.

Two questions, immediately raised by comrnen- tators, werc left open in Blankenshiy; both were sub- sequently addrcsscd in Jones v. W P Development Co. (1984). The first, answered in the affirmative, was whether an action for an intentional tort could be

102 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

maintained even after receiving compensation bene- fits. The second concerned the meaning of inten- tional tort. The Blankenship plaintiffs did not claim that Milacron had intended to harm them, but had de- liberately failed to provide a safe workplace, and had intentionally failed to notify appropriate agencies of the workplace hazards. While the Blankenship court referred to the Mandolidis "willful, wanton, and reck- less misconduct" standard, it was unclear if it had been adopted. Jones held that "an intentional tort is committed with an intent to injure another, or com- mitted with the belief that such an injury is substantially certain to O C C U ~ . " ~ ~ Thus, running entirely contrary to case law (Mandolidis excepting), Blankenship and Junes established the novel principle that if an em- ployer had reason to believe that injury would result from an unsafe workplace, had failed to warn em- ployees of the dangers to which they were exposed, and had failed to observe safety laws and report dan- gerous conditions, the employer would be liable at common law.

Blankenship and Jones (in combination with a se- ries of Ohio Supreme Court rulings that expanded the rights of workers) caused a furor. Amid claims that the court was discouraging new industries from entering the state and driving established industries out,36 the state legislature revised the compensation act.

The most significant questions addressed for purposes here concern the relationship between compensation benefits and common law awards and the intentional tort exception. On the former, the law provides that if injury, occupational disease, or death occurs through the intentionally tortious acts of an employer, then an employee may collcct workcrs' compensation benefits and bring a causc ol' action against the employer for an excess of damages over the amount received or receivable under law. Inten- tional tort is defined as "an act committed to injure another or committed with the belief that the injury is certain to occur." Substantial certainty is defined as an act done with "deliberate intent to cause an em- ployee to suffer injury, disease or condition of death." As one commentator noted, "the legislature," while "adopting the framework of the intentional tort as es- tablished by the Jones court," produced a definition that "stands in marked contrast." For "substantial certainty is a concept which is distinct from actual in- tent to injure. Thus, the legislature has seemingly made an apple-orange definition of intentional tort by defining substantially certain as deliberate intent."

negative implication. That is to say, courts using this standard define it in terms of what it is not. Thus, it is not sufficient to show that there was mere carelessness, recklessness or negligence, however gross it may be, because deliberate intcnt implies that the employer must have been determined to injure the employee. Stated positively, a deliberate in- tent to injure was defined as "an intentional or deliberate act by the employer to bring about the consequences of the act." [This] deliberate intent standard of an intentional tort is more than merely strict in theory. It is fatal in fact. In the absence of a "left jab to the chin," this standard will preclude an in- jured workcr from recovering for the inten- tional removal of a safety device or for the intentional exposure of an employee to a dangerous condition. This would appear to be especially true in cases of insidious dis- eases which remain latent for a period of many years before any manifestation ap- pears.37 A Michigan Supreme Court ruling provides the

most recent example of a successful judicial "assault" on the exclusivity "citadel."38 In Beauchamp v. Dow Chemical Co. (1986) the plaintiff, a research chemist, sued to recover for disabilities sustained as a result of his exposure to "agent orange" in the workplace. Wrestling with the definition of "intent," and drawing on Blankenship, the court held that an intentional tort had been committed when the employer knew with "substantial ccrtainty" that working conditions were harmful. ("If thc injury is substantially certain to oc- cur as a conscqucnce of actions the employer in- tcndcd, thc crnploycr is deemed to have intended the injuries as wcll.") O n the matter of legislative intent, the court had no compunctions about "theorization."

Including intentional torts within the ex- clusivity provision would mean that the legis- lature intended to limit substantially an em- ployee's recovery for intentional injury inflicted by an employer. It would mean that the legislature not only intended to limit the employer's liability but also intended to al- low an intentional tortfeasor to shift his li- ability to a fund paid for with premiums col- lected by innocent employers. Intentional misconduct would seem to be the type of be- havior the legislature would want most to de- ter and punish. Including intentional torts

The almost inevitable outcome will be that within the exclusivity provision would, in in order for an employee to sue his employer that sensc, be counterproductive because for an intentional tort, the employee must the lcgislaturc intended to limit and diffuse show that the injury was the product of the liability for intentional torts. Accidents are employer's deliberate intent. The term, "de- an inevitable part of industrial production, liberate intent," has largely been defined by intentional torts are not.39

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 103

The legislative response to Beauchamp struck what has been regarded as a middle ground. The law- makers thus resembled their California rather than their West Virginia and Ohio counterparts on this is- sue. While the statute in question requires specific intent to injure, thus modifying the exclusivity re- quirement, Beauchamp was softened (from the em- ployer's perspective), by defining intent as "actual knowledge than an injury was certain to occur and willfully disregarding that knowledge."40

An Assessment

At first blush, the significance of the intentional tort cases discussed here may appear negligible, es- pecially since in two of the four states concerned, the legislatures enacted limitations that not only over- rode judicial holdings but also bolstered the exclusive remedy of the workers' compensation laws.

What must be kept in mind, however, is that these cases are representative of a movement to "re- form" the workers' compensation system, not through legislatures but through courts. Legislative responses to the problems of the workers' compensa- tion system, it is rightly or wrongly alleged, have been influenced more by business and less by employee in- terests. Courts, prodded by the plaintiff's bar, have, in the classical manner, stepped into the breach. The intentional tortlphysical injuryldeath cases, address- ing questions of a duty to warn of novel and insidious dangers in the workplace (e.g., the long-term effects of exposure to toxic substances) and the efficacy of state and federal safety laws, provide the most visible and dramatic examples of judicial efforts to "rewrite" workers' compensation laws.41 The Chief Justice of the West Virginia Supreme Court of Appeals (who dissented in Mandolidis) put it this way:

There are certain classes of cases on the frontiers of the law. . . that are political dis- putes between interest groups. For example, workers who are injured on thc job arc con- stantly going to court in c h r t s to gcl lhc courts to erode the statutory immunity lrom an ordinary lawsuit that an employer who subscribes to a state workmen's compcnsa- tion fund enjoys. In many industrial states, courts are nibbling away at immunity in seri- ous accident cases where the employer has failed to follow prescribed safety standards or has ordered workers to do things that are abnormally dangerous. The workers knew that under prior court interpretation of the immunity statutes, they could not recover. They went to court to get new interpreta- tions of these old statutes. . . . [Such] efforts to change existing laws can be characterized as "disputes," but they are political disputes

rather than the factual disputes courts are theoretically in business to resolve.42

Mandolidis, Blankenship, and Beauchamp are such "frontier" cases, similar perhaps to early prod- ucts liability cases.43

The California, West Virginia, Ohio, and Michigan Courts

The high courts of California, West Virginia, Ohio, and Michigan differ in a number of respects. The California court ranks consistently high in inno- vation and activism. The West Virginia court has gen- erally ranked near the bottom in these regards. The Ohio court ranks relatively high on tort law activism and between the top and middle on innovativeness. The Michigan court is ordinarily rated very high on tort law activism (surpassing California), fairly high on innovativcness, and, with California, is among the state courts best known for developing a state consti- tutional civil liberties law. Thus, two of the courts showing aggressiveness with regard to the intentional tort exception are among the nation's most active generally. The California high court took a cautious approach to the subject. The Michigan Supreme Court, which generally enjoys leadership status, took its bearings from courts that do not have a similar reputation. Thus, in at least this area of the law, there is an uncertain correlation between how a court is characterized and what a court actually does. Further comparison of the four courts is illuminating.

Members of the California high court are se- lected by a variant of the merit selection system. Jus- tices are nominated by the governor, must be ap- proved by at least two members of a judicial nominating commission, and face voters in two reten- tion elections. If successful after the second election, justices serve a 1%-year term and are eligible for any number of terms thereafter. While there is disagree- ment about which judicial selection method produces thc most qualified justiccs, there is no gainsaying that thc Calilbrnia Supr-cmc Court has produced more than its sharc of both luminaries and outspoken pol- icy advocates. 'l'hc court has long been regarded as a leader, not only among state courts, but vis-a-vis fed- eral courts as well. Since the dual capacity exception to the exclusivity requirement was initiated in and has been nurtured in California, Johns-Manville should not be considered surprising; what may be surprising is the court's reluctance to permit a common law ac- tion for the initial injury, as contrasted to the aggrava- tion of the injury. On the other hand, the court might well have bclicved that the California legislature would take the concerns raised in the compensation cases seriously. Thc Johns-Manville doctrine. as noted earlier, was incorporated by statute. Although the legislature eliminated the dual capacity doctrine, it

104 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

did permit worker suits under circumstances that had previously invoked the dual capacity doctrine.44

West Virginia justices are selected in moderately competitive judicial elections, and are, for the most part, Democrats. Interim appointees of Republican governors are almost invariably defeated when they must run for election. Furthermore, "West Virginia voters have split their tickets when necessary to ex- press short-term policy preferences at the gubernato- rial level while relying on their more permanent alle- giances at the judicial 1evels2'45

Beginning in 1976, following the election of three new justices to the five-member court, the court commenced to take an activist stand more gen- erally and in workers' compensation cases specifi- cally, showing "little reluctance to substitute the ma- jority's assessment of the evidence for the factual findings of the workmen's compensation appeal board." More precisely, between January 1977 and September 1978, the court held in favor of the em- ployee in 49 out of 50 cases. In most, if not all of these cases, the court "redefined well-settled statutory in- terpretations," and "entered areas not ordinarily con- sidered within the scope of appellate review." A court, long Democratic, began to respond to new claims, and to assume a sympathetic posture toward working people.40 Indeed, as the dissenting Justice Richard Neely pointedly commented, "the court was ready, willing and eager to effectuate change."

A fair reading of the majority opinion im- plies to me that this court has been waiting for years to remove the yoke of oppres- sionfrom the workers of this state by pro- viding a vehicle for recovery of common law jury awards for negligently inflicted, work- related injuries in addition to the admittedly parsimonious awards of workmen's compen- sation.47

Ohio justices are selected in nonpartisan clcc- tions that are preceded by partisan primaries, a sys- tem unique to the state. From the end ol' the Second World War to the late 1970s, the appellate judiciary, despite the state's strong two-party tradition, was overwhelmingly Republican. State supreme court decisions tended to reflect the values of small town and rural interests.

Traditional electoral and jurisprudential pat- terns were abruptly shattered in the late 1970s and the early 1980s when the Democrats obtained first a 4-3 and subsequently a 6-1 majority on the court. The partisan shift was due to concerted efforts of the la- bor unions to "win" the court, believing that labor's goals would be more quickly and surely obtained through judicial rulings than through the slow and often unpredictable legislative process. Under the leadership of its controversial chief justice, Frank

Celebrezze, the court, as its chief proclaimed, be- came a "people's court," concerned with the "little guy or gal." The Ohio court reversed a long line of precedents pertaining to restrictions on suits against state and local governments, the rights of tenants and consumers, and workers injured during the course of employment. The court, in a complete turnabout, be- came prolabor and highly urban in orientation, re- sponsive to its new constituency. Blankenship, Jones, and other labor cases represented only a part, but a highly significant one, of what was described as a "quiet revolution."

The Ohio Supreme Court's adoption of the in- tentional tort exception may be attributed to a num- ber of factors. First, the court changed hands, going from one party to another. Second, the labor unions had been instrumental in changing the partisan com- position of the court. Third, Chief Justice Celebrezze not only had a judicial agenda, but perhaps hoped to parlay it into political advantage when pursuing his gubcrnatorial ambition. Finally, a majority of the jus- tices had no difficulty with the concept of an activist judiciary-or at least activist in some areas-and saw no reason why the court should continue to operate in its traditional deferential and self-effacing man- ner. (In this sense, the court is similar to at least one other state court, that of Alabama, described earlier, which precipitously and completely changed charac- ter).48

Michigan Supreme Court justices, like their Ohio counterparts, are selected in nonpartisan elec- tions. As in Ohio, the partisan primary provides the clue. In Michigan, nomination by political party con- vention for a place on the ballot, as well as media cov- erage, performs a similar function. The ascendancy of the Democratic party in the state, coupled with in- terim gubernatorial appointments, resulted, in the 1950s, in Democratic control of the court. The shift, as in Ohio, prompted substantial changes in the court's rulings. A court, closely divided on labor man- agement issues, hecame decidedly prolabor. As Sid- ncy Ulmcr obscrvcd in his study of the Michigan high court, "it is clear that in workmen's compensation and unemploymcnt compensation cases, Democratic justice is more sensitive to the claims of the unem- ployed and thc injured than Republican justice."49

The justices' party affiliations have been influen- tial in other areas as well, such as criminal appeals and reapportionment. Here, as in the labor cases, dis- sent rates have not been high, but disagreements on the court have been vociferous. In short, the Michi- gan high court, like Ohio's, has reflected the state's competitive political climate.50

While the Beauchamp court was Republican- controlled, thc ruling, it might be argued, reflects the court's long-standing approach to workers' compen- sation cases. Further, since the legislature was due to

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 105

enact a new definition of disability, the time may have appeared ripe to "suggest" further revisions in the workers' compensation system. The Michigan court, as the opinion and as history indicate, has few com- punctions about prodding or even defying the legisla- t ~ r e . ~ l

Conclusion This chapter has shown how one tort law innova-

tion was adopted and dispersed. It also supports the thesis that the patterns of adoption and diffusion of tort law doctrines are idiosyncratic. Further, it sup- ports the thesis that caution should be employed when making assumptions about the characteristics of state supreme courts. Whatever their reputations and traditions-distinguished, ordinary, activist, rest- raintist, bold, timid, leaders, followers, negators- state high courts do not always take positions that run true to form. Finally, as Canon and Baum have indi- cated, and as the Ohio, Alabama, and Michigan su- preme courts have demonstrated, a court can, in a relatively short period of time, undergo a radical transformation.

This cha~ te r is not intended to be read as an ad- vocacy for the intentional tort exception, nor as a criticism of the existing workers' compensation sys- tem. Nor is it intended as an argument for a particular brand of judicial activism. The chapter's lesson is that the further development of state constitutional law, now that lighthouse courts have pointed the way, may come from a variety of sources for a variety of rea- sons. A state court that has disregarded its own con- stitution may reverse course. One that had lcd the way (California, for example), may bccomc morc pas- sive. Or a court that had in no way distinguishcd ilsclf for many years might become a leader. The excep- tions to the exclusivity rules carved out by the West Virginia, California, Ohio, and Michigan courts illu- minate the infinite varieties inherent in the federal system, as well as the system's many, and often sur- prising, sources of policy initiatives.

NOTES

The Report of the National Commission on State Work- men's Compensation Laws (Washington, DC: the Com- mission, 1972), p. 15.

21bid., p. 119. 31bid., pp. 123-124. 4"Exceptions to the Exclusive Remedy Requirements of

Workers' Compensation Statutes," Harvard Law Review 96 (1983): 1641-1661, 1647-1658; Arthur J. Amchan, "Callous Disregard for Employee Safety: The Ex- clusivity of the Workers' Compensation Remedy against Employers," Labor Law Jorrnial (November 1983): 683-696. For a critical appraisal of the report, and for the federal legislation that was proposed, see James Robert Chelius, Workplace Safety arid Health: The Role of Work- ers' Conlpensation (Washington, DC: American Enter- prise Institute, 1977), chapters 4 and 5.

5Report of the National Commission on State Workmen's Compensation Laws, chapter 5.

6Quoted in Amchan, "Callous Disregard," p. 686. 7Amchan, "Callous Disregard," p. 686. 81ves v. South Buffalo Railway, 94 N.E. 431 (N.Y. 1911). gThe often-quoted phrase is William Prosser's. See, for example, William L. Prosser, John W. Wade, and Victor E. Schwartz, Torts-Cases and Materials (Mineola, New York: The Foundation Press, 1976), p. 1179.

lODriscoll v. Allis-Chalmer Co., 129 N.W. 401, 408-409 (Wis. 1911). For a discussion of changing judicial atti- tudes toward the fellow-servant rule, the impetus for re- form, and early workers' compensation statutes, see Lawrence M. Friedman and Jack Landinsky, "Social Change and the Law of Industrial Accidents," Coh~nibia Law Review 67 (1967): 50-82.

11 The phrase is described as an "old adage." "Election and Co-employee Immunity under Alabama's Workmen's Compensation Act," Alabama Law Review 31 (1979): 2-27, 4.

l2A large literature is devoted to the shortcomings of workers' compensation acts and their administration. For a summary of the problems and useful references, see "Exceptions to the Exclusive Remedy Requirements of Workers' Compensation Statutes." For the perspec- tive of a plaintiffs lawyer, see Allen Wilkinson, "Alter- native Theories to Workers' Compensation: Serving the Injured Worker Better," Trial (October 1983): 90-97; Amchan, "Callous Disregard."

13"Exceptions to the Exclusive Remedy Requirements," p. 1648. Friedman and Landinsky expressed concern over the ramifications of accidents, determined by courts to be compensable, that had "nothing to do with the impact of a machine on a man in an industrial setting." They warned that "if all the tendencies of the case law were followed to their logical limit, then workmen's compen- sation would end up covering for all illnesses, injuries and disabilitics which might somehow be linked to the job eilhcr c;~suall y, or because they happened during working houl.s," "Scxial Change and the Law of Indus- trial Acciclcnts." pp. 80-82. To a degree, their forebod- ings have bccn realized. "Exceptions to the Exclusive Remedy Rcquirernents"; Wilkinson, "Alternative Theories to Workers' Compensation"; William Bohyer, Montana Law Review 47 (1986): 157-180; "Exclusivity Provisions of Workers' Compensation Statutes: Will the Dual Injury Principle Crack the Wall of Employer Im- munity? University of Cincinnati Law Review 55 (1986): 550-571. Many dual injury cases involve alleged em- ployer deceit. See, for example, Johns-Manville Products Corp. v. Contra Costa Superior Court, 612 P.2d 948 (Cal. 1980), and discussion, note 33 and accompanying text.

'4''Right of Access to Civil Courts under State Constitu- tional Law: An Impediment to Modern Reforms or a Receptacle of Important Substantive Rights?" Rutgeis Law Journal 13 (1982): 399-477.

'=For discussion, see chapter 7 of this volume and litera- ture cited, note 25 therein.

'GDiscussion of the Alabama high court and cases is based on G. Alan Tarr and Mary Cornelia Aldis Porter, State Srrpreme Courts in State arid Nation (New Haven: Yale University Press. 1988). chapter 3.

"Grantham v. Denke, 359 So. 2d 785 (Ala. 1980). eluci- dated in Fireman's Fund American Insurance Co. v. Coleman, 394 So. W 334,343 (Ala. 1980), Justice Jones concurring.

106 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

18Fireman's Fund at 339-340. 1gCit. at 347, Justices Jones concurring. 2oCit. at 354, Justices Shores concurring. 21 "Election and Co-employee Immunity under Ala-

bama's Workmen's Compensation Act," Alabama Law Review 31 (1979): 2-27, 14.

22Much of the material for this section was drawn from Tarr and Porter, State Srcpreme Courts in State and Na- tion, pp. 30-40.

23PeterHarris, "Difficult Cases and the Display of Author- ity," Jo~rrnal of Law, Economics and Organization 1 (1985): 209-221, and "Structural Change in the Commu- nication of Precedent among State Supreme Courts, 1870-1970," Social Networks 4 (1982): 210.

24 Gregory A. Caldeira, "The Transmission of Legal Prece- dent: A Study of State Supreme Courts," American Po- litical Science Review 79 (1985): 178-194, 190, 192, and "On the Reputation of State Supreme Courts," Political Behavior 5 (1983): 83-108.

ZSCaldeira, "On the Reputation of State Supreme Courts"; Bradley C. Canon and Lawrence Baum, "Patterns of Adoption of Tort Law Innovations: An Application of Diffusion Theory to Judicial Doctrines," American Po- litical Science Review 75 (1981): 975-987 and "State Su- preme Courts as Activists: New Doctrines in the Law of Torts," in Mary Cornelia Porter and G. Alan Tarr, eds., State Supreme Courts: Policymakers in the Federal System (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 1982), chap- ter 4.

26Canon and Baum, "Patterns of Adoption of Tort Iaw Innovations," p. 985; Caldeira, "Thc Transmission of Legal Precedent," p. 179.

27For a sampling of the literature on the new judicial fcder- alism, see G. Alan Tarr, "Bibliographic Essay," Porter and Tarr eds., State Supreme Corrrfs: Policymakers in the Federal System, pp. 201-209,206-208. For a case survey, see Ronald K.L. Collins, Peter J. Galie, and John Kin- caid, "State High Courts, State Constitutions, and Indi- vidual Rights Litigation since 1980: A Judicial Survey," Publius: The Journal ofFederalism 16 (1986): 141-162. For an identification, based on the new judicial federalism literature, of civil libertarian activist state courts, see G. Alan Tarr and Mary Cornelia Porter, "Gender Equality and Judicial Federalism: The Role of Appellate Courts," Hustings Constitutional Law Quarter& 9 (1982): 919-974, 953-954. For the part played by state high courts in effec- tuating institutional and social change, which may be considered an outgrowth of the new judicial federalism, see Russell Harrison, "State Court Activism in Exclu- sionary Zoning Cases," in Porter and Tarr eds., State Su- preme Courts: Policymaking in the Federal System, pp. 55-82; Norman C. Thomas, "Equalizing Educational Opportunity through School Finance Reform: A Re- view Assessment," University of Cincinnati Law Review 48 (1979): 225-331.

Z8''New Jersey: The Legacy of Reform" chapter 5, in Tarr and Porter, eds., State Supreme Courts in State and Na- tion. Canon and Baum, "Patterns of Adoption of Tort Law Innovations," p. 977. Since 1975, however, "the Massachusetts Supreme Court has begun to take a newly activist position in support of changes in the tort law. As a result, no longer can this court be regarded as a bulwark of opposition to tort law activism." Baum and Canon, "State Supreme Courts as Activists," p. 101.

29"The Intentional Act Exception to the Exclusivity of Workers' Compensation," Louisiana Law Review 44

(1984): 1507-1530. Seven states provide employees with the option of bringing suits for certain kinds of torts. "Blankenship v. Cincinnati Milacron Chemicals, Inc.: Some Fairness for Ohio Workers and Some Uncertainty for Ohio Employers," University ofToledo Law Review 15 (1983): 403-436, 421.

30The phraseology derives from a few federal cases and from rulings of high courts in Alabama, Arkansas, Con- necticut, Florida, Georgia, Indiana, Illinois, Louisiana, and Oklahoma-all of which have strictly construed the immunity provisions of workers' compensation statutes. Successful intentional tort suits for physical injury have for the most part, involved physical assault by the em- ployer, an early seminal case being Boek v. Wong Hing, 231 N.W. 233 (Minn. 1930).

31 Arthur A. Larson, Tile Law of Workmen's Compensation, Sec. 68.13 (1978). For example of advocacy for an expan- sive interpretation of intentional tort, see "Expanding the Intentional Tort Exception to Include Willful, Wan- ton and Reckless Employer Misconduct," Notre Dame Law Review 58 (1982-83); and Wilkinson, "Alternative Theories to Workers' Compensation."

32Mandolidis v. Elkins Industries, 246 S.E. 2d 907 (W. Va. 1978). For a critical analysis of the case, see David M. Flannery, Joseph S. Beeson, M. Ann Bradley, and Richard P. Goddard, "The Expanding Role of the West Virginia Supreme Court of Appeals in the Review of Workmen's Compensation Appeals," West Virginia Law Review 81 (1978): 1-144. For its aftermath, see "In the Wake of Mandolidis: A Case Study of Recent Trials Brought undcr the Mandolidis Theory," West K~ginia Law Review 84 (1982): 893-915. In one case, Cline Joy M rg. Co., rcv'tl., 3 10 S.E. 2d 835 (W. Va. 1983) the award of tlamagcs was scveral times the employer's worth. The revised statule was enacted in 1983.

33Johns-Manville Products Corp. v. Contra Costasuperior Court, 612 P. 2.41 948 (Cal. 1980). For an unenthusiastic view of Johns-Manville, see Wilkinson, "Alternative Theories to Workers' Compensation," pp. 91-92. The New Jersey Supreme Court has seen fit to punish par- ticularly egregious employer behavior under the dual in- jury doctrine. Millison v. E. I. du Pont de Nemours and Co., 501 A. 26 505 (N.J. 1985). In some instances the dual injury doctrine has been held to include nonphysical in- juries such as defamation, emotional distress, and em- ployment discrimination and harassment. Battista v. Chrysler Corp., 454 A. 2d 286 @el. Super. 1982): Seals v. Henry Ford Hospital, 333 N.W. 26 272 (Mich., 1983): Belanoff v. Grayson, 434 N.E. 2d 717 (N.Y. 1982). The revised California labor code (West's Supplement 1988) states that "an employee may bring an action at law for damages against the employer. . . where the employee's injury is aggravated by the employer's fraudulent con- cealment of the existence of the injury and its connection with the employment, in which case the employer's li- ability shall be limited to those damages proximately caused by the aggravation. The proof of respecting ap- portionment of damages between the injury and any subsequent aggravation thereof is on the employer."

34Blanken~hip v. Cincinnati Milacron Chemicals, 433 N.E. 572 (Ohio 1982): cert. denied, 459 US. 857 (1982).

35Jones v. VIP Dcvclopment Co., 472 N.E. 26 1046 (Ohio, 1984). (Emphasis added.) Ohio commentary on the case was mixed, some approving, some disapproving. all somewhat uncertain as to the rule promulgated. "Blankenship v. Cincinnati Milacron Chemical Co.: Workers' Compensation and the New Intentional

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 107

Tort-A New Direction for Ohio," Capital University Law Review 12 (1982): 287-312; "Tort-Worker Com- pensation-Employer Immunity-An Employee Is Not Precluded by the Ohio Workers' Compensation Laws from Enforcing a Common Law Rcmcdy for I ntenlional Torts Committed by His Employers," Utiivivsity of Cin- cinnati Law Review 51 (1982): 682-696.

36For discussion of the Ohio Supreme Court's controvcr- sial "prolabor" and generally "populist" position, see Tarr and Porter, eds., State Supreme Courts in State m7d Nation, "Ohio: Partisan Justice," chapter 4.

37The Ohio statute was enacted in 1986. For its provisions and for discussion, see "The New Workers' Compensa- tion Law in Ohio: Senate Bill 307 WasNo Accident,"Ak- mn Law Review 20 (1987): 491-518,514-515.

38For an account of the ultimately successful efforts toper- suade courts to adopt an important consumer protection doctrine, see William L. Prosser, "The Assault upon the Citadel (Strict Liability to the Consumer)," Yale Law Journal 69 (1960): 1099-1148 and "The Fall of the Citadel (Strict Products Liability to the Consumer)," Minnesota Law Review 50 (1966): 791-848.

39Beauchamp v. Dow Chemical Co., 398 N.W. 26 882,889 (Mich., 1986).

40"Intentional Torts and Workers' Compensation: Beauchamp v. Dow Chemicals," Cooley Law Review 4 (1987): 707-723, 719, 723. Commentary concluded that "despite [legislative] attacks on judicial activism, the Beauchamp decision had at least one undeniable effect: it prompted action from a legislature which had failed to correct the situation. There was no statutory intentional tort exception before the Beauchamp decision, but since then, Michigan has joined the majority of states in refus- ing to allow an employer to hide behind the exclusivity of worker's compensation." The problem here, of course, is that "intent" has been difficult to define. What one court may regard as "intent," another may dismiss an "negli- gence."

4lThe National Commission on State Workmen's Com- pensation Lam, while conceding that lawsuits oftenpre- sented appealing alternatives to the compensation sys- tem, nonetheless cautioned that successful suits required substantial financing, and have "concentrated on [only] a narrow range of issues which encompass a compelling need." Report, p. 123.

42Richard Neely, Why the Court's Don't Work (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1983), p. 166. Neely was an associate jus- tice when Mandolidis was decided.

43See note 38. 44Much has been written about the California Supreme

Court. For an overview, see Mary Cornelia Porter, "State Supreme Courts and the Legacy of the Warren Court: Some Old Inquiries for a New Situation," in Porter and Tarr, eds., State Supreme Courts: Policymakers in the Fed- eral System, chapter 1. For the court's contribution to the development of tort law, see G. Edward White, The American Judicial Tradition: Profies of LeadingAmerican Judges (New York: Oxford University Press, 1976), chap- ter 13. The California Supreme Court consistently sup- ported the dual capacity doctrine, e.g. Bell v. Industrial Vangas, Inc., 637 P2d 266 (Cal., 198 I), until tlic Icgisla-

ture abolished the doctrine. "Exceptions to the Exclusive Remedy Requirement of Workers' Compensation Stat- utes," p. 1653, n. 76. In the 1986 judicial election the Cali- fornia high court lost its Democratic, liberal majority. As a result, fcwcr rulings favoring workers, consumers, ten- ants, and "untlcnlogs" generally might be anticipated.

45 1'11 i l ip I .. I )U ljois, 1 7 1 ~ 1 7 1 Ballot to Bench: Judicial Elections and the Qrrest jbr Accountability (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1980), passim, p. 139. The West Virginia high court is bcst known for its author-Chief Justice, Richard Necly, whose books, while informed by his ex- perience on thc slate bench, range far beyond parochial concerns. Wly the Courts Don't Work, and How Courts Govern America (New Haven, Connecticut: Yale Uni- versity Press, 1981).

46For discussion of the newly activist West Virginia court, see John Patrick Hagan, "Policy Activism in the West Virginia Supreme Court of Appeals," West L4ginia Law Review 89 (1986): 159-165. "The Expanding Role of the West Virginia Court of Appeals in the Review of Work- men's Compensation Appeals," pp. 1 and 2, note 4. There is disagreement about the influence of party affili- ation on judicial decision making in workers' compensa- tion cases. S. Sidney Ulmer, "The Political Party Vari- able in the Michigan Supreme Court," Journal of Public Law 11 (1960): 352-362; Edward Beiser and Jonathan Sil- verman, "The Political Party Variable: Workmen's Compensation Cases in the New York Court of Ap- peals," Policy 3 (1981): 521-531; David W. Adamany, "The Party Variable in Judges' Voting: Conceptual Notes and a Case Study," American Political Science Re- view 63 (1969): 57-72.

47Mandolidi~ v. Elkin Industries, Inc., 246 S.E. 26 907,909, 921.

48Discussion drawn from "Ohio: Partisan Justice," chapter 4, in Tarr and Porter, eds., State Supreme Courts in State andNation. (In 1986, the court, by a narrow majority, was recaptured by the Republicans. Chief Justice Celebreese did not win reelection.)

4QUlmer, "The Political Party Variable in the Michigan Supreme Court," pp. 354-355.

50The Michigan high court is intensely "political." High dissent rates have reflected (often acrimonious) dis- agreements as well as partisan divisions. For discussion and a summary of the literature, see "Democratic and Republican Justice: Judicial Decision-Making on Five State Supreme Courts," Cohrmbia Journal of Law and Social Pmblerns 13 (1977): 137-181, 160-165.

5' For the court's pointed reminder to the legislature that it would take a dim view of interference with the state con- stitutional guarantee of "freedom of expression" on "all subjects," see Porter, "State Supreme Courts and the Legacy of the Warren Court: Some Old Inquiries for a New Situation," in Porter and T a n eds., State Supreme Courts: Policymakers in the Fedeml System, chapter 1, p. 15. "When the legislature overturned a 1961 supreme court decision that had abolished the immunity of local governments from lawsuit, the court in turn held the leg- islature's action unconstitutional for procedural reasons. Iawrencc 13aun1, American Courts: Process and Policy (Ik~ston: I ioq,hton Mifflin Company, 1986), p. 310.

108 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 9

State Constitutional Law and State Educational Policy

The Legislature shall provide for the sup- port of a thorough and efficient system of free public schools. . . .

New Jersey Constitution, Article VIII, Sec. 14, para. 1.

Unlike the Constitution of the United States, the Constitution of New Jersey, like those of almost all the states,' mandates that the state legislature pro- vide for a system of public education. Until recently, however, the meaning of this obligation has remained something of a mystery. Whatever its meaning, his- torically the states have delegated most of the re- sponsibility for the implementation of this obligation to local school districts. Local school districts carried the principal responsibility for defining the content of education, for its management and supervision, and for its financial support.

This process of delegation raised interesting questions under state constitutions: (1) Was the legis- lature shirking its constitutional obligations by dele- gating so much of the responsibility to local districts? (2) Did the unequal distribution of resources among local districts to support education violate the equal- ity or uniformity provisions of state constitutions, or even the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution of the Unitcd States?

In 1973, the Supreme Court of thc Unilcd States rejected the last argument,2 that the school finance law of Texas violated the equal protection clause of the U.S. Constitution. State courts, however, have continued to struggle with state constitutional issues: what is a state's obligation to provide a "thorough and efficient" system of education, and what kind of equality must be guaranteed by a state?

As state courts-and state legislatures-grap- pled with these difficult constitutional issues, the court opinions and legislative debates raised the broadest questions about the meaning of "equality of

educational opportunity," and state legislatures be- gan to enact a wide range of educational reforms as they responded, in part, to court opinions. The conse- quence has been a reinvigoration of state educational policy, which has spread rapidly throughout the United States.3

This chapter will examine the dynamics of that constitutional-political process. This should not be taken to suggest that this particular process is some- how typical of state constitutional-political processes generally, for very little is "typical" in the United States. However, it will demonstrate the continuing importance of state constitutions and constitutional law as the basis of state policy.

The States and Mucation: An Historical Perspective

Of the first 14 American states (including Ver- mont, which joined the Union in 1791), seven pro- vided for some form of education in their first consti- tutions.4 The precise nature of these provisions varied. On the one hand, Section 44 of the Pennsylva- nia Constitution of 1776 seemed to mandate the es- tablishment of schools:5

A school or schools shall be established in each county by the legislature for the con- venient instruction of youth, with such salaries to the masters paid by the public, as may cnnblc them to instruct youth at low priccs. . . . On the othcr hand, the Massachusetts Constitu-

tion of 1780 was ambiguous about the state's obliga- tion:

Wisdom and knowledge, as well as virtue, diffused generally among the body of the peoplc, being necessary for the preservation of their rights and liberties; and as these de- pend on spreading the opportunities and ad- vantages of education in the various parts of the country and among the different orders

Advisory Commission on lntergovemmental Relations 109

of the people, it shall be the duty of Legisla- tures and Magistrates, in all future periods of this Commonwealth, to cherish the inter- ests of literature and the sciences, and all seminaries of them; especially the university at Cambridge, public schools and grammar schools in the towns. . . .6

The Massachusetts Constitution went on to provide that it was the duty of the legislature

. . . to countenance and inculcate the princi- ples of humanity and general benevolence, public and private charity, industry and fru- gality, honesty and punctuality in their deal- ings; sincerity, good humor, and all social af- fections, and general sentiments among the people.?

During the last decade of the 18th century and the first two of decades the 19th, the states began to implement these constitutional provisions.8 Gener- ally, they enacted two types of legislation: (1) laws en- couraging and sometimes even requiring local com- munities to provide schools, and (2) laws setting up small state schools funds to assist local communities in these efforts.9 Two great issues emerged out of these experiments in education: (1) Should schools be provided for all children, or only for those from families too poor to afford the tuition at private academies?"J (2) Should the schools be under public or private control?ll

By the middle of the 19th century, the propo- nents of the common school won both of these politi- cal struggles. Led by reformers, such as Horace Mann of Massachusetts and Henry Barnard of Connecticut, they succeeded in establishing the dominance of pub- lic schools, first in the cities and then in spreading the common school to the countryside.12 By the 1840s and 1850s, as states rewrote their constitutions, they usually included a provision that the state establish "public" or "common" or "free" schools and that the system be "efficient" or "thorough" or "uniform" or "general" and "open to a11."13

In addition, more of the states began to establish permanent school funds for distribution to local school districts, usually on a per capita basis, and cre- ated state administrative structures to supervise the growth and operations of the common schools.14 Naturally, the nature and extent of state involvement varied from state to state, depending on its own tradi- tion and circumstance.l5 However, to the extent that one can generalize at all, it is safe to say that the states' role was that of encouraging local communi- ties to meet the constitutional obligation for common schools.

By the end of the century, public schools, includ- ing some high schools, were in place throughout the

nation, and the states' concern began to shift from the number of schools to their quality.

Beginning with the studies of E.P. Cubberley in New York in the early years of the 20th century,ls educational researchers found that even with the sys- tem of flat, per capita grants, many districts were un- able to provide an adequate education. The problem was especially acute in rural areas with low property tax rates. They simply could not generate enough revenue to support adequate schools, especially as the provision of education became more cornplex-and expensive. Therefore, Cubberley and his followers recommended that the states guarantee each district a certain basic, or "foundation" level of education funding, regardless of their local property values. Thus, property-poor districts would receive more state aid than would wealthy ones. The concept spread gradually throughout the states, so that, even today, most states use some form of foundation sup- port.'?

Although these foundation plans were equaliz- ing, they did not equalize spending among the dis- tricts. Indeed, it was never claimed that a foundation plan would lead to equal per pupil expenditures. In fact, Paul Mort argued that every state needed some "lighthouse" districts that could afford the "risk capi- tal" to experiment. Successful experiments, Mort claimed, would gradually be adopted in other, less af- fluent districts.18 Even beyond this, the foundation plans were never as equalizing as the reformers hoped they would be. The continuing disparity in school district spending was a consequence of two po- litical necessities. First, the politics of state founda- tion plans required that all school districts receive some moncy, so that foundation aid was usually dis- trilwtcd ovcr and above the system of flat grants. Sec- ond, the plans provided only for a foundation level of education, and local districts were free to spend be- yond that levcl.lg Either because of their lack of property wealth or their unwillingness to tax them- selves at higher rates, some districts spent only the minimum, or barely above it.20

While the states worked to improve their foun- dation plans, usually by raising the foundation level and by weighing school district needs according to demographic factors and the nature of the student population, dissatisfaction continued to grow, so that by the 1960s a variety of forces coalesced to wage a full-scale legal and political battle against state school finance systems.

Two forces especially seemed to spur this attack. First, the civil rights movement was in full sway, and there was widespread concern for "equality." Second, property taxes, the mainstay of school finance, had risen rapidly, and there was a growing sense that they were inefficient and fundamentally unfair.2' Given the history of success by public interest lawyers in the

1 10 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

federal courts, it is not surprising that many of the in- itial attacks on school finance systems were waged in federal courthouses.22

The Federal Courts and State School Finance Laws

One of the first challenges to a state school fi- nance law emerged out of a desegregation contro- versy in Louisiana. There, a U.S. District Court re- jected the plaintiffs' claim that the state's detailed constitutional provisions for the distribution of state aid violated the equal protection clause of the Four- teenth Amendment.23 In unequivocal language, the court said:

There is simply no right, privilege or immu- nity secured by the Constitution and laws of the United States in any way being denied by these respondents when they allocate and disburse funds pursuant to the provisions . . . of the Louisiana Constitution.24

Three years later, a U.S. District Court in Illinois was equally abrupt when it rejected an attack on the state's school finance law.25 Here, the plaintiffs claimed that the only constitutionally permissible method for the distribution of state school funds would be "educational need." In rejecting the claim, the court quoted Justice Oliver Wcndcll Holmes' comment that "the Fourteenth Amcndmcnl is not a pedagogical requirement of the irnpracti~al."~~

Similarly, another district court rejected a chal- lenge to Virginia's school finance law,27 commenting that:

. . . the courts have neither the knowledge, nor the means, nor the power to tailor the public moneys to fit the varying needs of these students throughout the State.z8

The first victory-although a small and tempo- rary one-for the challenges of state school finance laws was in Florida.29 There, the federal court over- turned a specific provision of the state's school fi- nance law which had, in effect, placed a limit on local tax rates so that property-poordistricts were prohib- ited from taxing themselves at higher rates so as to provide the same level of school expenditure as more wealthy districts. The court held that this absolute limitation was a violation of the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. However, two years later, the U.S. Supreme Court vacated the judgment.s0

In 1971, there were two more far-reaching deci- sions. In both Minnesota3' and Texas,32 federal courts struck down state school finance laws as viola- tive of the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Reasoning that education is a "funda- mental interest," the courts found that there was no

"compelling state interest" which could justify the differentials among the school districts' capacities to support education.

However, these victories were short-lived, be- cause, in 1973 in San Antonio Independent School Dis- trict v. Rodriguez, the U.S. Supreme Court overruled the federal Court of Appeals in Texas23 holding that education is not a "fundamental interest," that the relationship between property-poor districts and poor people was too tenuous to justify a "suspect category," and that the state's method of financing education served a legitimate state interest, local control of education.

Much has been written on the Supreme Court's Rodriguez decision, and there is no need to review that literature here. Clearly, however, one of the Court's major concerns was that of an appropriate remedy. According to one commentator, "[Tlhe Court majority saw the danger of a Court-dictated financing scheme along . . . simplified lines-one child, one budget, or one school district, one taxbase; to the Court, a fearful symmetry."34 Any solution along these lines would raise extraordinarily difficult questions. For example: What is the relationship be- tween equal spending and equal educational oppor- tunity? How could a state deal with the special prob- lems of school districts with high-cost students, or with the unusual costs associated with very densely or very sparscly populated districts? Would the states be forccd lo "lcvcl up" all districts to the level of the highest spending district? Could districts tax them- selves at higher rates to provide enhanced educa- tional programs, and thus perpetuate spending in- equalities? Or would the states be forced to place some sort of tax or spending cap on the high spending districts? Finally, what would be the effect of a Court- imposed remedy on the tradition of local control? With the rejection of Rodriguez's claim, federal courts were not forced to confront these issues. But as the battleground shifted from federal courts and the U.S. Constitution to state courts and state consti- tutions, these difficult questions were addressed in many states.

State Courts, State Constitutions, and State School Finance Laws

While the annals of American state constitu- tional history are filled with taxpayer suits challeng- ing state tax and spending programs, including state and local taxation and spending for public schools,35 the modern period begins with the 1971 decision of the California Supreme Court in Serrano v. Priest.3" In Serrano, the California Supreme Court became thc first state supreme court to invalidate a state school finance system on equal protection grounds. Beginning with a determination that education is a "fundamental interest," the court found that the

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 11 1

state's concern for local control was not compelling enough to meet its "strict scrutiny" test. With regard to local control, the court said:

. . . so long as the assessed valuation within a district's boundaries is a major determinant of how much it can spend for its schools, only a district with a large tax base will be truly able to decide how much it really cares about education. The poor district cannot freely choose to tax itself into an excellence which its tax rolls cannot provide. Far from being necessary to promote local fiscal choice, the present financing system actually deprives the less wealthy districts of that option.37

Although the court's opinion implies a financing scheme that will provide equal per pupil spending, the court did not specify a remedy; rather, it merely remanded the case back to the lower court for further proceedings.38

The following year, in Robinson v. CahiN, the New Jersey school finance law was invalidated by the state's high court, but on an entirely different ground.39 The New Jersey court found that the de- centralized method of local school finance violated that provision of the New Jersey Constitution requir- ing the legislature to provide for a "thorough and effi- cient system of free public schools."40 The Court did not define the specific contours of such a "thorough and efficient" system, but did note that:

The constitution's guarantee must be under- stood to embrace that educational opportu- nity which is needed in a contemporary set- ting to equip a child for his role as a citizen and as a competitor in the labor market.41

Because education is a "fundamental interest," the Court said, the state must meet its "strict scrutiny"in defining and providing a "thorough and efficient" education.

California and New Jersey were not the only states to consider the constitutionality of their school finance systems. In fact, between 1971 and 1983, the constitutionality of state school finance statutes was considered by 21 different state supreme courts.42 Some were "equal protection" cases, as in Serrano; some were "thorough and efficient" cases, as in Robinson v. Cahill; others raised different state con- stitutional issues altogether. Whatever the particular allegation, the state supreme courts were fairly evenly divided in their responses: 12 courts upheld the state school finance statutes,43 while 9 held that they violated either the "thorough and efficient" or "equal protection" provision of the state constitu- tion.44

The courts articulated three reasons for rejecting challenges under the "thorough and efficient" clauses: that the clause did not suggest uniformity;

that the clause implied only a "basic" education; or that the definition of the clause was best left in the hands of the Icgislature. For example, the Maryland Supreme said that the constitutional provi- sion requiring "the Legislature . . . [to] establish throughout the State a thorough and efficient system of free public schools" did not "mandate uniformity in per pupil funding and expenditures among the State's school di~tricts."~e In Colorado, the Supreme Court held47 that its nearly identical constitutional provision did not bar such disparities "because that clause should not be interpreted to prevent local dis- tricts from supplementing beyond this minimum ~tandard."~a In almost all of these cases, the courts showed great deference to legislative judgments. For example, in New Y0rk,~9 where the plaintiffs had ar- gued that the school finance system should consider "municipal and education overburden" in the distri- bution of school funds, the Court said:

Because decisions as to how public funds will be allocated among the several services for which by constitutional imperative the Leg- islaturc is required to make provision are matters pcculiarly appropriate for formula- tion by the legislative body (reflective of and responsive as it is to the public will), we would be reluctant to override those deci- sions by mandating an even higher priority for education in the absence, possibly, of gross and flaring inadequacy.50

Similarly, the Idaho Supreme Court51 rejected a challenge to that state's school finance system be- M U S C

. . . to do otherwise would be an unwise and unwarranted entry into the controversial area of public school financing, whereby this court would convene as a "super-legisla- ture," legislating in a turbulent field of so- cial, economic, and political policy.52

In decisions based principally on state protection clauses, the courts usually held that education was not a "fundamental interest" and, therefore, that the disparities in school funding and expenditure caused by state finance systems needed to be justified only by a "rational purpose" test. For example, after deter- mining that education was not a "fundamental inter- est," the Oregon Supreme Court53 balanced "the in- terest impinged upon-educational opportunity . . . against the state objective in maintaining the present system of school financing-local control."54 In Ohio,55 after rejecting the "fundamental interest" contention, the court hcld that the disparity in fund- ing "is the product of a system that is [not] so irra- tional as to be a violation of the equal protection and benefit clause."56 Courts reached similar conclusions in Arizona,57 Illinois,58 and Michigan.60

112 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

On the other hand, nine state supreme courts struck down school finance statutes under either state constitutional "thorough and efficient" provi- sions or "equal protection" requirements. The Con- stitution of the State of Washington, for example, af- ter requiring that the legislature "provide for a general and uniform system of public schools," goes on to state that "it is the paramount duty of the state to make ample provision for all children residing within its borders."61 The Washington Supreme Court,62 in striking down the state's school finance law, made an explicit connection between these two provisions, maintaining that:

Flowing from this constitutionally imposed "duty" is its jural correlative, a correspon- dent "right". . . . Therefore all children resid- ing within the borders of the State possess a "right" arising from the constitutionally im- posed "duty."63

The legislature, by delegating so much of the finan- cial responsibility for education to local communities, was shirking its constitutional "duty" and violating the "rights" of state residents. Similarly, the Con- necticut Supreme Court64 had difficulty with the delegation of responsibility to local school districts. In finding the state's school finance law to be uncon- stitutional, the court commented that "the duty to educate is that of the state; delegating that duty does not discharge it."65 In finding Arkansas' school fi- nance law unconstitutional,66 the Court cornmcntcd that where local school districts could not provide the "general, suitable, and efficient" education required by the Constitution,e7 then the state must.

In the five cases in which state school finance laws were found to violate the equal protection clause of the state constitution, the courts tended to rely on the reasoning of the California Supreme Court in its Serrano decision, finding that education is a "fundamental interest" and that the state's concern with "local control" is insufficiently "compelling" to justify the disparities in funding and expenditure.

Regardless of the basis of the decision, and al- most independent of whether the state supreme court upheld or struck down the finance law, the court decisions started a virtual revolution in school finance as state legislatures across the nation were called on to struggle with defining the states' role in education and with creating funding mechanisms that could assure a "thorough and efficient" education.

State Legislatures, State Constitutions, and State School Finance Laws

According to a 1979 study by the Education Commission of the States, "Within the past decade, more that half of the states have passed laws signifi- cantly changing the way by which state aid is distrib-

uted to school districts."ea In some cases-California, Connecticut, Kansas, New Jersey, and Washington, for example-the legislatures were reacting to state supreme court decisions that had held the old sys- tems to be unconstitutional. In other states-Idaho and Massachusetts-there was the need to address funding problcms brought about by citizen-initiated property tax limitations. In most states, however, school finance reform was put on the agenda by a va- riety of factors, including not only court decisions and tax limitations, but also the need for property tax re- form, the research and networking activities of such groups as the Education Commission of the States and the National Conference of State Legislatures, federally funded studies of state school finance sys- tems, and the need to address the special educational requirements of high-cost segments of the pupil population, such as handicapped and bilingual stu- dents.69

Thus, school finance reform was not designed merely to equalize per pupil expenditures, although certainly the reform measures were equalizing in this sense.70 The school finance reform measures enacted by the states during the 1970s also addressed taxpayer equity, the high costs of bilingual, compensatory, and handicapped educational programs, and educational improvement generally. It was possible to pursue all of these goals simultaneously because state govern- ments wcre willing to put substantial new revenues into education. The magnitude of this effort can be gaugcd 1)y thc hct that state spending for education triplcd bctwccn 1969 and 1979, increasing from un- der $14 billion to approximately $42 billion. While lo- cal spending also increased during this period (from about $18 billion to $38 billion), the state share of the state-local cost of education went from about 43 per- cent to 52 percent.71 This increase in state support had several consequences for school finance reform.

First, the states were able to "level up" low spending districts toward the levels of the higher spending districts. Many states simply increased their foundation levels and adjusted their formulas so that almost all of the new funding went to the poorer dis- tricts. A few states, Utah and Montana, for example, found it necessary to include "recapture" provisions, so that a portion of the "excess" funds generated by wealthy school districts through property taxation went to the state for redistribution to the poorer dis- tricts.72 Other states made it difficult for high spend- ing districts to increase expenditures, either by re- quiring local voter approval or by putting a "cap" on the rate of increase.

Second, the new state money for school finance was often used for property tax relief. Property-poor districts had been forced previously to tax themselves at high rates to meet the rising costs of education. Many states-Colorado, Connecticut, Illinois, Kan-

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 113

sas, Michigan, New Jersey, Ohio, and Wisconsin, for example-adopted some form of district power equalizing formula, thus providing for a greater de- gree of taxpayer equity. In addition, other states adopted property tax circuit breakers to provide some property tax relief for elderly and low-income taxpay- ers.

Third, many states recognized the special high- cost needs of certain school districts and pupil popu- lations. Michigan, for example, recognized the prob- lem of "municipal overburden" by providing additional school aid to all districts in which the non- educational tax rate exceeded the state average by more than 25 percent. Florida pursued the same goal by building a cost-of-living factor into its school aid formula. Other states-Utah, New Mexico, Kansas, Colorado, Maine, Montana, Nebraska, and Texas, for example-adjusted their formulas so as to recognize the special problems of districts with small numbers of students, sparse populations, or rural isolation. States also recognized the high costs of special-needs pupils, either by improving the weighing system in their general aid formulas or by developing targeted categorical programs.

All of these changes took placc within thc con- text of continuing school finance litigation. The situ- ation that developed in California is an especially in- teresting example for the interaction of state courts, state legislatures, and political and fiscal develop- ments generall~.~3 After the supreme court's original Serrano decision in 1971, holding the state's school fi- nance law unconstitutional, the legislature enacted a palliative measure greatly increasing state funding for education and placing a cap on local school spend- ing. In 1976, the supreme court held that this was in- sufficient and that the amended law still violated the equal protection clause of the California Constitu- tion.74 In response, the legislature adopted an en- tirely new school finance law based on a district power equalizing formula. The new law also con- tained provisions for a massive program of educa- tional improvement. But nine months later, the vot- ers approved Proposition 13, which effectively eliminated 60 percent of local tax revenues and de- stroyed the fiscal assumptions underlying the school finance bill. The state legislature promptly passed a series of "bail-out" measures which, in effect, pro- vided more state funding for those districts most af- fected by Proposition 13. The California Supreme Court upheld the new school finance law,75 noting that "significant parity" had been achieved because over 90 percent of the per pupil expenditures within the state were within a range of $100.

Nevertheless, the supreme court's approval of the school finance law did not end the legislature's redefinition of the state's role in In 1983, Governor George Deukmejian announced that

he was willing to support $800 million in new state education aid, but only if there were "structural re- forms" in education. The resulting bill combined fur- ther school finance reform with fundamental changes affecting both students and teachers. The law, in the words of one commentator, "went beyond the techni- cal periphery of education into the core of the in- structional process to set standards on what should be taught, how it should be taught, and who should teach it."T7 Thus, starting with the fairly straightforward, al- though complicated issue of "fiscal neutrality," Cali- fornia began to address the most fundamental ques- tions about the role of the state in education.

Developments in other states, while not as dra- matic or well documented, followed a similar path. In A r k a n s a ~ , ~ ~ Connecticut,79 and New Jersey,so what began as school finance reform moved quickly to broader questions of school improvement and educa- tional reform. Even in those states where the state high court had upheld the state school finance law, state legislatures felt compelled to deal with matters of school finance and educational improvement. For example, in New Y ~ r k , ~ ' where the state court had upheld the school finance law, the legislature never- thclcss providcd $630 million in new state aid for education, thc largcst single-year increase in state history. In addition, the legislature adjusted the school aid formula to provide greater aid to low- wealth districts. In Texas,@ where the Rodriguez case originated, thc legislature provided $2.8 billion over three year sfor both equalization and school improve- ment purposes. Under the state's new foundation program, "the 71 poorest districts. . . received an ad- ditional $220.1 million or an average increase of 46.3 percent; the 176 wealthiest districts. . . lost $21.6 mil- lion, a 20.5 percent decrease in per pupil revenue."a The new state money was directed more at educa- tional improvement than at equalization.84 In the words of H. Ross Perot, the chairman of Texas' Select Committee on Public Education, "A million dollars for reform but not a penny for the status quo."85

In other states where state supreme courts had upheld school finance laws, legislatures nevertheless took second looks at education policies and often made significant financial and programmatic changes. State court decisions and opinions, and sometimes even the threat of court action, were among the many factors that led the states to recon- sider school finance and the role of the state in educa- tion generally.

Conclusion According to some observers, "School finance

through the local property tax is one of those estab- lished institutions that can profit from forced reex- amination."a6 In some ways, the U.S. Supreme Court's decision in the Rodriguez case was regretta-

114 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

ble. Perhaps it might have been better if the court had overturned Texas' school finance law and re- manded it back to the state for a "forced reexami- nation." Yet, such a ruling would have been problem- atic, because it would have subjected the states to continuing supervision by the federal judiciary. Such a forced reexamination has occurred without federal court mandates. Referring to the decision of the Cali- fornia Suureme Court in Serrano, Judith Areen and

guage. See Robert L. Brunhouse, The Counter- Revolu- tion in Pennsylvatzia 1776-1 790 (Harrisburg: The Pennsylvania Historical and Museum Commission, 1971).

6Constitution of Massachusetts, Chapter V, Section 11. 7Ibid. 8See R. Freeman Butts, Public Education in the United States: From Revolution to Reform (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1978).

QFor exam~le. Connecticut established a small school Leonard ROSS claim that it "was a bold and, so far as fund in 1796, funded largely from the sale of public land. can be told, singularly successful undertaking, if SUC- New York also established a small fund in 1795, but re- cess is defined in the precise sense of forcing a reex- pealed it in 1800. Delaware, Maryland, New Jersey, and

South Carolina established similar small funds between amination and encouraging a transition to a less ran- 1811 and 1817. For more details, see Butts, Public Educa- dom system . . . both in California and elsewhere."87 tion in the United States.

In a complex area like school finance, there may be important differences between decisions by the U S Supreme Court on the basis of the United States Constitution and decisions made by state supreme courts on the basis of state constitutions. If the U.S. Supreme Court had decided Rodriguez differently, it would have needed to articulate a single, uniform, national standard-probably either fiscal neutrality or equal per pupil expenditure. Neither standard seems flexible enough to accommodate the various purposes that a well-designed school finance system must serve, including both tax reform and school im- provement. However, state supreme courts, whether overruling or upholding state school finance statutes, have encouraged a reexamination of the state role in school finance and in education generally-a reex- amination that has led to significant changes.

NOTES

'The constitutions of 40 states clearly mandate that the legislature "establish," "maintain," "support," or "pro- vide for" some sort of system of public schools. There is some ambiguity about the constitutions of Iowa, Louisi- ana, Maine, Massachusetts, Mississippi, New Hamp- shire, New Mexico, Rhode Island, Tennessee, and Ver- mont. For example, Article IX, Section 6 of the Iowa Constitution provides that "The Legislature shall en- courage, by all suitable means, the promotion of intcllcc- tual, scientific, moral and agricultural improvcnicnt" (emphasis added). However, Section 12 of the same Arti- cle goes on to require that "The Board of Education shall provide for the education of all the youths of the State, through a system of Common Schools."

2San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. l(1973).

3See Lorraine McDonnell and Susan Fuhrman, "The Po- litical Context of Reform," in Van D. Mueller and Mary P. McKeown, eds., The Fiscal, Legal and PoliticalAspects of State Reform of Elementary and Secondary Education (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Ballinger Publishing Com- pany, 1986), pp. 43-64.

4The seven were Delaware, Georgia, Massachusetts, New Hampshire, North Carolina, Pennsylvania, and Ver- mont.

5It is interesting to note that this mandatory provision was not included when Pennsylvania wote a new constitu- tion in 1970; rather, it was replaced with permissive lan-

1OFor an excellent discussion of the role of the private academies, see Michael B. Katz, Class, Bureaucmcy and Schools (New York: Praeger Publishers, 1971). On the struggle over who should control the schools, see Diane Ravitch, The Great School Wars: New Yo& City, 1805-1973 (New York: Basic Books, 1974), esp. pp. 3-79.

l2See Butts, Public Education in the United States. 13Today, the most popular language is "general and uni-

form," used by seven states, and "thorough and effi- cient," also used by seven states. Other phrases in use in- clude "general, suitable and efficient," "thorough and uniform," "general and efficient," "uniform," "general, uniform, and thorough," "complete and uniform," and simply "efficient."

141n addition to Michael Katz's Class, Bureaucmcy and Schools, see also his detailed study of developments in Massachusetts, The Irony of Early School Reform (Bos- ton: Beacon Press, 1968).

'=The character of a state's involvement in education ap- pears to be a function of its political culture, its pattern and time of settlement, and its geography. For a study of the continuing impact of these factors on state education policy, see Frederick Wirt, "School Policy, Culture and State Decentralization," in Jay D. Scribener, ed., The Politics of Education (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977), pp. 164-187.

l6 E. P. Cubberley, School Funds and TheirApportionment (New York: Columbia University Teachers College, 1905). See also the later work of Cubberley's students, G. D. Straycr and K. M. Haig, The FinancingofEducation in the Sfale o fNew York (New York: The Macmillan Com- pany, 1923).

'7John Augenblick, "Taking Stock on School Finance Re- form: A State-Ievel Update," School Finance in the 1980s (Washington, DC: League of Women Voters Edu- cation Fund, 1982). p. 9.

j6See Paul R. Mort, State Support for Public Edzrcation (Washington, DC: The American Council on Educa- tion, 1933). Mort was also Cubberley's student at Colum- bia.

19For agood, brief explanation of foundation plans, see El- chanan Cohen, Economics of State Aid to Education (Lexington, Massachusetts: D.C. Heath and Company, 1974), pp. 50-52.

20The relationship between school district wealth and per pupil expenditure continues to evoke controversy. While there is a positive correlation between the two, local wealth is not the only determinant of spending. For a fuller discussion, See Patricia R. Brown and Richard F. Elmore, "Analyzing the Impact of School Finance Re-

Advisory commission on intergovernmental Relations 115

form," in Nelda H. Cambron-McCabe and Allan Odden, editors, The Changing Politics of School Finance (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Ballinger Publishing com- pany, 1982), pp. 107-138.

2l According to a study by the U.S. Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations, citizens rate the prop- erty tax as the "least fair." See Changing Public Attihrdes on Governments and Taws 1987 (Washington, DC: U.S. Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations, 1987), p. 5. In March 1972, the first date for which the data are available, 45 percent of Americans rated the property tax as the least fair.

Z2For a good discussion see, Frederick W. Wirt and Michael W. Kirst, Schools in Conflict IBerkelev. Califor- nia: ~ c ~ u t c h a n Publishing company, l%82), pp. 253-276.

Z3LeBeauf v. State Board of Education, 244 F.Supp 256 (1965).

24Ibid., 260. 25McInnis v. Shapiro, 293 F.Supp 327 (1968). ZeIbid., quoting Mr. Justice Holmes in Dominion Hotel v.

Arizona, 249 U.S. 265 (1919), 268. 27Burrus v. Wilkerson, 310 F.Supp 572 (1969). Z61bid., 572. 29Hargrave v. McKinney, 413 F2d 320 (1969). 30Askew v. Hargrave, 401 US. 475 (1971). 3'Van Dusartz v. Hatfield, 334 F.Supp 870 (1971). 32Rodriguez v. San Antonio Independent School District,

377 F2d 280 (1971). 33San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez

411 U.S. 1 (1973). 34 Judith Areen and Leonard Ross, "The Rodriguez Case:

Judicial Oversight of School Finance," in Philip B. Kur- land, ed., The Supreme Court Review 1973 (Chicago: Uni- versity of Chicago Press, 1974), p. 38.

35See, for example, Sawyer v. Gilmore, 109 Me. 169,83 Atl. 673 (1912); Miller v. Korns 107 Ohio St 287,104 N.E. 773 (1923), and; Ehret v. School District, 333 1%. 518,s A.W 188 (1939).

359 (1982); Board of Education v. Walter, 58 Ohio St. 368,390 N.E.2d 813 (1979); Olsen v. Oregon, 276 Ore. 9, 554 P.2d 139 (1976); Danson v. Casey, 484 Pa. 415, 399 A.2d 476,585 P.2d 71 (1978); Pauley v. Kelly, 162 W. Va. 672,255 S.E.2d 859 (1979); Buse v. Smith, 74 Wis.2d 550, 247 N.W.2d 141 (1976), and; Washakie County School District No. 1 v. Herschler, 606 P.2d 310 (1980).

43Arizona, Colorado, Georgia, Idaho, Kentucky, Mary- land, Michigan,* Montana, New York, Ohio, Oregon, and Pennsylvania. ereversing an earlier decision)

44Arkansas, California, Connecticut, Kansas, New Jersey, Washington; West Virginia, Wisconsin, and Wyoming. ereversing an earlier decision)

45Hornbeck v. Somerset County Board of Education. 461bid., 777. 47Lujan v. State Board of Education. 48Ibid., 1025. 49Board of Education v. Nyquist. 501bid., 369. 51 Thompson v. Engleking. 521bid., 640-41. 5301sen v. Oregon. 54Ibid., 155. 55Board of Education v. Walter. SBIbid., 821. 57Shofstall v. Hollins. 58People ex re1 James v. Adams, 40 Ill. App. 3d 189 (1976). 59 Woodahl v. Straub. 60Milliken v. Green. 61 Constitution of Washington, Article IX, Sections 1 and

2. 62Seattle School District No. 1 v. State. WIbid., 91. 64Horton v. Meskill. (?5Ibid., 816. 66Duprcc v. Alma School District No. 30. 67Constilution of Arkansas, Article XIV, Section 1.

- 1 - , 36Serrano v. Priest, 5 Cal.3rd 584, 584 P.2d 1241 (1971). 66Allan Odden and John Augenblick, School Finance Re-

37Ibid., 1252. form in the Slates: 1980 (Denver: Education Commission of the States, l980), p. 1.

381n Serrano v. Priest, 135 Cal.Rptr. 435 (19761, the trial 69FOr an analysis of the forces behind the school finance court also found the by then revised state school finance reform movement, see Susan Fuhrman, State Education law unconstitutional. Politics: The Case of School Fiance Reform (Denver: Edu-

3gRobinson v. Cahill, 62 N.J. 473,303 A.2d 273 (1972). cation Commission of the States, 1979), esp. pp. 15-20. 40New Jersev Constitution Article VIII, Section 4, ~ a r a . 1. 70There continues to be considerable debate about the 41 Ibid., 295. "equalizing" impact of school finance reform. For an in-

42Shofstall v. Hollins, 110 Ariz. 88, 515 P.2d 590 (1973); teresting analysis of the various meanings of equality, see

Dupree v. Alma School District No. 30,279 Ark. 340,651 the yearly reports published by the Education Commis-

S.W.2d 90 (1983); Serrano v. Priest, 5 Cal.3rd 584, 584 sion of the States under the title, School Finance Reform

P.2d 1241 (1971); Lujan v. State Board of Education, 649 in the States. See also, John E. Coons, "Recent Trends in

P.2d 1005 (1982); Horton v. Meskill, 172 Conn. 615,376 Science Fiction: Serrano among the People of Number,"

A.2d 359 (1977); Thomas v. McDaniels, 248 Ga. 632,285 in Roy C. Rist and Ronald J. Anson, eds., Education, So-

S.E.2d 156 (1981); Thomspon v. Engleking, 96 Ida. 793, cia1 Science and the Judicial Process (New York: Teachers

537 P.2d 635 (1975); Kansas v. State Board of Education, College Press, 1977), pp. 50-71, and Brown and Elmore,

219 Kan. 271,547 P.2d 699 (1976); Board of Education of "Analyzing the Impact of School Finance Reform."

Louisville v. Board of Education of Jefferson County, 71Computed from data in Allan Odden and John 458 S.W.2d 6 (1970); Hornbeck v. Somerset County Augenblick, School Finance Refonii in the States: 1980, p. Board of Education, 295 Md. 597,458 A.2d 758 (1983); 25. Milliken v. Green, 389 Mich. 1,203 N.W.2d 457 (1972); 72In Buse v. Smith. the Wisconsin Supreme Court struck Woodahl v. Straub, 164 Mont. 141,520 P.2d 776 (1974); such a "recapture" provision of the school finance law Robinson v. Cahill, 62 N.J. 473, 303 A.2d 273 (1972); because it violated the state constitutional requirement Board of Education v. Nyquist, 57 N.Y.2, 439 N.E.2d for "uniform taxation." On the other hand, the Montana

116 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Supreme Court upheld such a provision in Woodahl v. Strabu.

73For a description of the politics of school finance reform in California, see Fuhrman, State Edircation Politics: The Case of School Fiance Reform, pp. 50-60 and 72-78.

74Serrano v. Priest, 135 Cal .Rptr. 435,557 P2d 929 (1976). 75Serrano v. Priest, 226 Cal. Rptr. 584 (1986). 7%ee Diane Masell and Michael W. Kirst, "State Policy-

making for Educational Excellence: School Rcform in California," in Mueller and McKeown, The Fiscal, Legal and Political Aspects of State Rejbnn of Elenientary and Secondary Education, pp. 121-144.

77Ibid., p. 135. 78On school politics in Arkansas, see Diane D. Blair, Ar-

kansas Government and Politics: Do the People Ride? (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1988), pp. 252-263.

79On the politics of school finance reform in Connecticut, see Ellis Katz, American Education 1980: A Kewfrom the States (Washington, DC: Institute for Educational Lead- ership, 1981), pp. 14-17.

80On New Jersey, see Richard Lehne, Tlie Quest forJmtice: The Politics of School Finance Reform (New York: Longman, 1978).

81 See James G. Ward and Charles J. Santelli, "The Politi- cal Economy of Education Reform in New York," in Mueller and McKeown, The Fiscal, Legal and Political Aqectsof State Reform of Elementary and Secondary Edrr- cation, pp. 203-222.

@See Deborah A. Verstegen, Richard Hooker, and Nolan Estes, "A Comprehensive Shift in Educational Policy- making: Tcxits Educational Reform Legislation," in Muellcr and McKeown, The Fiscal, Legal and Political Aspectsof State Kefonn of Elementary and Secondary Edu- cation, pp. 277-308.

83Ibid., p. 300. 841bid., pp. 298-304. 85Ibid., 284. 86Areen and Ross, "The Rodriguez Case: Judicial Over-

sight of School Finance," p. 54. 87 Ibid., p. 55.

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 117

118 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

Chapter 10

State Constitutional Law: The Ongoing Search for Unity and Diversity - -

in the American Federal System The invention of American federalism in 1787

represented an attempt to provide for both unity and diversity: unity to meet the foreign and domestic chal- lenges that confronted the new nation, and diversity to accommodate the expanse of the nation and to maintain state and local political arenas in which citi- zens could make meaningful decisions. In the words of Daniel J. Elazar:

Federalism involved the linking of individu- als, groups, and polities in lasting but limited union in such a way as to provide for the en- ergetic pursuit of common ends while main- taining the respective integrities of all par- ties.'

The pursuit of both unity and diversity is quite com- patible. Unity and diversity are not opposites: the op- posite of unity is disunity, while the opposite of diver- sity is uniformity.

This does not deny the need for some uniformity, although it is clearly secondary to the need for unity. There are ways in which it is desirable to treat indi- viduals uniformly, and certainly there are occasions when the requirements of a national economy man- date uniform rules. For at least three reasons, how- ever, federalism also places high value on diversity. First, diversity in public policies reflects thc plur a I' ~ s m of the nation itself, in terms of its complex history, culture, geography, and people. Second, diversity fosters experimentation, allowing states and locali- ties to try out a variety of solutions to increasingly complicated problems. Third, by allowing communi- ties to make important policy choices, we encourage participation and foster democratic citizenship.

However, recognizing the need for both uni- formity and diversity does not tell us when to opt for one rather than the other. While common sense and logic are sometimes helpful in sorting out the com- peting needs for uniformity and diversity, there is no

clear, rational formula to make the choice for us. In- stead, the choice is left to the political process-to courts, legislatures, and executive agencies.

The Supreme Court and the Search for Balance

The Supreme Court of the United States has played, and continues to play, an important role in balancing the needs for uniformity and diversity. Chapter 2 of this study explored contemporary feder- alism doctrines of the U.S. Supreme Court and sug- gests that the Court's solicitude toward "Our Feder- alism" may create new opportunities for state economic policies. Although the situation is complex and still evolving, carefully drawn state statutes can pass constitutional muster under the Court's current doctrines of preemption, the dormant power of the commerce clause, and the takings, due process, and equal protection clauses of the Fourteenth Amend- ment.

Similarly, as suggested in chapters 4 and 6, the U.S. Supreme Court seems willing to show greater deference to diversity in crucial areas of state civil rights and liberties policy. The most promising devel- opment for federalism in this area is the doctrine of adequate and independent state grounds, under which thc U.S. Supreme Court will not review state court dccisions il' they are based clearly and unambi- guously on state, rather than federal constitutional grounds. The obvious implication of this doctrine is that if state policies are to be insulated from federal review, state court judges must base their decisions on their state constitutions.

It needs to be stressed that these Supreme Court doctrines, both in the economic and civil liberties fields, are evolving. One cannot predict how these doctrines will be used in the future. Chapter 2 of this study concluded with Napoleon's observation that, "The tools belong to the man who can use them."The U.S. Supreme Court appears to have provided the

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 119

states with new opportunities to forge their own con- stitutional polices. The future of these opportunities depends, in large part, on how the states use them.

State Constitutional Traditions Not only do state constitutions differ in function

and style from the Constitution of the United States, they also differ among themselves. According to Daniel J. Elazar, American state constitutions follow six distinct patterns.2

1. The Commonwealth Pattern. Typical in the New England states, these constitutions "are basi- cally philosophic documents designed first and fore- most to set a direction for civil society and to express and institutionalize a theory of republican govern- ment. . . . These constitutions, as brief or briefer than the federal document, concentrate on setting forth the philosophic basis for popular government, guar- anteeing the fundamental rights of the individual and delineating the elements of the state's government in a few broad strokes."

2. The Commercial Republic Pattern. This pat- tern prevails in the Middle Atlantic states and the states to their immediate west. According to Elazar, "These states have built their constitutions upon a se- ries of compromises required by the conflict of ethnic and commercial interests and ideals created by the flow of various streams of migrants into their terri- tories, and the early development of commercial cit- ies. . . . These constitutions tend to be longer than those written in the commonwealth mold, primarily because the compromises written into them have had to be made explicit and presented in detail to soften potential conflicts between rival elements that have sharply divergent views of what is politically right and proper."

3. The Southern Contractual Pattern. Elazar notes that except for North Carolina and Tennessee none of the southern states has had fewer than five constitutions, and he then goes on to suggest that, "Southern state constitutions are designed to diffuse the formal allocation of authority among many of- fices in order to accommodate the swings between oligarchy and factionalism characteristic of Southern state politics. Perhaps because of the fluctuating bal- ance of factions in many of the Southern states, their citizens have been more tempted to write into their constitutions materials normally included in ordinary legislation."

4. The Civil Code Pattern. Reflecting its unique history, Louisiana's constitutions "have been more like the basic civil codes of European countries-long [and] detailed."

5. The Frame of Government Pattern. Found among the less populated states of the Far West, these constitutions "are frames of government first and foremost. They reflect explicitly the republican and democratic principles dominant in the nation in

the late 19th century when their first constitutions were written, and then go on to specify the structure of state government and the distribution of powers within it in the style of the times. Their constitutions tend to be business-like documents of moderate length and reflect the relative homogeneity of the states themselves."

6. The Managerial Pattern. Written during the 19.50s, the constitutions of Alaska and Hawaii em- phasize "conciseness, broad grants of powers to the state executive branch, and relatively few structural restrictions on the legislature. Their constitutions also feature articles dealing with local government, natural resource conservation, and social legisla- tion."

This typology of state constitutional patterns is useful in many ways, particularly in reminding us that constitutions are not simple technologies that can be transferred from one setting to another. State consti- tutions, in Elazar's terms, connect "political ideas, political culture and institutional development." One finds both uniformity and diversity among state con- stitutions. Within each state constitutional pattern, one finds identical language and similarities in the application of such political ideas as the separation of powers. On the other hand, across patterns, one dis- covers considerable diversity in terms of the very pur- poses of government and the ways in which political authority is distributed, both among the branches of government and between the state and its communi- ties. Furthermore, even identical state constitutional provisions can have different meanings in different contexts. Thus, the phrase "a thorough and efficient system of public education" can take on different meanings within the contexts of different state con- stitutional traditions.

It is unlikely that this diversity among state con- stitutions threatens national unity or that a uniform- ity of state constitutions is either necessary or desir- able. The diversity of state constitutions is an expression both ol' the diversity of the nation itself and of the commitment of American federalism to al- low that diversity to be articulated in the most funda- mental ways.

State Constitutional Law and Individual Liberties

Whatever the merits of diversity among state constitutions, it is sometimes argued that we cannot accept diversity in matters of individual liberty. Americans, no matter where they live, are citizens of the United States, and must enjoy equally the rights guaranteed by the Constitution of the United States. The unstated premise underlying this argument is often the belief that a national definition of rights will expand the scope of individual liberty. The states, quite simply, are not to be trusted in this area.

Chapter 4 of this study explored this argument in some detail. It suggests, first of all, that the definition of rights is not always a matter of more or fewer

120 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations

rights. Often, it is a matter of resolving a conflict be- tween rights, as in the right of reporters to refuse to reveal their news sources versus the right to a fair trial, and the conflict between free speech and the protection of private property. Different states have resolved these conflicts differently. Most important, where state courts have recognized the legitimacy of the rights claimed on both sides of a conflict, they have struck different balances between them, seek- ing to accommodate both claims in keeping with its own state constitutional tradition.

Furthermore, the argument that the states are incapable of protecting rights adequately seems to have little merit in the context of the 1980s. Chapter 4 points out that, today, the states often take the lead in defining and expanding individual liberty. Chapter 6, which focuses on criminal procedure, documents the extent to which the states have shown sensitivity to the rights of criminal defendants.

Today, a total dependence on the national gov- ernment for a uniform definition of rights would, in all likelihood, diminish the scope of individual liberty in the United States. The development of an inde- pendent state constitutional law of civil liberties, on the other hand, would not only be likely to expand in- dividual rights but would also encourage experimen- tation in developing appropriate balances when rights are in conflict.

State Constitutions and Equality The principal equality provision of the U.S. Con-

stitution is the equal protection clause of the Four- teenth Amendment, which provides: "No State shall. . . deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws." State constitutions, on the other hand, contain a variety of equality provi- sions, often designed to serve quite different pur- poses. Chapter 5 of this study demonstrates how state courts have interpreted these state constitutional equality provisions to reach decisions quite different from those reached by the U.S. Supreme Court inter- preting the federal Constitution. For example, an 11- linois court held that the state's no-fault automobile insurance plan, which required the owners of private automobiles to purchase the no-fault insurance but imposed limitations on tort recoveries of persons in- jured by any type of motor vehicle, violated the Illi- nois Constitution's prohibition against "special laws," and a New Jersey Court held that the state's prohibi- tion against the use of state money to pay for abor- tions violated the state constitution, despite the fact that the U.S. Supreme Court had held that such pro- hibitions do not violate the equal protection clause of the federal Constitution.

Furthermore, while the U.S. Supreme Court has all but abandoned the federal equal protection clause as a defense of property rights, state supreme courts continue to make substantial use of their state consti- tutional equality provisions to limit state regulation of property. Chapter 7 of this study reports almost

100 cases in the last 20 years in which state courts have struck down state economic regulations as vio- lating state constitutional equality provisions.

However, many people are concerned about the protection of racial, ethnic, and religious minori- ties-as well as about sex discrimination-under state constitutions. The preceding chapters suggest that the record of the states in this regard has been mixed. On the one hand, chapter 4 points out that 19 states had enacted equal pay laws before the Con- gress of the United States passed its equal pay law in 1963; that 17 states had fair housing laws prior to the passage of a national fair housing law in 1968; and that 19 states have constitutional prohibitions against sex discrimination despite the failure to add a federal equal rights amendment to the U.S. Constitution in the 1970s. On the other hand, while chapter 5 reports on some major state supreme court decisions under their state ERAS, state supreme courts, by and large, continue to look to the U.S. Supreme Court for lead- ership in this field. Clearly, the richness of state con- stitutional equality provisions provides opportunity (and perhaps even a mandate) for state courts, as well as state legislatures and executives, to address these concerns.

State Constitutional Law and the Regulation of Property

Since 1937, the U.S. Supreme Court has allowed the states a relatively free hand in the regulation of property. State courts, as chapter 7 reports, continue to play an important role in the forging of state regu- latory policy. Employing state due process, equal pro- tection, or right-to-remedy clauses, state supreme courts have stuck down more than 350 state statutes since the U.S. Supreme Court all but abandoned the field in 1937. One should not conclude from this, however, that statc supreme courts are the captives of powerful, vested economic interests.

First, as chapter 3 of this study reminds us, state constitutions are designed primarily to limit legisla- tive authority. Because the states are the repositories of all power not delegated to the federal government, state constitutions are filled with limitations on the exercise of state power, and go into considerably more detail about the protection of personal and property rights than does the U.S. Constitution.

Second, because state constitutions are much easier to change than is the U.S. Constitution, judi- cial activism by state judges does not pose the same counter-majoritarian problem as would similar activ- ism by the federal judiciary. State constitutions are amended regularly as the public mood shifts.

These and other arguments about the proper role of the state judiciaries in the protection of prop- erty rights are detailed in chapter 7 of this study. However one resolves this difficult issue, it may be that the participation of state judges in the develop- ment of state public policies is quite different from the participation of the federal judiciary in state

Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations 121

policymaking. Clearly, the federal judiciary has cer- tain national interests to protect; it must, for exam- ple, assure that the economic policies of one state do not discriminate against the economic interests of the other states. On the other hand, state constitutions, written and ratified by state citizens, define the scope of state policy and the role of state courts in adjudi- cating disputes. Some state constitutions provide very detailed protections of property rights and clearly as- sign to the judiciary the role of enforcing them. Often, these constitutions are fairly easy to amend, and unpopular state supreme court decisions can be reversed through the amendment process. In a very immediate sense, decisions about the legitimacy of public policy and the role of the courts remain with the state and its citizens.

State Constitutional Law and Public Policy

Not only do state constitutions limit state legisla- tive authority, they also sometimes mandate legisla- tive action. In the two areas of public policy examined in this study-workers' compensation in chapter 8 and educational reform in chapter 9-both state con- stitutional limitations and mandates served as the framework for the development of state policy. With regard to workers' compensation, a few state su- preme courts looked to state constitutional right-to- remedy clauses to create exceptions to the exclusivity requirement of their workers' compensation statutes. In other words, they used a constitutional right as a limit on state constitutional authority. On the other hand, several state supreme courts turned to the con- stitutional mandate that the legislature provide for "a thorough and efficient system of public education" to strike down what they perceived to be inadequate fi- nancing and supervision of public education.

In neither case did the courts act alone; rather, they entered into what might be termed a dialogue with the political branches of government to bring about what many considered to be much needed change. Put somewhat differently, the state supreme courts did not, by themselves, make public policy; in- stead, by interpreting their own state constitutional limitations and mandates, they placed important pol- icy questions on the political agcndas of their states and continued to participate in the poli~ymaking process within the framework of their own state con- stitutional requirements.

It is also worth noting that these are two impor- tant policy areas that remain outside of the purview of the federal Constitution and the federal judiciary. Indeed, in the 1970s, the Congress of the United States deliberately decided not to enact a national workers' compensation statute, and the U.S. Su- preme Court, in 1973, held that the alleged inequities of state school finance schemes did not violate the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amend- ment to the federal Constitution. Thus, the reform of both workers' compensation plans and school finance

systems was left to the states. In both cases, state con- stitutional provisions and state political processes ap- pear adequate to the task of bringing about signifi- cant change.

This lack of federal involvement also raises the issue of what has been termed "horizontal federal- ism"-the diffusion of innovations among the states without significant participation by the federal gov- ernment. Judicial doctrines concerning school fi- nance diffused rapidly among the states, while court rulings on workers' compensation have spread more slowly. In both instances, the states, in adopting these innovations, have adapted them to their own needs and constitutional traditions.

Unity, Uniformity, and Diversity

Every coin of the United States carries the Latin inscription, "E Pluribus UnumV-translated as "one out of many."3 This commitment to both unity (the "one") and diversity (the "many") captures the value underlying American federalism. The American states function within the overarching framework of the U.S. Constitution and the values it embodies. At the same time, the American states are polities, em- powered by the U.S. Constitution to make policy choices in keeping with their own needs, cultures, and traditions. In keeping with this commitment to diversity, the states adopt their own constitutions ac- cording to their particular circumstances and govern themselves in conformity with their constitutional choices. As this study has demonstrated, there is con- siderable diversity in how the states structure their governmental processes and in how state courts in- terpret these basic charters.

Critics sometimes argue that either the federal Constitution has become so comprehensive that there is little room left for meaningful constitutional choices by the states, or that to the extent that there continue to be gaps in the federal Constitution, they ought to be filled quickly because the states are sure to misuse their power. We hope that this study has answered both of these criticisms and demonstrated that the states have considerable constitutional space, and, by and large, that they use it responsibly.

Daniel J. Elazar, E~ploring Federalism (Tuscaloosa: Uni- versity of Alabama Press, 1987) p. 5.

2Daniel J. Elazar, "Principles and Traditions Underlying American State Constitutions," Publilcs: the Jo1rn7al of Federalism 12 (Winter 1982): 11-26.

3Actually, there are five inscriptions on each American coin: the denomination, the word "Liberty," and the phrases "In God We Trust." "United States of Amer- ica," and "E Pluribus Unum." For an interesting analysis of America based on these five inscriptions, see John Kincaid, "E Pluribus Unum: Pluralist Diversity and Fed- eral Democracy in America," in Stephen L. Schechter, ed., Teaching about Atrierican Federal Democracy (Phila- delphia: CSF Associates, 1984), pp. 33-48.

122 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations U S GOVERNMENTPRINTING OFFICE 1989 - 624-017 - L302110299