The Changed Welfare Paradigm: The Individualization of The Social

25
Social Policy & Administration issn 0144—5596 Vol. 31, No. 1, March 1997, pp. 20–44 The Changed Welfare Paradigm: The Individualization of The Social Zsuzsa Ferge Abstract The first part of this paper offers a cumulative review of the changes in global objectives and operating principles and their global consequences, characteristic of the shift from the ideal type of the modern welfare state to the neo-liberal or post-modern paradigm. The paper then spells out some of the implications of this shift for social security in the “transition countries” of Central and Eastern Europe. The tendencies (from marketiza- tion to the spread of means-testing) are similar to those in the West; but they are much more marked and there is much less political and popular resistance to these changes. One of the crucial ingredients of the shift is the undermining of the age-old solidarity between generations, a trend also strongly recommended by the supranational agencies. The “catch”, or the “paradox of democracy” is that, for all the lack of resistance, people do not seem to approve of the rapid withdrawal of the state and the loss of their existential securities. Keywords Neo-liberalism; Post-modernism; Welfare statism; Central/Eastern Europe transition The collapse of state socialism came too late, and not only because it meant that those living in it had to live for too long in a bad political and economic system. From the perspective of this paper it came too late because, by the time of its advent, any post-war welfare consensus was by and large over in the West, and the ideas of the New Right were gaining ground and respectability everywhere. At the time of the revolutions of 1956 (Budapest), or even of 1968 (Prague), the “left” values of the Enlightenment could still play an important role, and “existing socialism” could be denounced as a sham and criticized as such in the name of “socialism with a human face”. In the new international climate of 1990 this was no longer possible: the rejection of “existing socialism” had to be categorical. The void created thereby has been filled by a more or less explicit social project derived from the old-new neo-liberal (Manchester liberal) ideology. This ideology has been slowly permeating all walks of life. Address for Correspondence: Professor Zsuzsa Ferge, Institute of Sociology and Social Policy, Eo ¨tvo ¨s Lorand University, 1088 Muzeum krt. 4/c, Budapest, Hungary. ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.

Transcript of The Changed Welfare Paradigm: The Individualization of The Social

Social Policy & Administration issn 0144—5596Vol. 31, No. 1, March 1997, pp. 20–44

The Changed Welfare Paradigm:The Individualization of The Social

Zsuzsa Ferge

AbstractThe first part of this paper offers a cumulative review of the changes in global objectivesand operating principles and their global consequences, characteristic of the shift from theideal type of the modern welfare state to the neo-liberal or post-modern paradigm. Thepaper then spells out some of the implications of this shift for social security in the“transition countries” of Central and Eastern Europe. The tendencies (from marketiza-tion to the spread of means-testing) are similar to those in the West; but they are muchmore marked and there is much less political and popular resistance to these changes. Oneof the crucial ingredients of the shift is the undermining of the age-old solidarity betweengenerations, a trend also strongly recommended by the supranational agencies. The“catch”, or the “paradox of democracy” is that, for all the lack of resistance, people donot seem to approve of the rapid withdrawal of the state and the loss of their existentialsecurities.

KeywordsNeo-liberalism; Post-modernism; Welfare statism; Central/Eastern Europe transition

The collapse of state socialism came too late, and not only because it meantthat those living in it had to live for too long in a bad political and economicsystem. From the perspective of this paper it came too late because, by the timeof its advent, any post-war welfare consensus was by and large over in theWest, and the ideas of the New Right were gaining ground and respectabilityeverywhere. At the time of the revolutions of 1956 (Budapest), or even of 1968(Prague), the “left” values of the Enlightenment could still play an importantrole, and “existing socialism” could be denounced as a sham and criticized assuch in the name of “socialism with a human face”. In the new internationalclimate of 1990 this was no longer possible: the rejection of “existing socialism”had to be categorical. The void created thereby has been filled by a more or lessexplicit social project derived from the old-new neo-liberal (Manchesterliberal) ideology. This ideology has been slowly permeating all walks of life.

Address for Correspondence: Professor Zsuzsa Ferge, Institute of Sociology and Social Policy, Eotvos

Lorand University, 1088 Muzeum krt. 4/c, Budapest, Hungary.

¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and

350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.

The impact of the new ideology on social policy is well known (e.g. Block etal. 1987, Bosanquet 1983, Pierson 1992). Here we dwell on the theme for tworeasons. First, focusing on the developed countries (the “first world”), we workthrough the implications of the ideological shift for those aspects of social lifewhich impact directly or indirectly not only on social security but also on socialintegration. Second, and following on from this, we try to spell out some of theconsequences of this shift for the countries undergoing societal transformationin Central and Eastern Europe.

The Modern Versus the Post-modern Welfare Paradigm

The dream of the “good society”—the ambitious plan of Beveridge, the idealwelfare state—never fully materialized. Instead there have been differenttypes of “welfare states” (Wilensky and Lebeaux 1965, Titmuss 1974,Esping-Andersen 1990), attaining varying degrees of success in the pursuit ofsuch grand objectives as the eradication of poverty or the reduction ofinequality. There are many possible explanations for the post-war welfareconsensus, such as it was, which emerged none the less. Wartime experienceand the ensuing solidarity, the competition with “existing socialism”, aseemingly unlimited increase in economic resources from the mid-1950s on,the strengthening of civil society: these may all have played a part. However,we do not want to deal with the causes here, rather with the processes involved.

Manifestly, the welfare consensus was never complete. There had alwaysbeen “dissenters”—as analysed for instance by Hirschman (1991). But thenear-consensus was expressed in the dominant political discourse, in theproducts of mainstream social science, and, most importantly, in the votes ofcitizens. The essence of the consensus was the modern liberal belief in theperfectibility of society,1 in the existence of rational means to reduce injusticeswithout gravely harming freedoms. It was also a shared belief that the statehad a major role to play in the implementation of this project.

On the basis of these assumptions, one may construct an “ideal type” of themodern European welfare regime, describing its major features including theproject itself, its goals, its actors, its institutions, its instruments, and some ofits social implications on the national and global level.

The welfare consensus started to dissolve from the mid-1970s on. Onceagain we do not concentrate on the causes of this process or attempt to weighup the respective roles of economic factors (such as the slowing down ofeconomic growth or the sharpening of international competition), politicalfactors (such as the collapse of the Soviet bloc) or social factors (ranging fromthe waning of wartime solidarity to the tax-revolt of the rich). Instead we focuson the outcome of the changes. As with the “modern” paradigm, an attemptwill be made to construct the new “ideal type” of society and of the socialpolicy which goes with it, termed alternatively by different authors neo-liberal,post-Fordist, post-industrial or post-modern (Taylor-Gooby 1995, Therborn1995). Once again, this is a paradigm which has not actually been fullyimplemented anywhere. Rather, one may observe everywhere a processleading in this direction, with perhaps a hidden agenda characterized by neo-liberal values and impregnated with the interests of national and international

21¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

capital. One of the economic advisers working in Hungary since the transitionsummed up the new project, in effect, when he observed: “Foreign advisersdeeply believe in Western capitalism. As far as the philosophical basis of theirthinking is concerned, including the basic values impacting on it, they areliberal in the sense that they highly value individual freedom of decision-making and individual responsibility. They also believe that the welfare state isdead.” (Major 1996, emphasis added)

Cumulative Table: The change of paradigm with regard to systems of social policy:Basic characteristics of two ideal typesa

Part 1Global project for the transformation of the Social State:b

Major objectives

Topics of thesocietal project

Old paradigm of the 20th century

The modern “European” socialstate

New paradigm of post-industrialism or

post-modernism

Approach tosocial reproduc-tion

Endorsement of collective responsi-bility for social reproduction(humans, goods, institutions, rela-tionships) to some degree—bymeans of various forms of genuine orenforced solidarity (between gen-erations, within and betweengroups, etc.)

Individualized responsibility for so-cial reproduction

Explicit rejection of collective re-sponsibility and of “impersonal”,i.e. group, intergenerational solid-arity

Social inequali-ties

Efforts to control and if possible toreduce the inequalities of social andphysical life chances, the transmis-sion of social disadvantages

Unchecked thriving of inequalitiesin the name of individual freedom ofchoice

Acceptance of unemployment,poverty, segmentation, marginal-ization

Economicpurpose

Economic equilibriumAt least partial satisfaction of

needs agreed upon by public con-sensus which are inadequatelycovered by the market

Economic growthIncrease of productivity and

economic efficiency

Quality of society An integrated society (efforts prothe reduction of segregation anddisaffiliation)

Social cohesion to reduce socialconflicts, to ensure internal socialpeace (co-operation)

No particular concern for socialintegration (“There is no such thingas society”)

National and international com-petitiveness

a The summary table is inspired by a lecture of Goran Therborn at the Bielefeld meeting in 1995 ofthe European School on Historical and Comparative Sociological Research of Social Policy, andshamelessly uses the insights of various authors.b In using the expression of “social state” instead of welfare state I follow the suggestion of RobertCastel (1995).

22 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

The old and the new project

The two paradigms will be compared in a composite cumulative table to be setout in five parts. Part 1 highlights the main topics or key themes of both the oldand the new paradigms. The component parts are almost self-explanatory, atleast if it is assumed that such complex phenomena as social or humanreproduction, social integration or solidarity are understood in a similar wayby the average reader (if such exists). In the approach followed here, socialreproduction offers a convenient framework to analyse social processes andpotential conflicts, and also to locate various subsystems within it. Even moreimportantly, it suggests (as I have argued elsewhere, Ferge 1979) that socialpolicy may have a strong link with, and important functions to fulfil inconnection with, human and social reproduction. The connecting linkbetween social policy and social reproduction is the dual concept of physicaland social life chances.2 Physical life chances refer to the length of life one mayexpect in the different walks of life and to the sufferings one has to live with.(Not only in relatively poor countries, but even in France unskilled workers of35 have a life expectancy which is ten years shorter than that of professionals.)Social life chances refer to the probability one has of attaining a better or worsesocial position and to the degree of freedom and autonomy one has in choosinga life course or career. Clearly life chances also depend on the presence orabsence of enabling conditions. Both research and logic suggest thatinequalities of physical and social life chances may be reduced when there isdeliberate social intervention directed to this end (Ferge and Miller 1987).

In short, the new project is about the withdrawal from social commitmentsand hence, by implication, about the rejection of the importance of anintegrated society or even of society: the individualization of the social (Guillem-ard 1986, Rosanvallon 1995).

Dominant institutions and operating principles

The main changes in the dominant institutions and operating principles at thesocial level follow from the objectives of the new paradigm. The key institutionof the new world is, obviously, the market, with as little public intervention aspossible. The ideal type of a democratically organized nation state hadbecome, during the last century, a field of forces wherein the state (politicalpower), the market, and “civil society” held each other in check in order tocorrect the failures of each, and especially to prevent domination of one sphere,or one logic, over all the others. The concepts of “social state”, or of welfarestate, or of a social market economy all refer to this state of affairs. Theequilibrium between these forces has always been a delicate matter, but it isbeing rapidly undermined by the new paradigm. Out of the three pillars of theformer delicate balance, the market is gaining ground at the expense of the twoother forces. Also, as the economy is becoming increasingly globalized, thestructure of the market is changing: multinational firms and supranationaleconomic agencies tend to dominate the former national market actors. AsRiccardo Petrella puts it: “The enterprise acquires a new historical legitimacyinasmuch as it has been granted by the state the function of safeguarding and

23¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

promoting the well-being of the ‘local’ society. In so doing the enterpriseprivatizes and internationalizes, for its own ends, the social role of the state.”(Petrella 1995).

The increasing role of the market has at least two structural or macro-levelimplications worth mentioning. One concerns economic rationality. Out ofthe possible logics or rationalities of the economy as analysed by Weber,formal rationality is becoming dominant. Also, formal rationality which is stillrather broadly defined by Weber, as “capable of being expressed in numerical,calculable terms” (Weber 1968, quoted in Wallerstein 1996: 13) is reducedto its purest type. In the modern self-regulating market (Polanyi 1994)calculation means, in fact, the optimization of inputs and outputs, or themaximization of profit. Other rationalities are superseded by this formalmarket rationality. Substantive rationality as defined by Polanyi (Dalton1968) is lost sight of altogether. This one-sided approach excludes from thepost-modern paradigm the assessment of the outcome of economic activityagainst “certain criteria of ultimate ends” (Weber 1968); namely some valuescale such as, for instance, the satisfaction of needs or the distribution of theresults of economic activity.

The other implication is that the formal rationality of the market is imposedon all or most other subspheres of social reproduction, supplanting their owninherent operating principles or relatively autonomous logics. Works of art,the organization of Oxford colleges,3 the activities of social policy, or even themost insignificant acts of everyday life are all subjected to the profitabilitycalculus. This tendency is expressed in the widely quoted slogan of MiltonFriedman suggesting that there is no such thing as a free lunch, or in the moresophisticated analysis of Jurgen Habermas about the “colonization of the life-world” by the market (Habermas 1981).

With all these moves, another important key concept of post-modernity—pluralism—becomes almost self-defeating. A paradox occurs. The perva-sive new ideology exalts freedom: the importance of the freedom of choice ofindividuals, the rejection of monopolistic or uniform solutions, in short,pluralism in all fields. (Incidentally, theories of post-modernity suggest thatthe decoupling of structural determinism and autonomous individual self-determination is not only possible, but the essence of post-modern societies.)These ideas and ideals are attractive and challenging. In reality, though, thereare factors which seem to impose hardening constraints on the scope forautonomous choices and pluralistic solutions. One of them concerns thepoor—whether increasingly poor countries, or the increasingly poor in richcountries—whose freedom of choice is restricted or made altogether void bylack of means. The other factor limiting choice is the increasingly pervasiveand monolithic ideology about the unquestionable superiority of a market-driven world. It is repeatedly suggested for instance by home-bred liberals andsupranational agencies that, instead of a wide variety of welfare regimes whichhave always been marked by home forces and traditions (or path-dependencyin the term of David Stark), there exists allegedly just one “right” social policyfully compatible with a market economy.

Obviously, the values underpinning the “modern” and the “post-modern”ideology are also radically different. Over and above “equality”, which seems

24 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

to have become obsolete in the post-modern world, two other values are alsolosing ground in a big way. One of them is solidarity (whether spontaneous orenforced), implying an acceptance of some common interest and horizontallyshared “sacrifice” or responsibility to make this interest prevail. The rejectionof solidarity is made possible by the widespread acceptance of the propriety ofthe exclusive pursuit of the individual’s interest. Post-modern ideology doesnot of course justify selfishness per se. The legitimization is done through thedefinition of the characteristics of the “post-modern individual” who “adopts apost-modern anti-causal point of view because s/he has no desire to assumeresponsibility or insist on his/her role as an agent. . . . In the absence of causeand effect, the post-modern individual cannot be held personally accountablebecause things ‘just happen’.” (Vaillancourt Rosenau, quoted in Vaillan-court Rosenau and Bredemeier 1993: 361).

The other value which seems to fall into disrepute is the search forexistential security by collective means. Instead, individual security has to beassured—if one feels necessary to ensure it at all and is able to do so—byindividually, hence freely chosen, instruments. For those who are unable toassure themselves (and who may well coincide with those who are thought tolack the “modern” trait of long-term rationality “to defer gratification”) theremay remain something of the former collective arrangements. These mayconsist of no more than a minimum level of compulsory insurance of health orpensions which (as precedents show) may be well below any acceptablestandard if they are the only resource. When even this fails, there remains the

Cumulative Table: Part 2Dominant institutions and operating principles at the level of the nation state

Old paradigm New paradigm

Dominantinstitutions

Market, state, civil society Markets and quasi-marketsInternational corporations and

supranational agencies

Dominanteconomic ration-ality

Substantive and formal Formal

Relationships be-tween socialsubsystems

Relative autonomy of subsystems(economy, culture, law, socialpolicy, etc.) as for their finality,function, logic or “substantive ra-tionality”

Supremacy (domination) of theeconomy and its formal rationality

(“Colonization of the life-world”and of all subsystems)

Underlyingvalues of social(societal) policy

Justice and social equityReduction of social inequalitiesSolidarity (ingrained or

enforced)Absolute and relative existential

security at the individual and coll-ective level

Individual freedom (Freedom tochoose)

CompetitivenessIndividual autonomy and re-

sponsibility for present and futuresecurity

At most minimal existentialsecurity by public means

25¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

charitable gift of benevolent organizations or individuals. Part 2 of thecumulative table sums up these principles and processes.

Instruments of social policy

The new trend entails a fundamental transformation of the former instrumentsof social policy. Universal solutions or access tied to citizenship or residence arealtogether repudiated by the new paradigm. Social insurance based onemployment and contribution paid is to undergo fundamental changes so as tobecome more “market-conforming”. It has to be purged as much as possiblefrom its solidaristic or redistributive components; its level and scope arereduced in order to make way for private insurance. An important corollary ofthe weakening of social insurance is the erosion of real or virtual “socialproperty”.4 It is a key institution: the social property constituted by socialinsurance is a forceful countervailing factor of private ownership (Castel1995).

The void created by the abolition of universal benefits and the curtailmentof social insurance provisions is occupied by social assistance selectivelyoffered to the “truly needy”. The move affects benefits in cash, in kind, andalso in services. The problem is that, if social assistance is financed by publicmoney, it is also a form of social solidarity, even if constrained. Hence theencouragement of private charity and the moral gloss attached to it. In orderto give incentives to it, tax benefits may be offered, entailing reverseredistribution and an invisible welfare state. This, however, is seldomcondemned by the critics of the visible welfare state (Kvist and Sinfield 1996).

The process involved implies the delegitimation not only of the technique,but also of the raison d’etre of collective protection against collective risks. Eventhe aspiration to collective security is denounced as the denial of freedom.According to Peter Ambros for instance: “Freedom is related to adulthood inthe same way as security is to dependency” (Ambros 1994, quoted in Ferge1996).

There is clearly a paradox here. Social insurance had been invented orgeneralized when (1) the new risks of an industrial, mass society emerged, andwhen (2) the old ties linking generations and small communities together, andinsuring thereby a sort of “natural” solidarity, started to weaken or fall apart.But the risks, if anything, have become larger in the post-Fordist world forinstance with seminal changes on the labour market (e.g. with mass unem-ployment and “atypical” jobs), and solidaristic networks even further eroded.If such facts are taken into account, it is hard to find rational reasons to justifythe deliberate destruction of the institutions of collective protection. Yet, socialinsurance is seen to have become superfluous.

Another aspect of the change of instruments is that the new climate is nonetoo favourable to social rights, which are not considered real rights (Sunstein1994). One possible cause for this antipathy is that these so-called positiverights are allegedly much more costly than the “negative” rights. Freedomrights belonging to the first generation of rights are often seen as not requiringactive state intervention and as therefore “inexpensive”. Another argument,particularly valid in the case of the transition countries (as discussed below),

26 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

emphasizes that social rights—even if included in a constitution—cannot beimplemented. Hence to declare them is to undermine constitutionalism (Arato1996).

However counter-arguments are also appearing. It is pointed out that theenforcement of civil and political rights is also costly, because their im-plementation requires elections and a parliament as well as police, courts andprisons (Coote 1992). Some maintain that the implementation of minimalsocial rights depends more on political will than on material resources (Juhasz1995). The onslaught on social rights certainly weakens the unconditionalright to life which formed an integral part of the social democratic project ofthe social state which used to be described as decommodification (Esping-Andersen 1990). If anything, the complete disappearance of this term is amarker of the new times.

Meanwhile, there used to be another value or right appearing in legislationaround the time of the Enlightenment: the right to dignity. While this wouldseem to be the foundation of modern citizenship, and a key term in modernsocial policy discourse,5 I have found (up to now) amazingly little on theinterpretation and the implications of this concept. Yet if ways of life surelyincompatible with human dignity such as begging, homelessness or garbagesearch (rummaging through the garbage cans of others—a spreading practicein many towns of Eastern Europe) are becoming so widely accepted as to seem“natural”, then surely something is wrong with human dignity.

However, while the rights of the poor seem to weaken, there is undeniableprogress in the acknowledgement of the rights of groups or minorities whichare newly emerging or gathering strength. Women have been the first to makereal headway. More recently, less numerous groups have followed suit,including homosexuals, handicapped people and others. There is probably arelationship between post-modernism and the recognition of the right to differ.But the new trend is related to the rejection of the “modern” categories of classor social determinism in general.

The erosion of the social state may be perhaps better understood if oneapplies a “modern” sociological frame of reference. It seems that elements ofpublic redistribution which do not serve the “enlightened self-interest” ofrelatively strong and vocal groups are hard to defend against renewed attacks.The “trimming” of welfare benefits is relatively more frequent if the benefitserves only the poorer or less powerful groups (social assistance itself, but alsounemployment or sickness benefits for instance). See part 3 of the cumulativetable.

Old and new actors

With the alteration of values and institutions, the field of the actors and themodes of operation of social policy are also changing. The state—as alreadyimplied—is shedding its former load. It is diminishing its responsibilities forlegislating on social rights and for the enforcement of these rights. It is alsocurtailing its role with regard to financing social policy and delivering services.The first function is in part irreplaceable but is in part being reduced, via theregulation of the framework of the new welfare solutions, into one of “the

27¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

Cumulative Table: Part 3Changes in the instruments of social policy

Old paradigm New paradigm

Instruments Universal benefitsSocial security and social insur-

ance (public assistance included)“Social property” within social

insuranceSocial contractsCollective bargaining

Insurance:Public insurance on a minimal level,Private insurance encouraged

Assistance, public and private,Private charity encouragedBusiness contracts

Citizenship,rights

Social citizenship, combining civil,political and social, economic,cultural, etc. rights

Strong social rights (with a rightto appeal)

At least partial decoupling ofmarket contracts and the right to life(“decommodification”)

Emphasis on the right to dignity(even if in need of help)

Emphasis on civil and political,i.e. “negative” rights

Acknowledgement of (civil andpolitical) rights for “minorities”achieving visibility and voice(women, homosexuals, handicap-ped, etc.)

Weak or contested social rights,emphasis on purchased rights

management of pluralism”.6 Financing may remain a state function at least solong as “quasi-markets” are accepted as a solution (Le Grand and Bartlett1994). The other part of financing as well as service delivery is being shifted tofamilies, to the voluntary or NGO sector and ultimately to the market. Therole of the market is sure to increase thereby. The role of civil society may alsoincrease, but it is changing. It may become much more important as servicedeliverer, whilst its political function—that of giving voice to the claims of civilmovements—may weaken. This is likely to happen if the market plays itspost-modern role of “seduction” well (Bauman 1988), and/or if the media areendorsing fewer public functions as these become more and more marketized(Keane 1989).

Another aspect of this process is the attempt to subordinate the professionalexpertise and knowledge of the traditional “vocations” to technocratic(managerial) concerns. This process may be seen as rationally grounded. Thealmost feudal authority of the professions (the medical or the teachingprofessions for instance) is hardly compatible with the ongoing democratiza-tion of human relations. For the same reasons it is increasingly unacceptablethat the professions should dictate needs, or solutions to need satisfaction, inan authoritarian way. The professional gatekeepers, the professional lobbiesand such like may have bred distrust. Many professional arguments may havebeen self-serving, promoting the status and prestige of the professions ratherthan the interests of the client groups.

Furthermore, professionals have rarely been successful in managing scarceresources. They do not easily accept that, along with the substantiverationality of their own activity (for instance to give to the patient the best

28 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

possible medical care), they also have to reckon with the scarcity of resources.The allocation of resources requires “counting”—even if the profit motive(calculation with profit) cannot be reconciled with the substantive logic of theprofession.7

Professionals might have found adequate answers to the first type ofcriticism by weakening their own knowledge monopolies, by empowering theirclients, by realizing that their professional charisma should not be taken forgranted but should be “earned”. But they became defenceless in the face of theeconomic argument. The technocrats could take power from, and over, theprofessionals because the non-economic evaluation of the outcome of profes-sional activity is not compatible with the new paradigm. The takeover does noteliminate the former knowledge-monopoly and professional conceit, it merelyshifts them. A new professional group, namely the technocrats, starts todominate the more traditional professions. It is an open question what willhappen to traditional professional ethics under these conditions.

Alongside their professional roles, intellectuals also functioned traditionallyas critics of society. Over and above the safeguard and the transmission ofknowledge, it used always to be a function of intellectuals to formulatequestions concerning the status quo and to work out the answers, the so-calledheterodoxies offering new explanations and alternative world visions(Bourdieu 1977). This role (whether filled by intellectuals or by others) iscrucial in any society which does not consider itself perfect. However, the voiceof social critics seems to have become more feeble. One interpretation could beincreasing difficulties over access to the media. Furthermore one frequentlyhas the impression that the ruling political class of the liberal democracies isbecoming so self-assured as to feel entitled to ignore criticism even when it hasmass support. Yet again, there is a tentative explanation connected to the“paradox of democracy”, to the effect that, while the formal instances ofparticipation in public life are guaranteed, people increasingly withdraw frompolitics because they feel more and more impotent in relation to it. This mayhave to do with the distortion of the structure of public (and mass)communication as described by Habermas (1981). Also, the alienation frompolitics may be related to the process of globalization whereby the nationstates which used to be the designated centres of political life lose their grip ontheir own destiny, as their own citizens lose their hold on “their” state. Thecentre of power shifts upwards. And this, as Norbert Elias saw it, “increasesthe impotence of the individual in relation to what is happening at the top levelof humanity” (Elias 1991: 165). This may be a pervasive feeling in the case ofintellectuals too, particularly if they do not have potent organized allies.8

The transformation of the target groups (who may also be considered actorsin social policy) hardly needs additional explanation. If selectivity becomesthe main way of access, then the targets will be the “truly needy” instead of thecitizens or the insured persons. The former targets constituted collectivecategories, while the truly needy are only a disjoint set of individuals. This shiftrepresents a clear and explicit case of the individualization of the social. Thechange corrodes the power position of the beneficiaries of central redistribu-tion. Clearly, the possibility and hence the probability of the self-organizationof the scattered poor is slim.

29¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

The development of human resources as a legitimate objective is in allprobability related to the concern with increasing productivity and efficiency.This is a positive implication of the post-Fordist organization of production. Ithas, however, some equivocal features. The preoccupation with the immediateuse of knowledge may restrict the domain of legitimate learning. A moreserious consequence may be the indirect devaluation of those who may not beuseful for “productive” purposes. Those concerned are, in the first place, theelderly and people living with handicaps. The members of the second grouptry to react by organizing themselves, and have indeed obtained some rights inline with the new tolerance of difference. The ageing population is in a worsesituation. It seems to me that the increasingly loud rhetoric about theunsustainability of the current pension systems, and hence the necessity tolower the collective provisions for the elderly is related to their loss of economic

Cumulative Table: Part 4Changes at the level of actors

Old paradigm New paradigm

The role of theState

“Management” of social change(including social policy as an instru-ment of change)

Financing of the majority of con-sensually agreed needs

Legislation about, and guaranteeof, social rights

Production and delivery of ser-vices

“Management” of welfare plural-ism

Marginal (residual) financing ofthe welfare sector

Main agentsshaping the(social policy)system

State bureaucracy (of the nationstate)

Social movements, civil societyThe “Professions” (represen-

tatives of various sciences) and in-tellectuals

National and international bureau-crats and technocrats (managers)

The target groupsof social policy

Citizens (denizens)Insured personsDisadvantaged groups, families,

individuals

“Truly needy” and deserving indi-viduals or families

“Minorities” achieving visibility,expressing new needs (migrants,drug addicts, homosexuals, etc.)

Potentially productive workers(potential human capital)a

Main agents ofservice delivery

State—large extentFamily—varyingNon-profit sector, voluntary

agencies—varyingMarket—marginal

Market and quasi-market—dominant

Family and NGO sector—en-couraged

State—minimizedMedia—role increasing

a See Taylor-Gooby (1995), and also Commission on Social Justice (1994)

30 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

value.9 The rejection of intergenerational solidarity in the name of individualresponsibility is in all likelihood both a cause and a consequence of thedevaluation of the ageing population (see part 4 of the cumulative table).

Implications of the paradigmatic change at the global level

The shift from the old to the new paradigm has important repercussions at theglobal level also. At the national level, the actors in the three main spheres—the market, politics and civil society—could, under democratic conditions,co-operate and, at least to some extent, control and limit each others’“colonizing” endeavours, whereas at the global level this relative equilibriumamong different forces is weak or missing. The countervailing forces of themarket—“international governance” and international civil society—areweak, underdeveloped or non-existent. The comparison of the efficiency of theUN and of the IMF may illustrate this point. (About their relationship seeDeacon in Swaan 1994.)

Alongside the process of globalization and the integration of the worldeconomy, tendencies of fragmentation, polarization or disintegration are alsogaining ground. As Norbert Elias put it: “Human beings are at presentinvolved in an immense process of integration which not only goes handin hand with many subordinate disintegrations but can at any time give wayto a dominant disintegration process” (Elias 1991: 165). Integration means,amongst other things, that the locus of power is shifting upwards, fromthe smaller communities to the central state, and then to a global centreinvolving, as we have already pointed out, the “disempowerment” of in-dividuals.

Disintegration may take different forms and may be triggered by variedcauses. One of its aspects is the increasing income gap between the groups ofmore or less “developed” or developing countries (Townsend 1995). Out of the5.4 billion inhabitants of the Earth:

• 3.1 billion, close to 60% of mankind, live in the 40 poorest countries,with a per capita GDP of $US350 a year (only around $US100 inMozambique, Tanzania and Ethiopia);

• 1.4 billion, around 26%, live in the 62 middle-income countries with aper capita GDP between $US700 and 7000; and

• 0.8 billion, 15%, in the 22 richest countries. In the last group, theaverage per capita GDP is $US21,000, with Switzerland at the top,having $US33,600 per head per year (World Bank 1993).

The bottom has, thus, about 300 times less than the top. The implica-tions are manifold. The average life span in the poor countries is 25 to 30years less than in the richer countries. Thus the convergence so muchtalked about in the last decades seems to be fading away, giving way togrowing gaps between rich and poor countries—with consequences whichmay not be promising or reassuring in the long run (see part 5 of thecumulative table).

31¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

Cumulative Table: Part 5Consequences at the global level (“globalization”)

Old paradigm New paradigm

Interest negotia-tion at the globallevel

Efforts to harmonize varied inter-ests

Supremacy of the interests of inter-national (global) capital (the“international state” and “interna-tional civil society” are weak)

Relation betweenregions andcountries of vary-ing economicstrength

Efforts (not always successful) toreduce the economic gap betweencountries

Spontaneous “catching up” in somecases (East Asia); increase of thedevelopment gap elsewhere, be-tween regions and countries, centresand peripheries

Power relationsbetweencountries

Efforts to establish horizontal inter-national relations

Efforts to preserve the relativeautonomy of the nation states

Increase of power and influence ofsupranational political unions and(economic) agencies

Weakening of the autonomy ofthe nation states

Some Implications for Social Security in the “Transition Count-ries” of Central and Eastern Europe

Over-zealous alignment to the new expectations

The downgrading of the state and the cutting-back of welfare systems as beingthe main or only culprit with regard to public (over)spending are everywhereon the agenda. In the transition countries (or so it seems to me) the argumentssound more pervasive, perhaps more aggressive, than elsewhere and, at leastin some cases, there is a higher degree of compliance with the new ideologythan in the developed democracies of Western Europe. The causes of a moreassertive ideological style (used both by home and foreign ideologists) and ofless home resistance to the dismantling of the institutions of social policy aremanifold. A thorough analysis is much needed, which I am not ready orwilling to try to offer at this stage, lacking the necessary psychological andhistorical distance. Let me mention, though, some of the likely causes for this“overshoot”.

• The values underpinning social policy have become more dele-gitimated and/or more corrupted than in the stable liberal democracies. Thisis particularly true for values such as equality or solidarity. Since the press isgenuinely free in Hungary, for instance, the blueprint Social Justice (Commis-sion on Social Justice 1994) or the manifesto of French intellectuals,“Chomage, appel au debat” (Le Monde 1995), could have been published, butwould have met with hostile silence. Those who try to reaffirm those valuesand the instruments promoting them appear either as naive idealists yearningfor a turn to social democracy which seems to be irrevocably lost, or as zealotsnot for social policy or its basic values, but for the Stalinist past. The words of

32 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

Richard Rose highlight the point well. He argues for more selectivity and theabolition of broader systems of social protection in Central-Eastern Europe:

establishing universalistic and compulsory programmes of social protec-tion is popular today, but it is contrary to historical developments. Suchprogrammes were not initially provided in the West European welfarestates: they emerged after a half century of developments that startedwith contribution-funded programmes for those able to pay. EastEuropean systems today are at the start of a lengthy transition process, inwhich their fiscal and administrative resources are backward by compar-ison to Western Europe. To recommend that such societies introduce comprehen-sive and universalistic social protection programmes on the Scandinavian model is to bea welfare Bolshevik (Rose 1993, emphasis added)

Let me not comment on the fact, conveniently forgotten here, that mostcountries of Central and Eastern Europe had already undergone the said halfcentury or more. Their system of comprehensive social insurance programmesstarted to develop a century or so ago (Voirin 1993).

• The transition countries are mostly poor. State revenues have rapidlydwindled because of the overall fall in production (tables 1a, 1b and 1c in theAppendix); because they privatized first the most profitable industries andactivities and were forced to hold on to the “losing propositions”; because thepower of the State to collect taxes and contributions is reduced owing to thefear of discouraging capital, especially foreign capital; because of the blackeconomy; sometimes because of too close links between the new economic andthe political elite, who are in turn the debtors and the collectors; because thewillingness to pay taxes and contributions is trapped in a vicious downwardspiral with deteriorating services; because the relationship between govern-ment and citizens is not one based on mutual trust; and so forth.10 In countrieswhich are heavily in debt, the servicing of debts intensifies the difficulties.

Cutbacks in state spending have therefore been more than justifiable.Nevertheless, why the welfare system should have become the main target ofthe cutbacks requires further explanation. The role of neo-liberal economistshas been one factor. The reluctance of the new rich to support the new poor, orto share less unequally the burden of the transition, is an easily understand-able sociological fact. But the explicit recommendations of the supranationalagencies have also been important. Let me quote just one example:

the present level of expenditure on social (cash and in-kind) transfersplaces Hungary on-par with high EU spender countries, the Scandinav-ian countries, and well above both low-income EC countries and non-EUOECD countries. . . . Since neither the revenue effort commensuratewith high spending nor a large fiscal deficit represent sound macro-economic strategies, an expenditure cutting strategy is necessary. (WorldBank 1994a: 2)

• The Stalinist system (even in its later, more liberal period) entailed a

33¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

stifled social structure. The ideological and political system prevented theemergence of groups with capitalist inclinations (competitiveness, search forownership and profit-making activities). Nevertheless, there have emergedgroups motivated by these interests and ready to avail themselves of the newopportunities. Their way of action has been much less inhibited than couldhave been the case under conditions of gradual capitalist evolution. Indeed,even unlawful actions could find easy self-justification, being construed asreactions against former oppression. This is all the more true because onesuch group consists of the descendants of the pre-war ruling class, whosewealth had been confiscated in the early years of Stalinism and whosefamilies had later undergone harsh political persecution. Others had enteredthe path to entrepreneurship under the former system, but could not go thewhole way because of the political limits. (This is particularly true inHungary.)

• Both of the above groups are, amongst other things, in search ofprofitable markets—and the marketization of former public services is apromising field, on several counts. Inasmuch as they are “quasi-markets” (LeGrand and Bartlett 1994), that is, inasmuch as they are at least partly fundedby public money (for instance by “contracting out”), solvent demand isassured. Even if marketization goes the whole way—since the whole point inCentral and Eastern Europe, after all, is to liberate the budget altogether fromsuch outlays—there is an almost captive clientele forced to buy these servicesat whatever cost they are offered. An interesting case in point is that of thecompulsory membership of a private pension fund (the Chilean model, discussedbelow), now on the agenda in Central and Eastern Europe.

• In each country there has emerged a group of “neophytes”, trulybelieving in the magnanimous omnipotence of the market and in theuncontrollable depravity of the State. Part of this group (in Poland, inHungary, but also in Russia) is made up of economists who had been the maincritics of the former system—given that criticism of the economy had been theonly tolerated route to trenchant analysis. The other part consists simply ofpolitical opportunists, always keen to demonstrate their allegiance to the newdominant ideology of any new political power.

• One of the most important and positive results emanating from thechanged system has been the advent of political democracy, and the (re-)emergence of civil society. However, it will take some time for civil society tobecome strong enough to defend itself and the rights—social rights in-cluded—it considers essential. Western societies are seemingly more success-ful at resisting changes dictated from above, at least in respect of those welfareinstitutions which benefit the majority. The mass demonstrations in France inthe winter of 1995, or in Germany in the spring of 1996, amply prove this point.Whereas in the new democracies the organization of civil society is, as yet,weaker and governments are, as yet, less aware of the importance of takingpeople’s opinion into account.

34 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

Solidarity between generations

Ideas for the transformation of systems of social security dated from right afterthe transition. In some cases, to be sure, particularly in the case of familybenefits, the first conservative governments may have been reluctant to takeaction. The most vocal proponents of change in such cases were thesupranational agencies. On the basis of international comparisons, their first“target” was provision for children and families, since these seemed to bemuch more lavish than those prevailing in most Western systems. Amongstothers, the following points were raised:

• The share of family allowance was assessed as “too high”, especiallyby the IMF and the World Bank, and also later by the OECD. It waspointed out that family allowance expenditure amounted to 1 to 3 percent of GDP in most Western countries, while it was between 2 and 4per cent in the Eastern ones. Therefore cutbacks have been recom-mended to accord with budgetary constraints.

• The ratio of family allowances to wages was higher than in marketeconomies, and covered a higher percentage of children’s needs (atbest around 30 per cent of a subsistence minimum). Hence theargument that family allowance was a wage subsidy, and played therole which, in market economies, is played by wages. It was alsoindicated that flat-rate family allowances represented an adverseincentive to increasing wage differentials.

• The staged increase in allowance, up to the third child, was judgedunacceptable because of its pro-natalist objective and its “wasteful-ness”.

It has to be added that the World Bank had important suggestionsbeneficial to the system of family allowances. For instance it alwayscondemned the politically discriminatory elements such as discriminationagainst the non-employed (in ex-socialist countries each and every socialbenefit had become conditional on employment). Hence in Hungary, forinstance, the family allowance became universal from April 1990 on. Also,most of its recommendations about family benefits were about group-targetingand taxation; not about increased selectivity (Barr 1994).

Despite increasing needs, and despite the high exclusion and inclusionerrors of targeting, the family benefit system was changed in the transitioncountries both quantitatively and qualitatively. Family allowances—whetherinsurance-based or universal—have gradually been transformed intomeans-tested assistance in most countries (Fajth 1996). There remain,though, some elements of group-targeting. For instance the Czech Republicmade family allowance means-tested in April 1995, but retained the universalmaternity grant (Castle-Kanerova 1996). Hungary made both child andmaternity benefits means-tested in April 1996, but retained universal access inthe case of families with three and more children. However, the value of thebenefits was gradually eroded even for those who were not excluded from theschemes, because there was no, or inadequate, indexation, notwithstanding

35¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

relatively high inflation rates. Whilst, according to UNICEF, a “minimumbenefit level should comprise about 10 to 15 per cent of the average wage,allowance schemes in most countries currently offer a benefit under the 10 percent threshold, and in two countries the benefit is even below 5 per cent”(Fajth 1996: 22). The success of the cutbacks seems indubitable. Familyallowances expressed as a percentage of the GDP (even given falling GDP)radically decreased everywhere. Between 1989 and 1993 or 1994 they wentdown from 1.2 to 1 in the Czech Republic, from 2.9 to 1.5 in Slovakia, from 2.0to 1.3 in Poland and from 2.9 to 0.7 in Romania (Fajth 1996: 25). The coverageand level of maternity benefits also deteriorated in most cases, while the ratioof children in nurseries declined everywhere, most dramatically in the CzechRepublic, Russia and the Baltic States (1996: 34).

All in all, the transition countries followed this lead. So much so that—together with unemployment, other forms of withdrawal from the labourmarket, declining real wages, the contraction of (free or cheap) child careinstitutions, and also the erosion of family benefits—child poverty in thetransition countries has become one of the best-known negative features of thenew scenario (UNICEF 1994).

The decrease in family benefits did not help the budgetary balance much.But their contraction made more conspicuous the “redistributive bias” infavour of the elderly. The scene was then set for the “second act”. The criticismof the pension system as being too broad, as giving too little to too many, asfailing to conform to actuarial insurance principles, has been on the agendasince the transition.11 But the attacks gained new vigour from about 1994.“Empirical data suggest that the old are not disproportionately poor in manycountries. In Hungary, Poland and Russia, families with young children aremore likely than old pensioners to be poor” (World Bank 1994b: 77). Suchobservation does not apply exclusively to the transition countries, but also tosome countries in Latin America, and to most OECD countries (1994b: 77).

The case for pension reform has been vigorously urged on the countries allover the transition region. The model recommended by all outside agenciesand adhered to by home-bred liberals is a milder variant of the Chilean reform,a multi-pillar pension scheme. The main features of the multi-pillar system are(World Bank 1994b: 292):

• a mandatory tax-financed public pillar designed to alleviate poverty;• a mandatory funded, privately managed pillar (based on personal

accounts or occupational plans) to handle people’s savings;• a supplementary voluntary pillar (again based on personal saving).

It is certainly true that in most countries pensioners did not fare much worsein the first years of transition than the active earners, especially in countries(such as Hungary) where pensions have been indexed to wages. Those withhigher pensions may have lost more where the increase of pensions wasregressive. This also meant, though, that poor pensioners had been relativelybetter protected than the better-off. However, wages are extremely lowrelative to the new (Western-type) price system,12 and pensions are lowerthan wages. While pensioners may be better off—in terms of equivalent

36 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

income—than households where the head is unemployed, they are worse offthan families where the head is an active earner, and much worse off thanfamilies of active earners without children. In other words: pensioners are notamong the main losers, but the majority of them are on the verge of, or alreadyin, poverty—and pensioners are largely under-represented in the top quintileof the population (see tables 1a, 1b and 1c in the Appendix).

This is not the place to analyse in detail either the situation of pensioners orthe latest pension reform plans. The point I want to emphasize here concernsthe combined impact of the endeavours described above on social integration,especially the unwritten contract of solidarity between generations. By eradicatinguniversal family benefits, one side of the contract was already harmed. It is avery different thing to help the truly needy, and yet another to make it visiblethat the community considers children as future social actors. By emphasizingthe importance of individual private saving schemes devoid of any solidaristicelement, the other side of the contract is invalidated. In fact, official bodiesrepeatedly bring home the message that the old should care for themselves,and not burden the young with their sustenance. That is why it seems to me—to say the least—cynical to blame the pensioners for the poverty of children.Yet this may easily happen, as when a private pension fund in Hungary has apublicity stunt presenting a sad little girl complaining: “And how shall Iprovide for you?”, or when a representative of the World Bank comments uponthe findings of UNICEF about the poverty of children in the transitioncountries. The Economist (16 December 1995) presented some of these findingsand asked for comments upon them: “I tell people in Eastern Europe—saysLouise Fox, a World Bank pundit—that pension policy is impoverishing theirchildren. The demands of pensioners are taking food out of the mouths of working people’schildren” (emphasis added). No doubt, data presented in table 1 of theAppendix do not cover the worst-off countries, especially those where civilwars add to the tragedy of everybody, children in the first place. But they arenone the less representative of a large part of the region, and suggest thatpensioners do not fare much better than families with children. However,unfortunately, there is no civil association like “Generation United” either inthe individual countries, or on the international scene, to prevent the pitting ofone generation against the other13 and social scientists are much less vocal onthis issue than for instance in England (e.g. Walker 1996).

People’s voice

The worldwide projects of the withdrawal of State responsibility for servicesand transfers which serve both social integration and protection of existentialsecurities does not seem to meet with the general approval of people.According to Jacek Kuron, Poles “regarded ‘socialist social justice’ as a totallyacceptable norm”. They condemned its distortions, but not the principle ofthis basic myth. “To build a new social order while rejecting a myth in whichPoles believe—I maintain it is impossible” (Kuron 1993).

This opinion comes out clearly from the SOCO project. The attraction of thevelvet revolutions is apparently fading in the light of the new experiences. Putmore precisely, the societies in transition are becoming more differentiated.

37¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

entiated. The younger, more educated people, possessed of more entrepreneu-rial spirit are increasingly satisfied, while there is a growing minority or even amajority who think the new system is worse than the previous one (table 2 inthe Appendix).

There are many reasons for people’s disappointment, but amongst them arecertainly the loss of security and the withdrawal of the State. In practice, in allfive countries in the survey, people are making clear distinctions betweenvarious public responsibilities. For instance, the responsibility for themaintenance of children is seen as “half-and-half”, half private, half publicresponsibility. Private responsibility is also endorsed to a large extent in thecase of higher, even of secondary, education. However, health, the protectionof handicapped people, primary education and decent pensions are all thoughtto rate very high on the agenda of state responsibilities (see table 3 and figure 1in the Appendix). Unfortunately, I have not been able to find exactlycomparable data for Western countries. However, what evidence existssuggests that people are against the destruction of collective protection. Inmany cases, the evidence shows an increasing awareness of the importance ofsocial security—despite government endeavours and powerful rhetoric to thecontrary (see table 4 in the Appendix). The phenomenon also belongs to theparadox of democracy. The voice of the people may be there—but it arrives atthe top feeble and distorted.

An allegory from the New Testament, and its rewriting by a Hungarianwriter in the early 1930s, may illustrate the point. All the gospels relate the taleof Jesus and Barabbas. The custom was to release one prisoner at the feast day.Pontius Pilate gathered the high priests, the leaders and the people in order tolisten to them and follow their desire. One of the prisoners was Barabbas, themurderer. Pilate asked the people whom they wanted to be released, Barabbasor Jesus. The crowd requested the release of Barabbas and Jesus was crucified.In the short story of the Hungarian novelist, Frigyes Karinthy, however, Pilatelooks round the assemblage and asks:

“And whom shall I release now, Barabbas or the one from Nazareth?” Arumble emerged, the voice of the crowd sounded like thundering. Andthey shouted: Barabbas. And then they looked upon each other and werefrightened, because separately each of them cried: the Nazarene.

In the case of the social State, the voice of the individuals forming themajority supporting the State may be less thundering. But when it arrives atthe top, it is no less distorted. The analogy is not perfect, though. Pilate—bothin the Bible and in the short story—ostensibly tries to save Jesus. This does notseem to be the case with the current rulers and the social State.

In other words, the minimal state which disclaims any responsibility for the“public good” does not correspond with the wish of the citizens. It seems to methat the future success of a free and democratic society depends to a largeextent not only on economic growth—for all that in the relatively poorcountries of Central and Eastern Europe this is also a must. Economic growthalone is not likely to bring about social cohesion and a willingness to worktogether on constructing a new and better society. People also need hope about

38 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

a better future—hope that they will be able to live and age in dignity. Thecurrent politics and social policy do not seem to assure this hope for the largegroups of the less educated, the ageing, those already on the margins of societybecause of lasting unemployment, homelessness or other old and new forms ofpoverty, or simply to those who care about the quality of society they live in.The dangers of deceived expectations are many, from resignation and politicalpassivity, to the turn of populism. The unconditional espousal of the newparadigm of welfare should be reconsidered, and a rethinking of the role of theState should be put on the social agenda.

Appendix

Table 1aa

Equivalent monthly income in the households of active earners and pensioners,with and without children ($US)

Head of household Czech Poland Hungary Germany SlovakiaRepublic

No child under 18 (in school)

Active earner 220 140 192 1153 169Pensioner 136 120 123 924 108Other (e.g. unemp.) 164 110 111 774 93Total 171 129 146 983 134

At least one child under 18 (in school)

Active earner 162 113 155 873 116Pensioner 132 87 124 686 92Other 126 59 84 592 81Total 159 107 144 836 113

All households

Active earner 184 122 170 1013 131Pensioner 136 115 123 921 106Other 136 75 95 725 85Total 166 117 146 942 122

a The survey furnishing these data was carried out as part of the SOCO projectinitiated and co-ordinated by the Institute for Human Studies, Vienna. Thecountries covered included the Czech Republic, former East Germany,Hungary, Poland and Slovakia. The first results are presented in theInternational report on the Social Consequences of the Transition (Ferge et al.

1995).

Table 1bEquivalent income of pensioners as a percentage of the equivalent income of

households where the head is active earner

Is there any child Czech Poland Hungary Germany Slovakiaunder 18 Republic

No child 62 86 64 80 64Child 82 76 80 79 79Total 74 94 73 91 81

39¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

Table 1cEquivalent income of households with children as a percentage of the equivalent income of

households without children

Head of household Czech Poland Hungary Germany SlovakiaRepublic

Active earner 74 81 81 76 69Pensioner 97 72 100 74 86Other (unemp.) 77 54 76 76 87Total 93 83 99 85 84

Table 2Percentage of respondents according to whom the

new system is better or worsea

Czech Hungary Poland SlovakiaRepublic

The new system is better

1991 71 31 51 431995 57 26 44 32

The new system is worse

1991 14 40 23 351995 23 51 39 51

a The sample consisted of individuals in 1991, ofhouseholds in 1994.Source for 1991: Hartl (1994), 1995: Ferge et al.

(1995). There are no comparable data for EastGermany.

Table 3Average score for state responsibility for the various items by country

(Scores from 1 to 5, 1Dleast, 5Dmost responsibility)

Items in increasingorder of mean scores

CzechRepublic

Poland Hungary Germany(East)

Slovakia Region,

total

6 Cost of children 3.2 2.8 3.7 3.8 3.2 3.36

2 Care under 6 3.3 3.3 3.6 3.7 3.6 3.48

5 Higher educ. 3.0 3.7 4.0 4.2 3.3 3.66

8 First home 3.7 3.5 4.2 3.2 4.0 3.72

4 Secondary e. 3.7 4.2 4.2 4.4 3.9 4.09

9 Jobs 3.9 4.3 4.5 4.6 4.4 4.33

1 Health care 4.5 4.4 4.4 4.6 4.6 4.50

3 Primary educ. 4.5 4.7 4.3 4.5 4.5 4.50

10 Handicapped 4.5 4.7 4.3 4.5 4.5 4.50

7 Decent pensions 4.5 4.6 4.6 4.7 4.7 4.63

Country mean 3.91 4.03 4.19 4.23 4.09 4.09

40 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

Figure 1Distribution of scores for state responsibility

Table 4Taxes and state spending (England)

If the government could choose 1983 1986 1990 1993 1994

in % of respondents

decrease taxes, spend less on health,education and social security

9 5 3 4 4

keep taxes and spending on currentlevel

54 44 37 29 33

increase taxes, spend more on health,education and social security

32 46 54 63 58

Source: Taylor-Gooby (1995).

Acknowledgement

Plenary paper prepared for the Annual Conference of the British Social PolicyAssociation, Sheffield, 16–18 July 1996.I am grateful to Adrian Sinfield and C. J. Finer for helpful comments.

Notes1. Wallerstein (1996) describes succinctly, in connection with the role of social

science, the liberal project of social betterment, the rational belief in its feasibility.2. These two concepts are not too far removed from the two “basic needs” defined by

Doyal and Gough (1991), which they term health and autonomy. I continue to usemy own concepts of physical and social life chances because they are moredescriptive than normative, and because they are related to social dynamics.

3. The management consultants Coopers and Lybrand were asked to assess Oxford

41¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

University. They found, as related in The Times by Roger Scruton in 1996, that “allthose colleges duplicating resources. . . , wasting precious money on their separatelibraries, their separate kitchens, their separate domestic lives, and their separatedomestic quarrels—surely the whole lot should be poured into a singlecauldron . . .”

4. The concept of social property is used in this sense by Castel (1995). The propertyis real in case of a collectivist funded system, and it is virtual in a pay-as-you-gosystem.

5. See among others the Council Recommendation of 1992 of the EuropeanCommunity about social assistance.

6. The expression is borrowed from Goran Therborn. This new role of the state isdescribed in minute detail e.g. in Barr (1994).

7. For the difference between counting and calculating (with profit) see Bourdieu(1977).

8. There are always efforts to counter this tendency. In early October 1996,simultaneously with similar events at about ten universities over the country, 2000people gathered at Columbia University, New York, at a teach-in, “The Fight forAmerica’s Future”. It happened for the first time since World War II thatintellectuals and labour leaders attempted to join forces for revitalizing socialmovements against unjust and divisive societal tendencies (Spectator, 24 September1996, and personal communication from Herbert Gans).

9. Let me not dwell upon the uncanny parallel with the discriminative practices of“state socialism” against those deemed “unproductive”, including the handicap-ped, the aged and similar groups.

10. This statement may seem to be at odds with the strong feelings about stateresponsibility. However, the two feelings may co-exist. Distrust towards themarket may for instance be still greater than that towards the state.

11. The flaws and inconsistencies of the pension system were discovered long beforethe transition. In Hungary, for instance, quite radical reforms had beencontemplated since the mid-1980s. However, they remained within the earnings-related and solidaristic paradigm and the pay-as-you-go system was not to beradically changed.

12. The purchasing power of the average wage in the transition countries seems to beabout 6 to 10 times lower than in the developed countries.

13. I am grateful to Terry Hokenstad for having informed me about the purpose andorganization of Generations United in the US.

ReferencesAmbros, P. (1994), Freedom or security. Hungarian Lettre Internationale, Spring.Arato, A. (1996), Alkotmany es kontinuitas Kelet-Europaban (Constitution and

continuity in Eastern Europe). Vilagossag, 3.Barr, N. (ed.) (1994), Labor Markets and Social Policy in Central and Eastern Europe: The

Transition and Beyond, published for the World Bank and the London School ofEconomics and Political Science, a World Bank book, Oxford University Press:Oxford.

Bauman, Z. (1988), Sociology and Postmodernity. Sociological Review, 36, 4: 790–813.Block, F., Cloward, R. A., Ehrenreich, B. and Fox Piven, F. (1987), The Mean Season:

The Attack on the Welfare State, Pantheon Books: New York.Bosanquet, N. (1983), After the New Right, Heinemann: London.Bourdieu, P. (1977), Outline of a Theory of Practice, Cambridge University Press:

Cambridge.

42 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

Castel, R. (1995), Les Metamorphoses de la question sociale. Une chronique du salariat, Fayard:Paris.

Castle-Kanerova, M. (1996), Social security in the Czech Republic: The market,paternalism or social democracy?, in May, M., Brunsdon, E. and Craig, G. (eds.),Social Policy Review 8, SPA.

Commission on Social Justice (1994), Social Justice: A Strategy for National Renewal,Vintage: London.

Coote, A. (1992), The Welfare of Citizens: Developing New Social Rights, IPPR, RiversOram Press: London.

Council Recommendation of 24 June 1992 on Common Criteria Concerning SufficientResources and Social Assistance in Social Protection Systems. 92/442/EEC, OfficialJournal No. L 245/46, 26 August 1992.

Dalton, G. (ed.) (1968), Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi,Doubleday: New York.

Deacon, B. (1994), Global social policy actors and the shaping of post-Communistsocial policy. In Swaan 1994: 58–79.

Doyal, L. and Gough, I. (1991), A Theory of Human Need, Macmillan: London.Elias, N. (1991), The Society of Individuals, Blackwell: Oxford.Esping-Andersen, G. (1990), The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism, Princeton Univer-

sity Press.Fajth, G. (1996), Family support policies in Central and Eastern Europe. UNICEF

International Child Development Center, Florence, Italy. Paper prepared for theNational Academy of Sciences/National Research Council Task Force onEconomies in Transition Workshop, Washington DC: 19–20 September.

Ferge, Zs. (1979), A Society in the Making: Hungarian Social and Societal Policy, 1945–1975,Penguin: Harmondsworth.

Ferge, Zs., and Miller, S. M. (eds.) (1987), Dynamics of Deprivation, Gower: Aldershot.Ferge, Zs. (1996), Freedom and security. International Review of Comparative Public Policy,

vol. 7.Ferge, Zs., et al. (1995), Societies in transition. International report on the Social

Consequences of the Transition, a survey carried out as part of the SOCO projectinitiated and co-ordinated by the Institute for Human Studies, Vienna. Cross-national report on five countries, prepared by Zsuzsa Ferge, Endre Sik, Peter Robertand Fruzsina Albert.

Guillemard, A. M. (1986), Le Declin du social, Presses Universitaires de France: Paris.Habermas, J. (1981), Theorie des kommunikativen Handels, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp

Verlag.Hartl, J. (1994), Perceptions of social safety in the Czech and Slovak Republics,

Hungary and Poland. In Bozoky, A. (ed.), Democratic Legitimacy in Post-CommunistSocieties, T-Twins Publishing House: Budapest.

Hirschman, A. O. (1991), The Rhetoric of Reaction, Belknap Press of Harvard UniversityPress, Cambridge, MA.

Juhasz, G. (1995), A szocialis biztonsaghoz valo jog alkotmanyos ujraszabalyozasa ele.Esely, 3.sz.

Keane, J. (1989), “Freedom of press” in the 1990’s (Hungarian translation of aconference held in Budapest). Esely, no. 2.

Kuron, J. (1993), Soziale Gerechtigkeit als soziale Bewegung. Transit, 6.Kvist, J., and Sinfield, A. (1996), Comparing Tax Routes in Denmark and the United

Kingdom, Danish National Institute of Social Research: Copenhagen.Le Grand, J. and Bartlett, W. (eds) (1994), Quasi-Markets and Social Policy, Macmillan

Press: Basingstoke and London.Le Monde (1995), Chomage, appel au debat. 28 June.Major, I. (1996), Kulfoldi tanacsadok (az) atalakulasban (Foreign advisers during the

43¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997

transition). 2000, majus.Petrella, R. (1995), The European Future: Competitive Innovation or a New Social Contract?,

European Cultural Foundation: Amsterdam.Pierson, C. (1992), Beyond the Welfare State? The New Political Economy of Welfare, Polity

Press: Cambridge.Polanyi, K. (1994), The Great Transformation, Beacon Press: Boston.Ringen, S. and Wallace, C. (eds) (1993), Societies in Transition: East-Central Europe

Today, Prague Papers on Social Responses to Transformation, vol. I, CentralEuropean University: Prague.

Rodgers, G. and van der Hoeven R. (1995), New Approaches to Poverty: Analysis andPolicy–III, International Institute for Labour Studies: Geneva.

Rosanvallon, P. (1995), La Nouvelle question sociale. Repenser l’Etat-Providence, Seuil: Paris.Rose, R. (1993), Who needs social protection in East Europe? A constrained empirical

analysis of Romania. In Ringen and Wallace (1993).Sunstein, C. (1994), Against Positive Rights, Manuscript at the Central European

University, Budapest, Hungary.Swaan, A. (ed.) (1994), Social Policy beyond Borders: The social question in transnational

perspective. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.Taylor-Gooby, P. (1995), Comfortable, marginal and excluded: Who should pay

higher taxes for a better welfare state? In R. Jowell et al., British Social Attitudes, the 12thReport, SCPR, Dartmouth.

Therborn, G. (1995), European Modernity and Beyond: The Trajectory of European Societies,1945–2000, Sage: London.

Titmuss, R. M. (1974), Social Policy: An Introduction, Allen and Unwin: London.Townsend, P. (1995), Poverty in Eastern Europe: The latest manifestation of global

polarization. In Rodgers and Hoeven (1995).UNICEF (1994), Central and Eastern Europe in Transition: Public Policy and Social

Conditions: Crisis in Mortality, Health and Nutrition, Economies in Transition Studies,Regional Monitoring Report, no. 2, August.

Vaillancourt Rosenau, P., and Bredemeier, H. C. (1993), Modern and postmodernconceptions of social order, Social Research, vol. 60, no. 2, summer.

Voirin, M. (1993), La Securite sociale dans les pays d’Europe centrale et orientale:Reformes et continuite. Revue Internationale de Securite Sociale, no. 1: 29–70.

Walker, A. (ed.) (1996), The New Generational Contract. Intergenerational relations, Old Ageand Welfare. UCL Press: London.

Wallerstein, I. (1996), Social science and contemporary society. International Sociology,March.

Weber, M. (1968), Economy and Society, Badminster: New York.Wilensky, H. L., and Lebeaux, C. N. (1965), Industrial Society and Social Welfare, Free

Press: New York.World Bank (1992), Hungary, Reform of Social Policy and Expenditures, World Bank

Reports, Washington DC.World Bank (1993), World Development Report: Investing in Health. World

Development Indicators 1993. Crisis in Mortality, Health and Nutrition, Interna-tional Bank for Reconstruction and Development, Oxford University Press: NewYork.

World Bank (1994a), Family Benefits, Manuscript, Budapest.World Bank (1994b), Averting the Old Age Crisis: Policies to Protect the Old and Promote

Growth, Policy Research Report, Oxford University Press: Oxford.

44 ¥ Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1997