Philosophical Roots of the Concept of Nudges

24
WORKING PAPER: DO NOT QUOTE Anne BrunonErnst, ECPR 2024 Aug 2015, Montreal University (CANADA) (French Nudge Project, funded by Ecole de droit, Sciences Po, Paris) 1 Philosophical Roots of the Concept of Nudges 1 Anne BRUNONERNST Institut Villey (PanthéonAssas University) and Centre Bentham (Ecole de droit, IEP, Paris) Introduction As citizens, 2 consumers and individuals, nudges 3 are becoming an increasing part of our daily lives. Nudges are however only one set of tools within a wider array of paternalistic approaches to individuals, politics and economics. Indeed for a fuller account of this new way of controlling individuals, other competing approaches will have to be discussed such as choice architecture, soft paternalism, hard paternalism etc. The crux of the matter is that these concepts have problematic implications in respect to individual freedom, autonomy, and, by the same token, of potential choice manipulation that could arise from them. 4 There is therefore a vital need to understand both the workings of these tools based on human psychology and to determine whether they are legitimate interference to individual choices. All around the world, academics, but also politicians and journalists join in to try work out an assessment of nudges. 5 The present talk wishes to contribute to the debate in presenting an intellectual history perspective 1 On 18 th May 2015, at the University PanthéonAssas, a draft of this paper was presented at the French Nudge Project Research Seminar as “Benthamland or Millland : Nudges in Perspective”, a NUDGEExtra legal normativities and public policies project, funded by the Ecole de Droit, Sciences Po, Paris (FRANCE). 2 See for e.g.: Cass Sunstein’s position as the Administrator of the White House’s Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs in the Obama Administration, Richard Thaler’s involvement in the British Conservative Party in 2009 or the existence of a Behavioural Insight Team in the UK Cabinet. 3 The term was coined by Sunstein and Thaler, as repeatedly used in their publications, among which: Sunstein, Cass R. and Thaler, Richard H., ‘Libertarian Paternalism Is Not An Oxymoron’, University of Chicago Law Review, 704 (2003) : 1159f; Sunstein, C. and Thaler, R., Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth and Happiness, New Haven, Yale University Press, 2008; Sunstein, Cass, ‘Nudges and Public Policy’, Paper at the International Behavioural Insights Conference, Sydney, 23 June 2014; Sunstein, C. Why nudge? The Politics of Libertarian Paternalism, New Haven, Yale University Press, 2014. 4 Rebonato, R., Taking Liberties: A Critical Examination of Libertarian Paternalism, NewYork, Palgrave Macmillan, 2012; White, M. D., The Manipulation of Choice: Ethics and Libertarian Paternalism, NewYork, Palgrave Macmillan, 2013 5 See for e.g.: numerous articles published in The Guardian (Mona Chalabi, ‘Does a government nudge make us budge?’, published on November 12, 2013, in The Guardian, Online edition, at http://www.theguardian.com, accessed 19/5/2015) or in The New York Times (Catherine Bennhold, ‘The Minsitry of Nudges’, published on December 7, 2013, in New York Times, Online edition, at http://www.nytimes.com, accessed 19/5/2015). But also in nonEnglish media (Etienne Gless, ‘Le nudge marketing ou comment vendre sans contraindre’, published on July 16, 2013, in L’Express, Online edition, at http://lentreprise.lexpress.fr, accessed 19/5/2015).

Transcript of Philosophical Roots of the Concept of Nudges

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

1  

Philosophical  Roots  of  the  Concept  of  Nudges1    

Anne  BRUNON-­ERNST  

Institut    Villey  (Panthéon-­Assas  University)  and  Centre  Bentham  (Ecole  de  droit,  IEP,  Paris)  

 

 

Introduction  

As  citizens,2  consumers  and  individuals,  nudges3  are  becoming  an  increasing  part  of  our  

daily   lives.   Nudges   are   however   only   one   set   of   tools   within   a   wider   array   of  

paternalistic   approaches   to   individuals,   politics   and   economics.   Indeed   for   a   fuller  

account   of   this   new   way   of   controlling   individuals,   other   competing   approaches   will  

have  to  be  discussed  such  as  choice  architecture,  soft  paternalism,  hard  paternalism  etc.  

The  crux  of  the  matter  is  that  these  concepts  have  problematic  implications  in  respect  to  

individual  freedom,  autonomy,  and,  by  the  same  token,  of  potential  choice  manipulation  

that   could   arise   from   them.4   There   is   therefore   a   vital   need   to   understand   both   the  

workings  of  these  tools  based  on  human  psychology  and  to  determine  whether  they  are  

legitimate   interference  to   individual  choices.  All  around  the  world,  academics,  but  also  

politicians  and  journalists  join  in  to  try  work  out  an  assessment  of  nudges.5  The  present  

talk  wishes  to  contribute  to  the  debate  in  presenting  an  intellectual  history  perspective  

                                                                                                               1  On  18th  May  2015,  at  the  University  Panthéon-­‐Assas,  a  draft  of  this  paper  was  presented  at  the  French  Nudge  Project  Research  Seminar  as    “Bentham-­‐land  or  Mill-­‐land  :  Nudges  in  Perspective”,  a  NUDGE-­‐Extra-­‐legal  normativities  and  public  policies  project,  funded  by  the  Ecole  de  Droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris  (FRANCE).  2  See  for  e.g.:  Cass  Sunstein’s  position  as  the  Administrator  of  the  White  House’s  Office  of  Information  and  Regulatory  Affairs  in  the  Obama  Administration,  Richard  Thaler’s  involvement  in  the  British  Conservative  Party  in  2009  or  the  existence  of  a  Behavioural  Insight  Team  in  the  UK  Cabinet.  3   The   term  was   coined   by   Sunstein   and  Thaler,   as   repeatedly   used   in   their   publications,   among  which:  Sunstein,   Cass   R.   and   Thaler,   Richard   H.,   ‘Libertarian   Paternalism   Is   Not   An   Oxymoron’,   University   of  Chicago  Law  Review,   70-­‐4   (2003)  :   1159f;   Sunstein,   C.   and  Thaler,  R.,  Nudge:   Improving  Decisions  About  Health,  Wealth  and  Happiness,  New  Haven,  Yale  University  Press,  2008;  Sunstein,  Cass,  ‘Nudges  and  Public  Policy’,   Paper   at   the   International  Behavioural   Insights   Conference,   Sydney,   2-­‐3   June  2014;   Sunstein,   C.  Why  nudge?  The  Politics  of  Libertarian  Paternalism,  New  Haven,  Yale  University  Press,  2014.  4   Rebonato,   R.,   Taking   Liberties:   A   Critical   Examination   of   Libertarian   Paternalism,   New-­‐York,   Palgrave  Macmillan,  2012;  White,  M.  D.,  The  Manipulation  of  Choice:  Ethics  and  Libertarian  Paternalism,  New-­‐York,  Palgrave  Macmillan,  2013  5   See   for   e.g.:   numerous   articles   published   in  The   Guardian   (Mona   Chalabi,   ‘Does   a   government   nudge  make   us   budge?’,   published   on   November   12,   2013,   in   The   Guardian,   Online   edition,   at  http://www.theguardian.com,  accessed  19/5/2015)  or  in  The  New  York  Times  (Catherine  Bennhold,  ‘The  Minsitry   of   Nudges’,   published   on   December   7,   2013,   in   New   York   Times,   Online   edition,   at  http://www.nytimes.com,  accessed  19/5/2015).  But  also  in  non-­‐English  media  (Etienne  Gless,  ‘Le  nudge  marketing  ou  comment  vendre  sans  contraindre’,  published  on  July  16,  2013,  in  L’Express,  Online  edition,  at  http://lentreprise.lexpress.fr,  accessed  19/5/2015).  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

2  

(as   opposed   to   psychology,   economics   or   behavioural   economics   as   are   often   used   in  

discussions  on  nudges)  on  these  new  regulatory  instruments.  

 

It   is  not   the  purpose  of   the  present   talk   to   look  at   the   influence  of  philosophers   in   the  

shaping  of  nudges,  as  indeed  the  notion  of   influence  is  difficult  to  trace;  and  as  nudges  

owe   certainly   more   to   the   development   of   psychology   and   to   the   application   of  

behavioural  insights  to  economics  than  to  philosophy.  This  is  not  to  say  that  heritage  of  

philosophers   in   nudges   is   not   generally   acknowledged   both   by   academics   and   in   the  

media,   as   in   the   case   of   JS   Mill.6   However,   I   contend   that,   in   most   of   these   cases,  

philosophers  are  used  with  strategic  rather  than  exegetic  purpose.7  There   is  an  urgent  

need  to  put  the  theoretical  underpinnings  and  the  pragmatic  implementation  of  nudges  

into  perspective  and  draw  the  lessons  from  such  an  experiment.    

 

I  will  not   look   into   JS  Mill’s  heritage,  but   into   that  of   the  British  philosopher  and   legal  

reformer   Jeremy   Bentham   (1748-­‐1832).   Indeed   Bentham’s   concept   of   indirect  

legislation   is   particularly   relevant   to   our   discussion   here.   At   the   beginning   of   the  

industrial   revolution,   at   a   time   when   changing   work   relationships   required   a   new  

organisation  of  society,  Bentham  was  at   the  forefront  of   the  reflexion  on  new  forms  of  

regulation.  He  will  be  remembered  for  his  Panopticon  schemes  (which  started  out  as  a  

Russian   factory   under   the   supervision   of   his   brother   Samuel,   before   being   the   well-­‐

known  panoptic   prison)   but   also   his  Constitutional   Code.  The   interest   of   academics   in  

Bentham’s   investigation   of   alternative   forms   of   regulation   has   first   arisen   from   the  

Bentham-­‐Foucault   debate   on   biopolitics,8  which   highlighted   the   pivotal   importance   of  

Bentham’s   legal   and   non-­‐legal   forms   of   regulations   encapsulated   in   the   concept   of  

                                                                                                               6  See  for  e.g.:  David  Brown,  ‘Review  :  ‘Why  Nudge?’,  by  Cass  R  Sunstein’,  published  on  May  4,  2014,  in  the  Financial  Times,  Online  edition,  at  http://www.ft.com,  accessed  19/5/2015,  Cass  R.  Sunstein,  ‘It’s  For  Your  Own   Good:   Against   Autonomy:   Justifying   Coercive   Paternalism   by   Sarah   Conly’   published   on   April   25,  2013,  in  the  New  York  Review  of  Books,  Online  edition,  at  http://www.nybooks.com,  accessed  19/5/2015,  and  Mona  Chalabi,  ‘Does  a  government  nudge  make  us  budge?’.  7  See  paper  by  the  present  author  on  ‘JS  Mill  and  Nudges’  in  the  Journal  of  European  History  of  Ideas  [under  submission]  8  See  S.G.  Engelmann,   ‘”Indirect  Legislation”:  Bentham’s  Liberal  Government’,   in  Polity,  35:  3  (2003):  pp.  372f,   C.   Laval,   ‘La   chaîne   invisible’,   Revue   d’études   benthamiennes   [e-­‐journal],   1   (2006),   posted   on   1st  September  2006,  accessed  on  15th  January  2012.  URL  :  http://etudes-­‐benthamiennes.revues.org/63;  and  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  (ed.),  Beyond  Foucault.  New  Perspectives  on  Bentham’s  Panopticon,  Aldershot:  Ashgate,  2012  and    Utilitarian  Biopolitics:  Bentham,  Foucault  and  Modern  Power,    London:  Chatto  and  Pickering,  2012.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

3  

indirect  legislation.9  Following  the  work  of  Michael  Quinn,  time  has  come  to  offer  a  more  

balanced  view  of  the  mechanisms  offered  by  indirect  legislation.  A  more  subtle  picture  is  

now   emerging   of   a   regulatory   system   which   offers   new   and   unmapped   forms   of  

regulation  which  are  both  legal  and  non-­‐legal.  

 

First,   I  suggest  we  look  into  the  meaning  of   indirect   legislation,  trying  to  draw  the  line  

between   this   form  of   regulation  and   its   converse,   direct   legislation   (Part   II).   Second,   I  

highlight   the   similarities   between   nudges   and   some   types   of   indirect   legislation   (Part  

III).   Lastly,   I   see   how   the   lessons   Bentham   draws   from   his   experiment   with   indirect  

instruments  could  contribute  to  the  nudge  debate  (Part  IV).10  The  aim  of  my  intellectual  

history   perspective   on   Bentham’s   theory   of   social   regulation   allows   a   reappraisal   of  

nudges’  impact  on  individual  freedom.    

 

Nudges,  choice  architecture,  soft  paternalism,  hard  paternalism  etc.  as  these  normative  

tools  will   be  discussed  all   along   the  present   talk,   it  might  be  better   to   settle   early   the  

meaning  of  the  terms,  which  will  be  discussed  in  the  arguments  which  follow.    There  are  

no  standard  definitions,  as  most  writers  have  made  up  a  working  definition  that  fit  the  

purpose   of   their   arguments.11   Nonetheless,   for   a   clearer   understanding   of   the   issues  

raised   later   in   this   talk,   imperfect  definitions  might  be  better   than  no  definition  at   all.  

Part  I  thus  opens  up  with  a  definition  section.  

 

1. Definitions  and  Comparisons  

The   first   definition   is   that   of   nudges.   Cass   R.   Sunstein   &   Richard   Thaler’s   coined   the  

term.  Sunstein  defines  nudges  as  ‘initiatives  that  maintain  freedom  of  choice  while  also  

                                                                                                               9    A.  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  “Le  gouvernement  des  normes  :  Jeremy  Bentham  et  les  instruments  de  régulation  post-­‐modernes”,   in   Archives   de   philosophie,   78   :   2   (2015),   pp.   309-­‐322   and   Brunon-­‐Ernst,   A.   and   Van  Waeyenberge,   A.,   “Effects   of   the   open   method   of   coordination   (OMC)   in   research   and   innovation:  legislation  in  EU  policy-­‐making?  ”,  in  Journal  of  Legal  Pluralism  and  Unofficial  Law,  2015,  pp.  1-­‐17;  and  M.  Bozzo-­‐Rey,   ‘Back  to  Bentham:  Indirect  Legislation  and  Nudge’,  Conference  at  the  Bentham  Seminar,  UCL,  London,  18  March  2015.  10  This  method  was  also  used  by  the  same  author   in  previous  work  on  postmodern   forms  of  regulation.  Working   from   the  perspective  of   intellectual  history   and  Bentham’s  work  on  postmodern  normativities  has  allowed  to  highlight  some  controlling  instruments  common  to  different  initiatives.  See  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  “Le  gouvernement  des  norms”  and  Brunon-­‐Ernst  and  Van  Waeyenberge,  ““Effects  of  the  open  method  of  coordination  (OMC)  in  research  and  innovation”.    11  See  Sunstein’s  criticisms  and  changes  to  Rebonato’s  definition  of  nudges  in  Rebonato,  Taking  Liberties  (Sunstein,  Why  nudge?,  p.  58-­‐59).  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

4  

steering  people’s  decisions  in  the  right  direction’.12  There  are  several   important  points  

to   make   about   this   definition.   First,   nudges   aim   to   alter   people’s   behaviour.   It   is  

conceived   as   a   tool   to   be   used   by   people  wishing   to  modify   other   people’s   behaviour  

(governments,   businesses,13   parents   etc).   Nudges   have   the   advantage   of   a   scientific  

method   based   on   psychology,   which   makes   the   response   of   individuals   to   certain  

initiatives  predictable.   In   that  respect,   it  appears  as  an   ideal   tool   for  governments  and  

businesses  alike.  The  second  point   is   that   individuals  nudged  are  not   forced  to  modify  

their  behaviour.  Even  if  the  preferred  option  is  more  likely,  they  still  have  the  choice  to  

select  another  option,  which  is  not  preferred  by  the  nudger.  A  characteristic   feature  of  

nudges   is   that   they  make   their   reversal   possible,   that   is   the   nudgee   can   override   the  

nudger’s   or   the   choice   architect’s   preference.14   As   A-­‐L   Sibony   and   F.   Alemanno   note:  

‘Nudge   is   therefore   presented   as   a   distinctive,   alternative  way,   characterized   as   being  

minimally   burdensome,   low-­‐cost   and   choice-­‐preserving,   to   help   promote   regulatory  

goals.’15   The   third   point   is   that   nudges   are   initiatives   operatig   in   the   interest   of   the  

nudgee.  You  will  have  noted  the  use  of  the  word  ‘right’  in  Sunstein’s  definition.  It  is  the  

nudger  who  determines  the  right  goals  for  nudgee.  The  goals  are  therefore  only  right  in  

the   eye  of   the  nudger,  who   can  have   a   very  different   agenda   from   the  nudgee.   In   this  

respect,  a  nudger  is  a  paternalist.  

 

S.  Conly  defines  paternalism  as:  ‘a  practice  wherein  people  are  forced  to  perform  actions  

that   bring   about   good   consequences   for   themselves’.16   It   is   the   beneficent   aim   of   the  

initiative   devised   by   the   paternalist   that   determines   the   paternalistic   nature   of   the  

intervention   on   choice.   Nudges   are   paternalist   as   they   are   initiatives   devised  with   an  

aim.  However  not  all  paternalist  initiatives  aim  at  benefitting  the  individual.  Some  aim  at  

benefitting   society   or   the   financial   interests   of   a   company.   Indeed   when   it   comes   to  

paternalist   initiatives  operating  in  a  business-­‐related  environment,   the  presumption  of  

                                                                                                               12  Sunstein,  Why  nudge?,  p.  17.  13   Alberto   Alemanno   and  Anne   Lise   Sibony   (eds.),  Nudging   and   the   Law.  What   Can   EU   Law   Learn   from  Behavioural  Sciences?,  Oxford:  Hart  Publishing,  2015,  Forthcoming.  Alemanno  and  Sibony  distinguish  the  purpose  government  initiatives  from  business-­‐related  ones.  See  Alemanno  and  Sibony  (eds.),  p.  18-­‐19.  14  Nudges  are  referred  to  as  the   ‘mildest  and  most  choice-­‐preserving  forms  of   intervention’,   in  Sunstein,  Why  nudge?,  p.  17.    15  Alemanno  and  Sibony  (eds.),  pp.  5.  16   Conly,   Sarah,   Against   Autonomy  :   Justifying   Coercive   Paternalism,     Cambridge   University   Press:   New  York,  2013,  p.  48.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

5  

benevolence  is  rebutted,  as  the  nudge  is  likely  enhance  business  profits  at  the  expense  of  

effective  consumer  freedom  of  choice.17    

 

There   are   two   types   of   paternalism.   Means/ends   paternalism18   and   soft/hard  

paternalism.19   It   is   sometimes   difficult   to   draw   the   line   between   soft   and   hard  

paternalism.   I   believe   the   main   distinction   lies   in   the   degree   of   paternalist’s  

intervention:   if   the   nudgee   is   given   less   opportunities   to   reverse   the   nudge   then   the  

degree  of  nudging   is  more   intense,   thus  qualifying   the   initiative   for   a  hard  paternalist  

status  rather  than  soft.  

 

What  is  then  the  difference  between  nudges  and  choice  architecture,  another  term  used  

in  my  talk  so  far?  Choice  architecture  refers  to  the  background  against  which  choices  are  

made.20   Any   environment   which   is   organised   by   man   and   where   choice   is   required  

involves   choice   architecture.   Choice   architects   can   voluntarily   (or   involuntarily)  

organise  an  environment  to  make  one  choice  more  likely.  Nudgers  are  one  type  of  choice  

architects:  those  who  voluntarily  organise  an  environment  to  maximise  choice  according  

to  certain  goals  (political,  health-­‐related,  economic,  etc.),  while  minimizing  cost.    

 

In   the   terminological  discussion  above,   a  picture  of  nudges   is   emerging  as  an  array  of  

utility-­‐driven,   cost-­‐effective,   beneficent   initiatives   based   on   scientific   assessment   of  

motives   individuals  have   to   act.  This  description  draws  a   likeness  of  nudges,  which   is  

very   similar   to   the   utilitarian   project.   Bentham   was   the   first   (and   the   last)   British  

philosopher   to   endeavour   to   create   a   system   of   government   based   on   the   science   of  

motives.   Bentham   explains   the   founding   principles   of   his   system   at   the   start   of   the  

Introduction  to  the  Principles  of  Morals  and  Legislation:  

Nature  has  placed  mankind  under  the  governance  of  two  sovereign  masters,  pain  

and  pleasure.   It   is   for   them  alone   to  point  out  what  we  ought   to  do,  as  well  as   to  

determine  what  we  shall  do.  On  the  one  hand  the  standard  of  right  and  wrong,  on  

                                                                                                               17  On  this  point,  see  n.  13.  18  Sunstein,  Why  nudge?,  pp.  61-­‐71.  Means  paternalism  refers  to  initiatives  which  provide  steps  in  order  to  make  the  nudgee  achieve  the  end  promoted  by  the  paternalist.  19   Ends   paternalism   which   clearly   steers   the   nudgee   towards   the   preselected   choice.   S.   Conly   makes  roughly   the   same   distinction   with   the   two   concepts   she   uses:   libertarian   paternalism   and   coercive  paternalism.  See  Conly,  Against  Autonomy,  chapter  1.      20  Sunstein,  Why  nudge?,  p.  14.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

6  

the  other  the  chain  of  causes  and  effects,  are  fastened  to  their  throne.  They  govern  

us  in  all  we  do,  in  all  we  say,  in  all  we  think:  every  effort  we  can  make  to  throw  off  

our  subjection  will  serve  but  to  demonstrate  and  confirm  it.   In  words  a  man  may  

pretend   to   abjure   their   empire:   but   in   reality   he  will   remain   subject   to   it   all   the  

while.   The   principle   of   utility   recognises   this   subjection,   and   assumes   it   for   the  

foundation  of  that  system,  the  object  of  which  is  to  rear  the  fabric  of  felicity  by  the  

hands  of  reason  and  of   law.  Systems  which  attempt  to  question   it,  deal   in  sounds  

instead  of  sense,  in  caprice  instead  of  reason,  in  darkness  instead  of  light.21  

The  basis   for  Bentham’s   statement   is   scientific   observation.  The  observation  Bentham  

makes  helps  him  to  isolate  a  psychological  feeling  shared  by  all  sentient  beings.22  They  

are   at   the   source   of   our   actions:   human   beings   avoid   pain   and   seek   pleasure.   When  

individuals  decide  to  act  or  to  refrain  from  acting,  they  do  so  on  account  of  the  pleasure  

they  will  derive  or  the  pain  they  will  avoid.  Bentham’s  utilitarian  system  is  rooted  in  a  

scientific  analysis  of  the  psychological  springs  of  human  action.  Bentham’s  philosophical  

endeavour   goes   beyond   this   initial   psychological   assessment,   as   he   derives   from   this  

scientific  observation  a  moral  standard.  Pleasures  and  pains  are  not  only  what  motivate  

us  to  act,  they  are  also  the  standard  of  right  and  wrong.  In  this  quote,  Bentham  not  only  

gives   the   regulator   tools   to   frame   initiatives  which   alter   behaviour,   but   also   the   goal  

towards   which   behaviour   should   be   steered:   pleasure   rather   than   pain.   Bentham’s  

purpose  is  even  clearer  in  the  following  quote:  

The  principle  of  utility  is  the  foundation  of  the  present  work  […].  By  the  principle  

of  utility   is  meant   that  principle  which  approves  or  disapproves  of  every  action  

whatsoever  according  to  the  tendency  it  appears  to  have  to  augment  or  diminish  

the   happiness   of   the   party  whose   interest   is   in   question:   or,   what   is   the   same  

thing  in  other  words  to  promote  or  to  oppose  that  happiness.  I  say  of  every  action  

whatsoever,  and  therefore  not  only  of  every  action  of  a  private  individual,  but  of  

every  measure  of  government.23  

                                                                                                               21  J.  Bentham,  Introduction  to  the  Principles  of  Morals  and  Legislation,  in  Burns,  J.  H.,  Dinwiddy,  J.  R.  et  Rosen,  F  (eds.),  The  Collected  Works  of  Jeremy  Bentham,  Oxford  :  Clarendon  Press,  1996,  [1789],  p.  11  22  R.  Harrison,  Bentham,  London:  Routledge  &  Kegan  Paul,  1983,  p.  177.  Note   that   in   Introduction  to   the  Principles  of  Morals  and  Legislation,  Bentham  did  not   restrict   the   feeling  of  pleasure  and  pain   to  human  beings  only;  he  clearly  said  that  animals  could  experience  pleasure  and  pain.  23  Bentham,  Introduction,  p.  11.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

7  

There  seems  to  be  enough  similarities  between  Bentham’s  utilitarianism  and  nudges  to  

warrant  the  more  thorough  comparison  we  are  now  presenting.  

 

Now  that  the  linguistic  pitfalls  of  any  study  of  nudges  have  been  cleared,  the  present  talk  

can   move   on   to   its   core   argument   on   the   philosophical   underpinnings   of   the   nudge  

debate.  

 

2. Direct  and  Indirect  Legislation  

a. History  of  the  Text  and  Bentham’s  Terminology  

Bentham   is   remembered  as  a   legal   reformer,  who  stands   in   the  shadows  of  one  of  his  

most   famous  disciple:   JS  Mill.  One  of   the   reasons  of   this   neglect   is   that   the   sources   of  

Bentham’s  work  are  not  easily  accessible  (although  thanks  to  the  work  of  the  Bentham  

Project,   this   is   becoming   less   so).24  Writings   on   indirect   legislation   are   to   be   found   in  

many   different   manuscripts,   written   in   two   languages   (French   and   English)   and  

(re)published  by  two  different  editors.  Bentham  starts  writing  on  indirect  legislation  in  

1782,  in  a  document  named  Plan.  He  does  so  as  part  of  his  reflexion  on  what  would  have  

been  chapter  1825  of  the  Introduction  to  the  Principles  of  Morals  and  Legislation  referred  

to   in   the   quote   above.26   This  work   is   then   continued   in   French,   as   part   of   a   series   of  

manuscripts  entitled  Projet.  Etienne  Dumont,  his  Genevan  editor,  then  takes  up  some  of  

the  material  on   indirect   legislation   to   include   it  with   the  Traités  de   legislation   civile   et  

pénale,  which  is  first  published  in  French  in  1802.27  The  Traités  are  then  translated  into  

French  and  included  in  the  edition  of  the  Works  of  Jeremy  Bentham  in  1838-­‐43,  compiled  

                                                                                                               24   When   Bentham   died,   a   first   edition   of   his   works   was   compiled   by   his   secretary   John   Bowring.  Unfortunately  the  edition  was  far  from  scientific,  aggregating  parts  of  manuscripts  with  others,  publishing  versions  by  unapproved  editors,  publishing  English  translations  from  French  editions,  omitting  the  most  unpalatable  writings  on  religion  and  sex.  A  second  edition  is  now  underway  at  the  Bentham  Project  (UCL,  London),   publishing   volumes   directly   from   the   manuscript   sources.   Since   1968,   thirty   volumes   (of   an  anticipated  70  volumes)  of  the  new  collected  works  have  been  published.  30  volumes  in  48  years.  There  is  another   50   years   of   estimated   work   to   be   carried   out   before   the   final   complete   edition   of   Bentham’s  writings  be  made  available  to  the  wider  public.  Until  the  scientific  edition  is  completed,  the  only  accurate  source  of  Bentham’s  works  is  to  be  found  in  the  manuscripts  in  the  UCL  or  the  British  Library  fund.    25   Bentham’s   Introduction   contains   sixteen   chapters.   Chapter   17  was   extended   into  Of   Laws   in   General,  now  published  as  Limits  of  the  Penal  Branch  of  Jurisprudence,  and  deals  with  the  differences  between  civil  and  criminal  law,  basing  itself  on  the  analysis  of  what  ‘a  law’  is.  Chapter  18  was  meant  to  be  on  means  to  prevent  crimes,  that  is  the  ‘preventive’  branch  of  legislation,  otherwise  known  as  ‘indirect  legislation’.  26    Bentham,  Introduction,  p.  11.  27   J.   Bentham,  Traités   de   legislation   civile   et   pénale,  pref.  M.   Bozzo-­‐Rey,   A.   Brunon-­‐Ernst,   E.   de   Champs,  Paris,  Dalloz,  2010.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

8  

by  John  Bowring,  Bentham’s  last  secretary  and  executor.28  The  present  talk  investigates  

the   manuscript   and   published   sources   available   on   indirect   legislation.   However,   the  

present   speaker   believes   that   the   corpus   of   indirect   legislation   should  be   extended   to  

include  Bentham’s  writings  of  poor  law,29  the  Police  Revenue  Bill,30  political  economy31  

and   civil   law32   in   an   attempt   to   bring   a   fuller   picture   of   the   various   applications   of  

indirect  legislation.  

 

A   second   reason   for   our   philosophers   and   intellectual   historians   to   have   overlooked  

Bentham’s   work   and   heritage   is   that   Bentham   creates   a   new   self-­‐sufficient   system,  

which  uses   it   own   terminology   to  describe   its   objects.  This   is   all   the  more   true  of   the  

concept   of   indirect   legislation,   which   needs   to   be   defined.   To   understand   it,   the  

converse,  direct  legislation  also  needs  to  be  explained.  In  a  nutshell,  if  direct  legislation  

corresponds  to  laws  (although  as  we  shall  see  later,  Bentham’s  understanding  of  a  law  is  

more  encompassing  than  its  present  acceptation),  indirect  legislation  cannot  be  merely  

equated  with  non-­‐legal  regulatory   instruments.  The   legal/non-­‐legal  divide  needs   to  be  

explored.  

                                                                                                                 28  /ADD  REFERENCE/J.  Bentham,  Works  of  Jeremy  Bentham,  ed.  J.  Bowring,  1838-­‐1843,  11  Vols.  29   J.   Bentham,  Writings   on   the   Poor   Laws,   in   ed.  M.   Quinn,  The  Collected  Works  of   Jeremy  Bentham,   2   vols  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  2001),   vol.  1;   J.  Bentham,  Writings  on   the  Poor  Laws,   in.   ed.  M.  Quinn,  Collected  Works,  2  vols  (Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press,  2010),  vol.  2.  30  /ADD  REFERENCE/Bentham,  Works,  p.  XXX.  31  The  available  printed  editions  on  Bentham’s  economic  writings  are   to  be   found   in   J.  Bentham,   Jeremy  Bentham’s   Economic  Writings,   ed.  W.   Stark,   3   vols   (London:   George  Allen   and  Unwin,   1954)   and   in   the  Bowring  edition;  however,  M.  Quinn   is   editing  a  new  scientific   edition  of  Bentham’s   economic  writings.  The   reference   to   all   the   Bentham   economics   manuscript   sources   were   given   by   Dr   Michael   Quinn  (Bentham  Project,   UCL),   currently   editing   the   three   volumes   of   the  Economics  Writings   in   the  Collected  Works.  32  Bentham’s  writings  on  civil  law  have  not  all  been  edited.  Those  who  are  still  in  manuscript  form  are  to  be  found  in  UCL  boxes  4,  29,  30,  31,  32,  33,  37,  97,  98,  99,  100,  107a,  107b,  146  et  160.  Bentham’s  thought  on   civil   law   can   be   found   in   the   following   books:   J.   Bentham,   Manual   of   Political   Economy,   ed.   John  Bowring,  The  Works  of   Jeremy  Bentham,  Edinburgh,  1843,  vol.  3,  pp.  31-­‐84  ;   J.  Bentham,  Principles  of  the  Civil   Code,   ed.   John   Bowring,   The   Works   of   Jeremy   Bentham,   Edinburgh,   1843,   vol.   1,   pp.   297-­‐364  ;   J.  Bentham,  A  General   View   of   a   Complete   Code   of   Laws,   ed.   John  Bowring,  The  Works   of   Jeremy  Bentham,  Edinburgh,  1843,  vol.  3,  pp.  155-­‐210  ;   J.  Bentham,  Pannomial  Fragments,  ed.   John  Bowring,  The  Works  of  Jeremy  Bentham,   Edinburgh,  1843,   vol.   3,  pp.  211-­‐230  ;   J.  Bentham,  Nomography,   ed.   John  Bowring,  The  Works   of   Jeremy   Bentham,   Edinburgh,   1843,   vol.   3,   pp.   231-­‐283  ;   J.   Bentham,  Logical   Arrangements,   ed.  John   Bowring,   The   Works   of   Jeremy   Bentham,   Edinburgh,   1843,   vol.   3,   pp.   284-­‐295  ;   J.   Bentham,  Introduction  ;   J.   Bentham,   Of   the   Limits   of   the   Penal   Branch   of   Jurisprudence,   in   P.   Schofield   (ed.),   The  Collected  Works   of   Jeremy  Bentham   (Oxford:  Oxford  University   Press,   2010)   ;   J.   Bentham,  Constitutional  Code,  Vol.  1,  ed.  Fred  Rosen,  J.H.  Burns,  Oxford,  Clarendon,  1983  ;  J.  Bentham,  Legislator  of  the  World,  eds  Philip  Schofield  and  Joathan  Harris,  The  Complete  Works  of   Jeremy  Bentham,  Oxford,  Clarendon,  1998  ;   J.  Bentham,  Théorie  des  Fictions,  trad.  G.  Michaut,  Paris,  Editions  de  l’Association  Freudienne  Internationale,  1996.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

9  

Bentham’s   whole   intellectual   endeavour   can   be   aptly   summarized   as   the   attempt   to  

control   individual   action.   There   are   two   ways   to   control   individual   or   collective  

behaviour:   first,   direct   legislation,   otherwise   known   as   enacted   legislation   or   law,  

defined   as   the   expression   of   the   will   of   the   lawgiver   addressed   to   those   who   are  

subjected   to   his/her   will,   with   the   aim   of   controlling   their   actions   and   backed   by  

sanctions33  in  case  of  non-­‐compliance;34  and  second,  indirect  legislation,  which  is  are  the  

acts  taken  by  the  lawgiver  (or  any  other  agent)  to  influence  the  conduct  of  others,  either  

in  the  place  of  legal  punishment  (non-­‐legal  forms  of  regulation)  or  as  an  accessory  to  it  

(legal  form  of  regulation).35    

 

Control   in   Bentham   thus   operates   through   legal   and   non-­‐legal   means.   However   the  

distinction   is   not   necessarily   relevant   in   Bentham’s   plan   as   it   is   clear   that   all   laws  

contribute   to   the   formation   of   an   architecture   of   choice,   that   is   to   the   shaping   of   an  

environment   in   which   individuals   will   make   choices.36   There   is   a   tendency   to   read  

nudges  as  regulatory  mechanisms  used   to  replace   legal   instruments.  Although  there   is  

evidence  of  nudging  in  the  law,37  the  main  difference  remains  one  of  degree.  Nudgers  or  

soft-­‐paternalists  are  interested  in  default  options  which  are  easy  to  overcome,  and  this  

focus  seems  only  compatible  with  non-­‐legal  means  of  regulation  rather  than  legislation,  

which   is   the   preferred   option   of   hard-­‐paternalists.   However   for   Bentham   even   direct  

legislation   mandates   choices,   which   need   not   be   complied   with,   as   the   would-­‐be  

offender  might   choose   the  pain  of   punishment  over   the  pleasure  of   deriving   a  benefit                                                                                                                  33   See   J.   Bentham,  Of   the   Limits   of   the   Penal  Branch   of   Jurisprudence,   in   P.   Schofield   (ed.),   The  Collected  Works   of   Jeremy   Bentham,   Oxford:   Oxford   University   Press,   2010.   However   some   commentators   have  shied  away  from  this  interpretation,  finding  in  Bentham  signs  of  a  disposition  to  obey  (see  Constitutional  limits  and  the  Public  Sphere:  A  Critical  Study  of  Bentham’s  Constitutionalism,  Oxford,  Hart  Publishing,  2000,  49)   to  account   for   the   complex   reasons  why   individuals   abide  by  a   rule   (HLA  Hart,  Essays  on  Bentham:  Studies  on   Jurisprudence  and  Political  Theory,  Oxford,  Clarendon  Press,  1982,  252).  Their  arguments  are  convincing   and   complement   a   punishment-­‐orientated   law   in   Bentham   (Brunon-­‐Ernst,   Utilitarian  Biopolitics,  67-­‐85),  but  cannot  replace  overwhelming  evidence  of  the  primacy  of  punishment.    34  Bentham,  Traités,  24  and  M.  Bozzo-­‐Rey,  ‘Le  statut  du  principe  d’utilité  dans  la  philosophie  politique  de  Jeremy  Bentham’,  PhD  dissertation,  Paris  Ouest-­‐Nanterre-­‐La  Défense  University,  2007.  35  S.  Engelmann,  ‘”Indirect  Legislation”:  Bentham’s  Liberal  Government’,  in  Polity,  35:  3  (2003):  pp.  372f;  M.  Bozzo-­‐Rey,   ‘Le  statut  du  principe  d’utilité  dans  la  philosophie  politique  de  Jeremy  Bentham’;  Brunon-­‐Ernst,   Utilitarian   Biopolitics.   For   instance,   enacting   legislation   to   criminalize   the   purchase   of   services  offered  by  prostitutes   is  a   clear  example  of  direct   legislation  as   it  has   the   intended  effect  of  prohibiting  certain  categories  of  individuals  from  behaving  in  certain  ways  by  the  threat  of  a  legal  sanction.    However,  It   is  also  to  be  viewed  as   indirect   legislation  as   its  primary  goal   is  to  prevent  prostitution  by  prostitutes  (See  Bentham,  Traités,  pp.  375-­‐377).  36   M.   Quinn,   “Jeremy   Bentham,   Choice-­‐Architect:   Law,   Indirect   Legislation   and   the   Context   of   Choice",  Nudge  Project  Research  Seminar,  Université  Catholique  de  Lille,  19  juin  2015.  37  Sibony  and  Alemanno.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

10  

from  his  crime.  Therefore  the  distinction  between  legal  and  non-­‐legal  means  of  control  

as  it  is  understood  by  nudgers  does  not  overlap  the  one  made  by  Bentham.  

 

b. Indirectness  of  Indirect  Legislation  

A  better  grasp  of   indirect   legislation   (and   its   converse,  direct   legislation)   is  needed   to  

understand   the   thin   line   dividing   legal   and   non   legal   indirect   provisions.   To   date,  

courtesy   of  Michael   Quinn,   only   explanation   of   the   indirectness   of   indirect   legislation  

was  unearthed  from  the  manuscripts:  

7.  Seventh  Division.  Direct  legislation,  indirect  legislation.  I  call  direct  laws  those  

which  go  straight   to   their   target:   that   is  prohibiting  or  ordering   the  act   itself   in  

question  in  criminal  law;  expressly  deciding  that  a  title  to  property  or  a  position  

will  belong  to  this  or  that  individual  in  civil  or  constitutional  law.  All  other  means  

would  be  called  indirect.  The  same  law  which  is  direct  in  one  respect  in  relation  

to   an  end   is   indirect   in   relation   to   another   end.  This  division  was  perceived  by  

some  writers  but  not  determined;  and  nobody  has  ever  drawn  this  division  to  its  

ultimate  conclusion.  However,  it  can  be  considered  as  complete.38      

Bentham   points   the   indirectness   of   new   branch   of   legislation   as   opposed   to   the  

directness  of  direct  legislation.  The  obliqueness  of  indirect  legislation  refers  not  so  much  

to  the  non-­‐legal  nature  of  the  tools  used  by  indirect  legislation,  but  to  the  indirect  means  

used  by  the  legal  provision  to  achieve  a  certain  aim.  This  definition  will  nonetheless  be  

qualified   later,   as   we   will   see   that   indirect   legislation   can   also   encompass   non-­‐legal  

forms  of  control  which  are  akin  to  modern-­‐day  forms  of  regulation  such  as  nudges.  

 

Notwithstanding   this   explanation   of   indirect   legislation,   a   common   ground   of   all   the  

definitions  to  be   found  in  Bentham’s  writings  are  that   they  are  negative  definitions,  as  

indirect  legislation  is  defined  by  its  opposite:  direct  legislation.  Bentham  explains  in  the  

Plan:  

                                                                                                               38   UC   xxxiii.   111-­‐12.   I   am   grateful   to  M.  Quinn   for   this   quote.   ‘7.   Septieme  Division.   Législation   directe,  législation   indirecte.   J’appelle   loix   directes   celles   qui   vont   directement   à   leur   but:   savoir   par   exemple  défendre  ou  ordonner  l’acte  même,  dont  on  a  affaire  quand  il  s’agit  du  droit  pénal,  arrêter  expressement  qu’un  droit  de  propriété  ou  d’office  sera  en  telles  ou  telles  mains  quand  il  s’agit  du  droit  civil  ou  du  droit  constitutionnel.   Toute   autre   façon   d’agir   peut   être   appellée   indirecte.   La  même   loi   qui   est   directe   à   un  égard,  par  rapport  à  tel  fin,  est  indirecte  par  rapport  à  un  autre.  Division  entrevue  par  quelques  auteurs,  mais  non  determinée,  &  que  personne  ne  s’est  encore  avisé  de  pousser  à  bout.  Cependant  elle  peut  être  regardée  comme  complette’  [the  speaker’s  translation]  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

11  

To  begin  with  delinquency,  the  sovereign  may  be  said  to  act  against  delinquency  

in  the  way  of  direct  legislation,  in  as  far  as  he  contents  himself  with  prohibiting,  

under  such  penalties  as  seem  competent  to  each  case  considered  simply  by  itself,  

the  several  acts  which  are   intrinsically  obnoxious   to  him:   that   is,   supposing   the  

principle  of  utility  to  be  that  by  which  he  governs  himself,  the  several  acts  from  

which  he  conceives  mischief   to  arise.  To   the  head  of   indirect   legislation  may  be  

comprised  whatever   else   can  be  done   in   the  way  of   law   in   subservience   to   the  

same  end.39    

Let  us  spend  some  time  explaining  the  meaning  and  purpose  of  this  statement.  Bentham  

refers   to   the   field   of   criminal   law  mainly,   but   as  mentionned   in   the   first   quote   above,  

indirect   legislation  can  also  apply   to   the   fields  of  civil  and  constitutional   law.  Here   the  

sovereign   is  given   two   tools   to   fight  crime:  direct   legislation,  which  prohibits  acts  and  

punishes   any   transgression   of   the   said   prohibition   (our   criminal   laws   proper),   and  

indirect   legislation.   Indirect   legislation   seeks   to   achieve   the   same   aim   as   direct  

legislation,  but  using  different  means  (rewards  rather   than  punishments,   for  example)  

or  different  objects  (accessory  laws  to  use  Bentham’s  phrase,  that  is  adjective  law).  This  

is,   I   believe,   the   way   the   phrase   ‘whatever   else   can   be   done   in   the   way   of   law   in  

subservience  to  the  same  end’  should  be  understood.  

 

c. Indeterminacy  of  Indirect  Legislation  

In  our  main  quote  above,  indirect  legislation  is  referred  to  ‘whatever  else’,  which  points  

to   the   indeterminacy   of   the   means   used   by   such   a   method.   This   indeterminacy   is  

exemplified  in  the  indirect  ways  in  which  Bentham  tries  to  define  a  field,  which  cannot  

be   defined   in   an   unmediated   way.   Metaphors   help   to   draw   parallels   with   other  

mechanisms.  Bentham  compares  indirect   legislation  with  the  fluids  circulating  inside  a  

plant,  thus  reeling  out  metaphors  originating  in  nature  (storm,  sap  etc.).40  Bentham  also  

uses  geometry  to  explain  the  workings  of  indirect  legislation,  whereby  direct  legislation  

is   the   straight   line   where   indirect   legislation   is   an   oblique   line.41   He   also   refers   to  

                                                                                                               39  J.  Bentham,  Plan,  see  Bentham  Project  transcript  of  Plan  [my  emphasis]  40  ‘[I]n  the  [case  of  direct  legislation]  [the  legislator]  endeavours  to  carry  his  point  as  it  were  by  storm:  in  the  [case  of  indirect  legislation],  by  sap’,  in  Bentham,  Plan.  41   ‘In   the   [case   of   direct   legislation],   [the   legislator]   aims   directly   at   his   mark,   he   attacks   the  mischief  directly  and   in   front:   in   indirect   legislation  he  attacks   it  by  oblique  and   sometimes   scarcely  perceptible  approaches’,  in  Bentham,  Plan.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

12  

theatrical   and   hunting   metaphors,   with   the   idea   of   the   hunter   catching   game   and  

operating  behind  the  scenes,  screened  from  human  eyes.42  

 

The   indeterminacy   of   indirect   legislation   cannot   be   settled   by   a   straightforward  

definition.   Would   a   description   of   initiatives   falling   under   the   scope   of   indirect  

legislation   help   settle   the   meaning   of   this   new   category?   Bentham’s   lists   of   indirect  

initiatives   can   be   referred   to.   In   the   Traités,   Bentham   mentions   controlling   people  

through   pay,43   awarding   honours   to   reward   certain   types   of   behaviour,44   regulating  

data-­‐saving,45   promoting   public   education   rather   than   private,46   freeing   the   press,47  

indemnifying   the  victims  of   crime48   etc.     In   the  manuscript   source  named  Plan,  which  

pre-­‐dates   the  Traités,  Bentham  notes   that   the   following   indirect   initiatives:  procedure,  

prevention  of  crimes,  benevolence,  poor  law,  prevention  of  drunkenness,  promotion  of  

culture,   advocacy  of   activity  on   the   Sabbath,   rules   to   strengthen   the   administration  of  

justice,  new  remedies  for  crimes  of  honour,  information,  publicity  of  public  proceeding,  

marking  of   individuals,  registers,  standards  of  quantity  and  quality,  stamps,  account  of  

people  (census)  etc.  These  two  lists  gather  what  seems  to  be  a  hodgepodge  of  unrelated  

fields.  Bentham  was  well  aware  of  the  fact  as  he  writes  that:    

If   of   the   expedients   which   we   shall   proceed   to  mention   under   the   head   of  

indirect   legislation  there  should  be  some  which  may  appear  referable  to  the  

other  head  […].49  

Such  statements  are  far  from  helpful  to  circumscribe  the  meaning  and  scope  of  indirect  

legislation.   However   Bentham   believes   that   ‘the   sphere   of   indirect   legislation   will   be  

found  to  be  immense  in  detail  but  still  circumscribed  by  certain  bounds.’50  

 

The   issue   then   is   to   find   the   bounds   that   circumscribe   indirect   legislation.   Indirect  

legislation   could   not   be   defined;   neither   could   it   be   limited   by   open-­‐ended   list   of                                                                                                                  42  ‘In  Direct  Legislation,  the  Legislator  puts  on  his  armour  of  artificial  terrors,  and  stands  forth  confessed:  In  Indirect  he  nets  every  thing  by   imperceptible  wires,  keeping  himself  behind  the  curtain’,   in  Bentham,  ‘Appendix  I’,  in  Bentham,  Plan.  43  Bentham,  Traités,  p.  356.  44  Bentham,  Traités,  p.  356.  45  Bentham,  Traités,  pp.  369-­‐70.  46  Bentham,  Traités,  pp.  388-­‐90.  47  Bentham,  Traités,  p.  392f.  48  Bentham,  Traités,  pp.  404-­‐5.  49  BENTHAM,  Plan,  op.  cit.    50  Bentham,  Plan,  see  Bentham  Project  transcript  of  Plan  [my  emphasis]  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

13  

unrelated   acts.   However,   it   seems   that,   with   the   help   of   traditional   legal   divisions  

(criminal,   civil   and   constitutional),   Bentham   manages   at   least   to   situate   indirect  

legislation   within   the   architecture   of   laws.   There   is   a   consensus   among   Bentham  

scholars   that   indirect   legislation   deals   with   criminal   law.51   The   definition   of   indirect  

legislation   given   at   the   beginning   of   the   present   talk52   identified   criminal   law   as   the  

privileged  field  of  action  of   indirect   legislation.  The  issue  of  whether  civil   law  can  be  a  

field  of  operation  of  indirect  legislation  is  more  contentious.  Some  Bentham  scholars  do  

not  see  in  Bentham’s  works  any  sign  of  the  operations  of  indirect  legislation  in  the  field  

of   civil   law.  They  are   correct   in   the   sense   that  Bentham  did  not  develop   the   theory  of  

indirect   civil   law   to   the   same  extent   as   indirect   criminal   law.  This   statement  does  not  

imply  that,  in  practice,  Bentham  did  not  apply  indirect  means  of  control  to  issues  related  

to  civil   law.  In  the  example  above,  mention  is  made  of  marriage.  Within  the  traditional  

division   of   law,   marriage   remains   a   civil   issue.53   Other   academics   support   the  

contention.54   Constitutional   law   is   rarely   mentioned   as   allowing   indirect   legislation.  

However  Bentham  is  clear  that  there  can  be  indirect  constitutional  law.55    

 

It   seems   that   our   modern   day   categories   are   inadequate   to   make   sense   of   what   is  

indirect   legislation.   It   overlaps   both   civil,   criminal   and   constitutional   law;   as   well   as  

                                                                                                               51  See  in  particular  the  work  of  D.  Lieberman/ADD  REFERENCE/.  52   ‘To  begin  with  delinquency,   the  sovereign  may  be  said  to  act  against  delinquency  in  the  way  of  direct  legislation,   in  as   far  as  he  contents  himself  with  prohibiting,  under  such  penalties  as  seem  competent  to  each   case   considered   simply  by   itself,   the   several   acts  which  are   intrinsically  obnoxious   to  him:   that   is,  supposing  the  principle  of  utility  to  be  that  by  which  he  governs  himself,  the  several  acts  from  which  he  conceives  mischief   to   arise.   To   the  head  of   indirect   legislation  may  be   comprised  whatever   else   can  be  done  in  the  way  of  law  in  subservience  to  the  same  end’  (Bentham,  Plan)  see  note  15.  [my  emphasis]  53  The   statement   is  not   true   if  we   consider  Bentham’s  division  of   laws:   civil   law   is   a  dictionary  of   legal  concepts,  whereas  criminal  law  contains  the  punishment  attached  to  each  offense.  For  a  discussion  on  the  division  of  law  in  several  branches  and  a  bibliography,  see  A.  Brunon-­‐Ernst  ‘Délimiter  la  branche  civile  du  droit:  Bentham  et  la  quête  impossible’,  in  Bentham,  juriste.  Guillaume  Tusseau  and  Malik  Bozzo-­‐Rey  eds.,  Paris:   Economica,   2010,   pp.   177-­‐200;   and   A.   Brunon-­‐Ernst,   ‘Of   the   Limits   of   the   Civil   Branch   of  Jurisprudence  :  Background,  définitions  and  limits  of  Bentham’s  discussion  on  civil   law  in  Limits’,   in  The  Legal   Philosophy   and   Influence   of   Jeremy   Bentham:   Essays   on   'Of   the   Limits   of   the   Penal   Branch   of  Jurisprudence',  dir.  G.  Tusseau.  London:  Routledge,  2014,  pp.  117-­‐128.  54  S.G.  Engelmann,  ed.,  Selected  Writings  of  Jeremy  Bentham,  /ADD  REFERENCE/,  p.  12.  55   Bentham,  Traités,   p.   392:   ‘Constitutional   law   has   its   direct   and   indirect   legislation;   direct   legislation  consists   in   setting   up   the   offices   to  which   public   power   is   allocated   […].   Indirect   legislation   consists   in  general  precautions  to  prevent  the  misconduct,  incapacity  or  embezzlement  among  those  who  administer  in  chief  or  as  deputies’  [‘Le  droit  constitutionnel  a  sa  législation  directe  et  indirecte  :  la  législation  directe  consiste  dans  l'établissement  des  offices  entre  lesquels  toute  la  puissance  politique  se  trouve  partagée  :  il  n'en  est  pas  question  dans  cet  ouvrage.  La   législation   indirecte  consiste  dans  des  précautions  générales,  qui  ont  pour  objet  de  prévenir  l'inconduite,  l'incapacité  ou  les  malversations  de  ceux  qui  administrent  soit  en  chef,  soit  en  sous-­‐ordre.’]  [Translated  by  the  speaker]  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

14  

procedural  law  and  adjective  law;  it  deals  with  issues  related  to  poor  relief,  prostitution,  

marriage,   benevolence,   religion   etc.   Bentham   was   aware   of   the   difficulty   of   making  

indirect   legislation   fit   into   any   category.     However   Bentham   did   not   think   that   the  

efficacy  of  indirect  legislation  would  depend  on  what  he  considers  as  problems  related  

to   the   organisation   of   knowledge.   He   writes:   ‘it   will   be   no   great   matter:   nothing   of  

moment  will  turn  upon  the  accuracy  of  the  division’.56  

 

If   the   modern   scholar   finds   it   as   difficult   today   to   identify   clear-­‐cut   guidelines   to  

distinguish   indirect   legislation   both   from   legislation   and   from   any   other   form  of   non-­‐

legal  social  control,  Bentham  indicates  that  in  his  own  endeavour  he  also  found  himself  

in  a  tight  corner.    

 

3. A  Hierarchy  of  Norms  

The  main  quote  above  illustrates  also  the  fact  that  indirect  legislation  is  always  defined  

in  comparison  with  direct   legislation.  Examples  of   this  are   rife.57  This  also  means   that  

direct  and  indirect  legislation  are  not  to  be  understood  as  equal  in  value,  as  they  do  not  

operate   at   the   same   normative   level.   Indeed,   from   the   beginning   Bentham   created   a  

hierarchy  between  both  regulatory  instruments.  This  point  is  found  in  the  quote  above  

but  also  reasserted  in  the  quote  below:  

Indirect   legislation  may  assist  direct,  but  can  not  supersede  it.    The  one  and  the  

other   must   go   hand   in   hand.   The   events   which   call   for   the   infliction   of  

punishment  may  be  more  rare:  but  punishment  must  always  be  held  up.58  

Some  consequences  must  be  drawn  from  the  hierarchy  of  legal  norms  thus  highlighted.  

The  full  meaning  of  the  concept  can  only  be  understood  if  the  converse  concept,  direct  

legislation,   is   grasped.   On   account   of   the   close   relationship   between   both   forms   of  

control,  it  seems  now  necessary  to  give  a  short  outline  of  Bentham’s  legal  theory.    

 

Bentham  defines  a  law  as:  

                                                                                                               56  Bentham,  Plan.  57  ‘By  Indirect  Legislation,  the  physical  power  of  taking  the  measure  opposed  is  taken  away.  Direct  suffers  the   physical   power   to   remain,   but   against   the   interest   plays   off   another   interest.   Indirect   Legislation  operates  by  causing  men  not  to  have  certain  desires,  instead  of  thwarting  them  when  they  are  arisen’,  in  Bentham,  ‘Appendix  I’,  in  Plan  [my  emphasis]  58  Bentham,  Appendix  B,  in  Plan  [my  emphasis]  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

15  

A   law   may   be   defined   as   an   assemblage   of   signs   declarative   of   a   volition   or  

adopted   by   a   sovereign   in   a   state,   concerning   the   conduct   to   be   observed   in   a  

certain  case  by  a  certain  person  or  class  of  persons,  who  in  the  case  in  question  

are   or   are   supposed   to   be   subject   to   his   power:   such   volition   trusting   for   its  

accomplishment   to   the   accomplishment   of   certain   events   which   it   is   intended  

such   declaration   should   upon   occasion   be   means   of   bringing   to   pass,   and   the  

prospect  of  which  it  is  intended  should  act  as  a  motive  upon  those  whose  conduct  

is  in  question.59  

The  definition  exemplifies  the  specificity  of  Bentham’s  concept  of  law,  which  has  a  much  

wider  meaning  than  that  given  by  other  jurists,  as  it  includes  any  mandate  given  by  an  

individual   to  another,  where   there   is  a   relationship  of  obedience  and  where   the  order  

will  be  enforced   in  case  of  disobedience.  An  order  given  by   the  Monarch  or  a  piece  of  

legislation  passed  by  Parliament  is  as  much  an  instance  of  direct  legislation  as  any  other  

form  of  delegated  legislation,  such  as  the  order  given  by  the  master  to  his/her  servant,  in  

the   course   of   business,   or   a   parent   to   his/her   underage   child.   In   the   first   series   of  

examples,  the  law  will  be  said  to  be  made  by  conception,  and  the  second  by  adoption.60  

What  makes  a  law  a  law,  is  not  only  who  orders  whom,  since  (almost)  anyone  can  be  the  

sovereign  as  long  as  s/he  can  see  his/her  will  enforced.    

 

What  is  paramount  in  defining  a  law  is  whether  there  are  means  to  enforce  the  rule  in  

case   of   non-­‐compliance.   Thus   punishment   lies   at   the   heart   of   direct   legislation.61  

However,  if  Bentham’s  legal  theory  were  to  ground  legal  power  in  punishment  alone,  it  

would   provide   insufficient   tools   to   understand   the   complexity   of   today’s   world.  

Regulation  in  Bentham  uses  other  sanctions  than  legal/political  sanction/punishment  to  

help  secure  compliance.  Indeed,  in  Bentham,  there  are  four  sanctions:  the  political/legal  

sanction,  which  is  used  when  legal  punishment  is  applied,  the  moral/popular  sanction,  

when  the  people  pass  judgment  on  the  acts  of  another,  the  natural  sanction,  when  an  act                                                                                                                  59  J.  Bentham,  Of  the  Limits  of  the  Penal  Branch  of  Jurisprudence,  in  The  Collected  Works  of  Jeremy  Bentham,  Oxford,  OUP,  2010,  p.  24  [my  emphasis]  60   Bentham,   Limits,   p.   45.   See   also   M.   Bozzo-­‐Rey,   ‘Le   statut   du   principe   d’utilité   dans   la   philosophie  politique  de  Jeremy  Bentham’.  61  Other  commentators  have  shied  away  from  this  interpretation,  finding  in  Bentham  signs  of  a  disposition  to  obey  (see  Ben-­‐Dor,  p.  49)  to  account  for  the  complex  reasons  why  individuals  abide  by  a  rule  (see  Hart,  Essays  on  Bentham,  pp.  252-­‐7).  Their  arguments  are  convincing  and  complement  a  punishment-­‐orientated  law   in  Bentham   (see  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  Utilitarian  Biopolitics,  pp.   67-­‐85),   but   cannot   replace  overwhelming  evidence  of  the  primacy  of  punishment.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

16  

of  nature  makes  the  consequences  of  one’s  actions  bear  upon  oneself,  and  the  religious  

sanction,   when   individuals   act   in   certain   ways   to   comply   with   the   commands   of   a  

transcendent  being.  

 

The   comparison   with   direct   legislation   highlights   a   common   object   (controlling  

behaviour  to  maximize  utility),  common  regulatory  mechanisms  (the  use  of  one  of  more  

of  the  four  sanctions)  and  the  diverse  nature  of  the  legislator,  as  the  indirect  legislator  is  

any  person  who  acts  as  a  choice  architect.  Indeed  commentators  are  increasingly  aware  

of  the  combined  role  of  direct  and  indirect  legislation  in  controlling  behaviour.62    Indeed  

Stephen  Engelmann  writes:    

Bentham   conceives   all   legislation   as   control,   and   in   this   sense   it   is   direct   and  

indirect   at   the   same   time.   […]   So   indirect   legislation   recommends  ways   for   the  

legislator  to  enlist  other  sanctions.63  

A   more   minute   study   of   the   ways   sanctions   are   used   will   enable   us   to   identify   the  

specificity  of  indirect  legislation,  as  compared  with  other  means  of  control.    

 

4. Indirect  Legislation  and  Nudges  

When   legislating   directly,   the   legislator,   or   any   other   individual,   uses   motives   and  

sanctions   to  direct  behaviour  of   the  offender.  However  when  operating  at   the   level  of  

indirect  legislation,  the  legislator  acts  either  on  the  motives  of  a  different  player  (i)  or  on  

motives  from  a  different  angle  (ii).  

(i) In   this   first   form   of   indirect   legislation,   uses   the   same   sanctions   as   direct  

legislation,   that   is   the   political/legal   sanction.   A   specific   act   is   forbidden.   The  

commission  of   the   forbidden  act  will   lead  to  the   infliction  of  a  punishment,   the  

amount   of  which   is  measured   to   outweigh   the   probable   benefit   to   be   derived  

from  the  crime,  thus  with  the  hope  of  deterring  the  criminal  from  committing  the  

crime.   The   only   difference   is   that   instead   of   punishing   the   wrongdoer,   the  

legislator   punishes   another   player  who  might   benefit   also   from   the   act   of   the  

wrongdoer,   or   a   player   who  might   encourage   the   criminal   to   commit   his/her  

                                                                                                               62  See  Engelmann,  ‘”Indirect  Legislation”:  Bentham’s  Liberal  Government’,  pp.  372-­‐3,  Bozzo-­‐Rey,  ‘Le  statut  du   principe   d’utilité   dans   la   philosophie   politique   de   Jeremy   Bentham’,   and   Brunon-­‐Ernst,   Utilitarian  Biopolitics.  63   Engelmann,   ‘”Indirect   Legislation”:   Bentham’s   Liberal   Government’,   p.   371,   quoted   by   M.   Quinn,   in  University  College  London,  Bentham  Lecture  on  Indirect  Legislation.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

17  

crime,  or  be  instrumental  in  the  commission  of  the  offence.  For  example,  instead  

of   punishing   the   drunken  man,   Bentham’s   legislator  would   inflict   penalties   on  

the  bar   tender   for   the  sale  of  alcohol  or  on   the   farmer  who  produces  and  sells  

hops;   instead  of   punishing   the  prostitute,   the  pimp  or   the   consumer  would  be  

targeted.  In  this  form,  indirect  legislation  defines  accessory  offences  rather  than  

regulatory  mechanisms  akin  to  nudges.  It  is  not  the  case  with  the  second  form  of  

indirect  legislation.  

(ii) In   the   second   form   of   indirect   legislation,   the   legislator   uses   different   tools   to  

regulate  behaviour.  He/she  will  endeavour   to  nip  any  obnoxious  desires   in   the  

bud,   by   creating   an   environment   that   prevents   them   from   flourishing,   for  

example.   This   is   akin   to   the   way   in   which   nudgers   use   human   psychological  

flaws  to  make  the  choice  of  certain  option  more   likely   than  others.  One  way   in  

which   Bentham   does   this   is   in   setting   default   options.   He   writes:   ‘Indirect  

Legislation   operates   by   causing   men   not   to   have   certain   desires,   instead   of  

thwarting   them   when   they   are   arisen’.64   By   limiting   the   range   of   options   to  

choose  from,  Bentham  sets  default  options,  thus  gearing  individual  behaviour  in  

certain   ways,   which   are   more   likely   to   maximise   the   utility   of   individuals.  

Because   it   centres  on  human  desires,  and  because   it   is  a   form  of  social   control  

that  inflicts  less  pain  than  legal  punishment,  it  can  legitimately  stray  away  from  

the  field  of  crimes  per  se  (and  the  wrongful/criminal  acts  which  are  its  object),65  

to   control   almost   all   areas   of   individual   and   collective   behaviour,   such   as  

poverty,  drunkenness  etc.    

 

The  distinction  made  here  between  the  first  (legal)  form  of  indirect  legislation  and  the  

second   (non-­‐legal)   form   of   indirect   legislation   is   central   to   our   discussion   today   and  

resonates  with  the  nudge  debate.  The  title  of  Alemanno  and  Sibony  ‘s  book  is  Nudging  

and   the   Law,   thus   clearly   stating   that   nudges   can   operate   in   a   legal   framework   and  

                                                                                                               64  Bentham,  ‘Appendix  I’,  in  Plan.  Bentham  makes  a  similar  contention  in  the  later  Traités,    p.  341:  ‘L’objet  de  la  législation  directe  est  de  combattre  les  désirs  pernicieux  par  des  prohibitions  et  des  peines  dirigées  contre   les   actes   nuisibles   auxquels   ces   désirs   peuvent   donner   naissance.   —   L'objet   de   la   législation  indirecte   est   de   contreminer   leur   influence,   en   augmentant   la   force   des   désirs   moins   dangereux   qui  peuvent  entrer  en  rivalité  avec  eux’.    65  See  the  reasons  given  by  Bentham  to  allow  an  act  to  be  considered  as  a  crime  in  Bentham,  Limits,  p.  7:  ‘These   cases,   it   may   be   remembered,   are   of   four   sorts:   1.  Where   punishment   would   be   groundless.   2.  Where  it  would  be  inefficacious.  3.  Where  it  would  be  unprofitable.  4.  Where  it  would  be  needless.’    

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

18  

within  the  law.  Political  scientists  and  some  legal  scholars  have  been  interested  in  the  

nudge   phenomenon   on   account   of   its   displaying   non-­‐legal   forms   of   social   regulation.  

Nudging   was   seen   as   an   effective   and   cost-­‐effective   policy   tools,   as   it   did   not   entail  

costly   legislative   instruments   (costly   in   terms   of   the   task   of  managing   the   execution,  

correct   implementation  and  punishment   in  case  of  non-­‐compliance  with  the   initiative,  

and   costly   in   terms   of   the   degree   of   intervention   on   people’s   freedom   of   choice).  

However,   these   tools   can   also   be   used   in   a   high-­‐cost   environment   (i.e.   legislation)   to  

enhance   the   effectiveness   of   the   goals   it   sets   out   to   achieve.   This   legal   approach   to   a  

concept   which   was   mainly   discussed   among   political   scientists   up   to   now,   can   be  

reconciled   if   one   considers   choice-­‐altering   initiatives   (or   in   other   terms,   freedom-­‐

restraining   initiatives)   as   lying   on   a   continuum   of   degrees   of   interference   from  mild  

nudging  to  compulsory  legal  provisions.  Initiatives  need  to  be  ordered  on  a  scale  from  

milder   forms   of   intervention   on   the   individual’s   freedom   of   choice   (dubbed   soft  

paternalism   or   nudges)   to   more   intrusive   forms   of   intervention   (dubbed   hard  

paternalism).  The  highest   level   of   intrusiveness  on   individual   choice   is   reached  when  

the  initiative  takes  the  form  of  a  law.66    

 

This   distinction   between   the   primary   (legal)   form   of   indirect   legislation   and   the  

secondary   (non-­‐legal)   form   of   indirect   legislation   needs   to   be   further   explored   by  

looking   into   the   series   of   parameters   to   be   taken   into   account   when   acting:   the  

conditions   under   which   the   act   is   committed   (which   Bentham   names   motives   for  

action)   and   the   sanctions   (or   rewards)   imposed   on   the   commission   or   the   non-­‐

commission  of  acts.    

 

In   Traités,67   there   are   three   motives   to   act:   power   (to   be   understood   as   the   legal,  

physical   or   financial   power,   depending   on   the   manuscript   sources),   knowledge,   and  

interest  (that  is  the  motive  to  act).  The  first  aims  to  deprive  an  individual  of  the  power  

of  behaving  in  a  way  the  sovereign  (in  Bentham’s  sense)  does  not  wish  him/her  to  act.  

Bentham  names  it   the   ‘nanny  policy’,  as   it   is  the  attitude  of  nurses  when  looking  after  

                                                                                                               66  Sunstein,  Why  nudge?,  pp.  17-­‐18.  67   Traités   de   législation   civile   et   pénale   was   first   edited   by   Etienne   Dumont   in   French   with   Bentham’s  manuscripts,   and   later   translated   back   into   English   as   Principles   of   Penal   Law,   and   republished   in   the  Bowring  edition  of  the  Works  of  Jeremy  Bentham.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

19  

children,   taking   away   the   power   to   act.68   He   does   not   believe   it   is   a   relevant   control  

mechanism   for   indirect   legislation,   in   which   indirect   means   of   control   target   the  

accessory   or   other  motives   to   act.   The   second   seeks   to   circulate   knowledge,   so   that,  

thanks   to   a   wider   understanding   of   facts   and   of   the   consequences   of   one’s   actions,  

individuals  will  be  more  likely  to  make  the  right  decision  for  themselves.  The  third,  and  

most   important   tool   of   indirect   legislation,   are   inclinations.69   Inclinations   are   indeed  

paramount,  as  they  are  the  reasons  why  individuals  decide  to  act  (motives).  Inclinations  

(i.e.   interests   to   act)   are   generally   triggered   by   the   combined   forces   of   power   and  

knowledge.  

 

There  are  different  ways  of  directing  inclination.  Each  society,  in  a  particular  place  and  

at  a  particular  time,  has  its  own,  since  each  generation  has  its  own  range  of  values  and  

modes  of  life.  When  Bentham  gives  specific  instances  of  how  the  sovereign  can  control  

behaviour,   he   clearly   states   that   they   are   isolated   examples,   and   that   governments,  

institutions  and  organisations  should  find  their  own  indirect  regulatory  tools.70    

 

Indirect   legislation   works   mainly   with   knowledge.   It   supplies   knowledge   to   prevent  

crimes  or  to  promote  behaviour  that  will  maximise  utility.  If  individuals  are  aware  of  the  

ways   in  which   fraudsters   defraud   their   victims,   they  will   be  more   unlikely   to   fall   for  

their  tricks.  But  knowledge  can  also  be  used  to  promote  utility  maximizing  behaviour.  If  

I  have  information  on  population  trends,  I  can  set  up  a  business  that  will  tap  into  those  

resources.  Here  with  indirect  legislation,  as  with  contemporary  nudges,  the  legislator  or  

any   other   choice   architect   tries   to   improve   our   cognitive   limitations   to   fight   crime   or  

maximise  utility  more  generally.  Knowledge  is  thus  operative  for  both  forms  of  indirect  

legislation.  Is  knowledge  always  a  nudge?  Provision  of  information  by  economic  players  

or   by   government   agencies   must   not   always   be   considered   as   a   nudge   or   as   soft  

paternalism.   It   only   counts   as   a   nudge   when   the   information   is   provided   with   a  

                                                                                                               68  Bentham,  Traités,  vol.  3,  p.  332.  Idea  also  used  twice  in  the  Plan  as  ‘policy  of  the  nursery’  (§  2)  and  in  the  teachings  of  the  foolish  and  the  wise  nurses  (Appendix  I).  69  Bentham,  Traités,  p.  333.  70  Bentham,  Traités,  p.  355.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

20  

particular  aim  or  with  a  view  of  satisfying  a  particular  need.71  Provision  of   random  or  

non-­‐selected  information  is  not  a  nudge.72  

 

Indirect   legislation   channels  motives   in   certain   directions   thanks   to   the   combined   or  

alternate  operations  of  power,  knowledge  and/or  inclinations.  However,  in  order  to  be  

fully   effective,   the   inducements   provided   by   indirect   legislation   generally   need   to   be  

backed   by   sanctions,  which   act   as  motives   for   individual   action.  Of   the   four   sanctions  

described  above,  in  the  primary  (legal)  indirect  legislation  the  political/legal  sanction  is  

operative,  and  in  secondary  (non-­‐legal)  indirect  legislation,  the  popular/moral  sanction,  

through  the  Public  Opinion  Tribunal  (POT),  is  the  one  mainly  used.73    

 

The  POT  is  a   fictional  and  temporary  tribunal,  made  up  of  members  of   the  community  

interested  in  a  given  issue  and  passing  judgement  on  the  behaviour  of  public  officials  or  

other   individuals.   It   thus   hands   down   the   popular/moral   sanction   against   deviating  

groups  or  individuals.  Bentham  trusts  the  POT,  through  the  credit  or  discredit  it  will  cast  

on  certain  types  of  behaviour,  to  promote  certain  actions  and  discourage  others.  It   is  a  

self-­‐regulating  principle   in   society,   according   to   the  values  of   a  given  community  on  a  

given  issue  at  a  given  time.74  The  POT  relies  on  the  widespread  desire  of  human  beings  

to  fit  in,  thus  to  comply  with  a  behaviour  set  out  as  a  norm  of  the  community.  

 

Indirect  legislation  is  understood  as  using  three  different  tools  –  power,  knowledge,  and  

inclination   –   in   order   control   individuals.   The   use   of   public   opinion,   which   corrects  

behaviour  deviating  from  the  norm  set  by  the  community,  is  of  particular  importance  to  

                                                                                                               71  Sunstein,  Why  nudge?,  p.  64.  72   For   comments   on   provision   of   information   as   an   instrument   common   to  many   non-­‐legal   normative  tools,  see  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  “Le  gouvernement  des  normes  :  Jeremy  Bentham  et  les  instruments  de  régulation  post-­‐modernes”,  pp.  320-­‐321.  73  Bentham,  Traités,   pp.   380-­‐2;   392-­‐402   (for   the   constitutional   use  of   the  popular   sanction   through   the  Public  Opinion  Tribunal,  POT).  Human  beings  have  no   control  over   the  natural   events,   thus   the  natural  sanction  cannot  be  used  as  the  basis  of  legislation,  that  is  of  rationalised  and  scientific  policy-­‐making.  The  role   of   the   religious   sanction   is   more   ambiguous.   Bentham   recognises   that   it   can   have   an   effect   on  controlling  the  behaviour  of  God-­‐fearing  individuals.  However,  the  religious  sanction  as  it  does  not  aim  to  maximise  utility  but   a  body  of   rules   encapsulated   in   religious  dogma,   cannot  be   the  basis  of  Bentham’s  utilitarian  state.    74  For  the  operations  of  the  POT,  see  F.  Rosen,  Jeremy  Bentham  and  Representative  Democracy.  A  Study  of  the  Constitutional  Code,  Oxford,  Clarendon  Press,  1983;  LJ  Hume,  Bentham  and  Bureaucracy,  Cambridge,  Cambridge   University   Press,   1980;   P.   Schofield,  Utility   and   Democracy.   The   Political   Thought   of   Jeremy  Bentham,  Oxford,  Oxford  University  Press,  2009;  and  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  Utilitarian  Biopolitics,  67-­‐85.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

21  

add  motivation  to  individuals  to  act  in  the  way  that  is  required  from  them.75  Through  the  

use  of  default  options  and  the  combined  use  of  knowledge  and  the  sanction  of  the  POT,  

Bentham   plays   on   the   psychological   springs   of   individuals   to   conform   to   a   behaviour  

that  is  presented  as  a  norm.  In  its  second  form,  indirect  legislation  thus  uses  some  of  the  

regulatory  mechanisms  as  contemporary  nudges  as  described  by  Thaler  and  Sunstein.  

 

The  table  below  summarises  the  differences  highlighted  between  the  different  forms  of  

indirect  legislation  described  by  Bentham.  

 

Type   of  

indirect  

legislation  

Target   Motive   Sanction   Is  it  a  nudge?  

Primary  form  

(legal)  

Accessory   Power  

Knowledge  

Inclination  

Political/legal  

Moral/popular  

No  

Secondary  

form   (non  

legal)  

Behavioural  

bias  

Knowledge  

Inclination  

Moral/popular   Yes  

 

The   present   talk   has   so   far   highlighted   regulatory   mechanisms   in   Bentham’s   theory  

which   are   akin   to   contemporary   nudges.   The   aim   was   to   put   the   theoretical  

underpinnings  and  the  pragmatic  implementation  of  nudges  into  perspective.  Bentham  

thinks  he  is  the  first  to  theorise  regulatory  mechanisms  he  names  indirect  legislation.  As  

an  intellectual  historian,  the  present  talk  has  allowed  to  identify  the  philosophical  roots  

of  nudges,  which  have  wrongly  been  hailed  as  new  regulatory  mechanisms.  Beyond  the  

issue   of   historical   accuracy,   the   question   arises   of   what   can   Bentham’s   theorisation  

bring  to  improve  our  understanding  of  nudges.  

 

5. Lessons  of  Indirect  Legislation  

                                                                                                               75   On   the   issue   of   the   importance   of   public   opinion   and   peer   pressure   in   the   operation   of   indirect  legislation,   see  examples  given   in  Brunon-­‐Ernst  and  Van  Waeyenberge,   ‘Indirect   legislation   in  EU  policy  making  :   The   case   of   the   open   method   of   coordination’;   and   in   Brunon-­‐Ernst,   ‘Le   gouvernement   des  normes  :  Jeremy  Bentham  et  les  instruments  de  régulation  post-­‐modernes’.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

22  

 

In   the   1780s   and   in   the   1790s,   Bentham  develops   very   powerful  method   of   ascribing  

(unlimited)   power   over   individuals.   He   calls   this   method:   indirect   legislation.   The  

present  talk  has  shown  that  indirect  legislation  covered  widely  different  areas  of  action,  

some   of   which  would   fall   under   the   heading   of   the   law,   and   others   not.   Some   of   the  

initiatives  promoted  by  indirect  legislations  are  rooted  in  secrecy  as  direct  legislation  is  

in   publicity.   Some   administrative   processes   (one   example   is   registration   etc.)   can   be  

publicized  without  undermining  their  efficacy.  Indirect   initiatives  based  on  knowledge,  

to  inform  with  the  aim  of  preventing  crimes,  need  to  be  publicized  to  be  effective.  Some  

others   cannot.   For   example,   many   of   the   indirect   rules   relating   to   the   prevention   of  

poverty,  addiction  etc.  would  lose  their  power  if  they  were  expressed  and  explained  to  

the  general  public  (public  sham  executions  for  example).    

 

This  talk  has  shown  that  similar  methods  of  social  control,  backed  by  the  development  

of  behavioural  sciences,  some  of  which  are  inherited  from  Bentham’s  indirect  legislation,  

are   now   being   increasingly   applied   by   governments   and   companies   all   around   the  

world.   However,   at   the   turn   of   the   19th   c,   any   mention   of   indirect   legislation   was  

dropped   by   Bentham   in   his   theoretical   writings   and   practical   projects.   What   is   the  

reason  of  this  disappearance  of  any  mention  of  indirect  legislation?  

 

One  of  the  reasons  which  can  be  given  is  that  the  methods  used  by  indirect   legislation  

conflict  with  the  ultimate  aims  of  Bentham’s  utilitarian  society.  Indeed,  Bentham  wishes  

to  make   individuals   as   happy   as   possible   in   their   communities.   To   do   so,   he   bets   on  

institutions  that  will  promote  happiness.  Key  to  the  success  of  his  plan  is  the  wide  array  

of  safeguards  against  individuals  or  groups  seeking  to  deviate  the  benevolent  aims  of  the  

institutions   for   their   own   selfish   purposes.   In   Bentham’s   plan,   the   best   possible  

safeguard   against   misrule76   is   publicity.   Secrecy   hides   misdoings,   but   publicity,   at   all  

levels  of  public   life,   reveals  any  misdoing.  Publicity   in  Bentham   is  not  a  prop.   It   is   the  

very  core  of  his  system.    

                                                                                                               76  Of  note  the  fact  that  Bentham  thought  indirect  legislation  could  also  be  applied  to  fight  misrule:  ‘There  remains  that  branch  of  legislation  which  is  or  might  be  directed  against  misrule.  Even  under  this  head  the  distinction  between  direct  and  indirect  legislation  may  be  still  preserved;  though  the  limits  between  those  branches  are  scarcely  so  distinct  nor  is  the  distinction  itself  of  so  much  importance  in  this  case  as  in  the  former’  in  Bentham,  Plan.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

23  

 

 

Indeed,   the   very   nature   of   some   initiatives   falling   under   the   heading   of   indirect  

legislation  is  secrecy.  Bentham  was  well  aware  of  the  fact  and  mentioned  it  regularly  in  

his   writings,   as   here   in   Limits,   at   the   time   when   Bentham   was   writing   his   indirect  

legislation  projects,  were  mention  of  secrecy  is  made:  

Legislation  is  a  state  of  warfare:  political  mischief  the  enemy:  the  legislator  is  the  

commander:   the   moral   and   religious   sanctions   his   allies:   punishments   and  

rewards  …   the   forces  he  has  under  his   command:  …  direct   legislation,   a   formal  

attack   made   with   the   main   body   of   his   forces   in   the   open   field:   indirect  

legislation,   a   secret   plan   of   connected   and   long-­‐concerted   operations,   to   be  

executed  in  the  way  of  stratagem  or  petite-­guerre.77  

Why  is  secrecy  so  essential  to  indirect  legislation?  For  certain  initiatives,  their  efficiency  

is   based   on   the   fact   that   individuals   are   generally   unaware   that   their   desire   is   being  

manipulated.   Take   the   following   telling   example:   behavioural   science   has   established  

that   individuals   are  prone   to   comply  with  behaviour   that   is   presented   as   the  norm  of  

action.   As   a   consequence,   advertising   campaigns  make   good   use   of   the   fact,   referring  

frequently  to  the  wide  number  of  people  who  approve  of  a  product  (99%  of  women  are  

happy  with  the  effects  of  an  anti-­‐wrinkle  cream,  79%  of  people  donate  in  times  of  global  

emergency   etc).  Would   the   same   campaigns   have   the   same   effects   if   individuals  were  

forewarned  that  their  assent  or  benevolence  was  being  manipulated  by  the  impression  

they  get  that  they  need  to  comply  with  what  everybody  else  does?  

 

Strangely   enough,   if   any   mention   of   indirect   legislation   disappears   from   Bentham’s  

writings  and  his  project   is  neither   completed  nor  published,  Bentham  continues  using  

forms   of   control   akin   to   indirect   legislation   of   the   primary   (legal)   form,   that   is   using  

accessory   law   to   further   his   aims.   In   that   form,   indirect   legislation   seems   compatible  

with  a  well-­‐governed  utilitarian  State.  

 

A   utilitarian   State   could   not,   without   endangering   its   structure   and   the   safeguards  

against   misrule,   promote   at   the   same   time   publicity   and   secrecy.   From   the   grave,  

                                                                                                               77  Bentham,  Limits,  p.  233.  

WORKING  PAPER:  DO  NOT  QUOTE  Anne  Brunon-­‐Ernst,  ECPR  20-­‐24  Aug  2015,  Montreal  University  (CANADA)    

(French  Nudge  Project,  funded  by  Ecole  de  droit,  Sciences  Po,  Paris)      

24  

Bentham  asks  modern-­‐day  regulationists  to  raise  the  same  questions:  can  a  government  

created   for   the   benefits   of   the   governed   be   properly   managed   if   it   taps   into   the  

behavioural   failings   people   are   unaware   of?   Can   a   State  which   does   not   publicize   the  

reasons  of  its  action  escape  the  threat  of  tyranny?