Do transhumanist arguments from human nature provide us with sufficient reason to support...

31
1 Do transhumanist arguments from human nature provide us with sufficient reason to support enhancement technologies? Emily Morphy Student Number: 600011989 June, 2013 I hereby certify that, except where references show otherwise, all the material contained in the attached dissertation is entirely my own work.

Transcript of Do transhumanist arguments from human nature provide us with sufficient reason to support...

  1  

     

   

 

Do transhumanist arguments from human nature provide us with sufficient reason to

support enhancement technologies?  

Emily  Morphy  Student  Number:  600011989  

   

June,  2013  I  hereby  certify  that,  except  where  references  show  otherwise,  all  the  material  

contained  in  the  attached  dissertation  is  entirely  my  own  work.                  

  2  

         

   

Figure  1.  The  mythological  depiction  of  the  story  of  Prometheus.  In  this  image  Prometheus  is  receiving  punishment  from  the  Gods,  after  stealing  fire  to  give  to  

mankind.  

           

  3  

Table  of  Contents  1)  Introduction  ...................................................................................................................  4  2)  Defining  enhancement  technologies  .....................................................................  8          2.1)  The  enhancement/treatment  distinction  ..............................................................  8          2.2)  Do  means  matter  morally?  .......................................................................................  12  

3)  Human  nature  in  the  enhancement  debate  ......................................................  14  

4)  Assessing  the  transhumanist  approach  through  philosophical  anthropology  ....................................................................................................................  18  5)  Conclusion  ....................................................................................................................  28  

6)  References  ...................................................................................................................  29      

                                         

         

  4  

1)  Introduction    This  essay  will  propose  that  transhumanist  arguments  from  human  

nature  do  not  provide  us  with  sufficient  reason  to  support  enhancement  

technologies.  After  clarifying  the  concept  of  enhancement,  I  will  provide  a  

framework  for  understanding  how  human  nature  is  used  within  the  

enhancement  debate.  Specifically,  transhumanist  literature  refers  to  human  

nature  both  explicitly  and  implicitly  and  rests  on  a  historically  prevalent  view  

that  humans  are  by  nature  meant  to  master  nature  (Merchant,  1989).  Drawing  

on  the  work  of  Arnold  Gehlen,  I  propose  this  is  an  accurate  observation.  

However,  I  argue  that  this  observation  alone  cannot  provide  us  with  sufficient  

reason  to  support  enhancement  technologies.  In  particular,  I  suggest  the  

tranhumanist  movement  uses  the  human  drive  to  mastery  to  uphold  their  

morally  singular  approach  towards  human  nature  (Murray,  2007).  This  

approach  fails  to  acknowledge  that  mans  ability  to  “act  within  the  world”  is  

fundamentally  connected  to  his  “organic  deficiencies”  (Gehlen,  2002).    

Following  this,  I  argue  the  transhumanist  movement  needs  to  adopt  a  more  

detailed,  unified  understanding  of  human  nature  in  their  endeavour  to  change  it.    

 

Nevertheless,  before  addressing  the  above  arguments  in  turn,  one  must  

have  an  understanding  of  the  enhancement  debate  at  hand.  Transhumanism  is  a  

loosely  defined  philosophical  movement,  which  supports  the  use  of  

enhancement  technologies  to  overcome  the  limitations  of  human  nature  

(Bostrom,  2005(a):  202).  Transhumanists  seek  to  guide  us  towards  a  

“posthuman”  condition  (More,  1996).  In  this  posthuman  condition,  individuals  

will  have,  “greatly  exceeded  the  maximum  central  capacities  currently  attainable  

to  man”  (Bostrom,  2008:  1).  For  instance,  transhumanists  often  visualise  vast  

increases  in  human  health-­‐span.  “Healthspan”  is  our  capacity  to  remain  fully  

healthy,  active  and  productive,  both  mentally  and  physically,  and  it  has  been  

suggested  that  the  maximum  healthspan  currently  attainable  to  man  does  not  

exceed  far  past  80  years1.  However,  if  one  could  drastically  slow  down  the  aging  

                                                                                                               1  Although  individuals  often  live  longer  than  80  years  old,  they  do  not  normally  retain  the  capacity  to  be  fully  healthy,  active  and  productive  past  this  age,  nor  in  

  5  

process  through  genetic  engineering2  they  might  stretch  our  healthspan  to  

unimaginable  lengths,  making  it  posthuman  (Bostrom,  2008:  7).  With  such  a  

posthuman  healthspan,  individuals  would  live  longer,  indefinitely  free  from  

disease  and  aging,  exploring  a  wide  range  of  desirable  life-­‐plans.  However,  

transhumanists  are  not  only  concerned  with  improving  the  human  healthspan,  

but  insist  all  central  human  capacities  should  be  brought  to  a  posthuman  level  

(Bostrom,  2008:  7).  In  particular,  transhumanists  discuss  increasing  our  

intellectual  and  physical  capacities,  as  well  as  the  level  of  control  we  have  over  

our  emotional  states  and  moods  (Bostrom,  2005(a):  202-­‐3).  Transhumanists  

believe  through  improving  our  general  central  capacities,  we  will  not  only  begin  

to  overcome  our  biological  limitations,  but  will  be  able  to  explore  the  “larger  

space  of  possible  modes  of  being”  (Bostrom,  2005(b):  19).  The  possible  modes  of  

being  attainable  in  a  posthuman  state  would  be  better  and  more  worthwhile  

than  those  available  to  us  now  in  our  limited  human  states  (Bostrom,  2005(b):  

19).  Following  this,  transhumanists  often  emphasis  the  moral  urgency  of  

bringing  about  a  posthuman  state  through  enhancement  technologies,  helping  us  

to  lead  better  lives  and  overcome  suffering  (Bostrom,  2005(b):  19)  

 

  In  promoting  widespread  use  of  enhancement  technologies  to  bring  about  

a  posthuman  state,  transhumanists  emphasize  the  importance  of  both  

morphological  and  reproductive  freedom  (Bostrom,  2005(a):  203).  

Morphological  freedom  maintains  that  individuals  should  be  allowed  broad  

discretion  over  which  technologies  to  apply  to  themselves.  Similarly,  

reproductive  freedom  insists  parents  should  be  free  to  decide  which  

reproductive  technologies  to  use  when  having  children  (Bostrom,  (a)  2005:  203).  

The  reason  these  freedoms  are  crucial  to  the  transhumanist  agenda,  is  to  avoid  

any  single  or  authoritarian  approach  towards  enhancement  technologies  being  

imposed  on  all  (2005(a):  205).  The  movement  recognises  that  individuals  will  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                             comparison  to  their  younger  selves.  Following  this,  we  may  differentiate  healthspan  enhancements  from  lifespan  enhancements.  The  latter  would  include  living  longer,  without  living  younger  for  longer.  (Bostrom,  2008:  7)  2  See  Gems,  David.  (2003).  Is  More  Life  Always  Better?  The  New  Biology  of  Aging  and  the  Meaning  of  Life.  The  Hastings  Center  Report  33  (4).  pp.31-­‐39  for  further  details  on  the  progress  and  research  going  into  finding  the,  “gene  for  aging”.  

  6  

differ  profoundly  on  their  beliefs  towards  human  enhancement,  and  should  be  

free  to  express  such  beliefs  (2005  (a):  203).  One  may  question  whether  

morphological  or  reproductive  freedom  could  really  prevent  such  outcomes.  Yet,  

for  the  purposes  of  our  discussion  it  is  more  significant  to  acknowledge  how  

transhumanism  emphasises  individual  self-­‐expression  and  self-­‐creation  as  being  

an  authentic  and  valuable  part  of  human  enhancement  (DeGrazia,  2000).  

Drawing  on  Thomas  Murray’s  discussion  of  ‘human  nature  within  the  

enhancement  debate’,  we  will  consider  in  greater  depth,  this  transhumanist  idea  

of  “the  self-­‐made  man”  (Murray,  2007:  502).  Specifically,  I  will  analysis  whether  

such  an  understanding  of  man  is  persuasive,  or  provides  us  with  a  reason  to  

support  enhancement  technologies.  After  all,  wilful  self-­‐design  is  seen  as  a  

distinctly  human  enterprise  by  transhumanists,  and  often  valued  for  its  own  sake  

(Murray,  2007:  501).    

 

Despite  the  suggestions  above,  the  range  of  individuals  who  oppose  the  

use  of  enhancement  technologies  to  alter  the  human  condition  may  be  called  

‘bio-­‐conservatives’  3  (Bostrom,  2005  (a):  202).  Some  of  the  influential  writers  

within  this  field  include,  Leon  Kass,  Francis  Fukuyama,  Bill  McKibben,  George  

Annas,  Wesley  Smith  and  Jeremy  Rifkin.  Bio-­‐conservatives  often  demand  broad  

bans  on  enhancement  technologies,  producing  a  large  variety  of  objections  to  

support  this  claim  (Bostrom,  2005(a):  202).  Nevertheless,  Baylis  and  Robert,  

suggest  most  of  the  bio-­‐conservative  objections  to  enhancement  technologies  

typically  belong  to  one  of  the  following  categories  (Baylis  and  Robert,  2004:  5):  

(i)  enhancement  technologies  are  intrinsically  wrong;  (ii)  the  effectiveness  of  

enhancement  technologies,  and  their  likely  negative  biological  consequences;  

(iii)  the  widespread  misuse  of  enhancement  technologies,  producing  harmful  

social  consequences;  and  (iv)  the  means  of  achieving  laudable  ends  are  not  all  

equally  morally  meritorious  (Baylis  and  Robert,  2004:  6).  Criticisms  belonging  to                                                                                                                  3  As  noted  by  Parens  in  “Authenticity  and  Ambivalence:  Towards  Understanding  the  Enhancement  Debate”  (2005:  34),  the  contra-­‐enhancement,  bio-­‐conservative  camp  does  not  merely  consist  of  political  conservatives.  Following  this,  the  difference  between  bio-­‐conservatives  and  transhumanists  should  not  be  understood  in  purely  political  terms.  There  are  a  large  number  of  those  opposed  to  enhancement  technologies  are  also  political  liberals,  such  as,  Susan  Bordo,  Alice  Dreger,  Carl  Elliott,  and  Thomas  Murray  to  name  a  few.    

  7  

the  first  category,  may  question  whether  enhancement  technologies  will  

transgress  divine  or  natural  laws.  Such  objections  can  be  argued  on  either  

religious  or  secular  grounds,  and  oppose  a  transhumanist  understanding  of  

“what  it  means  to  be  human”  (Baylis  and  Robert,  2004:  6).  In  the  second  

category,  enhancement  technologies  are  criticised  for  fear  of  threatening  genetic  

diversity,  or  entailing  an  unacceptable  level  of  risk  of  harm  for  those  being  

enhanced.  Similarly,  the  third  category  of  objections  reject  enhancement  

technologies  on  the  basis  they  threaten  to  widen  the  gap  between  the  “haves”  

and  the  “have-­‐nots”,  promote  social  conformity  and  homogeneity,  undermine  

free  choice  and  would  entail  a  misuse  of  social  resources  (Baylis  and  Robert,  

2004:  6-­‐13).  Finally,  the  last  category  questions  whether  the  means  by  which  

certain  enhancement  technologies  try  and  achieve  praiseworthy  ends  matter  

morally.    

 

The  categories  proposed  by  Baylis  and  Robert  demonstrates  the  range  of  

objections  used  by  bio-­‐conservatives  within  the  enhancement  debate4.  This  

essay  is  not  an  attempt  to  address  all  criticisms  directed  at  the  transhumanist  

agenda.  However,  I  will  consider  whether  various  bio-­‐conservative  objections,  

particularly  those  surround  human  nature,  become  more  persuasive  in  light  of  

observations  made  within  philosophical  anthropology.  In  doing  so,  I  will  

encourage  one  to  consider  whether  a  pro-­‐enhancement  “romantic-­‐Promethean”  

view  of  human  nature,  being  to  dominate  nature,  should  really  be  seen  as  a  

persuasive  approach,  leading  to  desirable  outcomes  (Murray,  2007:  501).  

Furthermore,  although  the  divide  between  those  pro  and  contra-­‐enhancement  is  

very  distinct,  it  is  important  to  remember  that  a  key  difference  between  those  

who  are  anti-­‐enhancement  and  pro-­‐enhancement  largely  rests  on  an  

appreciation  of  different  values  (Parens,  2005).  As  noted  by  Bostrom,  bio-­‐

conservatives  draw  attention  to  the  ‘subtle  human  values’  they  fear  will  be  

                                                                                                               4  I  have  draw  upon  the  categories  discussed  by  Francoise  Baylis  and  Jason  Robert.  However,  objections  to  enhancement  technologies  are  often  used  in  combination  with  each  other,  making  a  case  against  enhancement  more  persuasive.  Furthermore,  the  suggested  categories  do  not  represent  all  criticisms  ever  use  within  the  context  of  this  debate,  mainly  a  variety  of  which  are  commonly  used  by  bio-­‐conservatives.    

  8  

eroded  by  technological  mastery,  claiming  transhumanists  need  to  develop  more  

sensitivity  for  these  concerns  (Bostrom,  2005(b):  22).  Meanwhile,  

transhumanists  emphasize  the  possible  improvements  for  human  well-­‐being  and  

flourishing  attainable  through  technological  advance,  arguing  that  bio-­‐

conservatives  should  try  and  appreciate  the  realization  of  these  great  values  

made  possible  by  venturing  beyond,  rather  than  preserving,  our  current  state  

(Bostrom,  2005(b):  22).  Nevertheless,  both  perspectives  agree  we  face  a  realistic  

prospect  of  technological  development  that  will  enable  us  to  substantially  

transform  the  human  condition  in  this  century  (Bostorm,  2005  (b):  22).  

 

 

2)  Defining  enhancement  technologies  

  2.1)  The  enhancement/treatment  distinction      

In  discussing  the  permissibility  of  enhancement  technologies  it  is  

important  to  understand  what  is  included  and  excluded  by  the  term.  What  do  we  

mean  when  we  say  someone  has  been  enhanced?  What  is  the  difference  between  

technologies  that  work  as  a  therapy  and  those  that  take  an  individual  beyond  

“normal”  functioning  or  health?  Enhancement  technologies  come  in  a  variety  of  

forms  and  are  typically  contrasted  with  technologies  used  for  therapy  or  

treatment.  However,  the  distinction  between  therapy  and  enhancement  may  

sometimes  appear  arbitrary  (DeGrazia,  2005(a)).  Therefore,  let  us  acknowledge  

the  difficulty  in  tightly  defining  enhancement  technologies  before  questioning  

how  such  technologies  threaten  different  ideas  of  what  it  means  to  be  human.    

 

The  term  ‘technology’  itself  can  be  used  to  express  almost  any  range  of  

different  things,  actions,  processes,  methods  and  systems  (Kline,  2003:  209).    For  

both  Heidegger  and  Jacques  Ellul,  technology  was  an  entire  way  of  being  in  the  

world,  a  social  and  material  phenomena  (Kass,  2002:  33).  Hence,  while  the  term  

often  refers  to  a  particular  tool  or  machine,  it  also  refers  to  a  wide  range  of  

techniques  outside  of  the  merely  physical  or  material  (Kass,  2002:  32).  Similarly,  

when  speaking  of  “enhancement  technologies”  one  may  be  addressing  a  

  9  

multitude  of  different  processes,  ranging  anywhere  from  drinking  coffee  to  

nanotechnology.  Nevertheless,  enhancement  technologies  can  be  defined  as,  

“those  technologies  employed  for  the  purpose  of  enhancement”  (DeGrazia,  

2005(b):  205).  Under  this  definition,  the  same  technology  will  appear  to  be  an  

enhancement  in  certain  contexts,  yet  not  in  others  (DeGrazia,  2005  (b):  206).  

Following  this,  DeGrazia  suggests  exercise,  cosmetic  surgery,  SSRIs,  steroids,  and  

genetic  technologies  can  all  be  seen  as  enhancements  when  used  to  fulfil  a  desire  

for  self-­‐improvement,  beyond  what  is  needed  for  normal  health  (Juengst,  1998:  

32;  DeGrazia,  2005(a):  263).  On  the  other  hand,  when  these  technologies  are  

used  to  restore  an  individual  back  to  normal  health,  or  in  response  to  genuine  

medical  needs,  they  may  be  considered  a  therapy  or  treatment.  Although  both  

forms  of  technologies  are  aimed  towards  human  improvement,  the  purposes  for  

which  they  are  used  is  what  allows  us  to  identify  them  (Juentst  1998:  32;  

DeGrazia,  2005(a):  263).  

 

However,  DeGrazia  acknowledges  some  of  the  difficulties  that  arise  from  

the  common  enhancement/therapy  distinction.  He  notes  that  in  certain  cases  the  

distinction  between  treatment  and  enhancement  will  appear  arbitrary  because  

our  distinction  between  normal  and  abnormal  health  will  sometimes  appear  

arbitrary  (DeGrazia,  2005(a):  263).  Consider  his  discussion  of  the  drug  Prozac.  

DeGrazia  refers  to  the  example  of  a  woman  called  ‘Marina’,  who  desires  to  use  

Prozac  as  a  means  of  improving  her  personal  life,  sociability  and  performance  at  

work  (DeGrazia,  2000:  35).  Although  she  suffers  from  various  psychological  

issues,  she  does  not  have  any  diagnosable  disorder.  Therefore,  Marina’s  use  of  

Prozac  would  be  seen  as  an  enhancement,  bringing  her  to  a  state  that  is  above  

normal  functioning  health  and  making  her  “better  than  well”(Elliot,  2003).  

However,  one  might  reasonably  question  this  distinction.  Specifically,  one  might  

reject  the  idea  that  Marina  should  not  receive  Prozac  on  the  basis  it  is  an  

enhancement  that  would  not  be  responding  to  any  genuine  medical  needs.  After  

all,  it  has  been  argued  that  patients  such  as  Marina  are  not  meaningfully  or  

significantly  different  from  those  patients  who  barely  qualify  as  having  a  

psychological  disorder,  yet  are  still  prescribed  the  drug  as  treatment  (DeGrazia,  

2005(a):  263).  Following  this,  it  is  not  clearly  identifiable  when  technologies  

  10  

such  as  Prozac  finish  working  as  a  therapy  and  start  acting  as  a  form  of  

enhancement.    

 

Similarly,  the  growing  demand  for  synthetic  growth  hormone  (GH)  in  

America  also  helps  demonstrate  how  the  distinction  between  normal  and  

abnormal  health  can  appear  arbitrary5.  Children  who  are  very  short  due  to  a  

deficiency  in  growth  hormone,  are  prescribed  synthetic  GH  as  a  treatment.  

However,  there  are  children  who  are  equally  as  short,  yet  classified  as  “normal”  

because  their  height  is  inherited  from  their  parents  and  they  have  acceptable  

levels  of  GH  (DeGrazia,  2005(b):  206).  For  these  children  to  receive  synthetic  GH  

it  would  be  considered  an  enhancement.  Yet,  both  groups  of  children  suffer  the  

same  disadvantages  of  being  short  in  a  culture  that  values  tall  stature  and  stand  

to  gain  equally  from  receiving  the  drug  (White,  1993;  Parens,  1998:  6).  

Therefore,  one  may  question  how  meaningful  it  is  to  claim  that  the  first  group  of  

children  are  receiving  a  treatment  to  bring  them  to  normal  functioning  health,  

while  the  second  group  would  be  receiving  an  enhancement  that  takes  them  

above  and  beyond  normal  functioning  health.  Arguably  the  

treatment/enhancement  distinction  merely  obscures  our  responsibility  to  

respond  to  the  equal  suffering  of  both  groups  and  should  be  revaluated  (Parens,  

1998:  6).  After  all,  if  both  groups  of  children  will  gain  equally  from  receiving  

synthetic  GH,  how  is  the  latter  group  being  made  better  than  well,  or  being  

taking  beyond  normal  functioning  health?  Again  the  distinction  between  normal  

and  abnormal  health  appears  weak.  Furthermore,  the  capacities  used  to  

distinguish  normal  health,  not  only  vary  within  a  population  but  also  within  the  

lifespan  of  a  single  individual  (Roache,  2007:  122).    Consider,  as  humans  mature  

their  physical  and  mental  capacities  increase  within  certain  boundaries,  yet  as  

they  grow  old,  these  same  capacities  decline  drastically  (Roache,  2007:  122).  

Following  this,  one  may  question  whether  a  technology  that  would  enable  an  

elderly  person  to  have  the  same  physical  stamina,  visual  acuity  and  reaction  time  

as  he  experienced  in  his  youth,  would  constitute  as  an  enhancement  or  a  therapy  

                                                                                                               5  For  background,  see  White,  Gladys.  (1993).  Human  Growth  Hormone:  The  Dilemma  of  Expanded  Use  in  Children.  Kennedy  Institute  of  Ethics.  Journal  (3),  pp.401-­‐409.  

  11  

(Roache,  2007:  122)?  This  type  of  intervention  would  restore  an  individual’s  

capacities  back  to  those  experienced  in  earlier  life,  reducing  the  risk  of  illness  

and  disease.  Nevertheless,  such  an  intervention  may  be  understood  as  existing  

outside  the  proper  domain  of  medicine,  working  as  a  healthspan  enhancement  to  

slow  the  aging  process  past  normal  functioning  health  (Roache,  2007:  122).    

 

Following  this,  Erik  Paren’s  acknowledges  at  the  root  of  this  problem,  is  

the  failure  to  find  a  single,  universally  accepted  conception  of  what  “health”  is  

(Parens,  1998:  3).  Consider,  Norman  Daniels  or  those  who  uphold  a  “hard-­‐line”  

conception  of  health,  which  define  a  healthy  state  as  one  that  is  free  from  disease  

and  disability  (Parens,  1998:  3).  On  the  other  hand,  the  World  Health  

Organisation  define  their  concept  of  health  as  a  “state  of  complete  physical,  

mental  and  social  well-­‐being”  (Parens,  1998:  3).  Following  these  definitions,  it  is  

not  surprising  that  we  struggle  to  find  a  universally  accepted  definition  of  what  

“going  beyond  health  to  enhancement”  means,  since  the  concept  of  “health”  itself  

is  under  question  (Parens,  1998:  3).  After  all,  if  one  believes  being  healthy  is  

being  free  of  disease,  then  Marina’s  use  of  Prozac  will  be  an  enhancement,  

whereas  if  one  supports  a  definition  of  health  closer  to  that  of  the  World  Health  

Organisation,  her  use  Prozac  would  be  classified  as  a  treatment.  Equally,  the  

definition  of  health  one  endorses  would  influence  their  stance  on  whether  

children  with  “normal”  GH  should  receive  synthetic  GH,  or  whether  certain  

technologies  are  outside  the  proper  domain  of  medicine.  Hence,  whilst  the  

definition  of  “health”  one  supports  is  no  trivial  matter,  it  is  important  to  

acknowledge  that  an  element  of  personal  opinion  always  plays  a  role  within  the  

context  of  this  debate,  meaning  our  definition  of  what  is  an  enhancement  or  an  

enhancement  technology  suffers  under  exceptional  circumstances.  Nevertheless,  

although  the  status  of  an  enhancement  technology  can  be  problematic,  DeGrazia  

suggests  that  such  a  distinction,  however  vague,  is  identifiable  in  most  cases  

(DeGrazia,  2005(a):  263).  Specifically,  it  is  identifiable  with  those  technologies  

that  look  to  fundamentally  alter  the  human  condition  and  bring  about  a  

posthuman  state,  such  as  genetic  engineering  or  nanotechnology.  Furthermore,  

bio-­‐conservatives  need  this  distinction  in  order  to  name  the  class  of  intervention  

they  intend  to  oppose  and  to  prevent  the  concept  of  enhancement  from  

  12  

collapsing  into  a  concept  of  technology  more  generally  (Roache,  2007:  122;  

DeGrazia,  2005(a):  263).  For  these  reasons,  this  essay  will  continue  on  the  basis  

that  such  a  distinction  can  be  meaningfully  discussed.  

 

 

  2.2)  Do  means  matter  morally?    

  As  suggested,  an  enhancement  technology  is  a  technology  employed  for  

the  purposes  of  enhancement-­‐  fulfilling  a  desire  for  self-­‐improvement  beyond  

what  is  needed  for  “normal”  functioning  health.  Nevertheless,  DeGrazia  suggests  

another  common  way  enhancements  are  identified  by  is  the  nature  of  their  

‘means’,  regardless  of  whether  or  not  the  intervention  is  deemed  medically  

necessary  (DeGrazia,  2000:  36;  Juengst,  1998:  38).  He  believes  many  forms  of  

self-­‐improvement  are  identified  and  deemed  admirable  if  they  are  achieved  by  

natural  means.  Similarly,  other  forms  of  self-­‐improvement  are  identified  as  being  

artificial  and  hence  morally  problematic  (DeGrazia,  2000:  36).  For  example,  if  an  

individual  studies  for  an  exam  or  exercises,  his  activities  are  praised  as  virtuous,  

enhancing  physical  and  intellectual  development.  On  the  other  hand,  if  an  

individual  uses  Ritalin  to  improve  intellectual  achievements  or  steroids  to  

improve  athletic  performance,  his  enhancements  are  understood  as  artificial,  

corrosive  shortcuts  that  render  the  self-­‐improvement  they  produce  as  morally  

suspect  (DeGrazia,  2000:  36).    

 

However,  transhumanists  reject  a  distinction  between  the  artificial  and  

the  natural,  emphasising  the  way  in  which  unnatural  enhancement  technologies  

pursue  the  same  desirable  goals  or  ends  as  generic  enhancement  (Baylis  and  

Robert,  2004:  5;  Parens,  1998:  12).  Parens  describes  this  as  “an  argument  from  

precedent”  (Parens,  1998:  12).  Despite  never  being  put  into  such  an  explicit  

form,  he  suggests  the  implicit  structure  of  this  argument  is  as  follows:  We’ve  

always  used  means  A  to  achieve  end  A;  means  B  also  aims  to  achieve  end  A;  

therefore  means  B  is  morally  unproblematic  (Parens,  1998:12).  For  example,  

Savulescu  makes  a  claim  such  as  this  when  discussing  genetic  engineering.  He  

writes,  “there  is  no  morally  relevant  difference  between  producing  a  smarter  

  13  

child  by  immersing  that  child  in  a  stimulating  environment,  giving  the  child  a  

drug,  or  directly  altering  the  child’s  brain  or  genes”  (Savulescu,  2007:  522).  

Despite,  some  of  these  interventions  being  “artificial”  and  some  being  “natural”,  

Savulescu  insists  such  a  distinction  is  irrelevant,  for  in  all  cases  the  child’s  

intellectual  development  is  improved.  Furthermore,  without  a  morally  relevant  

difference  between  natural  enhancement  and  artificial  enhancement,  why  not  

support  enhancement  technologies  also  looking  to  improve  the  human  condition  

as  simply  being  “more  of  the  same”  (Baylis  and  Robert,  2004:  13;  Brock,  1998)?    

 

  Yet,  Cole-­‐Turner  suggests  the  objection  regarding  ‘means’  is  not  merely  a  

superficial  claim  that  natural  is  always  good  and  artifice  is  always  bad  (Cole-­‐

Turner,  1998:  152).  To  claim  human  enhancement  is  praiseworthy  only  when  it  

is  achieved  by  natural  means  would  be  a  limited  argument  (Cole-­‐Turner,  1998:  

152).  It  would  provoke  questions  such  as,  why  is  the  “natural”  better  than  the  

“artificial”?  However,  new  artificial  means  of  self-­‐improvement  will  most  likely  

help  us  achieve  our  goals  more  quickly  and  efficiently  than  natural  means.  

Furthermore,  it  is  not  necessarily  clear  that  we  are  “natural  beings”  who  are  

meant  to  exist  “naturally”,  in  any  strict  sense  of  the  word.  This  idea  will  be  

discussed  at  greater  length  with  Gehlen,  who  suggests  humans  have  always  lived  

in  a  “second  nature”  (Gehlen,  2002:  66).  Nevertheless,  for  now  it  is  significant  to  

note  that  arguments  based  on  “means”,  do  not  necessarily  reject  enhancement  

technologies  simply  because  they  are  artificial  or  unfamiliar.  Rather,  bio-­‐

conservatives  question  whether  the  means  of  human  enhancement  are  purely  

instrumental,  or  could  be  understood  as  valuable  in  themselves,  independent  of  

their  ends  (Cole-­‐Turner,  1998:  155;  Baylis  and  Robert,  2004:  13).  Whilst  

transhumanists  suggest  enhancement  technologies,  from  education  to  germ-­‐line  

engineering,  all  exist  on  a  continuum  which  promotes  the  same  goal  of  human  

enhancement,  bio-­‐conservatives  do  not  think  it  is  clear  the  ends  justify  the  use  of  

any  and  all  possible  means  (Baylis  and  Robert,  2004:  13).  They  suggest  that  the  

experience  of  human  accomplishment  may  be  valuable  rather  than  just  the  

accomplishment  itself.  For  instance,  the  experience  of  climbing  a  mountain  peak  

may  be  valuable  due  to  the  physical  and  mental  discipline,  the  experience  of  the  

gradually  opening  vistas,  and  the  sense  of  personal  accomplishment  involved  in  

  14  

climbing,  all  independent  of  reaching  the  peak  itself  (Cole-­‐Turner,  1998:  155).  

Hence,  if  one  was  to  fly  to  the  top  of  the  mountain  rather  than  climb  it,  they  

might  feel  “cheated”  of  the  experience  of  climbing,  despite  achieving  their  end  

more  easily.  Similarly,  certain  enhancement  technologies  might  “cheat  us”  of  the  

value  experienced  by  the  traditional  means  of  human  enhancement  primarily  

because  they  help  us  achieve  our  ends  more  efficiently  (1998:  155).    

 

Following  from  this,  Leon  Kass  suggests  enhancement  technologies  

disrupt  the  character  of  a  human  ‘being-­‐at-­‐work-­‐in-­‐the-­‐world’  and  presents  us  

with  issues  surrounding  ‘authenticity’  (Kass,  2003).  He  claims  enhancement  

technologies  that  allow  us  to  skip  certain  means  of  experience,  cannot  really  

produce  a  transformation  that  is  genuinely  our  own  as  an  individual  or  a  human  

being  (2003).  On  the  other  hand,  DeGrazia  suggests  that  “the  self”  is  not  a  not  a  

pre-­‐existing  reality  that  we  should  conform  too  (DeGrazia,  2000:  36).  Rather,  he  

understands  authenticity  and  self-­‐creation  as  being  process  in  which  we  shape  

ourselves,  and  choose  the  means  for  ‘self-­‐design’  (2000:  37).  Underpinning  the  

concept  of  “authenticity”  is  the  idea  that,  if  one  is  not  true  to  themselves  as  a  

human  being,  they  will,  “miss  the  point  of  their  life,  they  will  miss  what  being  

human  is  for  them”  (Parens,  A:  35).  Following  this,  Parens  acknowledges  that  

different  conceptions  of  authenticity  grow  out  of  different  understandings  of  

ourselves  and  our  proper  relationships  to  the  world  (Parens,  A:  36).  However,  

what  exactly  are  the  different  understandings  of  ourselves,  and  how  may  they  

determine  a  proper  relationship  towards  enhancement?    

 

 

3)  Human  nature  in  the  enhancement  debate    

As  suggested,  developments  within  molecular  biology  may  eventually  

make  it  possible  for  us  to  alter  our  condition,  or  fundamentally  remake  human  

nature  (Gannet,  2010).  Although  it  is  worth  noting  that  discussion  into  this  topic  

is  highly  speculative,  already  in  1969  Sinsheimer  claimed,  “for  the  first  time,  in  

all  time,  a  living  creature  understands  its  origin  and  can  undertake  to  design  its  

  15  

future”  (in  Kevles,  1992:  18;  Buchanan  et  al,  2000:  87).  Transhumanist  

aspirations  may  not  only  threaten  the  survival  of  the  species  but  will  challenge  

our  basic  idea  of  what  it  means  to  be  human  (Stock,  2002:  1).    Following  this,  

Hans  Jonas  suggests  a  reflection  on  the  “image”  of  man  and  on  what  is  humanly  

desirable  is  more  urgent  than  ever  before  (Jonas,  2003:  200).  Unfortunately,  

Jonas  also  suggests,  that  “philosophy  is  sadly  unprepared  for  this  task”  (2003:  

200).  Perhaps  a  key  reason  for  this  is  that  there  is  no  single,  universal  

understanding  of  the  “image”  of  man.  As  demonstrated  by  Leslie  Stevenson  and  

David  Haberman,  some  individuals  are  inclined  to  view  humans  as  essentially  

the  products  of  evolution,  programed  to  pursue  self-­‐interest,  reproduce  genes  

and  fulfil  biological  drives  (Haberman  and  Stevenson,  1998:  3).  Others  insist  

there  exists  some  transcendent,  objective,  potentially  divine  purpose  for  human  

lives  and  human  history  (1998:  3).  Meanwhile,  writers  such  as  Marx,  suggest  

there  is  no  such  “essential”  human  nature,  only  the  capacity  to  be  moulded  by  

society  and  its  economic,  political  and  cultural  forces  (1998:  3).  Nevertheless,  

different  ideas  of  the  human  are  not  only  important  to  the  individual,  but  

radically  affect  the  kind  of  society  we  live  in  and  the  kind  we  would  like  to  live  in  

(Trigg,  1998:  2).  As  noted  by  Trigg  “without  some  conception  of  what  it  is  to  be  

human,  no  one  can  say  much  about  human  societies  or  practices”  (1998:  3).  

 

  Following  this,  Murray  acknowledges  three  key  ways  of  thinking  about  

human  nature  in  relationship  to  the  ethics  of  enhancement  (Murray,  2007:  502).  

He  suggests  human  nature  can  be  viewed  as  either  raw  material,  as  a  contour  of  

the  given,  or  as  a  normative  guide.  Of  these  perspectives,  the  transhumanist  

movement  upholds  a  view  human  nature  as  raw  material.  This  approach  

involves  an  acceptance  that  our  nature  holds  no  moral  significance  (2007:  502).  

Whilst  it  is  often  argued  by  bio-­‐conservatives  there  is  something  “precious”  in  

our  given  nature  we  should  preserve  from  enhancement  technologies,  

transhumanist’s  reject  such  claims.  For  instance,  Leon  Kass  argues,  “We  need  

more  than  a  generalized  appreciation  for  nature’s  gifts.  We  need  a  particular  

regard  and  respect  for  the  special  gift  that  is  our  own  given  nature”  (Kass,  2003).  

However,  Nick  Bostrom  suggests  the  “gifts”  of  nature  are  “sometimes  poisoned  

and  should  not  be  accepted”  (2005(a):  205).  In  particular,  he  believes  our  own  

  16  

“own  species-­‐specified  natures  are  a  rich  source  of  much  that  is  thoroughly  

unrespectable  and  unacceptable-­‐  susceptibility  for  disease,  murder,  rape,  

genocide,  cheating,  torture,  racism.”  (2005(a):  205).  Consequentially,  human  

nature  does  act  as  a  guide  to  what  is  desirable  or  normatively  right  for  

transhumanists,  but  rather  is  seen  as  ‘‘raw  material’  to  be  moulded  how  we  

desire  (Murray,  2007:  503;  Bostrom,  2005(a):  205).  For  instance,  Bostrom  

describes  human  nature  as,  “a  work-­‐in-­‐progress,  a  half-­‐baked  beginning  we  can  

learn  to  remould  in  desirable  ways”  (Bostrom,  2003:  493).  When  accepting  

human  nature  as  raw  material,  an  acknowledgement  of  human  “plasticity”-­‐  the  

belief  that  our  bodies  are  malleable,  and  transformable-­‐  is  necessary  (Silver,  

1998).  Following  this,  transhumanists  suggest  it  is  not  only  permissible  to  

change  ourselves  through  cosmetic  surgery  or  performance  enhancing  drugs,  but  

also  through  more  radical  alterations  (Murray,  2007:  503).  In  particular,  genetic  

engineering  becomes  acceptable  on  the  basis  it  may  help  us  transform  into  the  

creatures  we  imagine  we  want  to  be  and  overcome  our  current  biological  

limitations.    

 

Nevertheless,  whilst  transhumanists  primarily  view  human  nature  as  raw  

material  with  no  moral  authority,  they  tend  to  emphasis  another  key  aspect  of  

our  nature  when  discussing  enhancement  technologies.  This  aspect  is,  “our  

ability  to  intend  coupled  with  the  skill  to  remake  ourselves  according  to  our  own  

design”  (Murray,  2007:  503).  Through  emphasising  this  capacity,  transhumanists  

argue  enhancement  technologies  would  not  undermine,  but  rather  improve,  

what  is  “fundamentally  human”  (Savulescu,  2007:  531).  Julian  Savulescu,  for  

example,  makes  this  claim  through  his  discussion  of  performance  enhancing  

drugs  in  sport.  He  writes,  “Far  from  being  against  the  spirit  of  sport,  biological  

manipulation  embodies  the  human  spirit-­‐  the  capacity  to  improve  ourselves  on  

the  basis  of  reason  and  judgement.  When  we  exercise  our  reason,  we  do  only  

what  humans  can  do”  (Savulescu,  2004:  667).  Gregory  Stock  makes  a  similar  

point  in  his  book,  “Redesigning  Humans”,  when  he  refers  to  the  mythological  

story  of  Prometheus.  In  this  story  Prometheus  improves  the  human  condition  

  17  

permanently  after  he  steals  fire  from  the  Gods  to  give  to  man6  (Stock,  2002:  2).  

However,  Stock  suggests  we  do  not  find  Prometheus’  actions  shocking  because  

they  are  “too  characteristically  human”,  as  is  the  desire  for  us  to  improve  

ourselves  with  radical  human  enhancements  once  such  technology  becomes  

available  (2002:  2).  Following  these  observations,  one  may  argue  Stock  and  

Savulescu  allow  an  exception  to  the  idea  of  human  nature  is  raw  material  with  no  

moral  authority  (Murray,  2007:  503).  These  arguments  understand  human  

nature  in  a  morally  singular  way,  suggesting  that,  “people  should  shape  

themselves.  Wilful  self-­‐design,  from  this  perspective  is  a  distinctly  human  

enterprise  and  therefore  to  be  valued  for  its  own  sake.  We  are  meant  to  be  self-­‐

makers”  (Murray,  2007:  501-­‐3).    

 

Despite  claims  above,  a  central  idea  within  bio-­‐conservativism  is  our  

obligation  to  understand  human  nature    “as  contours  of  the  given”.  To  view  

human  nature  “as  contours  of  the  given”,  is  to  dismiss  the  idea  that  human  

wilfulness  and  technical  skill  could  provide  us  with  a  reason  to  support  radical  

enhancement  technologies  or  unlimited  human  enhancement.  In  ‘The  Case  

Against  Perfection’,  Michael  Sandel  rejects  such  technologies  on  the  basis  they  

fail  to  acknowledge  our  responsibility  to  express  gratitude  for  the  giftedness  of  

life  (Sandel,  2007).  He  writes,  “  if  bioengineering  made  the  myth  of  the  ‘self-­‐made  

man’  come  true,  it  would  be  difficult  to  view  our  talents  as  gifts  for  which  we  are  

indebted,  rather  than  as  achievements  for  which  we  are  responsible.  This  would  

transform  three  key  features  of  our  moral  landscape:  humility,  responsibility  and  

solidarity”  (Sandel,  2007:  86).  Leaving  aside  whether  his  predictions  are  

accurate  for  the  moment,  we  can  begin  to  discern  the  deeper  danger  for  Sandel  

(Parens,  2005:  37;  Murray,  2007).  He  is  arguing,  on  secular  grounds,  against  

hyper-­‐agency,  or  rather  the  Promethean  aspiration  to  remake  nature,  including  

human  nature,  to  serve  our  purposes  and  satisfy  our  desires  (Sandel,  2007:  88).  

If  we  perused  this  “Promethean  aspiration”  through  enhancement  technologies,  

we  would  forget  that  life  is  a  gift-­‐  albeit  from  an  unknown  giver-­‐  would  mistake                                                                                                                  6  N.B.  Gehlen  himself  also  makes  a  comparison  to  man  and  Promethues.  He  writes,  “Like  Prometheus,  he  must  direct  his  energy  to  what  is  removed,  what  is  not  present  in  space  or  time  […]  he  lives  for  the  future  and  not  the  present”  (2002:  62).  

  18  

the  sort  of  creatures  we  really  are  and  the  way  the  world  really  is  (Parens,  2005:  

37).  In  contrast  to  transhumanist  accounts  of  human  nature,  this  perspective  

does  not  see  man  as  unlimitedly  manipulable  (Murray,  2007:  503).  It  does  not  

prioritize  human  wilfulness  and  technical  skill  over  all  other  human  capacities,  

and  it  encourages  more  modesty  over  our  ability  to  alter  our  nature  and  our  

ability  to  decide  which  alterations  are  desirable  (Murray,  2007:  503).  Murray  

suggests  Sandel’s  approach  understands  human  nature  as  being,  “complex  and  

often  morally  ambiguous,  [telling]  us  something  about  the  boundaries  of  what  is  

possible  and  desirable”  (2007:  503).  Whilst  some  enhancements  are  “out  of  

bounds”,  others  fit  well  into  the  contours  of  our  given  nature.  It  is  under  these  

grounds  that  bio-­‐conservatives  such  as  Sandel  attempt  to  reject  transhumanist  

aspirations  for  enhancement  technologies,  yet  not  all  technology  in  general.  

 

However,  to  what  extent  is  the  Promethean  aspiration  to  re-­‐make  nature  

a  fundamental  part  of  human  nature?  Furthermore  could  transhumanists  be  

justified  in  elevating  it  above  all  other  human  capacities  to  form  a  case  for  

enhancement  technologies?  Before  claiming  that  the  “idea  of  the  self-­‐made  man”  

is  a  myth,  or  that  we  have  a  responsibility  to  express  gratitude  for  the  giftedness  

of  life,  I  believe  one  must  clarify  their  understanding  of  what  it  means  to  be  

human.  Turning  to  observations  made  within  philosophical  anthropology,  one  

may  begin  to  achieve  such  clarification.    

 

4)  Assessing  the  transhumanist  approach  through  philosophical  anthropology      

As  suggested,  human  wilfulness  and  technical  skill  is  emphasised  

throughout  transhumanist  literature.  Drawing  on  the  work  of  Arnold  Gehlen,  one  

may  initially  find  vast  support  and  justification  for  these  claims.  For  instance,  

using  Herders  concept  of  the  deficient  being,  Gehlen  suggests  the  basic  defining  

characteristic  of  man  is  “action”  (Gehlen,  2002:  62;  Gehlen,  2003:  213)  According  

to  Gehlen,  the  use  of  weapons,  fire  and  hunting  techniques,  all  belong  to  the  

behaviour  patterns  designed  to  preserve  the  species.  Specifically,  Gehlen  

  19  

discusses  “replacement  techniques”  that  allow  us  to  preform  beyond  the  

potentials  of  our  organs,  such  as  fire,  which  provides  man  with  more  security  

and  warmth  than  he  could  on  his  own  (Gehlen,  1980:  3).  “Strengthening  

techniques”,  that  allow  us  to  extend  the  performance  of  our  bodily  equipment  

whilst  still  reinforcing  natural  abilities,  such  as  our  use  of  a  hammer,  microscope  

or  telephone  (1980:  3).  Furthermore,  Gehlen  suggests  man  also  uses,  “facilitation  

techniques”,  which  operate  to  relieve  burdens  placed  upon  human  organs,  saving  

them  effort  and  disengaging  them-­‐  for  example,  a  wheeled  vehicle  relieves  us  

from  transporting  materials  by  hand  (1980:  3).    Although  he  acknowledges  

certain  technologies  may  operate  on  all  three  principles-­‐  consider  an  airplane  

that  provides  us  with  wings  we  do  not  have,  out  preforms  animal  flight  and  

relieves  us  of  contributing  to  our  own  movement-­‐  it  is  significant  to  note  that  

Gehlen,  like  transhumanists,  also  makes  a  connection  between  mans  organic  

shortcomings  and  his  ability  to  rise  above  such  shortcomings  through  inventive  

intelligence7  (2003:  213).  Following  these  observations,  it  is  unsurprising  

transhumanists  such  as  Bostrom  discuss  the  human  capacity  to  “expand  the  

boundaries  of  their  existence  and  to  find  a  way  around  the  limitations  and  

obstacles  experienced  in  life”  (Bostrom,  2005(b):  1).  However,  what  exactly  are  

man’s  organic  shortcomings?  Furthermore,  how  do  such  shortcomings  connect  

to  inventive  intelligence  or  enable  the  development  of  technology?  

 

  Gehlen  suggests  man  is  unable  to  survive  in  any  natural,  uncultivated  

environment,  primarily  due  to  his  morphological  deficiencies  (Gehlen,  2002:  63).  

In  a  biological  sense,  such  deficiencies  amount  to  a  lack  of  adaptation,  a  lack  of  

specialization,  and  a  failure  to  develop,  all  of  which  are  essentially  negative  

features  (2002:  63).  For  instance,  in  Der  Mensch,  Gehlen  uses  evidence  from  

comparative  embryology  to  insist  that  the  human  gestation  period  is  too  short  

(by  several  months)  to  bring  a  human  foetus  to  the  same  level  of  maturity  at  

birth  as  the  foetuses  of  closely  related  species  (Gehlen,  1980:  3).  Similarly,  

                                                                                                               7  This  connection  was  first  made  by  Ernst  Kapp  in  his  Philosophie  der  Technik  (1877)  and  shortly  after  by  Ludwig  Noire  in  Das  Werkzeug  [The  Tool]  (1880)  where  he  wrote:  “Then  man  became  released  from  his  nature,  for  he  became  his  own  creator,  created  his  own  organs,  became  a  tool  maker,  a  tool  making  animals”.  (Gehlen,  2003:  213)  

  20  

Gehlen  discusses  the  human  “bite”,  in  order  to  demonstrates  how  a  lack  of  gaps  

between  the  teeth  and  an  undetermined  structure  make  him  neither  a  herbivore  

nor  a  carnivore  (Gehlen,  2002:  63).  Providing  examples  such  as  these,  Gehlen  

describes  man  as  an  “undetermined”  and  “unfinished”  being-­‐  by  this,  Gehlen  

means  man  is  a  problem  to  himself,  having  to  draw  on  his  own  aptitudes  and  

talents  in  a  way  no  other  animal  does  simply  to  survive  (2002:  61).  For  instance,  

he  notes  that  humans  have  no  natural  protection  against  inclement  weather,  

have  no  natural  organs  for  defence  or  attack,  need  an  unusually  long  period  of  

protection  during  infancy  and  may  be  viewed  as  having  a  dangerous  lack  of  

instincts  (2002:  63).  However,  whilst  humans  are  characterised  by  their  

deficiencies,  Gehlen  believes  other  organic  forms  tend  to  become  highly  

specialized  and  adapted  to  specific  environments  within  natural  development.  

For  example,  deep  oceans,  rivers,  rainforests,  and  mountain  ranges  are  all  

specific  environments  where  we  find  specialized  animals  suited  to  survive  in  

such  areas  (2002:  63).  Even  a  comparison  of  humans  to  great  apes  allows  us  to  

see  how  “hopelessly  unadapted”  man  is  in  contrast  to  the  rest  of  nature-­‐  Gehlen  

describes  great  apes  as,  “highly  specialized  arboreal  animals  with  overdeveloped  

arm  for  swinging,  feet  designed  for  climbing,  body  hair  and  power  canine  teeth”  

(2002:  63).  Perhaps  such  observations  begin  to  explain  why  many  other  animals  

possess  much  stronger,  sharper  senses  than  humans.  Nevertheless,  although  

man  exhibits  an  absence  of  specialization,  which  appears  primitive  from  a  

developmental,  biological  standpoint,  his  “undetermined”  nature  is  essential  for  

turning  survival  into  both,  “his  greatest  challenge  and  his  greatest  

accomplishment”  (2002:  61).  

 

  Although  the  above  statement  needs  clarification,  we  are  beginning  to  

understand  what  is  meant  when  transhumanists  claim  that  the  human  desire  to  

acquire  new  capacities  is  as  ancient  as  the  species  itself8(Bostrom,  2005(b):  1).  

                                                                                                               8  N.B.  In  his  article,  “The  History  of  Transhumanist  Thought”,  Bostrom  discusses  the  cultural  and  philosophical  antecedents  to  transhumanism.  He  does  not  specifically  reference  any  philosophical  anthropologist.  Nevertheless,  I  have  chosen  Gehlen’s  work  in  an  endeavour  to  provide  a  unified  explanation  for  how,  and  why,  man  has  been  able  to  overcome  the  limitations  experienced  in  life.      

  21  

As  noted,  most  animals  have  a  specialized  organic  structure.  This  organic  

structure  has  adapted  to  an  unchanging  environment  and  allows  specific,  innate,  

instinctive  behaviour  to  be  carried  out  within  this  environment  (Gehlen,  2002:  

64).  Following  this,  Gehlen  suggests,  animals  are  “tied”  to  their  environment,  that  

their  specialized  organic  structure  and  specific  environment  are  mutually  

dependant  concepts  (2004:  64).  On  the  other  hand,  human  beings  who  lack  

specialization,  avoid  being  constrained  to  a  specific  environment  and  achieve  

what  Max  Scheler  describes  as  “world-­‐openness”  (Max  Scheler,  2002:  52).  

Whilst,  it  initially  it  appears  to  be  a  disadvantage  that  man  is  “world-­‐open”,  for  

his  perceptions  are  not  only  concentrated  to  what  is  necessary  for  basic  survival,  

it  is  under  these  conditions  that  man  is  able  to  reach  “his  greatest  achievement”  

and  become  an  “acting  being”  with  a  unique  place  in  the  world  (Gehlen,  2002:  

65).  Hence,  man’s  ability  to  “act”  depends  on  him  being  unspecialized  and  

deprived  of  a  natural  environment  to  which  he  is  adapted.  However,  what  

exactly  is  human  “action”,  and  how  is  it  achieved?  Gehlen  suggests,  “all  human  

actions  are  twofold”,  meaning  firstly,  that  man  actively  masters  the  world  around  

him  by  transforming  it  to  serve  his  purposes  (2002:  66).  However,  to  accomplish  

this,  he  believes  humans  have  to  draw  on  a  highly  complex  hierarchy  of  skills,  

establishing  a  “developmental  order  of  abilities”  based  on  the  potential  

usefulness  of  such  skills  (2002:  66).  This  order  of  abilities  is  “constructed  single-­‐

handedly  by  man”  –sometimes  overcoming  internal  resistance  from  man  himself.  

Nevertheless,  it  means  all  human  skills,  whether  sophisticated  or  basic,  are  

developed  by  man  through  a  process  of  coming  to  terms  with  the  world,  in  which  

survival  is  eventually  achieved  and  a  ranking  order  of  skills  is  also  developed  

(2002:  66).    

 

Furthermore,  when  discussing  mans  ability  to  actively  transform  the  

world  to  suit  his  own  ends,  Gehlen  acknowledges  there  is  no  such  thing  as  

“natural  men”  (Gehlen,  2002:  66).  Rather,  he  believes  humans  exist  in  a  “second  

nature”.  As  suggested,  humans  are  acting  beings  who  master  and  re-­‐create  

nature  due  to  their  organic  deficiencies.  Yet,  through  reconstructing  nature  to  

suit  their  own  needs,  humans  create  a    “culture  world”  or  “second  nature”  within  

which  they  can  survive  (2002:  67).  For  Gehlen,  the  culture  world  exists  for  man  

  22  

in  the  same  way  particular  environments  exist  for  animals  and  explains  why  

human  beings  have  no  natural,  geographically  defined  territories.  As  long  as  man  

is  able  to  construct  a  “second  nature”,  he  is  able  to  exist  almost  anywhere  on  

earth-­‐  whether  it  be  on  a  mountain  or  in  a  forest,  on  land  or  on  water  (2002:  67).  

Furthermore,  mans  self-­‐created  “second  nature”,  contains  the  conditions  

necessary  for  humans  to  develop  “replacement  technique”,  “strengthening  

techniques”  and  “facilitation  techniques”  (Gehlen,  2002:  66-­‐7;  1980:  3).  It  is  

within  the  cultural  realm,  humans  are  able  become  “world-­‐open”,  acting  beings,  

who  create  weapons  to  compensate  for  those  not  made  readily  available  to  them,  

and  who  devise  shelters  to  protect  themselves  against  the  weather  (Gehlen,  

2002:  66).  Following  these  observations  regarding  human  nature,  it  would  

initially  appear  we  have  support  for  transhumanist  arguments  from  human  

nature.  After  all,  Gehlen  discusses  man  in  a  surprisingly  transhumanist  manner.  

For  example,  he  writes,  “no  longer  an  infallible  machine  in  the  hands  of  nature,  

[man]  himself  becomes  a  purpose  and  an  objective  of  his  own  efforts”  (Gehlen,  

2002:  24).  This  comment  appears  to  be  an  extension  of  Max  More’s  claim  that,  

“humans  (and  transhumansts)  are  marked  by  a  persistent  desire  to  understand  

and  control  their  environment”(More,  1996).  After  all,  from  a  philosophical  

anthropological  perspective,  More’s  statement  expresses  what  we  have  just  

explored.  In  contrast  to  animals  who  must  follow  their  specialized  natures,  

human  beings  are  “world-­‐open”  and  able  to  gain  control  and  mastery  over  their  

contact  with  the  world  (Gehlen,  2002:  68).    

 

Furthermore,  Gehlen  has  not  only  provided  us  with  an  account  of  

understanding  how  human  wilfulness  and  technical  skill  is  able  to  occur,  but  he  

has  demonstrated  “action”  as  the  basic  defining  characteristic  of  human  beings,  

allowing  them  to  achieve  a  unique  place  within  the  world  (2002:  62).  Following  

this,  wilful  self-­‐design  is  a  distinctly  human  enterprise,  and  transhumanists  are  

justified  to  emphasize  this  point.  Beyond  this,  Gehlen  is  not  the  only  individual  to  

emphasis  this  unique  human  capacity  within  philosophical  anthropology.  It  is  

also  acknowledged  by  Michael  Landmann,  who  discusses  the  “anthropine  gap”  –

referring  to  the  lack  of  specialization  among  humans  as  considered  above-­‐  as  

being  a  precondition  for  human  “creativity”  (Landmann,  2002:  124).  For  

  23  

Landmann,  humanity  is  not  a  defective  species  that  compensates  for  its  

deficiencies  with  creativity.  Rather,  he  believes  humanity  is  ‘creative’  and  

consequentially  has  no  need  for  specialization,  which  would  only  work  as  a  

hindrance  to  it  (2002:  125).  By  claiming  that  humans  are  ‘creative’,  Landmann  

suggests  we  are  able  to  design  and  shape  our  activity  independently,  raising  it  

above  the  mere  “behaviour”  seen  in  animals  (2002:  125).  Furthermore,  

Landmann,  like  Bostrom,  refers  to  the  work  of  Pico  Della  Mirandola  to  reiterate  

his  point:  “Other  creatures  were  completed  by  God;  but  he  left  human  beings  

incomplete  and  instead  lent  us  a  part  of  his  own  creative  power.  With  it  we  

complete  ourselves”  (in  Landmann,  2002:  126).    

 

However,  despite  initial  similarities,  the  transhumanist  account  of  human  

nature  differs  from  those  we  just  looked  at  in  an  important  respect.  Whilst  is  may  

be  correct  for  transhumanists  to  acknowledge  man  as  an  “acting  being”,  or  even  

to  emphasize  human  wilfulness  and  technical  skill,  transhumanists  use  such  

observations  to  produce  an  argument  for  enhancement  technologies.  As  noted  by  

Allen  Buchanan  et  al,  most  theories  of  human  nature  do  not  entertain  the  

possibility  of  human  nature  itself  changing,  let  alone  the  ways  in  which  it  might  

be  changed  by  biotechnology  (Buchanan  et  al,  2000:  89)  Similarly,  Gehlen’s  

theory  of  human  nature  was  not  developed  for  the  purpose  of  impacting  any  

issues  surrounding  bioethics.  When  discussing  mans  ability  to  actively  transform  

the  world  around  him  to  suit  his  own  ends,  Gehlen  is  not  proposing  an  argument  

in  favour  of  man  transforming  his  own  biological  nature  to  suit  his  ends.  

Nevertheless,  transhumanists  such  as  Stock  appear  to  use  such  observations  to  

develop  their  morally  singular  approach  towards  human  nature,  applauding  

enhancement  technologies  as  affirming  human  wilfulness  and  technical  skill  

(Murray,  2007;  Stock,  2002).  However,  as  seen  in  Bostrom’s  rejection  of  the  bio-­‐

conservative  understanding  of  human  nature  as  a  normative  guide:  ‘There  is  too  

much  that  is  thoroughly  unrespectable  in  human  nature  (along  with  much  that  is  

admirable),  for  the  mere  fact  that  X  is  a  part  of  human  nature  to  constitute  any  

reason,  even  a  prima  facie  reason,  for  supposing  that  X  is  good’  (Bostrom,  2008:  

20).  That  is,  there  is  no  necessary  link  between  a  project  or  capacities  

distinctively  human  character  and  its  moral  desirability  (Murray,  2007:  502).  

  24  

The  fact  humans  are  uniquely  “acting  beings”,  does  not  in  itself  constitute  a  

reason  to  enhancement  human  nature,  so  that  what  is  “fundamentally  human”  

may  also  be  enhanced.  For  transhumanists  to  claim  this  is  the  case,  means  their  

argument  for  human  enhancement  is  subject  to  the  same  criticism  directed  

towards  bio-­‐conservatives  such  as  Leon  Kass.  Yet,  this  is  not  to  suggest  that  the  

link  between  the  distinctly  human  ability  to  self-­‐make  and  the  intrinsic  value  of  

the  project  of  self-­‐making  –with  enhancement  technologies-­‐  could  never  be  

made  (Murray  2007:  502).  Rather,  transhumanists  need  to  demonstrate  how  this  

link  can  be  made-­‐  how  they  may  elevate  one  human  capacity  over  the  rest.  

Furthermore,  once  they  have  demonstrated  how  this  link  can  be  made,  they  

would  need  to  consider  whether  the  distinctly  human  quality  of  self-­‐making  is  

limitless,  or  alternatively,  if  it  may  pose  constraints  on  enhancement  

technologies.  

 

Following  this,  we  arrive  at  another  issue  surrounding  the  Promethean  

notion  of  the  self-­‐made  man  and  its  legitimacy.  Murray  produces  this  criticism  

through  exploring  a  separate  instance  of  when  wilful  self-­‐design  and  self-­‐

creation  is  celebrated  (2007:  501).  Specifically,  he  suggests,  the  Rothmans  report  

also  captures  the  transhumanist  Promethean  ideal  in  its  discussion  of  anorexia.  

The  report  claims,  “Anorexia  is  the  cultivation  of  a  specific  image  as  an  image-­‐  it  

is  a  purely  artificial  creation  and  that  is  why  it  is  so  admired,  Will  alone  produces  

it  and  maintains  it  against  considerable  odds.”  (Rothmans,  2003:  129).  Aside  

from  the  fact  anorexia  threatens  to  destroy  the  very  self  that  is  both  the  agent  

and  object  of  the  impulses  towards  self-­‐design,  there  is  an  additional  concern  

(Murray,  2007:  502).  This  concern  is  with  the  remarkably  naïve  understanding  

of  image  cultivation  as  being  the  pure  product  of  individual  will,  rather  than  a  

complex  interaction  between  social  norms  and  an  individuals  search  for  identity  

and  acceptance  within  the  world  (2007:  502).  Murray  notes  it  is  no  coincidence  

that  anorexia  occurs  primarily  in  young  women,  who  experience  strong  cultural  

preferences  for  slimness,  and  whose  identity  is  still  largely  in  formation  due  to  

their  age  (2007:  502).  Similarly,  when  transhumanists  discuss  technological  self-­‐

design  as  if  it  will  merely  be  the  product  of  an  individuals  will,  they  do  not  

address  the  significance  of  this  interplay.  Although  one’s  own  values  and  self-­‐

  25  

conceptions  choose  the  means  by  which  an  individual  creates  himself,  these  

values  and  self-­‐conceptions  are  impacted  by  the  society  or  culture  that  human  

beings  must  necessarily  exist  in  (DeGrazia,  2000:  39).  Consequentially,  the  idea  

of  the  self-­‐made  man  wholly  determining  himself  with  biotechnology  is,  at  least  

partially,  a  myth  and  not  a  sufficient  reason  support  the  use  of  unlimited  

enhancement  technologies.    

 

However,  Landmann  suggested  human  beings  are  creative  and  

independently  shape  their  actions.  Yet,  how  can  he  make  such  a  claim  if  an  

individuals  will  is  so  affected  by  the  culture  they  are  born  into  the  world  

receiving?  He  acknowledges  whilst  animals  have  “primary  fixations”  that  last  

throughout  their  entire  lives,  human  beings  alternatively  must  be  determinable,  

plastic  and  impressionable  to  their  “second  nature”  (2002:  132).  For  instance,  

humans  are  so  impressionable  that  when  raised  by  wolves  or  bears  they  actually  

begin  to  take  on  the  habits  of  these  animals,  whereas  when  ducks  –or  other  

animals-­‐  are  raised  amongst  chickens  they  will  always  follow  their  nature  and  go  

to  the  water  (2002:  132).  However,  he  suggests  this  malleability,  educability,  and  

the  capacity  to  learn  is,  “the  psychological  counterpole  to  creativity”  and  does  

not  contradict  it  (2002:  132).  Rather,  he  suggests  a  productive  being  is  also  a  

receptive  being,  that  the  two  things  are  mutually  contained.    

 

 

Nevertheless,  through  elevating  the  human  as  a  being  that  is  unlimitedly  

malleable  and  self-­‐creating,  I  believe  transhumanists  fail  to  understand  human  

nature  in  the  complex  or  unified  way  we  have  explored.  Specifically,  when  

Gehlen  suggests  survival  is  both  man’s  greatest  challenge  and  his  greatest  

achievement,  he  believes  this  must  be  evident  throughout  his  entire  structure  

(Gehlen,  2002:  65).  Human  vulnerabilities  form  a  “coherent  whole”,  which  is  

manifested  in  his  world-­‐openness  and  is  the  foundation  for  man’s  character  as  

an  acting  being  with  a  unique  place  in  the  world  (2002:  64-­‐5).  However,  

transhumanists  do  not  understand  man’s  ability  to  control,  or  master  his  

surroundings  as  fundamentally  connected  to  his  “undetermined”  nature  or  his  

biological  deficiencies  (2002:  62).  In  the  case  of  Savulescu,  for  instance,  he  

  26  

suggests  the  human  capacity  to  make  normative  judgements  and  act  on  the  basis  

of  reason  is  what  separates  us  from  other  animals,  claiming  that  biological  

manipulations  would  improve,  rather  than  undermine,  what  is  “fundamentally  

human”  when  they  improve  our  capacity  to  engage  in  rational  and  normative  

judgements  (Savulescu,  2007:  531).  However,  Gehlen  has  formulated  a  structural  

definition  of  man,  which  does  not  rely  solely  on  the  characteristics  of  reasoning,  

or  of  the  mind  (2002:  64).  He  suggests  these  capacities  may  essentially  be  seen  

as  an  elaboration  of  the  basic  defining  characteristic  of  man-­‐  action-­‐  and  do  not  

in  themselves,  “bring  light  to  the  relationship  between  the  peculiar  human  bodily  

structure  and  the  human  mind”  (2002:  63).  Furthermore,  if  transhumanist  

arguments  from  human  nature  do  not  bring  light  to  the  relationship  between  the  

human  bodily  structure  and  the  human  mind  as  being  a  coherent  whole,  then  

they  entail  a  serious  limitation.  They  do  not  fully  understand  what  it  is  they  are  

seeking  to  change.  

 

Yet,  this  brings  us  to  a  broader  problem  for  the  transhumanist  movement.  

One  may  argue  that  the  way  in  which  transhumanism  attempts  to  understand  

arguments  from  human  nature  is  insufficient  from  the  beginning  as  it  entails  

“scientific  reductionism”  (Fukuyama,  2002:  162).  As  acknowledged  by  Max  

Scheler,  Western  Society  does  not  have  any  unified  idea  of  man  (2002:  45).  

Closely  related  to  the  Greek  tradition  that,  for  the  first  time,  suggested  man’s  

self-­‐consciousness  raised  him  to  a  unique  place  on  the  grounds  he  is  endowed  

with  ‘reason’,  is  the  doctrine  that  there  is  a  superhuman  ‘reason’  in  the  total  

universe  in  which  man  alone  of  all  creatures  is  the  participant  (2002:  45).  This  

view  is  a  tradition  of  its  own,  belonging  to  modern  science  and  genetic  

psychology  and  I  believe  it  is  also  expressed  throughout  transhumanism.  Scheler  

suggests,  from  this  view,  man  is  seen  as  a  recent  product  of  evolution,  a  being  

that  is  distinguished  from  its  antecedents  in  the  animal  world  only  by  the  degree  

of  complexity  of  energies  and  capacities  that  may  already  be  present  at  a  

subhuman  level  (2002:  45).  However,  he  suggests  this  increasingly  popular  view  

tends  to  hide  human  nature  more  than  it  reveals  it.  He  believes  -­‐in  contrast  to  the  

initial  claim  that  “for  the  first  time,  in  all  of  time,  a  species  can  understand  its  

origin”-­‐  there  has  been  no  time  in  history  where  man  has  been  so  much  a  

  27  

problem  to  himself  as  he  is  now  (pp.  46).  Similarly,  as  noted  by  Francis  

Fukuyama,  many  contemporary  Darwinians  believe  they  have  “demystified”  the  

problem  of  how  humans  came  to  be  through  the  reductionist  method  of  modern  

natural  science  (2002:  162).  This  is  the  claim  that  ultimately  every  human  

characteristic  can  be  traced  back  to  a  prior  material  cause.  For  instance,  one  who  

holds  this  view  might  believe,  “any  higher-­‐order  behaviour  or  characteristic,  

such  as  language,  can  be  traced  back  through  the  firing  of  the  neurons  to  the  

biochemical  substrate  of  the  brain,  which  in  turn  can  be  understood  in  terms  of  

the  simpler  organic  compounds  of  which  it  is  composed”  (Fukuyama,  2002:  162).  

However,  whilst  this  type  of  thinking  is  not  necessarily  false-­‐  after  all,  it  is  the  

foundation  of  extremely  successful  modern  science-­‐  it  is  problematic  to  the  

extent  it  does  not  help  us  sufficiently  explain  unique  human  traits  and  does  not  

provide  us  with  a  unified  understanding  of  man  (2002:  162).    

   

  Following  this,  one  might  want  to  question  whether  there  would  be  

increased  risks  or  unintended  consequences  for  enhancement  technologies  

(Kass,  2003)?  After  all,  without  having  a  unified  understanding  of  human  nature,  

is  there  any  guarantee  the  human  capacities  transhumanists  seek  to  extend  

through  biotechnology,  will  actually  be  extended  in  the  way  they  expect?  Leon  

Kass  suggests  that  no  biological  agent  used  for  the  purposes  of  “self-­‐perfection”  

or  mastery,  can  ever  be  entirely  safe  (Kass,  2003).  On  the  basis  of  ‘good  

conservative  medical  sense’,  Kass  believes  it  is  reasonable  to  assume  that  

anything  powerful  enough  to  enhance  system  A  is  likely  to  be  powerful  enough  

to  harm  system  B,  “the  body  being  a  highly  complex  yet  integrated  whole  in  

which  one  intervenes  partially  only  at  one’s  peril”  (2003).  However,  could  

concerns  for  the  risks  of  enhancement  technologies  be  increased  based  on  

Gehlen’s  findings?  Arguably,  enhancement  technologies  that  would  rid  man  of  

his  “unfinishedness”,  should  be  revaluated  by  transhumanists,  for  they  would  

simultaneous  undermine  mans  “world-­‐openness”  or  ability  to  “act”.  Although  

this  is  not  a  criticism  to  all  enhancement  technologies  promoted  by  

transhumanists,  for  not  all  enhancement  technologies  would  bring  about  this  

effect,  it  will  be  relevant  to  certain  pro-­‐enhancement  agenda’s.  For  instance,  a  

transhumanist  aspiration  to  produce  a  human  chimera  might  seek  to  genetically  

  28  

engineer  extra  adaptations  into  the  structure  of  a  human  from  an  animal  

(Streiffer,  2011).  However,  this  would  not  merely  be  a  case  of  adding  another  

capacity  on  top  of  the  structure  of  human  capacities  already  in  place,  but  may  

fundamentally  restructure  the  human,  perhaps  even  making  him  more  

specialized  to  a  specific  environment  or  eroding  some  of  the  conditions  

necessarily  needed  for  him  to  be  an  acting  being.    

   

5)  Conclusion    

  As  has  been  demonstrated  by  Gehlen,  human  beings  master  and  recreate  

nature  in  order  to  secure  their  existence.  However,  this  is  a  necessary  process  for  

a  being  for  whom  being  is  an  issue.  He  must  actively  transform  his  environment  

to  suit  his  own  purposes  in  order  to  survive.  On  the  other  hand,  the  process  of  

mastering  or  recreating  his  biological  nature  to  suit  his  own  purposes  is  not  

necessary  to  survival.  Furthermore,  it  may  undermine  the  unified,  coherent  

structure  that  belongs  to  a  human  being.  Transhumanist  arguments  from  human  

nature,  in  particular,  provide  us  with  an  account  of  human  nature  that  elevates  

certain  human  capacities  over  others,  without  understanding  that  the  entire  

structure  interrelated.  Following  this,  transhumanist  arguments  from  human  

nature  do  not  provide  us  with  sufficient  reason  to  support  all  possible  

enhancement  technologies  that  may  eventually  become  available.  

Transhumanists  need  to  develop  their  account  of  human  nature.  Furthermore,  

simply  because  humans  have  always  mastered  nature  successfully,  does  not  

mean  they  should  then  try  and  obtain  technological  mastery  over  their  own  

nature.    

           

  29  

6)  References    Baylis,  F.  and  Robert,  J.  (2004).  The  inevitability  of  genetic  enhancement  technologies.  Bioethics.  18  (1),  pp.1-­‐26.    Bostrom,  Nick.  (2008).  Why  I  want  to  be  a  Posthuman  when  I  grow  up.  In:  Gordijn,  B.,  et  al.  Medical  Enhancement  and  Posthumanity.  Oxford:  Springer.  pp.107-­‐137.    Bostrom,  Nick  and  Roache,  Rebecca..  (2007).  Ethical  Issues  in  Human  Enhancement.  In:  Ryber,  Jesper  New  Waves  in  Applied  Ethics.  Bastingstoke:  Palgrave  Macmillan.    Bostrom,  Nick.  (2005)(a)  ‘In  Defense  of  Posthuman  Dignity’,  Bioethics  19  (3)  pp.202-­‐212.    Bostrom,  Nick.  (2005)(b)  A  History  of  Transhumanist  Thought.  Journal  of  Evolution  and  Technology,  14  (1).    Bostrom,  Nick.  (2003)  ‘Human  Genetic  Enhancements:  A  Transhumanist  Perspective’,  Journal  of  Value  Inquiry  37(4)  pp.493-­‐506    Brock,  Dan.  (1998).  Enhancements  of  Human  Function:  Some  Distinctions  for  Policymakers'.  In:  Parens,  Erik  Enhancing  Human  Traits  Ethical  and  Social  Implications.  Washington  :  Georgetown  University  Press.  pp.48-­‐69.    Buchanan,  A.,  Brock,  D.,  Daniels,  N.  and  Wikler,  D  (2000).  From  Chance  to  Choice:  Genetics  and  Justice.  New  York:  Cambridge  University  Press.    Cole-­‐Turner,  Ronald.  (1998).  Do  Means  Matter.  In:  Parens,  Erik  Enhancing  Human  Traits  Ethical  and  Social  Implications.  Washington  :  Georgetown  University  Press.  pp.151-­‐161.    DeGrazia,  David  (2005)(a)  ‘Enhancement  Technologies  and  Human  Identity’,  Journal  of  Medicine  and  Philosophy  (30)  pp.261-­‐283.    DeGrazia,  David.  (2005)(b)  Human  Identity  and  Bioethics,  New  York:  Cambridge  University  Press      Degrazia,  David.  (2000)  ‘Prozac,  Enhancement,  and  Self-­‐Creation’,  The  Hastings  Center  Report,  30  (2)  pp.30-­‐40      Elliott,  Carl  (2003).  Better  Than  Well:  American  Medicine  Meets  the  American  Dream,  New  York:  W.W.  Norton.    Fukuyama,  Francis  (2002).  Our  Posthuman  Condition.  Surrey:  Bookmarque  Ltd.    Gannet,  Lisa.  (2010).  The  Human  Genome  Project  .  Available:  http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/human-­‐genome/.  

  30  

 Gehlen,  Arnold.  (2003).  A  Philosophical-­‐Anthropological  Perspective  on  Technology.  In:  Scharff,  Robert.  and  Dusek,  Val.  Philosophy  of  Technology:  The  Technological  Condition.  Oxford:  Blackwell  Publishing  Ltd.  pp.213-­‐221.    Gehlen,  Arnold.  (2002).  Man:  His  Place  and  Nature.  In:  Weiss,  D.  Interpreting  Man.  Aurora,  Colorado:  The  Davies  Group,  Publishers.  pp.59-­‐74.    Gehlen,  Arnold.  (1980).  Man  in  the  Age  of  Technology.  California  :  Columbia  University  Press.    Gems,  David.  (2003).  Is  More  Life  Always  Better?  The  New  Biology  of  Aging  and  the  Meaning  of  Life.  The  Hastings  Center  Report  33  (4).  pp.31-­‐39    Glover,  Jonathan  (1984).  What  Sort  Of  People  Should  There  Be?.  Oxford:  Pelican  Books.    Juengst,  Eric.  (1998).  What  Does  Enhancement  Mean?.  In:  Parens,  Erik  Enhancing  Human  Traits  Ethical  and  Social  Implications.  Washington  :  Georgetown  University  Press.  pp.29-­‐47.    Jonas,  Hans.  (2003).  Toward  a  Philosophy  of  Technology.  In:  Scharff,  Robert.  and  Dusek,  Val.  Philosophy  of  Technology:  The  Technological  Condition.  Oxford:  Blackwell  Publishing  Ltd.  pp.191-­‐205.    Kass,  Leon.  (2003)  Ageless  Bodies,  Happy  Souls:  Biotechnology  and  the  Pursuit  of  Perfection.  The  New  Atlantis      Kass,  Leon.  (2002).  Life,  Liberty,  and  Defense  of  Dignity:  The  Challenge  for  Bioethics,  San  Francisco:  Encounter  Books    Kevles,  Daniel.  (1992).  Out  of  Eugenics:  The  Historical  Politics  of  the  Human  Genome.  Codes  of  Codes.  pp.3-­‐36.    Kline,  Stephen.  (2003).  What  Is  Technology?.  In:  Scharff,  Robert.  and  Dusek,  Val.  Philosophy  of  Technology:  The  Technological  Condition.  Oxford:  Blackwell  Publishing  Ltd.  pp.210-­‐213.    Landmann,  Michael.  (2002).  The  System  of  Anthropina.  In:  Weiss,  D.  Interpreting  Man.  Aurora,  Colorado:  The  Davies  Group,  Publishers.  pp.123-­‐142.    Merchant,  C.  (1989)  The  Death  of  Nature:  Women,  Ecology,  and  the  Scientific  Revolution.  New  York.  Harper  and  Row.    Murray,  Thomas.  (2007).  Enhancement.  In:  Steinbock,  Bonnie  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Bioethics  .  New  York:  Oxford  University  Press.  pp.491-­‐515.    More,  Max.  (1996).  Transhumanism:  Towards  a  Futurist  Philosophy.  Available:  http://www.maxmore.com/transhum.htm.  

  31  

 Parens,  E.  (2005).  Authenticity  and  Ambivalence:  Towards  Understanding  the  Enhancement  Debate,  The  Hastings  Report  35  (3)  pp.34-­‐41.    Parens,  E:  (1998)  Enhancing  Human  Traits:  Ethical  and  Social  Implications,  Washington:  Georgetown  University  Press.    Parens,  Erik.  (1998).  Is  Better  Always  Good?.  In:  Parens,  Erik  Enhancing  Human  Traits  Ethical  and  Social  Implications.  Washington  :  Georgetown  University  Press.  pp.48-­‐69.    Roger  Trigg  (1988)  Ideas  of  Human  Nature.  An  Historical  Introduction,  Oxford:  Blackwell.    Rothman,  S.  M.,  and  Rothman,  D.  J.  (2003),  The  Pursuit  of  Perfection.  New  York:  Pantheon.  

Sandel,  Michael.  (2007)  The  Case  against  Perfection,  Cambridge,  MA,  and  London:  Belknap  Press  of  Harvard  University  Press.    Savulsecu,  Julian.  (2007).  Genetic  Interventions  and  the  Ethics  of  Enhancement  of  Human  Beings.  In:  Steinbock,  Bonnie  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  Bioethics  .  New  York:  Oxford  University  Press.  pp.516-­‐535.    Savulsecu,  J.,  Foody,  B.,  and  Clayton,  M..  (2004).  Why  we  should  allow  performance  enhancing  drugs  in  sport.  British  Journal  of  Sports  Medicine  .  38.  pp.666-­‐670.    Scheler,  Max.  (2002).  Man's  Place  in  Nature.  In:  Weiss,  D.  Interpreting  Man.  Aurora,  Colorado:  The  Davies  Group,  Publishers.  pp.45-­‐58.    Streiffer,  Robert.  (2011).  Human/Non  Human  Chimeras.  Available:  http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/chimeras/.    Silver,  Lee  (1998).  Remaking  Eden:  Cloning  and  Beyond  in  a  Brave  New  World  .  New  York:  Avon.    Stevenson,  Leslie  and  Haberman,  David  L.  (1998)  Ten  Theories  of  Human  Nature,  New  York/Oxford:  Oxford  University  Press.      Stock,  Gregory  (2002).  Redesigning  Humans.  New  York:  Houghton  Mifflin  Company  Boston.    Trigg,  Roger.  (1988).  Ideas  of  human  nature:  a  historical  introduction.  Oxford:  Blackwell.  pp.44-­‐45.    White,  Gladys.  (1993).  Human  Growth  Hormone:  The  Dilemma  of  Expanded  Use  in  Children.  Kennedy  Institute  of  Ethics.  Journal  (3),  pp.401-­‐409.