Between\tR2P and\tthe ICC: “Robust Peacekeeping” and the Quest for Civilian Protection (2015)

37
Between R2P and the ICC “Robust Peacekeeping” and the Quest for Civilian Protection Frédéric Mégret AssociateProfessor, Faculty of Law, McGill University Introduction .......................................................................................................................................................... 1 I. A Metamorphosis? .......................................................................................................................................... 3 A. Failure and Soul Searching ................................................................................................................... 3 B. From Protection of Civilians to Robust Peacekeeping .............................................................. 6 C. Implications for the Changing Nature of Peace Operations.................................................... 9 II. Relationship to R2P and International Criminal Justice ............................................................ 12 A. Differences and Affinities ................................................................................................................... 12 B. A ProState Bias? .................................................................................................................................... 15 C. Dynamic Articulation............................................................................................................................ 17 III. Moralization, Operationalization or Legalization? ..................................................................... 20 A. An Ambivalent Relationship to International Law.................................................................. 20 B. The Emergence of a Humanitarian Regime of Peacekeeping ............................................. 23 C. Law Catches Up? Towards Accountability for Civilian Protection ................................... 27 Conclusion........................................................................................................................................................... 33 Introduction Whilst there has been significant focus on the relationship between R2P and the ICC, 1 less attention has been paid to the influence of both on a phenomenon central to international reality: peace operations. Peace operations evidently predate these late 20 th Century developments by several decades. They are the reliable workhorse of the UN when it comes to international conflicts and emerge from quite a different reality to address quite different problems. Crucially for the purposes of this SPECIAL/SYMPOSIUM issue, where R2P often operates from the air, and the ICC from the Hague, peace operations often unfold directly in the very areas where the international crimes that R2P is supposed to avert and the ICC supposed to repress occur. 1 Benjamin N Schiff, ‘Lessons from the ICC for ICC/R2P Convergence’ (2010) 21 The Finnish Yearbook of International Law 101; Frédéric Mégret, ‘ICC, R2P and the Security Council’s Evolving Interventionist Toolkit’ [2011] Finnish Yearbook of International Law; Michael Contarino, Melinda NegrónGonzales and Kevin T Mason, ‘The International Criminal Court and Consolidation of the Responsibility to Protect as an International Norm’ (2012) 4 Global Responsibility to Protect 275.

Transcript of Between\tR2P and\tthe ICC: “Robust Peacekeeping” and the Quest for Civilian Protection (2015)

Between  R2P  and  the  ICC    “Robust  Peacekeeping”  and  the  Quest  for  Civilian  Protection    

Frédéric  Mégret  Associate-­‐Professor,  Faculty  of  Law,  McGill  University  

 Introduction  ..........................................................................................................................................................  1  I.  A  Metamorphosis?  ..........................................................................................................................................  3  A.  Failure  and  Soul  Searching  ...................................................................................................................  3  B.  From  Protection  of  Civilians  to  Robust  Peacekeeping  ..............................................................  6  C.  Implications  for  the  Changing  Nature  of  Peace  Operations  ....................................................  9  

II.  Relationship  to  R2P  and  International  Criminal  Justice  ............................................................  12  A.  Differences  and  Affinities  ...................................................................................................................  12  B.  A  Pro-­‐State  Bias?  ....................................................................................................................................  15  C.  Dynamic  Articulation  ............................................................................................................................  17  

III.  Moralization,  Operationalization  or  Legalization?  .....................................................................  20  A.  An  Ambivalent  Relationship  to  International  Law  ..................................................................  20  B.  The  Emergence  of  a  Humanitarian  Regime  of  Peacekeeping  .............................................  23  C.  Law  Catches  Up?  Towards  Accountability  for  Civilian  Protection  ...................................  27  

Conclusion  ...........................................................................................................................................................  33    

Introduction    Whilst  there  has  been  significant  focus  on  the  relationship  between  R2P  and  the  ICC,1  less  attention  has  been  paid  to  the  influence  of  both  on  a  phenomenon  central  to  international  reality:  peace  operations.  Peace  operations  evidently  predate  these  late  20th  Century  developments  by  several  decades.  They  are  the  reliable  workhorse  of  the  UN  when  it  comes  to  international  conflicts  and  emerge  from  quite  a  different  reality  to  address  quite  different  problems.  Crucially  for  the  purposes  of  this  SPECIAL/SYMPOSIUM  issue,  where  R2P  often  operates  from  the  air,  and  the  ICC  from  the  Hague,  peace  operations  often  unfold  directly  in  the  very  areas  where  the  international  crimes  that  R2P  is  supposed  to  avert  and  the  ICC  supposed  to  repress  occur.    

                                                                                                               1  Benjamin  N  Schiff,  ‘Lessons  from  the  ICC  for  ICC/R2P  Convergence’  (2010)  21  The  Finnish  Yearbook  of  International  Law  101;  Frédéric  Mégret,  ‘ICC,  R2P  and  the  Security  Council’s  Evolving  Interventionist  Toolkit’  [2011]  Finnish  Yearbook  of  International  Law;  Michael  Contarino,  Melinda  Negrón-­‐Gonzales  and  Kevin  T  Mason,  ‘The  International  Criminal  Court  and  Consolidation  of  the  Responsibility  to  Protect  as  an  International  Norm’  (2012)  4  Global  Responsibility  to  Protect  275.  

As  such  peace  operations,  although  answering  initially  to  very  different  logics  than  those  of  R2P  and  international  criminal  justice,2  can  also  be  seen  as  a  laboratory  where  their  influence  can  be  felt  in  real  time.  Moreover,  they  can  shed  light  on  the  relationship  between  the  two,  which  may  be  characterized  by  complementarity  but  also  tensions.  Peace  operations  can  be  one  of  the  international  community’s  first  line  of  defense  against  atrocities,  an  existing  asset  to  deal  with  threats  to  civilians;  and  they  can  also  be  a  space  of  relative  resistance  to  the  logic  underlying  R2P  and  international  criminal  justice.  At  stake  is  a  tension  between  the  specificity  of  the  peace  seeking  logic  in  its  traditional  form  and  an  increasingly  strong  emphasis  on  atrocity  prevention  and  repression.  The  question  may  well  be  asked,  therefore,  whether  it  is  R2P  and  the  ICC  that  will  have  a  significant  impact  on  peace  operations,  or  the  reverse?    Peacekeeping  traditionally  had  very  little  to  do  with  protecting  civilians.  Its  goal  was,  as  its  name  indicates,  to  maintain  peace.  It  might  well  be  expected  of  course  that  civilians  would  benefit  from  such  peace,  yet  peace  was  defined  largely  in  inter-­‐state  or  state  terms,  as  a  broader  public  good  that  was  not  justified  specifically  or  forcefully  in  relation  to  its  benefits  for  civilians.  Concretely,  peacekeepers  were  often  deployed  on  armistice  lines  where  they  might  face  tense  stand-­‐offs  between  different  armies,  but  from  which  civilians  were  typically  at  a  safe  distance.  At  any  rate,  peacekeepers  had  no  mandate  to  engage  in  policies  directly  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  civilians,  and  the  states  that  accepted  their  presence  would  not  have  wanted  them  to.  Typically,  a  traditional  peace  operation  would  not  have  considered  that  it  had  significant  responsibilities  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  civilians,  let  alone  expressed  in  strong  human  rights  or  legal  terms.    Nonetheless,  as  this  article  will  endeavor  to  show,  protection  of  civilians  has  slowly  attained  an  increasingly  central  position  in  the  design  and  implementation  of  peace  operations.  This  change  emerged  from  a  series  of  both  conceptual  and  operational  evolutions  that  took  a  long  time  to  take  hold,  and  only  did  so  as  a  result  of  repeated  and  persistent  crises  that  put  the  entire  concept  of  peace  operations  in  crisis.  In  the  background,  momentous  changes  were  taking  place  in  the  normative  environment  in  which  peace  operations  operate.  Whilst  international  peace  and  security  remain  foremost  as  a  justification  for  the  creation  of  peace  operations  and  in  the  minds  of  their  creators,  the  rise  of  what  Ruti  Teitel  has  described  as  “Humanity’s  Law”3  (a  convergence  of  international  humanitarian  law,  international  human  rights  law  and  international  refugee  law)  has  arguably  had  a  slow  but  often  decisive  impact  on  the  configuration  of  UN  operations.    This  article  seeks  to  explore  the  specific  course  that  peace  operations  have  taken  since  the  early  1990s  in  order  to  assess  the  degree  to  which  the  protection  of  civilians  and,  as  a  result,  a  greater  willingness  to  use  force,  has  become  a  dominant,  even  defining                                                                                                                  2  See  Walter  Lotze,  ‘Tale  of  Two  Councils  -­‐  The  African  Union,  the  United  Nations  and  the  Protection  of  Civilian  in  Cote  d’Ivoire,  A’  (2011)  3  Global  Responsibility  to  Protect  365,  375.  (pointing  out  that  the  story  of  Côte  d’Ivoire,  in  which  a  peace  operation  successfully  invoked  the  protection  of  civilians,  “may  be  less  about  the  success  of  the  responsibility  to  protect  concept  as  it  is  about  the  success  of  the  protection  of  civilians  approaches  which  the  Un  has  been  developing  for  its  peacekeeping  operations  over  the  course  of  the  past  decade.”)  3  Ruti  G  Teitel,  Humanity’s  Law  (Oxford  University  Press  2011).  The  regime  of  protection  of  civilians  in  peace  operations  is  often  a  bizarre  mix  of  various  sources,  none  of  which  are  ever  spelled  out  specifically.  It  clearly  borrows  from  the  humanitarian  and  human  rights  concepts  of  protection,  but  is  not  reducible  to  them  and  probably  errs  closer  to  the  former  than  the  latter.  

characteristic  of  peace  operations.  It  begins  by  charting  how  peace  operations  have  undergone  a  metamorphosis  of  sorts  as  a  result  of  the  rise  of  an  increasingly  strong  anti-­‐atrocity  turn  in  international  law  and  policy  (I).  It  then  examines  the  relationship  of  peace  operations  to  both  the  notion  of  R2P  and  the  ICC,  finding  certain  structural  affinities  between  all  three  (II).  Finally,  it  seeks  to  interrogate  the  extent  to  which  this  evolution  is  determined  by  international  norms  and  might  prompt  a  process  of  legalization  of  a  duty  to  protect  civilians  in  peace  operations  (III).  The  article  seeks  to  weave  together  strands  of  operational,  political  and  legal  thinking  about  peacekeeping  that  are  often  not  dealt  with  together  in  a  way  that  results  in  an  impoverishment  of  our  understanding  of  the  issues  at  stake.  

I.  A  Metamorphosis?    Peace  keeping  has  not  escaped  a  wave  of  soul  searching  and  questioning  about  what  states  and  international  organizations  such  as  the  UN  should  do  to  deal  with  mass  atrocity,  with  crucial  implications  for  how  peace  operations  should  deal  with  civilians  more  generally  (A).  This  has  led  to  the  emergence  of  the  protection  of  civilians  as  a  dominant  theme  in  UN  talk  and  the  idea  of  “robust  peacekeeping”  (B).  All  in  all,  this  evolution  creates  tremendous  challenges  for  the  very  nature  of  peacekeeping  (C).  

A.  Failure  and  Soul  Searching    Changes  in  the  conception  of  peacekeeping,  the  emergence  of  R2P  and  the  creation  of  the  ICC  share  a  common  root  in  the  tragedies  of  Bosnia  and  Rwanda.  Whatever  else  these  tragedies  may  stand  for  –  the  need  for  international  criminal  institutions  (ICTY/ICTR)  or  for  forceful  intervention  (NATO/Turquoise)  to  protect  civilians  –  they  certainly  stood  specifically  for  failures  of  peace  operations.  In  both  Bosnia  and  Rwanda,  peace  operations  were  deployed  on  the  site  of  atrocities,  offering  at  least  a  potential  for  protection,  yet  both  failed  dismally.  UNAMIR,  the  Rwandan  operation,  was  arguably  taken  more  by  surprise  than  UNPROFOR,  the  Bosnia  operation.  It  had  been  deployed  as  very  much  a  traditional  peace  operation.  It  was  not  specifically  tasked  with  averting  genocide  or  even  particularly  protecting  human  rights  but  to  monitor  the  Arusha  peace  agreement.  Although  there  had  been  forewarnings,  the  genocide  unfolded  suddenly  and  at  great  speed,  leaving  UNAMIR  little  time  to  react.  It  was,  at  any  rate,  ill-­‐equipped  to  stop  a  mass  atrocity  in  its  tracks.  Nonetheless,  whilst  some  commanders  seemed  overwhelmed  by  the  speed  and  magnitude  of  events,  others  improvised  tactical  protection  actions  that  provided  at  least  temporary  relief.  This  suggests  that  although  the  UN  would  have  had  difficulty  averting  the  genocide,4  it  would  at  least  have  averted  some  casualties.5  Overall,  the  UN  did  very  little  to  stop  the  genocide  and  has  since  been  frequently  faulted  for  it.6    

                                                                                                               4  Alan  J  Kuperman,  The  Limits  of  Humanitarian  Intervention:  Genocide  in  Rwanda  (Brookings  Institution  Press  2004).  5  Scott  Feil,  ‘Preventing  Genocide:  How  the  Early  Use  of  Force  Might  Have  Succeeded  in  Rwanda’  [1998]  Leadership  and  Conflict  Resolution  304.  6  Frederik  Grünfeld  and  Anke  Huijboom,  The  Failure  to  Prevent  Genocide  in  Rwanda:  The  Role  of  Bystanders,  vol  23  (Martinus  Nijhoff  Publishers  2007);  Romeo  Dallaire  and  Ray  Dupuis,  Shake  Hands  with  the  Devil  (Seville  Produtions  (Dallaire)  2007).  

The  situation  of  UNPROFOR  in  relation  to  Srebrenica  was  in  some  ways  more  damning.  The  war  in  the  former-­‐Yugoslavia  and  in  Bosnia  specifically  had  unfolded  in  slow  motion  for  more  than  2  years.  There  had  been  abundant  signs  of  the  nature  of  the  political  objectives  of  the  Bosno-­‐Serbs  and  the  extremes  to  which  they  might  resort  in  their  pursuit  of  an  ethnically  cleansed  Bosnia.  UNPROFOR  included  for  the  first  time  in  the  history  of  peace  operations  a  mandate  not  only  of  humanitarian  assistance  but  of  humanitarian  protection.  Strikingly,  it  was  the  UN  itself  that  had  created  “safe  areas,”  thereby  committing  itself  further  to  the  protection  of  specific  Bosnian-­‐Muslim  populations  that  had  regrouped  within  them.  Srebrenica  was  one  such  zone.  When  the  Bosno-­‐Serbs  decided  to  overwhelm  Srebrenica,  they  intimidated  and  manipulated  the  Dutch  UNPROFOR  contingent  into  collaborating  with  them  or  at  least  turn  a  blind  eye  to  the  separation  of  men  from  women  and  children.  It  is  estimated  that  thereupon  more  than  8,000  were  executed  and  buried  into  mass  graves.7    In  both  cases,  a  tremendous  feeling  emerged  that  the  UN  had  failed  its  responsibilities  in  not  preventing  atrocities.  If  nothing  else,  the  fall  of  Srebrenica  has  been  understood  as  a  massive  moral  failure,  one  in  which  an  institutional  ethos  was  allowed  to  predominate  other  ultimate  responsibility  for  the  “other.”8  Indeed,  few  episodes  have  created  as  much  soul  searching  about  the  UN’s  goals  and  standing  in  the  world  than  its  failures  in  Rwanda  and  Srebrenica.  The  UN  conducted  considerable  lessons  learnt  exercises  on  its  mistakes  in  both  theatres,  leading  to  a  Report  of  the  Secretary  General  in  the  case  of  Srebrenica9  and  of  an  Independent  Inquiry  in  the  case  of  Rwanda.10  The  unmistakable  conclusion  was  that  the  UN  had  made  mistakes,  and  had  failed  not  only  victims  but  the  international  community  in  general.    In  the  case  of  Srebrenica,  the  SG  expressed  his  “deepest  regret  and  remorse”  that  “through  error,  misjudgment  and  an  inability  to  recognize  the  scope  of  the  evil  confronting  us,  (the  UN)  failed  to  do  (its)  part  to  save  the  people  of  Srebrenica.”11  In  the  case  of  Rwanda,  a  similar  conclusion  would  be  repeated  over  the  years  in  mounting  crescendo  of  solemnity,  culminating  with  an  official  apology  presented  on  the  20th  anniversary  of  the  Genocide  by  Colin  Keating,  who  had  been  the  President  of  the  Security  Council  in  April  1994.  The  SG’s  High  Level  Panel  found  that  the  treatment  of  Rwanda,  abominable  in  itself,  also  raised  an  equity  issue  if  one  compared  its  actions  there  to  the  UN’s  swift  and  efficient  response  to  the  9/11  attacks.12  By  contrast  to  both  Srebrenica  and  Rwanda,  the  “concerted  pressure  swiftly  to  halt  large-­‐scale  killing”  in  East-­‐Timor  has  often  been  presented  as  an  example.13    

                                                                                                               7  D  Rohde,  Endgame:  The  Betrayal  and  Fall  of  Srebrenica,  Europe’s  Worst  Massacre  since  World  War  II  (Basic  Books  1998).  8  GÓ  Tuathail,  ‘The  Fall  of  Srebrenica  and  the  Ethics  of  UN-­‐Governmentality’  [1999]  Geography  and  ethics:  journeys  in  a  moral  terrain  120.  9  Report  of  the  Secretary-­‐General  pursuant  to  General  Assembly  resolution  53/35,  The  Fall  of  Srebrenica,  A/54/549,  15  November  1989.  10  Report  of  the  Independent  Inquiry  into  the  actions  of  the  United  Nations  during  the  1994  genocide  in  Rwanda,  S/1999/1257,  16  December  1999.  11  Report  of  the  Secretary  General,  supra  note  9,  para.  503.  12  UN  General  Assembly,  Report  of  the  High-­‐level  Panel,  supra  note  8,  para.  41.  13  Ibid.,  para.  87.  

As  will  be  further  explored  in  the  final  section  of  this  article,  this  soul  searching  fell  far  short  of  a  more  extensive  acknowledgement  of  some  form  of  legal  responsibility  for  the  deaths  that  occurred.  But  it  did  set  in  motion  a  whole  series  of  developments  that  were  to  profoundly  redefine  the  nature  of  peace  operations.  The  UN  found  that  both  in  Rwanda  and  Bosnia  it  had  failed  to  understand  the  full  magnitude  of  what  was  unfolding,  or  to  recognize  that  it  was  dealing  with  actors  that  manifested  a  form  of  evil  far  removed  from  the  sort  of  political  rationality  envisaged  by  traditional  peace  keeping  scenarios.  As  a  result,  a  lack  of  resolution  in  deciding  to  use  force  when  necessary  led  to  tragic  consequences.  The  UN  emerged  with  a  better  understanding  that  some  of  the  violence  entrepreneurs  it  was  confronting  would  not  be  amenable  to  the  traditional  pressures  to  respect  the  laws  of  war.  For  the  Independent  Inquiry  into  the  actions  of  the  United  Nations  during  the  1994  genocide:    

Faced  in  Rwanda  with  the  risk  of  genocide,  the  United  Nations  had  an  obligation  to  act  which  transcended  traditional  principles  of  peacekeeping.  In  effect,  there  can  be  no  neutrality  in  the  face  of  genocide,  no  impartiality  in  the  face  of  a  campaign  to  exterminate  part  of  a  population.  While  the  presence  of  United  Nations  peacekeepers  in  Rwanda  may  have  begun  as  a  traditional  peacekeeping  operation  to  monitor  the  implementation  of  an  existing  peace  agreement,  the  onslaught  of  genocide  should  have  led  decision-­‐makers  in  the  United  Nations  …  to  realize  that  the  original  mandate,  and  indeed  the  neutral  mediating  role  of  the  United  Nations,  was  no  longer  adequate  and  required  a  different,  more  assertive  response,  combined  with  the  means  necessary  to  take  such  action.14  

 Similarly  the  SG  noted  in  the  case  of  Srebrenica  that:    

With  the  benefit  of  hindsight,  one  can  see  that  many  of  the  errors  the  United  Nations  made  flowed  from  a  single  and  no  doubt  well-­‐intentioned  effort:  we  tried  to  keep  the  peace  and  apply  the  rules  of  peacekeeping  when  there  was  no  peace  to  keep.  Knowing  that  any  other  course  of  action  would  jeopardize  the  lives  of  the  troops,  we  tried  to  create  —  or  imagine  —  an  environment  in  which  the  tenets  of  peacekeeping  —  agreement  between  the  parties,  deployment  by  consent,  and  impartiality  —  could  be  upheld.    (…)  The  cardinal  lesson  of  Srebrenica  is  that  a  deliberate  and  systematic  attempt  to  terrorize,  expel  or  murder  an  entire  people  must  be  met  decisively  with  all  necessary  means,  and  with  the  political  will  to  carry  the  policy  through  to  its  logical  conclusion.15    

This  view  was  later  systematized  in  the  Brahimi  report  which  noted  that:    

(…)  impartiality  is  not  the  same  as  neutrality  or  equal  treatment  of  all  parties  in  all  cases  for  all  time,  which  can  amount  to  a  policy  of  appeasement.  In  some  cases,  local  parties  consist  not  of  moral  equals  but  of  obvious  aggressors  and  victims,  and  peacekeepers  may  not  only  be  operationally  justified  in  using  force  but  morally  compelled  to  do  so.16  

                                                                                                               14  UN  Security  Council,  Report  of  the  Independent  Inquiry,  supra  note  10,  pp.  50-­‐51.  15  Report  of  the  Secretary  General,  supra  note  9.  16  UN  Document,  Report  of  the  Panel  on  United  Nations  Peace  Operations,  A/55/305–S/2000/809,  21  August  2000,  para.  50.  

 Consequently,  the  UN  underwent  an  at  least  rhetorically  renewed  willingness  to  use  force  (“decisive  action”,  etc).  Although  this  was  not  only  to  avert  atrocities  and  also  involved  a  more  general  lesson  about  the  need  for  vigorous  pursuit  of  peace  in  the  face  of  “spoilers,”  it  was  particularly  clear  where  atrocities  might  be  involved.  If  “truly  safe  areas”  were  to  be  created,  for  example,  the  Secretary  General  concluded  following  Bosnia  that  they  ought  to  be  “fully  defended  by  a  credible  military  deterrent.”17  Brahimi  insisted,  after  referring  to  the  Rwanda  debacle,  that:    

the  Secretariat  must  not  apply  best-­‐case  planning  assumptions  to  situations  where  the  local  actors  have  historically  exhibited  worst-­‐case  behaviour.  (…)  It  means  bigger  forces,  better  equipped  and  more  costly,  but  able  to  pose  a  credible  deterrent  threat,  in  contrast  to  the  symbolic  and  non-­‐threatening  presence  that  characterizes  traditional  peacekeeping.  (…)  Such  forces  should  be  afforded  the  field  intelligence  and  other  capabilities  needed  to  mount  a  defence  against  violent  challengers.  (…)  Willingness  of  Member  States  to  contribute  troops  to  a  credible  operation  of  this  sort  also  implies  a  willingness  to  accept  the  risk  of  casualties  on  behalf  of  the  mandate.18  

 Thus  what  had  already  been  implicit  in  Bosnia  –  that  complex  internecine  conflicts  would  inevitably  call  upon  the  UN  to  up  the  ante  in  terms  of  use  of  force  –  became  more  generally  recognized  as  a  permanent  possibility  for  the  UN  after  the  Srebrenica  and  Rwanda  debacles.  Once  something  to  steer  clear  off,  the  “Mogadishu  line”  (the  one  symbolically  separating  peacekeeping  from  peace  enforcement)19  was  one  that  the  UN  anticipated  itself  as  crossing  much  more  readily  largely  as  a  result  of  concerns  for  civilians.      

B.  From  Protection  of  Civilians  to  Robust  Peacekeeping      Initially,  much  of  the  normative  impetus  for  changes  came  from  the  Genocide  convention,  and  the  rather  strict  obligations  it  imposes  on  states  and,  arguably,  international  organizations  to  prevent  genocide.  Rwanda  in  particular  had  foregrounded  genocide  as  the  crime  of  crimes.  Yet  the  relatively  high  threshold  of  genocide  and  the  difficulty  of  proving  all  its  elements  –  especially  in  the  real  time  conditions  of  an  unfolding  crisis  –    made  it  quite  narrow  a  normative  starting  point.  Concern  for  civilians  in  peace  operations  arises  far  short  of  this  extremely  high  threshold,  and  the  understanding  has  increasingly  been  that  peace  operations  should  be  involved  in  protecting  civilians  at  every  level  –    not  only  to  the  very  limited  extent  that  they  formed  part  of  a  protected  group  that  one  party  aimed  to  destroy  as  such.  The  cases  in  which  peacekeeping  forces  should  feel  a  responsibility  quickly  expanded  to  encompass  a  range  of  situations  where  civilians  might  find  themselves  in  danger.  

                                                                                                               17  UN  General  Assembly,  Report  of  the  Secretary-­‐General  Pursuant  to  General  Assembly  Resolution  53/35:  The  Fall  of  Srebrenica,  para.  499.  18  UN,  Report  of  the  Panel  on  United  Nations  Peace  Operations,  supra  note  16,  paras  51-­‐52.  19  After  the  failure  of  the  peace  operation  in  Somalia,  the  Secretary  General  asked  the  Council  to  deploy  UNISOM  I  and  UNISOM  II  to  create  conditions  on  the  ground  for  the  safe  delivery  of  humanitarian  assistance.  

 The  Security  Council  took  note  of  this  evolution  towards  the  end  of  the  1990s,  as  the  Rwanda  and  Srebrenica  reports  were  emerging.  Resolution  1265  is  notable  for  expressing  the  Council’s:    

…  willingness  to  respond  to  situations  of  armed  conflict  where  civilians  are  being  targeted  or  humanitarian  assistance  to  civilians  is  being  deliberately  obstructed,  including  through  the  consideration  of  appropriate  measures  at  the  Council’s  disposal  in  accordance  with  the  Charter  of  the  United  Nations.20  

 Indeed,  the  notion  of  protection  of  civilians  became  an  independent  cross-­‐cutting  theme  in  1999,  and  has  been  the  object  of  bi-­‐annual  Security  Council  meetings  ever  since.  In  that  context,  the  Under-­‐Secretary  General  developed  a  10-­‐point  platform  for  action  on  the  protection  of  civilians  in  armed  conflict.21  The  UN’s  capstone  doctrine  for  peacekeeping  identified  the  protection  of  civilians  as  one  of  four  “cross  cutting,  thematic  tasks”  that  peacekeepers  are  expected  to  fulfill,  even  when  it  is  not  explicitly  in  their  mandate.22  “Protection”  covers  a  range  of  issues  beyond  physical  protection  in  line  with  that  term’s  general  legal  humanitarian  understanding.  International  humanitarian  law,  international  human  rights  law,  refugee  law  and  domestic  law  all  contribute  to  outlining  protection’s    normative  framework.  The  broad  agenda  is  thus  one  of  protecting  populations  in  war.  Although  physical  protection  has  often  been  foregrounded  given  its  obvious  importance,  POC  is  arguably  broader  and  includes  a  range  of  more  traditional  activities  such  as  humanitarian  assistance  or  human  rights  monitoring.23    The  emphasis  has  been,  notably,  on  a  range  of  non-­‐violent  measures  that  peacekeepers  can  adopt,  ranging  from  the  most  strategic  to  the  most  tactical.  The  mere  “power  of  presence”  has  often  been  emphasized  as  at  times  crucial  and  there  is  evidence,  for  example,  that  it  deterred  génocidaires  in  places  like  the  ETO  in  Kigali  for  a  time.  The  role  of  peacekeepers  in  negotiating  access  to  civilians  has  been  emphasized,  as  well  as  the  need  to  demilitarize  refugee  camps.24  Peacekeepers  have  increasingly  been  given  mandates  to  disarm,  demobilize  and  reintegrate  ex-­‐combatants  who  might  otherwise  be  a  threat  to  the  civilian  population.25  They  have  been  asked  to  separate  combatants  from  civilians  in  refugee  or  IDP  camps.26  They  have  also  deployed  a  range  of  concrete  measures  and  tactics  to  protect  civilians  such  as  cordoning,  establishing  presences  close  to  vulnerable  civilian  centers.  Finally,  despite  persistent  suspicions  that  peacekeepers  

                                                                                                               20  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1265,  S/RES/1265,  17  September  1999,  para.  10.    21  This  was  introduced  by  Under-­‐Secretary  General  Egeland  at  a  meeting  of  the  Security  Council.  See  in  S/PV.4877,  9  December  2003,  p.  7.  22  UN  Department  of  Peacekeeping  Operations,  United  Nations  Peacekeeping  Operations:  Principles  and  Guidelines,  March  2008,  p.  16.  23  There  is  much  confusion  in  practice  between  different  grounds  for  and  concepts  of  protection.  For  a  more  thorough  treatment,  see  Haidi  Willmot  and  Scott  Sheeran,  ‘The  Protection  of  Civilians  Mandate  in  UN  Peacekeeping  Operations:  Reconciling  Protection  Concepts  and  Practices’  (2013)  95  International  Review  of  the  Red  Cross  517.  24  UN  General  Assembly,  Report  of  the  High-­‐level  Panel,  supra  note  8,  para.  236.  25  UN  Security  Council,  Report  on  the  protection  of  civilians  in  armed  conflict,  supra  note  7,  para.  65.  26  Ibid.,  para.  64.  

have  occasionally  been  part  of  the  problem,  they  have  gradually  crafted  a  role  for  themselves  in  terms  of  addressing  conflict  related  sexual  violence.27    Yet  aside  from  this  more  preventive  focus,  the  possibility  of  more  active  and  greater  use  of  force  by  peacekeepers  is  also  one  that  has  steadily  garnered  attention  in  New  York  and  in  the  field  under  the  moniker  of  “robust  peacekeeping”28  first  introduced  in  the  Brahimi  report.  Robust  peacekeeping  emerges  from  the  legacy  of  Bosnia  and  Rwanda  and  testifies  to  a  new  mood  within  peacekeeping  circles.  It  emerged  as  an  attempt  to  bridge  the  gap  between  peacekeeping  and  peace  enforcement  (the  elusive  “Chapter  VI  ½”),  which  claimed  to  safeguard  the  fundamental  commitment  to  impartiality  of  the  former  whilst  not  risking  the  UN’s  soul  by  failing  to  engage  in  the  latter.  It  is  one  that  emphasizes  the  need  for  peace  forces  to  protect  themselves  and  generally  operate  with  more  freedom.  It  has,  however,  gradually  foregrounded  the  possibility  that  peacekeepers  use  force  to  protect  civilians,  in  ways  that  subtly  tilt  peace  operations’  rules  of  engagement.  In  2003,  for  example,  DPKO’s  Best  Practices  Section  published  a  Handbook  on  United  Nations  Multidimensional  Peacekeeping  Operations  that  emphasized  that  instructed  peacekeepers  to  “actively  pursue  the  implementation  of  their  mandate  even  if  doing  so  means  going  against  the  wishes  of  one  or  more  of  the  parties  [to  the  conflict].”29  Self-­‐defense  was  described  as  “the  right  to  protect  …  any  other  persons  under  UN  protection.”30      Several  peacekeeping  operations  in  the  last  decade,  such  as  those  in  Sierra  Leone,  Burundi,  the  Congo,  Ivory  Coast  and  Sudan  show  the  sort  of  significant  normative  change  that  has  been  at  work.  The  first  resolution  to  ever  contain  language  of  this  sort  was  the  one  authorizing  UNAMSIL  in  Sierra  Leone  to  “afford  protection  to  civilians  under  imminent  threat  of  physical  violence.”31  Resolution  1291  of  24  February  2000  on  Congo  contains  the  following  paragraph:    

Acting  under  Chapter  VII  of  the  Charter  of  the  United  Nations,  decides  that  MONUC  may  take  the  necessary  action,  in  the  areas  of  deployment  of  its  infantry  battalions  and  as  it  deems  it  within  its  capabilities,  to  protect  United  Nations  and  co-­‐located  JMC  personnel,  facilities,  installations  and  equipment,  ensure  the  security  and  freedom  of  movement  of  its  personnel,  and  protect  civilians  under  imminent  threat  of  physical  violence.32  

 As  can  be  seen  from  this  broad  mandate,  the  protection  of  civilians  is  not  necessarily  at  the  heart  of  the  increased  authorization  of  force  (which  is  seen  as  primarily  connected  to  

                                                                                                               27  UNIFEM,  Addressing  Conflict-­‐Related  Sexual  Violence.  An  Analytical  Inventory  of  Peacekeeping  Practice,  2010.  28  Richard  Gowan  and  Benjamin  Tortolani,  ‘Robust  Peacekeeping  and  Its  Limitations’  [2008]  Robust  Peacekeeping:  The  Politics  of  Force  49.  29  UN  Department  of  Peacekeeping  Operations,  Handbook  on  United  Nations  Multidimensional  Peacekeeping  Operations  (New  York:  United  Nations,  2003),  p.  56.  30  Ibid.,  p.  57.  31  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1289,  S/RES/1289,  7  February  2000,  para.  10(e).  32  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1291,  S/RES/1291,  24  February  2000.  See  also  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1484,  S/RES/1484,  20  May  2003;  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1493,  S/RES/1493,  28  July  2003,  para.  27.  

a  broad  mission  implementation  agenda)  but  it  is  nonetheless  a  significant  and  noticeable  part  of  it.    Although  there  seems  to  have  been  a  lull  in  the  emphasis  on  civilian  protection  in  the  early  2000s,  this  began  to  change  notably  after  2007  and  the  perception  that  the  UN  was  once  again  failing  in  its  efforts  to  protect  civilians.  The  MONUC  mandate  was  subsequently  strengthened  so  that  it  was  asked  to  “ensure  the  security  of  civilians,  including  humanitarian  personnel,”  and  that  to  do  so  it  “use  all  necessary  means,  within  its  capabilities.”33  Similar  language  had  been  used  concerning  the  Ivory  Coast,34  Darfur,35  South  Sudan36  and  Liberia.37  In  fact,  the  protection  of  civilians  has  seemed  to  go  from  one  activity  among  many,  to  the  defining  (despite  persistent  doubts  about  its  own  definition)38  element  in  the  Congo  mission  and  others  on  the  basis  that  “successful  missions  are  those  that  deal  with  the  protection  of  civilians  as  an  integrated  part  of  their  aims.”39  The  consequences  of  such  a  development  were  visible  in  a  place  like  the  Ivory  Coast  where  the  peace  mission  ultimately  transformed  itself  into  a  full  fighting  force  to  remove  a  political  leader  who  was  increasingly  associated  with  attacks  on  civilians.  Some  recent  peace  operations  have  coincided  with  higher  levels  of  violence  as  a  result  of  peacekeepers  being  more  willing  not  only  to  defend  themselves,  but  to  defend  civilians.  One  incident  in  the  Congo  close  to  Goma  saw  UN  peacekeepers,  with  aerial  support  from  helicopters,  engage  and  kill  as  many  as  200  militia  members.40  

C.  Implications  for  the  Changing  Nature  of  Peace  Operations    Robust  peacekeeping,  to  the  extent  that  it  is  implemented,  has  significant  implications  for  the  very  nature  of  peace  operations.  Principally,  it  reframes  the  finality  of  peace  operations  towards  the  protection  of  civilians  and  the  prevention  of  international  crimes.  Of  course,  at  a  certain  level  the  protection  of  civilians  is  increasingly  seen  as  necessary  for  peace.  The  Security  Council  has  been  saying  this  much  at  least  since  the  early  1990s,  and  the  Secretary  General  is  keen  to  promote  civilian  protection  as  instrumental  to  good  peace  building.  For  example  he  insisted  that  peace  operations  should  “protect  civilians  to  protect  the  peace,”  because  the  “plight  of  civilians  …  complicates  political  negotiations  or  interests.”41    

                                                                                                               33  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1649,  S/RES/1649,  21  December  2005,  paras  8,  11.  34  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1528,  S/RES/1528,  27  February  2004,  para.  6(i).  35  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  1769,  S/RES/1769,  31  July  2007.    36  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  2057,  S/RES/2057,  5  July  2012.  37  UN  Security  Council,  Security  Council  Resolution  2066,  S/RES/2066,  17  September  2012.  38  There  is  a  tension,  in  particular,  between  a  concept  of  «  protection  »  informed  by  international  humanitarian  law  which  includes  a  host  of  activities  traditionally  undertaken  by  the  ICRC  and  humanitarian  actors  to  ensure  that  the  laws  of  war  are  respected  (and  which  they  typically  are  reluctant  to  see  endorsed  by  UN  operations),  and  a  more  narrow  understanding  of  «  physical  protection  »  where  peace  operations  protect  populations,  but  the  line  that  separates  the  two  is  often  blurry.  39  UN  Department  of  Peacekeeping  Operations  and  Office  for  the  Coordination  of  Humanitarian  Affairs,  Protecting  Civilians  in  the  Context  of  UN  Peacekeeping  Operations  (New  York:  United  Nations,  2009),  p.  23.  40  ‘UN  Helicopters  Strike  Congolese  Rebels  -­‐  Al  Jazeera  English’  <http://www.aljazeera.com/news/africa/2013/08/201382815950221122.html>  accessed  21  January  2015.  41  UN  Security  Council,  Report  on  the  protection  of  civilians  in  armed  conflict,  supra  note  7.  

In  this  context,  according  to  one  influential  DPKO/OCHA  study,  “The  security  of  civilians  in  post-­‐conflict  environments  is  critical  to  the  legitimacy  and  credibility  of  UN  peacekeeping  missions,  the  peace  agreements  they  are  deployed  to  help  implement,  and  the  institution  of  the  United  Nations  itself.”  The  issue  of  perceptions  of  the  local  population  has  been  emphasized,  as  well  as  the  notion  that  “peacekeeping  operations  that  are  ill-­‐prepared  to  address  large-­‐scale  violence  directed  against  civilians  will  falter  and  may  even  collapse.”  Moreover,  it  has  become  clear  that  “a  peace  agreement  that  does  not  bring  a  halt  to  armed  violence,  widespread  human  rights  abuses  and  violations  of  international  humanitarian  law—or  that  tolerates  continued  violence  against  sectors  of  the  population—cannot  lead  to  legitimate  governance.”  In  fact,  “the  inability  of  peacekeeping  missions  to  address  violence  against  civilians  in  the  past  has  damaged  the  standing  of  the  United  Nations  and  threatened  to  discredit  the  practice  of  peacekeeping  in  general.”42  In  this  context,  the  rebranding  of  peace  operations  as  fundamentally  about  civilian  protection  may  well  be  an  appealing  one  for  an  organization  such  as  the  UN  that  is  at  times  fighting  to  defend  its  legitimacy.  Protection  of  civilians  provides  a  seemingly  neutral  goal  that  may  seem  to  be  more  concrete  and  immediately  achievable  than  achieving  peace,  and  that  may  well  enhance  the  UN’s  authority.    The  shift,  for  all  its  utilitarian  justification,  is  nonetheless  a  significant  one,  that  involves  a  rupture  in  the  language  used.  The  emphasis  on  the  complementarity  of  all  goals  (peace  and  the  protection  of  civilians)  should  not  obscure  their  real  differences.  Peace  is  a  broad  political  goal.  The  commission  of  atrocities  against  civilians  will  certainly  compromise  it,  but  so  will  many  other  things.  Moreover,  the  search  for  peace  is  traditionally  understood  as  involving  political  compromises  between  states  or  a  state  and  non-­‐state  actors.  UNPROFOR  and  UNAMIR,  for  instance,  were  paralyzed  by  a  vision  of  having  to  protect  or  pursue  peace  above  all,  which  left  them  legally,  politically  and  morally  disarmed  when  confronted  with  extreme  violence  against  civilians.  Putting  civilian  protection  at  the  heart  of  the  UN’s  mandate  requires  a  very  deep  rethink  of  the  nature,  goals  and  purposes  of  peace  operations.  Most  significantly,  it  has  deep  implications  for  the  cardinal  principle  of  impartiality.  Traditional  peace  operations  were  based  on  the  impartiality  of  peacekeepers  (and  the  importance  of  that  requirement  had  been  if  anything  heightened  by  the  requirements  of  providing  assistance).  The  protection  of  civilians,  however,  especially  in  a  context  of  atrocity  commission  that  is  seen  as  emanating  primarily  from  one  side,  often  requires  them  to  choose  sides.    The  protection  mandate  is  certainly  impartial  in  that  it  is  impartial  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  different  civilian  victims.  A  victim  is  a  victim,  whether  at  the  hands  of  the  state  or  a  rebel  movement.  But  humanitarian  impartiality  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  victims  means,  precisely,  a  certain  partiality  against  those  who  prey  on  civilians.  DPKO’s  Handbook  for  example  emphasizes  that  “impartiality  does  not  mean  inaction  or  overlooking  violations.”43  This  taking  of  sides  is  not  quite,  as  was  traditionally  feared,  the  blatant  political  sort,  that  would  risk  fundamentally  compromising  a  mission’s  peace-­‐enabling  credentials.  But  it  is  one  that  typically  requires  determining  which  parties  are  responsible  for  atrocities  and  confronting  them.  It  is  thus  in  tension  with  the  more  traditional  striving  to  being  and  being  perceived  as  an  impartial  arbiter  which  has  increasingly  come  under  criticism  in  a  

                                                                                                               42  DPKO/OCHA,  Protecting  Civilians  in  the  Context  of  UN  Peacekeeping  Operations,  supra  note  38,  pp.  2-­‐4.  43  Ibid.,  p.  56.  

post  Cold  war  world.44  This  was  already  apparent  in  Bosnia  and  had  been  a  concern  for  the  Secretary  General,  who  saw  UNPROFOR’s  mandate  as  coming  dangerously  close  to  requiring  it  to  thwart  certain  military  objectives,  something  difficult  to  reconcile  with  the  delivery  of  independent  humanitarian  aid,  not  to  mention  the  role  of  impartial  arbiter  for  the  purposes  of  securing  a  peace  deal.  In  due  course,  Serb  forces  in  Bosnia  became  adamant  that  UN  forces  were  effectively  aligning  themselves  with  the  Bosnian  government.      The  taking  of  sides  in  peace  operations  has  always  been  problematic.  There  are  ways  of  course  in  which  institutional  design  can  reduce  the  confusion  that  arises  from  peace  operations  engaging  in  enforcement  action.  For  example,  the  “robust”  element  might  be  distinguished  entirely  from  the  peace  operation  (distinct  “peace  enforcement  units”),45  as  when  NATO  took  care  of  bombing  Bosno-­‐Serb  targets  in  the  former-­‐Yugoslavia  rather  than  UNPROFOR,  or  as  when  the  British  undertook  Operation  Palliser  to  rescue  UNAMSIL  in  Sierra  Leone,  or  Operation  Licorne  was  deployed  side  by  side  with  UNOCI  in  Ivory  Coast.  In  the  RDC,  a  separate  “intervention  brigade”  was  created,  in  ways  that  may  marginally  have  helped  MONUSCO  maintain  its  credentials  as  a  neutral  intermediary.  Nonetheless,  in  that  case  the  fact  that  the  Brigade  came  under  MINUSCO  command  suggested  that  it  was  fundamentally  seen  as  part  of  the  peace  effort,  not  as  something  running  parallel  to  it.  Although  Resolution  2098  that  created  the  Brigade  insisted  that  fighting  against  armed  groups  should  be  done  without  “any  prejudice  to  the  agreed  principles  of  peacekeeping”,  this  is  arguably  precisely  what  it  does.  In  practice,  it  will  be  very  difficult  to  fool  local  actors  that  this  other  emanation  of  the  international  community  is  entirely  distinct  from  the  existing  peace  keeping  force.    Aside  from  a  host  of  military,  operational,  institutional,  and  legal  challenges,46  the  issue  of  use  of  force  by  peacekeepers  remains  one  fraught  with  conceptual  problems.  For  example,  the  protection  of  civilians  will  need  to  be  weighed  against  the  overall  safeguard  of  the  mission,  an  issue  that  has  not  gone  away  simply  because  of  the  added  normative  urgency  of  protecting  civilians.47    Protecting  civilians  is  an  activity  that  is  difficult  to  carry  out  as  an  aside,  without  it  taking  over  an  entire  mission.  Taking  sides  will  be  particularly  problematic  in  a  context  where  all  parties  often  target  civilians,  even  if  one  side  does  so  more  for  political  or  military  reasons.  Even  the  protection  of  populations  in  safe-­‐areas  can  easily  be  mistaken  for  a  protection  of  a  particular  party’s  territory.  The  possibility  that  the  UN  will  intervene  in  ways  that  objectively  support  one  side  in  a  conflict  has  even  opened  up  the  possibility  of  groups  seeking  to  manipulate  peacekeepers  on  the  ground  to  incite  them  to  take  sides.    The  inevitable  slide  to  a  greater  use  of  violence  by  peacekeepers  is  bound  to  put  peace  operations,  and  the  legitimacy  of  their  mandates,  under  ever-­‐greater  scrutiny.  Interventions  here  and  there  to  protect  civilians  will  soon  be  known  across  a  conflict  zone  and  may  trigger  hostile  reactions.  It  is  difficult,  in  other  words,  to  “tactically”  protect  civilians  without  being  seen  as  “strategically”  taking  sides.  Protection  of  civilians                                                                                                                  44  RK  Betts,  ‘The  Delusion  of  Impartial  Intervention’  [1994]  Foreign  Affairs  20.  45  Adam  Roberts,  ‘The  Crisis  in  UN  Peacekeeping’  (1994)  36  Survival  93,  101–102.  46  On  these  issues,  particularly  those  involving  chain  of  command  and  mission  definition,  see  DPKO/OCHA,  Protecting  Civilians  in  the  Context  of  UN  Peacekeeping  Operations,  supra  note  38,  pp.  9-­‐12.  47  Thierry  Tardy,  ‘A  Critique  of  Robust  Peacekeeping  in  Contemporary  Peace  Operations’,  Journal  of  International  Peacekeeping,  vol.  18,  no.  2,  April  2011,  pp.  152-­‐167.  

may,  more  concretely,  lead  to  retaliations  against  peacekeepers  with  the  attendant  risk  that  they  will  be  confined  to  their  barracks,48  and  the  danger  that  an  entire  mission  will  be  compromised.49  Within  the  same  theatre,  it  will  be  hard,  if  not  impossible,  to  be  civilian  protector  one  day,  honest  mediator  the  next.  The  protection  of  civilians  may  clash  with  efforts  at  brokering  agreements  or  creating  the  political  conditions  for  peace.  Complex  tradeoffs  will  inevitably  arise,  for  example  between  protecting  oneself  and  protecting  others,  or  protecting  the  local  or  expatriate  populations.50  A  withdrawal  of  the  host  state’s  consent  remains  an  option.51  

II.  Relationship  to  R2P  and  International  Criminal  Justice    This  evolution  of  peace  operations  is  part  of  a  broader  phenomenon.  To  the  extent  that  peace  operations  have  evolved  at  the  intersection  of  the  emergence  of  R2P  and  international  criminal  justice,  one  might  expect  a  degree  of  conceptual  cross-­‐fertilization  (A).  One  interesting  affinity  between  all  three  may  be  a  certain  commitment,  beyond  the  fight  against  atrocities,  to  the  consolidation  of  weak  states  (B).  This  makes  it  possible  for  peace  operations  to  operate  dynamically  in  the  context  of  R2P  and  the  ICC,  even  as  they  remain  irreducible  (C).  

A.  Differences  and  Affinities      The  differences  between  robust  peacekeeping  and  international  criminal  justice  are  almost  too  evident  to  mention.  Like  robust  peacekeeping,  international  criminal  tribunals  emerge  as  a  response  to  international  atrocities.  Indeed,  there  has  long  been  a  line  of  argument  that  has  characterized  the  creation  of  the  ICTY  and  the  ICTR  as  precisely  resulting  from  the  failures  of  peacekeeping  and  as,  in  a  sense,  an  alternative  to  them.52  International  tribunals,  however,  evidently  function  through  different  modalities,  whose  specificity  lies  in  (i)  their  juridical  and  judicial  character,  (ii)  their  focus  on  individuals,  and  (iii)  their  inherently  repressive,  after-­‐the-­‐fact  nature.  One  could  add  that  international  criminal  tribunals,  unlike  peace  operations,  typically  operate  as  a  form  of  intervention  at  a  safe  distance  from  the  place  where  atrocities  are  being  committed.  Where  peace  operations  seek  to  avert  atrocities,  international  criminal  tribunals  seek  to  punish  them.      The  risk  of  confusion  between  “robust  peacekeeping”  and  R2P  is  more  likely  because  both  overlap  somewhat,  at  least  to  the  extent  that  they  potentially  involve  troop  deployment  and  assistance  to  the  state.  In  principle,  R2P  is  clearly  a  separate  

                                                                                                               48  The  killing  of  nine  Bangladeshi  soldiers  on  25  February  2005  by  a  militia  in  Congo  is  a  reminder  of  the  fundamental  vulnerability  of  peacekeepers  especially  when  they  expose  themselves  and  attract  the  ire  of  local  entrepreneurs  of  violence.  49  The  death  of  10  Belgian  peacekeepers  in  the  wake  of  the  Rwandan  genocide  had  a  considerable  role  in  leading  to  the  pullout  of  UNAMIR.  Interestingly,  when  killed,  they  had  just  sought  to  protect  a  civilian,  the  then  Prime  Minister.  50  Astri  Suhrke,  ‘Dilemmas  of  Protection:  The  Log  of  the  Kigali  Battalion’,  Journal  of  International  Peacekeeping,  vol.  5,  no.  2,  Summer  1998,  pp.  1-­‐18.  51  Congo,  for  example,  has  been  gradually  putting  the  UN  under  pressure  to  withdraw  its  operations  there.  52  Daphna  Shraga,  ‘The  Security  Council  and  the  Obligation  to  Prevent  and  Punish  Genocide’  [2010]  PISM  Series  257.  

development  from  the  protection  of  civilians  or  “robust  peacekeeping,”  one  that  is  not  specifically  concerned  with  peace  operations  and  truly  emerged  only  after  the  Kosovo  episode  in  1998.  The  idea  that  the  Security  Council  should  do  more  to  protect  civilians  in  peace  operations  anticipated  R2P  debates  by  several  years  and  was  in  fact  almost  entirely  distinct  from  it.  Robust  peacekeeping’s  civilian  protection  mandate  remains  largely  secondary  to  a  peace  keeping  agenda,  as  reflected  by  the  emphasis  put  on  force  protection.  R2P  is  concerned  with  the  responsibilities  of  states  and  the  international  community  at  large.  It  is,  at  heart,  an  elaboration  on  the  circumstances  in  which  the  international  community  should  be  willing  to  intervene  to  prevent  atrocities  (not  just  by  force).  It  involves  strategic  decisions  about  when  and  why  to  intervene,  typically  not  through  peace  operations,  for  example  because  the  atrocities  involved  are  of  an  order  of  magnitude  far  beyond  the  means  of  a  traditional  peacekeeping.  One  might  say  that  R2P  is  a  question  of  jus  ad  bellum,  where  robust  peacekeeping  operates  if  not  as  part  of  the  jus  in  bello,  at  least  as  part  of  a  much  more  tactical  version  of  the  jus  ad  bellum.    Tremendous  effort  has  gone  into  distinguishing  “robust  peacekeeping”  from  “peace  enforcement.”  The  Secretary  General  has  insisted  that  “While  the  work  of  peacekeepers  may  contribute  to  the  achievement  of  R2P  goals,  the  two  concepts  of  the  responsibility  to  protect  and  the  protection  of  civilians  have  separate  and  distinct  prerequisites  and  objectives.”53  There  are  sound  arguments,  moreover,  to  keep  peace  operations  and  R2P  separate.  For  example,  thinking  of  peace  operations  in  terms  of  R2P  may  create  misplaced  expectations  that  peace  operations  can  and  should  be  the  primary  tool  to  engage  in  enforcement  action  for  which  they  are  ill  fitted.  One  of  the  lessons  of  UNPROFOR  and  UNAMIR  is  that  they  might  have  engaged  in  more  robust  peacekeeping  in  discreet  locales,  not  that  they  could  as  such  have  provided  the  fer  de  lance  of  an  effort  to  stop  crimes  against  humanity  or  genocide.  Moreover,  R2P  exists  as  a  responsibility  quite  irrespective  of  whether  the  UN  already  has  a  presence  on  the  ground  in  the  form  of  a  peace  operation.  Peace  operations  protect  civilians  as  part  of  a  broader  mission  if  and  when  they  encounter  threats  to  civilians  (e.g.:  Democratic  Republic  of  Congo)  but  are  not  engaged  in  a  broader  enforcement  intervention  against  the  sovereign  (i.e.:  Libya).  Confusion  between  the  two  might  weaken  peace  operations  efforts  by  eliciting  starker  resistance  from  the  host  state  who,  having  accepted  a  peace  operation  might  be  surprised  to  suddenly  find  it  engaging  in  resolute  action  on  a  grand  scale  to  prevent  atrocities.  It  may  also  create  confusion  for  some  member  states.      Having  said  that,  in  theory  and  practice  there  are  several  potential  overlaps  between  peace  operations’  civilian  protection  mandate,  R2P  and  even  the  ICC.  As  Nicolas  Tsagourias  has  argued  in  relation  to  R2P  and  POC,  “the  two  concepts  are  “interlinked  and  indeed  constitute  parts  of  the  broader  concept  of  protecting  people  (they)  are  streams  of  the  same  concept”54  As  already  hinted,  all  three  share  a  common  ancestor.  Although  in  the  case  of  R2P  Kosovo  was  the  most  proximate  triggering  event,  its  emergence  is  haunted  by  the  early  90s  failures  of  Bosnia  and  Rwanda  (indeed  the  already  mentioned  Rwanda  and  Srebrenica  reports  came  out  soon  after  the  Kosovo  bombings).  As  to  the  ICC,  it  is  the  inheritor  to  two  ad  hoc  tribunals  that  were  created  as  

                                                                                                               53  A/66/874,  para.  16.    54  N  Tsagourias,  ‘Self-­‐Defence,  Protection  of  Humanitarian  Values  and  the  Doctrine  of  Impartiality  and  Neutrality  in  Enforcement  Mandates’  in  Marc  Weller  (ed),  The  Oxford  Handbook  of  the  Use  of  Force  in  International  Law  (Oxford  University  Press  2014).  

responses  Bosnia  in  Rwanda.  In  this  context,  both  R2P  and  international  criminal  tribunals  have  given  an  added  sense  of  urgency  to  what  the  UN  should  do  in  circumstances  where  threats  to  civilians  reach  the  level  of  atrocities.  They  may  help  reframe  “ordinary”  threats  against  civilians  as  looming  atrocities.  One  of  the  unintended  side-­‐effects  of  the  rise  of  the  R2P  and  the  ICC  may  be  the  extent  to  which  they  contribute  to  diagonally  reframe  peace  operations’  POC  mandate.  Both  help  transform  the  protection  of  civilians  in  peace  operations  from  a  highly  desirable  humanitarian  goal  for  peace  into  a  more  clearly  articulated  legal/moral  obligation  whenever  international  crimes  are  involved.55    More  subtly,  one  could  argue  that  there  has  been  a  process  of  discreet  mimetism  between  robust  peacekeeping,  R2P  and  the  ICC.  Both  R2P  and  the  ICC  have  provided  a  powerful  language  to  shape  expectations  about  the  role  of  the  international  community  in  relation  to  that  of  the  state.  One  of  the  key  components  of  R2P  is  the  idea  that  the  UN  is  legitimized  in  intervening  whenever  a  state  is  unable  or  unwilling  to  guarantee  the  security  of  its  citizens.  Similarly,  a  case  will  only  be  admissible  before  the  ICC  to  the  extent  that  the  state  is  unwilling  or  unable  to  prosecute  it.  The  core  idea  is  that  neither  are  supposed  to  substitute  for  the  sovereign  and  that  in  fact  the  goal  of  international  law  is  to  encourage  a  proper  use  of  sovereignty.56  This  is  a  way  of  thinking  that  is  also  familiar  to  peace  operations  which  are  seen  subsidiary  in  nature  to  the  state’s  own  responsibilities.    Indeed,  the  discourse  of  peacekeeping  often  draws  from  and  reproduces  tropes  that  have  become  familiar  from  R2P  and  the  ICC  and  stress  that  “the  protection  of  civilians  is  primarily  the  responsibility  of  the  host  government.”57  Even  as  it  confirms  the  mandate  of  MONUSCO  to  robustly  protect  civilians,  for  example,  the  Security  Council  stresses  “the  primary  responsibility  of  the  government  of  DRC  for  ensuring  security  in  its  territory  and  protecting  its  civilians  with  respect  to  the  rule  of  law,  human  rights  and  international  humanitarian  law.”58  The  UN’s  Master  List  of  Numbered  Rules  of  Engagement,  drafted  in  2002,  also  anticipate  use  of  force  by  peacekeepers  “when  competent  local  authorities  are  not  in  a  position  to  render  immediate  assistance.”59    Another  similarity  between  R2P,  the  ICC  and  robust  peacekeeping  is  the  notion  that  the  use  of  force  should  always  be  a  last  resort,  and  that  in  both  cases  prevention  is  the  key  goal.  In  this  context,  the  reinforcement  of  a  peace  operation’s  mandate  to  protect  civilians,  by  force  if  necessary,  is  often  narrowly  tailored  to  a  diagnosis  about  the  state’s  inability  to  do  so  in  the  circumstances,  in  ways  that  correspond  quite  closely  to  a                                                                                                                  55  In  that  respect,  it  has  been  noted  that  «  the  borders  between  a  ‘responsibility  to  protect’  operation  and  a  peacekeeping  operation  with  protection  elements  are  not  as  distinct  as  some  advocates  of  the  ‘responsibility  to  protect’  suggest  ».  Siobhán  Wills,  Protecting  Civilians:  The  Obligations  of  Peacekeepers  (Oxford  University  Press  2009)  253.  56  Markus  Benzing,  ‘Sovereignty  and  the  Responsibility  to  Protect  in  International  Criminal  Law’  in  Doris  König  and  others  (eds),  International  Law  Today:  New  Challenges  and  the  Need  for  Reform?  (Springer  Berlin  Heidelberg  2008)  <http://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-­‐3-­‐540-­‐75205-­‐9_2>  accessed  23  January  2015.  57  Draft  DPKO/DFS  Operational  Concept  on  the  Protection  of  Civilians  in  United  Nations  Peacekeeping  Operations,  para.  7.    58  SC/RES/2147  (2014).  See  also  Concluding  Observations  of  the  Committee  on  Economic,  Social  and  Cultural  Rights  Democratic  Republic  of  the  Congo  E/C.12/COD/CO/4,  20  November  2009.  59  United  Nations  Master  List  of  Numbered  ROE,  Guidelines  for  the  Development  of  ROE  for  UNPKO,  Provisional  Sample  ROE,  Attachment  1  to  FGS/0220.001,  United  Nations,  April  2002.  

perception  of  the  international  community’s  role  in  the  ICC  or  R2P  as  residual.60  In  other  words,  peacekeeping  powerfully  echoes  an  overarching  international  norm  of  the  subsidiarity  of  international  intervention  and  the  primary  responsibility  of  local  authorities.    

B.  A  Pro-­‐State  Bias?    The  move  to  civilian  protection  may  manifest  a  subtler  and  latent  structural  bias,  a  bias  that  is  also  well  in  evidence  in  R2P  and  the  ICC.  The  increased  use  of  force  in  peace  operations  to  protect  civilians  raises  two  plausible,  quite  different  scenarios.  In  the  first  case,  force  is  exercised  against  the  state  if  and  when  the  latter  threatens  civilians.  Such  a  move  is  not  inconceivable  on  a  very  ad  hoc  basis  or  as  an  in  extremis  measure  when  a  major  campaign  of  hostility  is  being  waged  against  civilians.  It  is  nonetheless  extremely  problematic  in  conditions  of  peacekeeping  because  it  is  almost  sure  to  be  incompatible  with  that  state’s  consent.  In  other  words,  there  is  a  strong  tension  if  not  an  absolute  incompatibility  between  peace  keeping  and  muscular  use  of  force  against  the  state,  which  suggests  that  robust  peacekeeping  of  this  kind  is  an  unlikely  possibility  (unless  a  peace  operation  gives  up  appearances  and  is  reframed  as  an  enforcement  one).  Indeed,  if  anything,  even  in  cases  where  the  state  is  suspected  of  committing  crimes,  peace  operations  have  tended  to  throw  their  authority  behind  the  sovereign,  as  if  paralyzed  by  the  possibility  that  they  might  undermine  their  viability  altogether.      Alternatively  (and  more  plausibly)  force  is  used  against  non-­‐state  actors  (i.e.:  typically  rebel  groups)  who  threaten  civilians.  The  dangers  here  are  very  different.  There  may  be  an  abundance  of  consent  from  the  host  state  who  will  see  UN  intervention  on  its  side  favorably.  In  effect,  muscular  protection  of  civilians  is  far  more  likely  to  be  exercised  against  non-­‐state  actors  than  against  states.  The  problem  in  this  case  is  the  risk  that  peace  operations  will  take  on  a  more  clear  anti-­‐non-­‐state  actor  bias.  This  is  a  fortiori  the  case  when,  as  with  MINUSCO  and  the  Forces  armées  de  la  République  démocratique  du  Congo  (FARDC),  UN  forces  are  specifically  asked  to  coordinate  with  or  even  support  state  forces  whose  “primary  responsibility”  in  ensuring  security  is  very  frequently  stressed.  Indeed,  it  is  already  clear  that  one  of  the  best  hopes  for  POC  may  lie  in  an  uneasy  alliance  between  certain  peace  operations  and  the  state’s  security  apparatus.61  The  impression  of  partiality  that  emanates  from  such  arrangements  may  be  reinforced  by  a  sense  that  the  state  is  not  an  impartial  security  provider,  but  in  fact  itself  the  result  of  processes  of  domination  by  certain  groups  (for  example,  in  the  case  of  the  FARDC,  the  Tutsi  dominated  CRDP),  not  to  mention  one  of  the  principal  causes  of  insecurity  to  civilians.    The  likely  shift  of  robust  peacekeeping  away  from  confronting  the  state  and  towards  combating  non-­‐state  actors  is  a  surprising  development  in  a  context  where  the  state  (Rwanda)  or  at  least  state-­‐like  actors  (e.g.:  the  Republika  Srpska  and  its  support  from  

                                                                                                               60  This  much  was  clear  in  the  context  of  the  Ivory  Coast  conflict,  and  the  subtle  evolution  of  the  wording  of  resolutions  which  occasionally  reminded  that  State  of  its  responsibilities  and  at  other  times  ‘forgot’  to  mention  them,  in  ways  that  manifest  an  “escalating  robustness”  Lotze  (n  2)  368..  61  J  Arthur  Boutellis,  ‘From  Crisis  to  Reform:  Peacekeeping  Strategies  for  the  Protection  of  Civilians  in  the  Democratic  Republic  of  the  Congo’  (2013)  2  Stability:  International  Journal  of  Security  and  Development  Art.  48.  

the  Yugoslav  Republic)  were  traditionally  thought  of  as  the  primary  danger  in  terms  of  committing  atrocity  crimes.  Yet  it  is  not  incompatible  with  a  certain  “Hobbesian  turn”  in  the  evolution  of  both  peacekeeping  doctrine  and  conflict  studies  more  generally,  and  an  investment  in  state  building  and  reinforcement  as  the  solution  to  problems  of  civil  strife.  The  UN  has  in  a  sense  already  long  taken  sides,  all  other  things  being  equal,  with  states,  and  this  is  evident  in  robust  peacekeeping  and  especially  peace  support  operations  which  clearly  contain  an  element  of  reestablishment  of  the  sovereign  order.62  A  country  like  the  Democratic  Republic  of  Congo  has  essentially  had  little  to  complain  about  when  it  comes  to  the  UN’s  contribution  to  the  reestablishment  of  its  sovereignty  on  its  territory.  On  the  downside,  coziness  with  the  state  will  certainly  make  it  harder  subsequently  to  simultaneously  fight  the  state  in  a  context  where  it  is  also  prone  (if  not  more)  to  commit  atrocities  against  civilians.  As  one  commentator  put  it,  “it  remains  a  challenge  for  any  commander  to  take  on  government  forces  with  which  they  had  been  operating  shoulder  by  shoulder  the  day  before.”63  Thus  the  state,  in  carefully  offering  its  cooperation,  may  also  buy  itself  a  certain  tranquility.    Ironically,  it  is  here  that  one  finds  some  of  the  subtlest  but  arguably  deepest  and  perhaps  most  problematic  analogies  between  robust  peacekeeping  and  both  R2P  and  the  ICC.  Both  begin  from  a  largely  contra-­‐sovereign  mystique,  originating  as  they  did  in  the  crimes  of  the  Bosno-­‐Serb  and  Rwandan  governments  (and  the  Nazis  and  Japanese  imperialists  further  down),  and  anticipating  a  Humanity  v.  Sovereignty  equation  in  which  states,  schematically,  as  the  prime  evil  doers.  In  the  best  of  cases,  international  criminal  tribunals  see  themselves  as  prosecuting  former  or  even  current  heads  of  states,  whilst  R2P  envisages  itself  as  being  deployed  against  the  state  that  is  unwilling  or  unable  to  protect  its  population  from  atrocities.  Helped  by  contingent  circumstances  (a  strong  Security  Council  backing,  a  relatively  weak  state),  this  is  indeed  what  they  do,  and  much  is  made  of  a  precedent  like  Libya,  seemingly  a  cas  d’école  or  both  R2P  and  the  ICC  working  according  to  plans.      Over  time,  however,  both  the  ICC  and  R2P  exhibit  unmistakable  signs  of  drifting  away  from  this  initial  and  superficial  contra-­‐sovereign  dynamic.  This  is  because  this  dynamic,  at  least  in  a  world  significantly  dominated  by  states,  is  invariably  paid  at  the  risk  of  inefficiency  and  even  irrelevance.  Hence  international  criminal  tribunals,  from  the  ICTR  to  the  ICC,  have  been  extremely  careful  about  confronting  the  very  authorities  on  whose  cooperation  they  rely  to  be  able  to  continue  to  operate.  Similarly,  the  most  significant  part  of  R2P  relies  on  cooperation  and  collaboration  with  the  state.  This  suggests  that  confrontation  with  the  sovereign,  whilst  possibly  inevitable  in  some  cases,  is  something  that  should  be  avoided  to  the  maximum.  Conversely,  international  criminal  tribunals  have  been  tempted  to  go  after  relatively  soft  targets  such  as  rebels  or  at  least  former  government  officers  that  no  longer  enjoy  the  state’s  shielding.  Similarly,  one  can  see  a  gradual  drift  of  R2P  discourse,  through  emphasis  of  the  first  two  pillars,  away  from  fighting  the  state  that  attacks  its  civilians  and  towards  helping  the  state  fight  the  non-­‐

                                                                                                               62  Draft  DPKO/DFS  Operational  Concept  on  the  Protection  of  Civilians  in  United  Nations  Peacekeeping  Operations,  para.  7  (“The  support  that  United  Nations  peacekeeping  operations  provide  to  host  governments  in  carrying  out  this  responsibility  enables  them  to  assert  their  authority,  protect  those  within  their  borders,  and  focus  on  rebuilding  the  nation  and,  its  institutions,  thereby  enhancing  the  sovereignty  of  States”).  63  MONUC  as  a  Case  Study  in  Multidimensional  Peacekeeping  in  Complex  Emergencies,  p.  106.  

state  actors  that  attack  its  civilians.  Both  R2P  and  the  ICC  redefine  themselves  over  time  as  being  about  the  proper  exercise  of  sovereignty.    Just  as  it  is  easier  for  the  ICC  to  prosecute  non-­‐state  actors  and  thus  benefit  from  state  cooperation,  and  just  as  R2P  is  deeply  premised  on  the  idea  of  helping  sovereigns  fulfill  their  duties,  it  is  easier  for  a  peace  operation  to  become  the  state’s  ally  in  fighting  rebels  than  to  take  on  the  state.  The  verdict  seems  to  be  that  the  protection  of  civilians  as  a  function  of  peacekeeping  is  also  heavily  invested  in  a  “Hobbesian”  vision  of  human  security,  one  in  which  the  state  must  ultimately  act  and  be  made  to  act  as  the  ultimate  guarantor  or  protection.  This  means  that  it  needs  to  be  reinforced  as  a  matter  of  urgent  priority,  even  in  contexts  where  its  record  is  extremely  fraught.  Given  the  failure  of  states  such  as  the  RDC  to  live  up  to  that  ideal,  however,  it  is  not  the  least  paradoxical  result  that  the  UN,  despite  its  insistence  on  state  responsibilities,  often  finds  itself  shouldering  the  lion’s  share  of  expectations  for  security  provision.64      

C.  Dynamic  Articulation    These  fundamental  affinities  between  robust  peacekeeping,  R2P  and  the  ICC  suggest  that  in  practice  these  various  institutions  may  be  coordinated  dynamically.  Peace  operations  may  certainly  become  part  of  R2P  strategies  and  the  Secretary  General  has  made  no  secret  of  the  need  to  “mainstream”  R2P  in,  among  others,  peacekeeping.65  The  second  pillar  of  R2P  maintains  that  the  international  community  has  a  responsibility  to  assist  the  state  to  fulfill  its  primary  responsibility:  it  will  often  do  so  through  peace  operations.66  For  example,  the  device  of  deploying  preventive  peace  operations  has  been  highlighted  by  the  Secretary  General  as  one  way  of  implementing  R2P.67  R2P  might  thus  be  considered  to  reshape  and  influence  a  range  of  activities  that  peace  operations  engaged  in  before  its  emergence  but  which  are  given  a  renewed  legitimacy  since  the  2000s.  As  the  SG  has  noted,  “Peacekeeping  missions  have  a  broad  range  of  mechanisms  which  are  aimed  at  supporting  peaceful  political  transitions  and  building  host  nation  capacity  to  protect  civilians.”68  For  example,  peace  operations  might  counter  propaganda  for  genocide  in  their  zone  of  deployment.69  More  generally,  almost  everything  that  a  peace  operation  does  for  the  protection  of  civilians  (whether  democratization,  economic  development  or  human  rights)  it  does  implicitly  or  explicitly  for  the  second  pillar  prevention  of  atrocities  as  well.      As  to  the  more  forceful  element  implicit  in  robust  peacekeeping,  it  may  have  some  affinity  with  R2P’s  third  pillar.  According  to  the  third  pillar,  if  the  state  manifestly  fails  to  protect  its  citizens  and  peaceful  measures  have  failed,  the  international  community  should,  in  extremis,  intervene  through  coercive  measures,  including,  in  extremis,  military  ones.  The  Commission  on  Sovereignty  and  Intervention,  which  laid  some  of  the  conceptual  basis  for  R2P,  had  already  made  it  clear  that  the  challenge  would  be  to  find  a  

                                                                                                               64  Boutellis  (n  61).  65  A/63/677,  para.  68.  66  A/666/874,  para.  16.  67  A/63/677,  para.  41.  68  A/666/784,  para.  16.  69  A/63/677,  para.  55.  

formula  that  would  come  very  close  to  that  of  robust  peacekeeping,  at  a  distance  from  both  traditional  peacekeeping  and  enforcement.70  In  effect,  short  of  enforcement  action,  the  granting  of  a  more  muscular  mandate  to  an  already  existing  peace  operation  is  an  obvious  way  in  which  to  modulate  the  international  community’s  action  in  a  way  that  begins  to  save  lives  without  antagonizing  the  host  state,  a  sort  of  first  stage  in  the  third  pillar  logic.  In  Rwanda,  for  example,  the  debate  was  whether  UNAMIR  should  be  reinforced  after  the  genocide  had  begun,  not  the  sending  of  an  entirely  new  enforcement  force.  Sometimes,  the  presence  of  a  force  on  the  ground  will  simply  make  it  much  more  practical  to  use  that  as  the  embryo  of  a  rapid  response  to  mounting  atrocities  (the  point  being  that  the  Rwandan  or  Srebrenica  genocides  did  not  exactly  leave  much  time  for  deliberation).      The  UN  of  course  is  keen  to  deny  that  peace  operations  effectively  transform  themselves,  through  attention  to  civilian  protection,  into  a  form  of  enforcement  action  more  akin  to  humanitarian  intervention:    

Although  on  the  ground  they  may  sometimes  appear  similar,  robust  peacekeeping  should  not  be  confused  with  peace  enforcement,  as  envisaged  under  Chapter  VII  of  the  Charter.  Robust  peacekeeping  involves  the  use  of  force  at  the  tactical  level  with  the  authorization  of  the  Security  Council  and  consent  of  the  host  nation  and/or  the  main  parties  to  the  conflict.  By  contrast,  peace  enforcement  does  not  require  the  consent  of  the  main  parties  and  may  involve  the  use  of  military  force  at  the  strategic  or  international  level,  which  is  normally  prohibited  for  Member  States  under  Article  2(4)  of  the  Charter,  unless  authorized  by  the  Security  Council.71  

 At  least,  however,  one  must  recognize  that  there  is  sometimes  a  dialectical  dynamic  between  elements  of  enforcement  and  peace  operations.  In  some  cases,  R2P  inspired  military  intervention  may  serve  to  support  an  existing  peace  operation,  in  essence  creating  the  space  for  it  to  operate.  For  example,  when  the  UN  Mission  in  Sierra  Leone  was  confronted  by  a  wave  of  attacks  and  commission  of  international  crimes  just  as  it  deployed,  its  credibility  was  upheld  by  organizing  a  British-­‐led  intervention  force.  Similarly,  Operation  Artemis,  led  by  the  European  Union  helped  MONUC  transition  to  a  more  robust  mandate  in  Ituri.  Conversely,  a  transition  is  conceivable  between  a  “robust  peace  operation”  whose  primary  mission  is  the  protection  of  civilians,  and  peace  enforcement  in  a  situation  where  the  protection  of  civilians  evolves  from  an  incidental  goal  as  part  of  more  or  less  traditional  peace  efforts  to  the  central  one  in  a  context  of  atrocity  commission.    The  line  between  “protecting  civilians”  and  averting  international  crimes  may  be  a  relatively  blurry  one,  requiring  constant  mandate  adjustments.  It  may  not  always  be  clear  what  attacks  against  civilians  are  not  simultaneously  constitutive  of  international  

                                                                                                               70  ICISS,  The  Responsibility  to  Protect,  2001  ,  para.  1.  23.  («  As  is  widely  recognized,  UN  peacekeeping  strategies,  crafted  for  an  era  of  war  between  states  and  designed  to  monitor  and  reinforce  ceasefires  agreed  between  belligerents,  may  no  longer  be  suitable  to  protect  civilians  caught  in  the  middle  of  bloody  struggles  between  states  and  insurgents.  The  challenge  in  this  context  is  to  find  tactics  and  strategies  of  military  intervention  that  fill  the  current  gulf  between  outdated  concepts  of  peacekeeping  and  full-­‐scale  military  operations  that  may  have  deleterious  impacts  on  civilians  71  UN  DPKO,  United  Nations  Peacekeeping  Operations:  Principles  and  Guidelines,  supra  note  23,  pp.  34-­‐35.  

crimes  (the  threshold  for  war  crimes,  in  particular,  is  not  very  high).  A  tactical  addendum  to  peace  operations  will  thus  be  often  at  risk  of  morphing  into  a  more  strategic  imperative,  the  idea  that  the  whole  peace  operation’s  raison  d’être  is  the  protection  of  civilians.  72    This  would  of  course  be  especially  true  in  cases  where  the  UN  is  not  confronting  isolated  violence  against  civilians,  but  a  more  systematic  campaign  triggering  R2P  concerns.  In  other  words,  one  may  well  run  into  a  number  of  situations  where  “the  measures  required  to  carry  out  the  assigned  tasks  or  to  meet  the  expectations  of  the  international  community  could  hardly  be  distinguished  from  forcible  humanitarian  intervention.”73  The  only  difference  is  that  robust  peacekeeping  still  sees  itself  as  operating  with  state  consent  –  albeit  somehow  still  conceivably  using  force  against  state  troops  if  they  threaten  civilians74  –  where  an  R2P  pillar  three  intervention  clearly  operates  against  the  state.  A  peace  operation,  however  robust,  is  unlikely  to  transform  itself  into  an  enforcement  force  against  the  state.  It  should  be  clear  nonetheless  that  the  two  operate  on  a  continuum  of  cooperation  with/constraint  against  the  state.75    When  it  comes  to  international  criminal  tribunals,  peace  operations  also  serve  evident  functions.  Their  existence  is  often  a  boon,  an  unlikely  field  presence  that  offers  at  least  some  prospect  for  enforcement  even  when  the  host  government  will  not  comply  with  requests.76  Although  quite  distinct  from  the  “ideal”  scenario  of  occupation  à  la  Nuremberg  or  Tokyo,  it  is  still  better  than  a  situation  of  almost  exclusive  dependency  on  a  recalcitrant  or  manipulative  territorial  state.  From  the  point  of  view  of  peace  operations,  the  idea  of  robustness  is  certainly  more  at  ease  with  the  strong  differentiating  thrust  of  international  criminal  justice.  In  principle  a  simple  arrest  should  be  reconcilable  with  the  use  of  non-­‐coercive  measures  and  thus  not  be  particularly  onerous.  If  evidence  were  required  that  criminal  prosecutions  are  conducive  to  the  goals  of  peacekeeping  (and  R2P),  some  peace  operations,  as  part  of  their  human  rights  and  rule  of  law  mandates,  have  carried  out  their  own  investigations  urging  domestic  and  international  prosecutions.77  

 

                                                                                                               72  Draft  DPKO/DFS  Operational  Concept  on  the  Protection  of  Civilians  in  United  Nations  Peacekeeping  Operations,  para.  7  («  it  should  be  noted  that  peacekeeping  operations  can  only  execute  the  protection  of  civilians  mandate  insofar  as  the  host  government  continues  to  provide  its  strategic  consent.  If  that  consent  is  withdrawn,  a  peacekeeping  environment  no  longer  pertains,  and  action  at  the  strategic  level,  including  by  the  Security  Council,  must  be  considered  ».)  73  T.  Modibo  Ocran,  ‘The  Doctrine  of  Humanitarian  Intervention  in  Light  of  Robust  Peacekeeping’,  Boston  College  International  and  Comparative  Law  Review,  vol.  25,  no.  1,  2002,  pp.  1-­‐58.  74  DPKO/DFS,  Framework  for  Drafting  Comprehensive  Protection  of  Civilians  Strategies  in  UN  Peacekeeping  Operations,  20  Jan,  2011,  para.  5.  This  is  largely  explainable  by  the  fact  that  although  a  government  may  give  consent  to  a  PKO  both  formally  and  operationally,  it  may  not  have  full  control  of  local  public  decision  makers  75  The  similarity  between  the  two  is  quite  clear  from  the  useful  attempt  to  draw  a  table  of  peace  operations  on  the  one  hand,  and  R2P  military  operations  on  the  other.  Responsibility  to  Protect  and  the  Protection  of  Civilians  Policy  Guide,  p  56  <http://www.academia.edu/2212015/Responsibility_to_protect_and_the_Protection_of_civilians_Policy_Guide>  accessed  23  December  2014.  76  Margherita  Melillo,  ‘Cooperation  between  the  UN  Peacekeeping  Operation  and  the  ICC  in  the  Democratic  Republic  of  the  Congo’  (2013)  11  Journal  of  International  Criminal  Justice  763.  77  E  Baylis,  ‘Reassessing  the  Role  of  International  Criminal  Law:  Rebuilding  National  Courts  through  Transnational  Networks’  (2009)  50  BCL  Rev.  1,  54–56.  

Indeed,  one  can  detect  a  trend  whereby  peace  operations  are  increasingly  asked  to  lend  their  muscle  to  the  arrest  of  wanted  fugitives.  Ideally,  the  two  will  operate  hand  in  hand.  The  Council,  for  example,  did  not  hesitate  to  grant  the  peacekeeping  mission  in  Liberia  a  mandate  to  arrest  Charles  Taylor.78  In  some  circumstances,  peace  operations  might  even  be  asked  to  arrest  some  of  the  very  persons  they  need  to  neutralize  to  protect  civilians  anyhow.  The  work  of  international  criminal  tribunals,  particularly  the  ICC  as  a  Court  that  is  working  more  or  less  in  real  time,  may  serve  a  sort  of  signaling  function,  describing  certain  acts  as  entailing  crimes  against  humanity,  genocide  or  war  crimes,  and  thus  directing  peace  operations’  efforts  towards  the  protection  of  civilians  and  the  prevention  of  atrocities.  This  much  has  already  been  suggested  in  the  context  of  R2P,79  and  there  is  no  reason  why  it  should  not  work  a  fortiori  with  robust  peacekeeping,  providing  legal  legitimacy  to  uses  of  force  that  might  otherwise  be  suspicious.      

III.  Moralization,  Operationalization  or  Legalization?      The  increased  “robustness”  of  peacekeeping  in  the  face  of  threats  to  civilians  is  also  an  opportunity  to  examine  peacekeeping’s  evolving  relationship  to  law  and  the  extent  to  which  it  is  the  result  of  and  a  contributor  to  processes  of  “legalization.”  As  will  be  seen,  the  starting  point  is  one  that  is  ambiguous  in  relation  to  international  law,  underlining  a  natural  resistance  of  peacekeeping  to  being  entirely  subservient  to  legal  imperatives  (A).  Yet  if  nothing  else  peace  operations’  evolution  towards  greater  emphasis  on  use  of  force  necessarily  affects  their  legal  regime  (B)  and  may  even  over  time  prompt  calls  for  accountability  for  its  “failures  to  protect”  (C).    

A.  An  Ambivalent  Relationship  to  International  Law    Many  of  the  developments  that  have  been  charted  so  far  are  informed  by  law.  In  redesigning  civilian  protection  as  above  all  a  way  of  averting  international  “atrocity  crimes,”80  the  UN  and  the  Council  began  the  process  of  replacing  a  political,  security  and  irenic  rationale  for  protection  by  a  uniquely  humanitarian-­‐law,  human  rights  and  criminal  justice  oriented  one.  As  a  result,  the  Council  has  arguably  redefined  what  peacekeeping  stands  for.81  Robust  peacekeeping  itself,  however,  has  a  somewhat  ambiguous  legal  status,  often  more  characteristic  of  an  evolving  institutional  soft  law  than  something  that  would  be  opposable  to  the  UN.  The  Secretary  General,  in  particular,  has  often  been  wary  of  engaging  on  a  path  that  might  prompt  calls  for  legal  forms  of  accountability,  emphasizing  the  need  to  move  to  robust  peacekeeping  as  principally  a  moral  and  operational  imperative.  The  paradox,  then,  is  that  the  move  to  robust                                                                                                                  78  Micaela  Frulli,  ‘A  Turning  Point  in  International  Efforts  to  Apprehend  War  Criminals  The  UN  Mandates  Taylor’s  Arrest  in  Liberia’  (2006)  4  Journal  of  International  Criminal  Justice  351.  79  M  Contarino  and  S  Lucent,  ‘Stopping  the  Killing:  The  International  Criminal  Court  and  Juridical  Determination  of  the  Responsibility  to  Protect’  (2009)  1  Global  Responsibility  to  Protect  560.  80  David  Scheffer,  ‘Genocide  and  Atrocity  Crimes’,  Genocide  Studies  and  Prevention,  vol.  1,  no.  3,  December  2006,  pp.  229-­‐250.  81  In  the  early  years,  international  criminal  justice  was  largely  seen  as  a  tool  of  the  Council  for  the  purposes  of  achieving  international  peace  and  security.  Increasingly  though,  it  is  as  if  the  Council  sees  itself  as  a  tool  to  prevent  the  commission  of  international  crimes.  The  relationship  between  the  two  remain  a  complex  one,  as  shown  by  the  complex  ballet  of  ICC  referrals/deferrals,  and  peace  operations’  occasional  reluctance  to  proceed  with  arrests  or  cooperate  with  investigations  and  trials.  

peacekeeping  is  precipitated  by  legal  developments  and  an  increasingly  legal  approach  to  civilian  protection,  yet  itself  remains  characterized  by  a  somewhat  cavalier  approach  to  the  law,  one  in  which  protecting  civilians  is  the  fulfillment  of  a  mandate,  a  form  of  noblesse  oblige  or  an  international  public  service,  but  not  quite  a  legal  obligation.  This  is  of  course  reminiscent  of  R2P  itself  as  a  concept  born  from  attention  to  legal  imperatives  but  whose  legal  status  is  kept  relatively  vague.82    This  does  not  mean  that  tensions  in  the  discharge  of  peacekeeping  will  not  occur.  They  may  arise,  in  particular,  from  the  interaction  of  peace  operations  with  the  activities  of  international  criminal  tribunals,  putting  in  stark  relief  the  contrast  between  a  regime  still  largely  dominated  by  operational  constraints  (peace  operations)  and  one  focused  on  a  much  more  principled  and  deontological  drive  to  legalize  (international  justice).  In  practice,  the  complementarity  of  international  criminal  justice  and  peace  operations  has  been  complicated  by  a  perception  that  prioritizing  a  justice  imperative  might  clash  with  and  even  endanger  the  operational  requirements  of  peace  operations,  including  civilian  protection.  Like  R2P,  international  criminal  justice  potentially  introduces  a  strong  axiological  element,  elevating  the  protection  of  civilians  from  a  highly  desirable  goal  of  harm  minimization  to  an  imperative  of  atrocity  prevention.  In  humanitarian  terms,  one  might  say  it  contributes  to  change  missions’  focus  from  assistance  to  protection.  The  ascending  and  imperative  value  of  international  criminal  justice  thus  puts  stress  on  a  “business  as  usual”  model  of  peacekeeping,  even  one  focused  on  protection  of  civilians.      In  this  context,  the  move  by  the  US  to  pressurize  the  Council  to  demand  a  deferral  from  the  ICC  of  any  investigations  that  might  concern  peacekeepers  was  often  criticized  as  a  typical  manifestation  of  American  unilateralism.83  In  truth,  however,  it  arguably  echoed  a  certain  pattern  of  the  UN’s  own  actions.  The  UN  has  often  sought  to  de-­‐emphasize  the  legal  obligations  of  peace  operations  particularly  as  they  result  from  the  needs  of  international  criminal  repression,  for  the  benefit  of  greater  operational  freedom.84  Of  course,  the  host  state  itself  (e.g.:  Sudan)  has  often  been  vociferous  that  one  cannot  have  a  peace  operation  in  its  territory  with  its  consent  that  is  simultaneously  tasked  with  arresting  state  officials.85  This  is  not,  however,  a  position  that  the  UN  has  vigorously  opposed,  perhaps  in  a  bid  to  save  particular  peace  missions.86  

                                                                                                               82  Jennifer  M  Welsh  and  Maria  Banda,  ‘International  Law  and  the  Responsibility  to  Protect:  Clarifying  or  Expanding  States’  Responsibilities?’  (2010)  2  Global  Responsibility  to  Protect  213;  Alex  J  Bellamy  and  Ruben  Reike,  ‘Responsibility  to  Protect  and  International  Law,  The’  (2010)  2  Global  Resp.  Protect  267.  83  Carsten  Stahn,  ‘The  Ambiguities  of  Security  Council  Resolution  1422  (2002)’  (2003)  14  European  Journal  of  International  Law  85;  Mohamed  El  Zeidy,  ‘United  States  Dropped  the  Atomic  Bomb  of  Article  16  of  the  ICC  Statute:  Security  Council  Power  of  Deferrals  and  Resolution  1422,  The’  (2002)  35  Vand.  J.  Transnat’l  L.  1503.  84  Salvatore  Zappala,  ‘Are  Some  Peacekeepers  Better  Than  Others  -­‐  UN  Security  Council  Resolution  1497  (2003)  and  the  ICC’  (2003)  1  Journal  of  International  Criminal  Justice  671,  671.  (noting  that  “admittedly,  the  resolution  met  the  demands  of  the  international  community,  voiced  by  the  UN  Secretary-­‐General,  and  thus  commanded  widespread  support  among  members  of  the  Security  Council.”  85  V  Peskin,  ‘The  International  Criminal  Court,  the  Security  Council,  and  the  Politics  of  Impunity  in  Darfur’  (2009)  4  Genocide  studies  and  prevention  304,  311.  86  For  example,  as  far  as  I  could  establish,  after  Al-­‐Bashir  nominated  Ahmad  Harun,  who  is  sought  by  the  ICC  for  atrocities,  as  Minister  of  State  for  Humanitarian  Affairs  and  Governor  of  South  Kordofan,  the  AU/UN  peacekeeping  mission  continued  to  collaborate  with  him.  More  generally  the  UN  and  member  states  have  not  vigorously  pressured  Khartoum  to  comply  with  arrest  warrants,  foregrounding  instead  the  

 This  ambivalence  has  long  been  visible  in  the  response  by  some  peace  operations’  to  international  criminal  tribunals’  for  cooperation.  In  theory,  as  has  been  seen,  the  goal  of  protecting  civilians  in  peace  operations  and  punishing  those  who  torment  them  should  be  largely  harmonious.  In  practice,  peace  operations  have  not  always  been  happy  to  oblige.  For  example,  they  have  at  times  been  reluctant  to  proceed  to  arrests  mandated  by  international  criminal  tribunals.87  Although  cooperation  has  sometimes  been  forthcoming,  the  UN  has  treated  requests  for  cooperation  by  international  criminal  tribunals  –  supposedly  to  protect  their  independence  –  as  if  they  emanated  from  states,  meaning  that  it  has  weighed  the  interests  of  justice  against  its  operational  necessities.88  Some  peace  operations  (e.g.:  the  African  Union  observer  mission  in  Sudan,  UNAMID)  have  not  even  technically  included  a  mandate  to  arrest  suspects.  NATO  once  argued  aggressively  that  to  the  extent  SFOR  as  a  peace  operation  created  by  the  Security  Council  had  a  similar  standing  as  the  ICTY,  it  was  inapposite  for  that  tribunal  to  order  it  to  provide  evidence,  and  this  could  endanger  future  peace  operations.89    In  the  case  of  the  ICC,  even  more  leeway  exists,  given  the  institutional  independence  of  the  UN,  to  deny  requests  for  cooperation  (including,  for  example,  for  protection  of  investigators,  victims  and  witnesses)  that  might  be  seen  as  in  tension  with  UN  operations.  90  In  the  Congo  context,  crucial  evidence  was  provided  to  ICC  investigators  by  MONUSCO  “intermediaries”  only  on  the  condition  of  confidentiality  agreements  which  eventually  almost  scuttled  the  prosecution’s  case  as  a  result  of  an  inability  to  reveal  exculpatory  evidence  to  the  defense.  This  underscores  the  unique  dependence  of  the  ICC  on  peace  operations,  but  simultaneously  the  unique  vulnerability  to  such  cooperation.  Indeed,  it  is  the  ICC  itself  that  consented  to  provisions  highly  protective  of  the  UN  ‘s  privileges  notably  when  it  comes  to  peace  operations.91  And  of  course  the  UN  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         deployment  of  the  mission.  See  Ibid  317.  («  In  sum,  obtaining  Khartoum’s  cooperation  in  the  quest  for  peace,  peacekeeping,  and  humanitarian  relief  (…)  has  so  far  trumped  the  ICC’s  quest  for  the  international  community’s  political  backing  in  the  prosecution  of  war  crimes.  »)  87  Jann  K  Kleffner,  ‘SFOR’s  Half-­‐Hearted  Compliance  with  Its  International  Obligations  to  Execute  Arrest  Warrants  of  the  ICTY’  (1999)  5  International  Peacekeeping  (Dordrecht)  80.  88  This  means  that  the  Secretary  General  has  taken  into  account  «  the  question  of  the  safety  of  potential  witnesses,  especially  if  continuing  to  serve  in  an  area  controlled  by  associates  of  persons  accused  in  a  tribunal  (sometimes  an  important  consideration  in  the  Balkans);  the  security  and  effectiveness  of  the  UN  mission;  the  confidentiality  of  the  internal  affairs  of  the  UN;  and  practical  considerations  such  as  the  difficulty  in  complying  with  demands  for  enormous  quantities  of  documentation  »).  Paul  C  Szasz  and  Thordis  Ingadottir,  ‘The  UN  and  the  ICC:  The  Immunity  of  the  UN  and  Its  Officials’  (2001)  14  Leiden  Journal  of  International  Law  867,  875.  89  ‘ICTY  Order  for  Disclosure  of  Information  by  NATO/SFOR’  (2001)  95  The  American  Journal  of  International  Law  401.  90  Han-­‐Ru  Zhou,  ‘The  Enforcement  of  Arrest  Warrants  by  International  Forces  From  the  ICTY  to  the  ICC’  (2006)  4  Journal  of  International  Criminal  Justice  202.  91  See  article  15(3)  of  the  General  provisions  regarding  cooperation  between  the  United  Nations  and  the  Court  («  In  the  event  that  the  disclosure  of  information  or  documents  or  the  provision  of  other  forms  of  cooperation  would  endanger  the  safety  or  security  of  current  or  former  personnel  of  the  United  Nations  or  otherwise  prejudice  the  security  or  proper  conduct  of  any  operation  or  activity  of  the  United  Nations,  the  Court  may  order  particularly  at  the  request  of  the  United  Nations,  appropriate  measures  of  protection.  In  the  absence  of  such  measures,  the  United  Nations  shall  endeavor  to  disclose  the  information  or  documents  or  to  provide  the  requested  cooperation,  while  reserving  the  right  to  take  its  own  measures  of  protection,  which  may  include  the  withholding  of  some  information  or  documents  or  their  submission  in  an  appropriate  form,  including  the  introduction  of  redactions.”  Larry  D  Johnson,  ‘The  Lubanga  Case  and  

itself  did  not  renounce  the  confidentiality  implicit  in  its  provision  of  evidence,  ultimately  putting  the  ICC  prosecutor  in  a  very  difficult  situation.    The  subliminal  message  seems  to  be  that  the  operational  necessities  of  peace  operations  (including,  presumably,  civilian  protection)  should  ultimately  trump  issues  of  accountability  (for  harm  to  civilians).  In  that  respect,  peace  operations  are  an  interesting  prism  to  observe  the  “peace  v.  justice”  dilemma,  with  every  institution  seemingly  arguing  pro  domo:  for  international  criminal  tribunals  there  can  famously  be  “no  peace  without  justice,”  where  peace  operations  are  more  likely  to  stand  for  the  proposition  that  there  can  be  no  justice  without  peace.92  In  sum,  whilst  peace  operations  are  increasingly  authorized  to  use  force  to  protect  civilians,  they  are  typically  and  somewhat  ironically  not  always  explicitly  allowed  to  use  force  to  arrest  those  who  commit  crimes  against  civilians  or  protect  those  who  seek  to  prosecute  the  latter.93  It  is  of  course  clear  that  cooperating  with  international  criminal  tribunals  might  turn  out  to  be  a  “tipping  point”  in  the  relationship  of  peace  operations  with  the  host  state.    The  general  impression  that  emerges  is  one  in  which  the  UN  largely  sees  itself  “outside”  the  accountability  problematique,  which  is  mostly  associated  with  the  work  of  international  criminal  tribunals.  This  explains  why  it  has  occasionally  had  difficulty  seeing  itself  as  an  accessory  to  the  work  of  international  criminal  justice.  It  may  also  explain  why  the  UN  is  so  resistant  to  claims  about  is  own  accountability.  Whilst  the  UN  has  committed  to  protecting  civilians,  acknowledged  its  past  faults,  and  strongly  condemned  those  who  participate  in  atrocities,  it  has  also  had  no  qualm  in  invoking  its  immunity  whenever  its  responsibility  was  sought  in  connection  with  peacekeeper  wrongdoing.94  Initial  soul-­‐searching  exercises  that  gave  the  impetus  to  the  development  of  Robust  Peacekeeping  were  framed  by  policy  considerations  as  well  as  principles.  But  they  were  seen  by  the  UN  largely  as  unilateral  changes  that  would  not  particularly  lead  to  any  form  of  accountability.  If  anything,  the  UN  would  carefully  review  its  own  actions  in  light  of  its  own  principles  and  on  its  own  terms.  UN  peacekeeping  thus  offers  the  intriguing  paradox  of  a  practice  that  is  heavily  premised  on  the  accountability  of  perpetrators,  yet  that  is  curiously  oblivious  to  its  own  accountability.      

B.  The  Emergence  of  a  Humanitarian  Regime  of  Peacekeeping    Nonetheless,  it  bears  emphasizing  that  international  law  has  made  some  strides  in  developing  a  legal  regime  that  adapts  to  the  evolving  nature  of  peace  operations.  It  is  one  from  which  peace  operations  arguably  benefit  and  that  can  theoretically  take  into  account  the  switch  from  impartial  arbiters  of  the  peace  to  a  more  active  civilian                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                            Cooperation  between  the  UN  and  the  ICC  Disclosure  Obligation  v.  Confidentiality  Obligation’  (2012)  10  Journal  of  International  Criminal  Justice  887. 92  The  fear  in  Sudan  in  particular,  magnified  by  Al-­‐Bashir’s  own  threat  to  put  an  end  to  the  peace  mission,  is  that  an  attempt  to  enforce  the  arrest  warrant  against  him  would  spell  an  end  to  the  UN/AU  effort  to  deploy  peacekeepers  and  thus  help  bring  an  end  to  conflict  and  provide  humanitarian  relief.  Christopher  Gosnell,  ‘The  Request  for  an  Arrest  Warrant  in  Al  Bashir  Idealistic  Posturing  or  Calculated  Plan?’  (2008)  6  Journal  of  International  Criminal  Justice  841,  844.  93  Note  that  this  has  not  prevented  peace  missions  from  providing  some  sort  of  protection  to  the  ICC  in  a  very  indirect  way.  Melillo  (n  76)  768–769.  94  F  Rawski,  ‘To  Waive  or  Not  to  Waive:  Immunity  and  Accountability  in  UN  Peacekeeping  Operations’  (2002)  18  Conn.  J.  Int’l  L.  103.  

protection  force.  The  regime  is  thus  both  significantly  protective  yet,  increasingly,  one  that  imposes  obligations  on  peace  operations.    To  begin  with,  then,  and  especially  as  long  as  peacekeepers  limit  themselves  to  their  traditional  role  as  impartial  go-­‐betweens,  the  emphasis  is  on  their  protection.  This  entails,  in  particular,  the  prosecution  of  those  who  would  attack  peacekeepers  or,  for  example,  take  them  hostage.  Revealingly,  for  all  their  shortcomings  in  protecting  civilians,  this  was  a  danger  experienced  by  both  UNPROFOR  and  UNAMIR  in  Bosnia  and  Rwanda  respectively.  The  Convention  on  the  Safety  of  United  Nations  and  Associated  Personnel  seeks  to  remedy  this  sort  of  problem  and  of  course  can  be  seen  indirectly  as  a  way  of  protecting  civilians  (a  peace  operation  that  is  constantly  the  target  of  attacks  is  in  no  position  to  protect  civilians).95  As  long  as  peacekeepers  do  not  become  participants  in  an  armed  conflict  (as  would  be  the  case  in  a  Chapter  VII  enforcement  mission),  they  are  entitled  to  special  protection,  akin  to  that  of  non-­‐combatants.  The  Rome  Statute  of  the  ICC  has  since  specifically  created  a  new  war  crime  of  attacks  on  peacekeepers.  International  criminal  tribunals  have  reinforced  the  sense  that  this  protection  is  real  by  prosecuting  individuals,  including  members  of  rebel  groups,  accused  of  having  committed  crimes  against  peacekeepers96  –  an  indication  that  international  criminal  justice  can  be  very  much  conducive  to  the  carrying  out  of  peace  operations.    The  challenge  of  robust  peacekeeping,  however,  is  that  in  permitting  further  use  of  force  it  potentially  precipitates  a  change  of  paradigm  for  the  UN  requiring  an  entirely  different  legal  regime.  If  peace  operations  do  aggressively  protect  civilians,  they  arguably  lose  any  “civilian”  status  that  they  may  have  claimed.  Indeed,  they  should  lose  that  status  on  the  basis  of  the  principle  of  the  equality  of  belligerents,  but  also  because  it  would  be  unfair  and  impractical  for  them  to  be  protected  persons  yet  simultaneously  be  able  to  engage  in  hostilities.  The  risk,  in  this  context,  is  that  force  will  be  used  abusively  even  where  it  is  justified  to  protect  civilians.  Although  this  is  by  no  means  necessarily  the  greatest  risk,  it  is  a  testimony  to  how  fast  things  have  been  moving  in  this  area  that  concerns  have  already  emerged  about  excesses  that  might  be  committed  in  the  course  of  robust  peacekeeping,  especially  in  a  context  of  R2P  and  ICC  infused  moral  urgency.  The  principal  obstacle  to  the  applicability  of  international  humanitarian  law  to  peacekeepers  was  lifted  by  the  Secretary  General’s  bulletin  on  the  applicability  of  international  humanitarian  law  to  peace  operations.97  This  has  not  entirely  dispelled  doubts,  however,  about  when  a  peace  operation  is  protected  and  when  it  operates  under  international  humanitarian  law.    There  is,  notably,  a  grey  zone  between  situations  in  which  the  UN  acts  as  a  traditional  “non-­‐participant”  peacekeeper  and  classic  chapter  VII  intervention.  Where  does  robust  peacekeeping  fit  in?  It  should  be  emphasized  that  robust  peacekeeping  is  of  course  both  a  mandate  and  a  form  that  peacekeeping  may  take  in  actual  circumstances.  Simply  because  a  peace  operation  has  a  robust  civilian  protection  mandate  does  not  mean  that  it  is  using  it,  or  using  it  dynamically  enough  to  be  described  as  a  participant  in  hostilities.  There  might  be  a  case,  for  example,  that  the  protection  of  civilians  on  the  margins  of  a                                                                                                                  95  Convention  on  the  Safety  of  UN  and  Associated  Personnel,  1994.  96  Alice  Gadler,  ‘Protection  of  Peacekeepers  and  International  Criminal  Law:  Legal  Challenges  and  Broader  Protection,  The’  (2010)  11  German  Law  Journal  585.  97  Secretary  General,  Bulletin  on  the  observance  by  United  Nations  forces  of  international  humanitarian  law,  6  August  1999.  

peace  operation  is  more  akin  to  police  work  (for  example  UNMIK  seeking  to  prevent  rioting  in  Kosovo)  and  should  not  warrant  the  application  of  international  humanitarian  law;  but  the  full  deployment  of  an  operation  to  stop  atrocities  in  their  track  could  almost  certainly  not  avoid  the  applicability  of  the  laws  of  war.    The  question  of  what  is  the  “armed  conflict”  that  triggers  the  applicability  of  the  laws  of  war  in  this  context  remains  quite  confused.  For  example,  the  mere  exercise  of  “self  defense”  by  a  mission  is  generally  not  understood  to  create  ipso  facto  an  armed  conflict,  but  is  the  protection  of  civilians  in  pursuit  of  a  mandate  to  that  effect  still  subsumable  within  self-­‐defense?  It  often  seems  as  if  the  meaning  of  self-­‐defense  has  been  stretched  to  incorporate  every  aspect  of  a  peace  operation’s  life.98  Tactical,  ad  hoc  interventions  to  protect  civilians  in  an  environment  that  remains  otherwise  fundamentally  defined  by  traditional  peacekeeping  principles  have  been  found  to  not  deprive  a  peace  operation  of  the  1994  Convention  protection.99  The  attitude  of  parties  on  the  ground,  however,  may  be  decisive,  in  that  it  frames  whether  the  operation  continues  to  operate  within  the  parameters  of  consent.  This  creates  an  intriguing  situation  where  the  withdrawal  of  consent  by  local  actors  may  create  a  de  facto  situation  of  hostility,  even  if  the  UN  is  not  keen  to  be  a  party  to  hostilities  itself  and  does  not  resort  to  violence.  Overall,  it  also  creates  a  situation  in  which  peacekeepers  are  considered    to  be  non-­‐combatants  by  nature  who  may  yet  become  combatants  by  their  activity,  and  for  whom  the  relevant  standard  is  that  of  “direct  participation  in  hostilities.”    In  addition,  even  assuming  that  peacekeepers  are  involved  in  hostilities  and  susceptible  to  international  humanitarian  law,  their  accountability  for  violations  is  hardly  a  foregone  conclusion.  This  is  not  the  place  to  examine  in  detail  the  many  obstacles  that  may  stand  in  the  way  of  accountability.  But  for  example  individual  peacekeepers  who  may  have  committed  war  crimes  will  have  immunity  from  host  state  domestic  courts  and  cannot  be  tried  by  the  UN  itself.  Although  the  contributing  state  could  prosecute  them  itself  and  that  possibility  is  increasingly  anticipated  in  troop  contribution  MOUs,  states  are  not  always  committed  to  honoring  that  obligation.  Moreover,  it  is  not  clear  that  the  UN  is  keen  to  follow  up  to  see  that  justice  is  being  done  back  in  the  home  country  (the  UN  may  seek  not  to  scare  contributing  states  off).    To  make  matters  worse,  the  international  community  has  occasionally  gone  out  of  its  way  to  grant  immunity  to  peace  keepers  (as  in  the  case  of  Security  Council  deferrals)  and,  at  any  rate,  the  ICC  may  have  more  urgent  concerns  than  prosecuting  relatively  isolated  crimes  by  peacekeepers.    A  further  risk  of  violations  has  appeared  in  a  context  that  highlights  one  of  the  risks  of  peace  operations’  “state  bias”  for  civilian  protection  and  accountability  purposes.  This  is  the  situation  in  which  a  UN  peace  operation  supports  a  state  to  combat  non-­‐state  actors.  The  best  known  example  of  this  is  MONUSC  supporting  the  Forces  armées  de  la                                                                                                                  98  Ola  Engdahl,  ‘Prosecution  of  Attacks  against  Peacekeepers  in  International  Courts  and  Tribunals’  (2012)  51  Military  Law  and  Law  of  War  Review  249,  271.  99  For  example,  the  Special  Court  for  Sierra  Leone  found  that  UNAMSIL  was  a  «  robust  peacekeeping  »  mission  but  that  its  members  were  still  protected  persons  whose  attack  constituted  a  crime.  There  was,  in  other  words,  a  difference  between  protecting  civilians  and  «  participating  in  hostilities  »,  and  even  the  use  of  force  against  the  RUF  by  UNAMSIL  was  in  self-­‐defence  and  therefore  not  constitutive  of  hostilities.  Prosecutor  v.  Issa  Hassan  Sesay,  Morris  Kallon  and  Augustine  Gbao  (the  RUF  accused),  Trial  Judgment,  2  March  2009,  paras.  1916-­‐1937.  Similarly,  the  ICC  found  that  the  AMIS  in  Sudan,  despite  «  provision  for  civilian  protection  »,  did  not  «  extent  to  a  peace  enforcement  or  disarmament  mandate  ».  ICC,  Abu  Garda  decision  on  the  conformations  of  charges,  paras.  97-­‐114.  

République  démocratique  du  Congo  (FARDC).  The  fear  is  the  UN  will  become  somehow  complicit  in  exactions  committed  by  the  FARDC,  even  as  part  of  a  broader  effort  at  ensuring  security  for  civilians.  Interestingly,  this  support  was  rationalized  on  pragmatic  grounds  as  enhancing  the  likelihood  that  the  FARDC  would  behave  adequately.  Alan  Dos,  the  head  of  MONUC  argued  that:    

…  since  military  offensives  were  inevitable,  MONUC’s  participation  in  FARDC  operations  would  at  least  reduce  their  negative  impact  on  the  population.  He  expected  that  in  exchange  for  UN  logistical  support  the  Congolese  authorities  would  make  significant  efforts  to  improve  the  behaviour  of  their  soldiers.  Also,  MONUC  involvement  would  in  theory  provide  peacekeepers  with  access  to  the  planning  stage  of  operations,  therefore  allowing  them  to  anticipate  associated  risks  for  the  population.100  

 Whether  this  risky  gamble  has  paid  out  is  unclear.  The  record  has  been  very  mixed  to  say  the  least,  with  some  arguing  that  the  militarization  of  Kivu  as  a  result  of  FARDC  deployment  has  created  more  rather  than  less  human  rights  violations.  The  situation  of  being  supposed  to  support  the  very  state  armed  forces  that  are  responsible  for  some  of  the  worst  crimes  committed  against  civilians  is  bound  to  be  an  uncomfortable  one  legally.  Although  MONUC  kept  track  of  violations  by  the  FARDC,  it  was  not  in  a  strong  position  to  voice  concern,  let  alone  use  force  against  Congolese  troops.  MONUC  does  not  seem  to  have  gained  much  control  over  the  actions  of  the  FARDC,  and  may  even  have  provided  them  with  a  renewed  cover.      Things  in  the  Congo  turned  so  sour  that  at  one  point  the  dominant  concern  became  that  the  UN  might  actually  be  complicit  in  violations  committed  by  the  Congolese  armed  forces  that  it  supported.  The  Office  of  Legal  Affairs  wrote  a  memo  to  that  effect  and  a  conditionality  policy  was  elaborated  and  adopted  by  the  Security  Council101  that  aimed  to  enhance  discipline  and  accountability  within  the  FARDC.  The  resulting  “Human  Rights  Due  Diligence  Policy  on  UN  support  to  non-­‐UN  security  forces”  is  an  important  document  that  aims  to  map  the  contours  of  this  difficult  new  area.  A  vetting  procedure  was  created,  notably  for  former  militias  integrated  in  the  Congolese  army.  The  idea  is  that  the  UN  will  simultaneously  direct  its  attention  at  threats  to  civilians  occasioned  by  rebel  groups  (by  fighting  them)  and  by  the  Congolese  state  (by  reforming  it).    Paralleling  R2P  jargon,  one  could  say  that  elements  of  both  second  (state  building)  and  third  (non-­‐state  actor  fighting)  pillar  were  involved.  It  is  open  to  question  whether  the  entire  exercise  serves  more  to  shield  the  UN  from  accusations  by  allowing  it  to  invoke  its  “due  diligence”  or  has  an  actual  effect  with  the  Congolese  armed  forces.  Overall,  the  latter  have  quite  successfully  resisted  any  serious  vetting  of  persons  suspected  of  war  crimes.  The  UN’s  lack  of  leverage  is  shown  by  the  FARDC’s  willingness,  if  they  fail  to  obtain  MONUC  support,  to  go  ahead  alone  with  their  offensives.  Nonetheless,  the  policy  has  not  been  entirely  toothless:  ONUSCO  suspended  support  for  41  out  of  391  FARDC  

                                                                                                               100  After  MONUC,  Should  MONUSCO  Continue  to  Support  Congolese  Military  Campaigns?  -­‐  International  Crisis  Group’  <http://www.crisisgroup.org/en/regions/africa/central-­‐africa/dr-­‐congo/vircoulon-­‐after-­‐monuc-­‐should-­‐monusco-­‐continue-­‐to-­‐support-­‐congolese-­‐military-­‐campaigns.aspx>  accessed  21  December  2014.  101  Security  Council  Resolution  1906  (2009).  

battalions  in  2013,  following  which  the  commanders  of  all  these  battalions  were  removed,  leading  eventually  to  a  reinstatement  of  UN  support.102      

C.  Law  Catches  Up?  Towards  Accountability  for  Civilian  Protection    For  all  these  developments,  the  one  question  that  remains  largely  unanswered  is  the  extent  to  which  peace  operations  have  an  obligation  to  provide  protection  and  might  be  held  accountable  for  a  failure  in  that  respect.103  There  is  every  reason  to  think  that  even  in  an  age  of  robust  peacekeeping,  under-­‐use  of  force  in  cases  where  civilians  are  threatened  remains  at  least  as  significant  as  excesses.  The  general  understanding,  outside  the  specific  case  of  peace  operations,  is  that:    

the  power  to  authorize  the  use  of  force  …  is  not  a  duty  to  do  so,  and  failure  to  authorize  does  not  entail  for  the  Security  Council  …  a  secondary  international  law  obligation  to  make  reparation  fro  breach  of  an  international  obligation.  The  power  to  authorize  the  use  of  force  under  Chapter  VII  of  the  Charter  remains  within  the  political  constrains  of  the  Council.104  

 But  might  peacekeeping  operations  already  deployed  on  the  ground  and,  possibly,  having  created  specific  expectations  of  protection  be  a  special  case  of  Security  Council  obligation?  This  is  obviously  a  vast  issue  and  only  some  of  the  more  salient  questions  will  be  briefly  covered  here.    Attempts  to  engage  the  responsibility  of  the  UN  or  its  agents  for  failures  to  protect  civilians  should  be  seen  as  part  of  a  broader  trend  of  seeking  to  make  international  actors  accountable.  In  the  UN  context,  what  was  initially  framed  as  merely  a  question  of  policy  and  institutional  good  is  already,  and  in  fits  and  starts,  being  framed  as  a  question  of  accountability.  Indeed  a  number  of  notable  cases  or  attempted  litigation  have  started  to  chip  at  what  must  otherwise  appear  as  a  monument  of  unaccountability.  The  process  has  been  a  slow  and  incremental  one,  focused  mostly,  perhaps  unsurprisingly,  on  the  emblematic  cases  of  Bosnia,  particularly  Srebrenica,  and  Rwanda.  Particularly  notable  are  two  judgments  of  Dutch  courts  in  the  case  of  Srebrenica,  one  brought  by  the  relatives  of  three  victims,105  the  other  by  the  organization  of  the  “Mothers  of  Srebrenica.”106  However,  it  is  worth  noting  that  at  least  one  other  case  concerning  the  responsibility  of  the  Belgian  state  and  several  Belgian  officers  in  Rwanda  during  the  

                                                                                                               102  Report  of  the  United  Nations  Joint  Human  Rights  Office  on  Human  Rights  Violations  Perpetrated  by  Soldiers  of  the  Congolese  Armed  Froces  and  Combatants  of  the  M23  in  Goma  and  Sake,  North  Kivu  Province,  and  in  and  around  Minova,  South  Kivu  Province,  from  15  November  to  2  December  2012.2012,  para.  42.  103  Siobhán  Wills,  ‘Military  Interventions  on  Behalf  of  Vulnerable  Populations:  The  Legal  Responsibilities  of  States  and  International  Organizations  Engaged  in  Peace  Support  Operations’  (2004)  9  Journal  of  Conflict  and  Security  Law  387,  406–413.  104  Shraga  (n  52)  268–269.  105  Netherlands  v.  Mustafic´,  No.  12-­‐03329  (Sup.  Ct.  Neth.  Sept.  6,  2013);  Netherlands  v.  Nuhanović,  No.  12-­‐03324  (Sup.  Ct.  Neth.  Sept.  6,  2013).  106  Mothers  of  Srebrenica  Ass’n  v.  Netherlands,  Dist.  Ct.  The  Hague  July  10,  2008,  No.  07-­‐2973;  App.  Ct.  The  Hague  Mar.  30,  2010,  No.  200.022.151/01.  

genocide  is  currently  making  its  way  through  a  Bruxelles  court.107  The  main  practical  problem  that  litigants  have  encountered  has  been  the  immunity  of  the  United  Nations.  The  Dutch  Courts,  in  particular,  affirmed  the  UN’s  immunity,108  a  decision  that  was  not  found  by  the  ECtHR  to  be  incompatible  with  the  Convention.109  Since  the  UN  could  not  be  sued  before  the  Court,  the  risk  was  that  no  one  would  be  held  liable.  The  upholding  of  the  UN’s  immunity,  regardless  of  its  merit,  effectively  deprives  us  of  a  final  judgment  on  whether  the  UN  as  an  international  organization  failed  in  its  obligation  to  prevent  genocide.  However,  it  does  so  only  on  procedural  rather  than  substantive  grounds  so  that  the  question  remains  open,  independently  of  whether  it  can  be  effectively  litigated,  as  to  whether  the  UN  complied  with  its  obligations.    A  central  question  in  this  context,  which  has  both  substantive,  procedural  and  strategic  dimensions,  is  the  extent  to  which  it  is  the  UN  that  is  responsible  for  the  failure  or  troop  contributing  states.  In  a  context  where  the  UN  cannot  be  sued,  it  becomes  particularly  tempting  to  focus  on  troop  contributing  states  as  a  way  to  at  least  move  forward.  Indeed,  the  preferred  and  most  successful  strategy  short  of  being  able  to  sue  the  UN  has  been  to  sue  the  troop  contributing  state  before  its  own  courts.    The  Dutch  cases,  for  example  proceeded  in  relation  to  the  Netherlands  on  the  quite  striking  basis  that  the  Dutch  state  had  effective  control  of  Dutchbat  in  the  days  leading  up  to  Srebrenica,  largely  because  it  communicated  orders  directly  to  it.  Similarly,  in  the  Belgian  case,  the  Bruxelles  Court  found  that  having  decided  to  pull  its  troops  out,  Belgium  had  effectively  reasserted  control  over  them.  The  cases  could  thus  proceed  against  the  Netherlands  and  Belgium,  as  states  which  obviously  did  not  enjoy  immunity  before  their  own  courts  (the  issue  would  have  been  quite  different  had  the  court  been  of  a  third  state).      Notwithstanding  the  inability  to  sue  the  United  Nations,  therefore,  suing  contributing  states  may  at  least  symbolically  and  concretely  reflect  on  what  might  be  the  UN’s  responsibility  (were  it  in  effective  control).  It  should  be  clear  however  that  in  all  but  exceptional  cases,  the  UN  will  have  effective  control  of  troops  under  its  command  and  that  there  are  strong  legal  and  policy  reasons  for  holding  the  UN  accountable110  (although  not  necessarily  exclusively  so).  In  previous  cases  before  the  ECtHR,  contributing  states  had  successfully  argued  that  peace  operations  were  subsidiary  to  the  UN,  and  that  all  acts  were  therefore  attributable  to  it.111  Although  tactically  attributing  responsibility  to  troop  contributing  states  in  cases  where  they  can  be  argued  to  have  strayed  away  from  UN  supervision  serves  its  purpose,  it  is  hardly  a  long  term  solution.  It  may  be  in  fact  that  the  exclusivity  of  responsibility  characteristic  of  such  debates  is  too  rigid  legally  and  not  optimum  from  a  policy  point  of  view,  even  though  the  case  law  on  this  is  only  emerging.112  One  approach,  suggested  by  Tom  Dannenbaum,  would  be  to  

                                                                                                               107  Tribunal  de  première  instance  de  Bruxelles,  71ème  chambre,  Jugement  avant  dire  droit,  R.G.  n°  04/4807/1  et  07/15547/A.  108  Mothers  of  Srebrenica  Ass’n  v.  Netherlands,  Dist.  Ct.  The  Hague  July  10,  2008,  No.  07-­‐2973;  App.  Ct.  The  Hague  Mar.  30,  2010,  No.  200.022.151/01  109  Stichting  Mothers  of  Srebrenica  v.  Netherlands,  App.  No.  65542/12  (Eur.  Ct.  H.R.  June  11,  2013).  110  Aurel  Sari,  ‘UN  Peacekeeping  Operations  and  Article  7  ARIO:  The  Missing  Link’  (2012)  9  International  Organizations  Law  Review  77.  111    112  André  Nollkaemper,  ‘Dual  Attribution  Liability  of  the  Netherlands  for  Conduct  of  Dutchbat  in  Srebrenica’  (2011)  9  Journal  of  International  Criminal  Justice  1143;  Tom  Dannenbaum,  ‘Killings  at  

move  from  a  criterion  of  effective  control  understood  as  “control  most  likely  to  be  effective  in  preventing  the  wrong  in  question,”  a  criterion  that  could  possibly  introduce  a  measure  of  fluidity  in  attribution  to  troop  contributing  states  or  the  UN  itself.113    The  Dutch  cases  are  interesting  in  their  own  right  for  how  they  describe  the  contours  of  the  obligations  of  contributing  states  in  ways  that  might  be  applicable  mutatis  mutandis  to  the  UN’s  own  responsibility.  The  decision  of  the  District  Court  in  the  Mothers  of  Srebrenica  decision  and  of  the  Supreme  Court  in  the  Mustafic/Nuhanović  decision  set  the  most  clear  standard  of  liability  for  “failing  to  protect”  by  a  state  that  has  deployed  a  peace  contingent  in  an  area  where  civilians  are  at  risk.  In  Mustafic/Nuhanović,  the  Dutch  Supreme  Court  found  the  Netherlands  responsible  for  the  deaths  of  four  Bosnian  Muslim  men  because  peacekeepers  had  ordered  them  to  leave  the  compound  during  the  massacre.114  In  the  Mothers  of  Srebenica  case,  the  court  found  that  the  Dutch  state  was  responsible  for  300  deaths  for  the  same  reasons.  In  these  two  cases  as  well  as  the  Belgian  one,115  knowledge,  whether  actual  or  constructive,  was  important  to  establishing  responsibility  and  was  conclusively  established  (in  Srebrenica  the  cases  concern  some  of  the  last  males  to  have  been  expulsed  from  the  camps).    However,  the  Dutch  decisions  are  also  quite  modest.  In  both  the  Mustafic/Nuhanović  and  Mothers  of  Srebrenica  cases  the  Dutch  state  was  responsible  because  the  individuals  in  question  had  been  within  the  Dutch  compound  and  Dutch  forces  were  actively  handed  over  to  the  Bosno-­‐Serbs.  What  was  at  stake,  therefore,  is  not  a  failure  to  protect  as  such,  but  a  specific  act  that  put  people  who  were  under  the  UN’s  direct  protection  in  harm’s  way  at  a  time  when  there  could  no  longer  be  any  doubt  that  they  would  be  put  in  harm’s  way.  This  is  of  course  not  insignificant:  if  UNAMIR  for  example  had  protected  all  of  the  Tutsis  and  moderate  Hutus  that  made  it  to  its  camps  instead  of  abandoning  them  to  their  fate,  a  significant  amount  of  lives  would  have  been  saved.  Nonetheless,  the  decisions  are  perhaps  as  noteworthy  for  what  they  find  the  state  not  to  be  liable  for  than  what  they  find  it  liable  for.      Thinking  about  what  might  lead  to  liability  for  a  failure  to  protect  by  a  peace  operation  is  at  this  stage  still  in  its  infancy.  No  one  is  accusing  the  UN,  for  example,  of  committing  genocide  in  Srebrenica  and  Rwanda,  and  this  dovetails  well  with  the  SG’s  sense  that  only  a  moral  or  political  failure  is  involved.  Traditionally,  the  greatest  reluctance  to  this  sort  of  responsibility  is  that  it  constitutes  a  liability  by  omission  and  that  there  is  normally  no  legal  obligation  to  act  heroically.  Nonetheless,  there  are  exceptions  to  the  notion  that  one  cannot  be  liable  for  omission.  For  example,  domestically,  “duties  of  care”  exist  in  relation  to  parents  when  it  comes  to  their  children.  Internationally,  the  areas  of  positive  duties  opening  the  way  to  responsibility  by  omission  are  broadly  speaking  those  of  

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         Srebrenica,  Effective  Control,  and  the  Power  to  Prevent  Unlawful  Conduct’  (2012)  61  International  and  Comparative  Law  Quarterly  713.  113  Tom  Dannenbaum,  ‘Translating  the  Standard  of  Effective  Control  into  a  System  of  Effective  Accountability:  How  Liability  Should  Be  Apportioned  for  Violations  of  Human  Rights  by  Member  State  Troop  Contingents  Serving  as  United  Nations  Peacekeepers’  (2010)  51  Harv.  Int’l  LJ  113.  114  Netherlands  v.  Mustafic´,  No.  12-­‐03329  (Sup.  Ct.  Neth.  Sept.  6,  2013);  Netherlands  v.  Nuhanović,  No.  12-­‐03324  (Sup.  Ct.  Neth.  Sept.  6,  2013).  115  Id.,  paras.  18  and  46.  («  …  les  défendeurs  ne  pouvaient  ignorer  les  crimes  de  guerre  à  grande  échelle  …  qui  se  commettaient  avant  l’évacuation  de  l’ETO,  et  qui  étaient  immanquablement  appelés  à  s’exercer  sur  les  réfugiés  de  l’ETO  dès  lors  que  la  protection  par  les  soldats  belges  cesserait  »).  

human  rights  (obligation  to  respect  and  protect),  international  humanitarian  law  (obligation  to  ensure  respect)  and  the  law  of  genocide  (obligation  to  prevent).116    Might  any  of  these  duties  be  applicable  to  the  UN?  Certainly  the  idea  that  simply  because  the  UN  is  not  a  party  to  the  Geneva  Conventions  and  other  humanitarian  treaties,  it  has  no  broader  obligation  to  take  responsibility  for  their  enforcement  (as  opposed  to,  at  best,  abide  by  their  terms)  seems  ill-­‐conceived  and  excessively  legalistic.117  The  obligations  to  not  commit  the  proscribed  conduct  in  the  Genocide  Convention,  human  rights  treaties  and  the  Geneva  Conventions  are  in  a  sense  inseparable  from  the  obligation  to  ensure  that  others  (under  certain  conditions)  do  not  either.  There  is  no  shortage  of  arguments  suggesting  that  the  UN  is  bound  by  the  same  obligations  that  states  are  bound  by  and  that  the  UN  routinely  promotes  vis-­‐à-­‐vis  them.118  Otherwise,  it  would  simply  to  be  too  easy  for  states  to  engage  through  an  international  organization  in  activities  that  they  could  not  engage  in  independently  and  thus  defeat  the  object  and  purposes  of  the  conventional  obligations  they  have  undertaken.  Even  in  the  absence  of  a  specific  mandate  to  that  effect,  it  is  generally  accepted  that  peace  operations  would  at  the  very  least  have  an  obligation  to  prevent  atrocities  that  are  unfolding  right  before  them119  flowing  from  the  general  economy  of  the  UN  Charter.120    In  fact,  ironically,  some  of  the  UN’s  own  soul  searching  may  have  provided  the  cue  to  efforts  at  accountability.  If  the  UN  can  candidly  assess  its  faults,  goes  the  reasoning,  then  it  must  be  that  it  recognized  that  it  has  failed  in  a  duty;  if  it  increasingly  commits  itself  to  a  view  of  its  obligations  including  a  strong  component  of  protecting  civilians,  then  it  must  be  that  it  recognizes  that  that  duty  had  certain  beneficiaries;  and  if  it  subsequently  fails  in  fulfilling  that  duty,  then  it  would  be  only  natural  for  such  beneficiaries  to  be  alert  to  the  fact  that  their  rights  have  been  violated  as  a  result.  It  is  in  the  nature  of  “policy”  that  it  is  often  informed  by  norms  yet  may  in  turn  create  norms.  This  is  especially  the  case  concerning  grave  matters  of  international  law,  to  which  one  does  not  commit  lightly.  The  repetition  and  emphasis  on  the  mandate  of  civilian  protection,  influenced  as  it  is  by  the  specter  of  atrocities,  can  only  over  time  create  expectations  that  the  UN  is  serious  about  this  commitment,  even  if  the  UN  itself  is  clear  that  it  is  not  displaying  the  sort  of  opinio  juris  that  could  one  day  be  turned  against  it.  In  addition,  one  might  pay  attention  to  the  degree  to  which  the  UN  has,  in  actual  peace  operations,  “created  obligations  for  itself”  by  granting  peacekeeping  troops  specific  mandates  that  restate  and  reinforce  for  a  particular  place  and  time  what  might  otherwise  be  seen  as  somewhat  inchoate  duties.121  

                                                                                                               116  The  most  comprehensive  and  convincing  treatment  to  date  of  the  obligations  informing  a  general  mandate  to  protect  of  peacekeeping  missions  is  in  Wills  (n  55).  117  Ray  Murphy,  ‘United  Nations  Military  Operations  and  International  Humanitarian  Law:  What  Rules  Apply  to  Peacekeepers?’  (2003)  14  Criminal  Law  Forum  153.  118  F  Mégret  and  F  Hoffmann,  ‘The  UN  as  a  Human  Rights  Violator?  Some  Reflections  on  the  United  Nations  Changing  Human  Rights  Responsibilities’  (2003)  25  Human  Rights  Quarterly  314.  119  Brahimi  report,  supra  note  16,  para.  62  (“peacekeepers  –  troops  or  police  –  who  witness  violence  against  civilians  should  be  presumed  to  be  authorised  to  stop  it,  within  their  means,  in  support  of  basic  United  Nations  principles”).  See  also  Master  list,  supra  note  59.  120  Willmot  and  Sheeran  (n  23).  121  The  claimants  in  the  Mothers  of  Srebrenica  case  duly  noted  that  Dutchbat  had  specifically  been  asked  to  take  blocking  positions  to  prevent  the  Bosnian  Serves  from  advancing  on  Srebrenica.  In  the  Belgian  case,  the  claimants  noted  that  the  officers  were  asked  to  “contribute  to  the  security  of  Kigali.”  On  the  

 Perhaps  even  more  crucially,  a  common  exception  in  domestic  legal  systems  to  the  idea  that  omissions  do  not  render  liable  is  when  an  intervener  actually  makes  representation  to  someone  in  need  that  they  will  help,  including  representations  on  which  such  victim  relies.  One  might  therefore  pay  attention  to  the  extent  to  which  representations  were  made  to  civilians  that  they  would  be  protected,  including  in  ways  that  might  have  led  them  to  disarm,  thus  potentially  further  binding  the  UN.122  The  very  presence  of  Dutch  forces  in  Srebrenica  or  Belgian  forces  in  Kigali  already  implied  a  commitment  to  at  least  the  objectives  of  their  respective  missions,  if  not  a  whole  lot  more.  Such  a  unilateral  commitment,  backed  of  course  by  the  UN’s  own  statutory  obligations,  must  count  for  something,  especially  if  it  is  relied  upon  by  those  to  whom  it  is  made  (and  even  though  its  status  under  international  law  is  a  little  fuzzy).  The  UN  itself  recognized  as  much  when,  in  its  report  on  Rwanda,  it  highlighted  as  relevant  the  “perception  and  the  expectation  of  protection  created  by  [the  PKO’s]  very  presence.”123  This  is  what  the  Mothers  of  Srebrenica  argued  before  the  ECtHR  when  they  suggested  that  the  UN  had  “entered  into  an  agreement  with  the  inhabitants  of  the  Srebrenica  enclave  (including  the  applicants)  to  protect  them  inside  the  Srebrenica  ‘safe  area’  in  exchange  for  the  disarmament  of  the  ARBH  [Army  of  the  Republic  of  Bosnia  and  Herzegovina]  forces  present.”  If  this  agreement  is  acted  upon,  or  even  if  there  is  an  objectively  created  belief  that  the  UN/troop  contributing  states  will  rise  to  their  responsibilities,  then  that  creates  certain  expectations  that  are  legally  significant.      Indeed,  it  is  important  to  note  that  UNPROFOR  and  UNAMIR  were  evidently  not  “good  Samaritans”  in  Bosnia  and  Rwanda  respectively,  which  could  (but  were  under  no  obligation  to)  have  taken  it  upon  themselves  to  voluntarily  protect  and  rescue  civilians.  Rather,  their  presence  in  the  theatre  of  atrocities  was  over-­‐determined  and  saturated  by  their  mandates  and  a  variety  of  obligations.  This  is  why  the  application  by  the  Dutch  courts  of  the  case  law  of  international  human  rights  bodies  and  the  focus  on  effective  territorial  control  (which  the  claimants  did  not  particularly  challenge)  is  confusing,  apart  from  the  fact  that  other  norms  than  human  rights  were  implicated.  Under  international  human  rights  law,  states  are  liable  for  human  rights  violations  when  they  have  jurisdiction  which  may  include,  inter  alia,  control  of  certain  territory.  International  human  rights  law  is  basically  neutral  as  to  where  and  when  states  should  exercise  jurisdiction:  it  merely  follows  that  effectivity.  Under  that  simple  test,  the  Dutchbat  did  have  control  of  its  compound  (and  therefore  was  liable  for  failing  to  protect  civilians  within  it)  but  did  not  have  “control”  of  areas  beyond  it  (and  therefore  was  not  liable).    

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                         distinction  between  peacekeepers’  general  responsibility  to  protect  and  “  mission  responsibility  to  protect”  in  some  operational  documents,  see  Wills  (n  55)  261.  122  Although  the  literature  on  the  moral  hazards  of  international  intervention  has  focused  on  the  danger  that  rebel  groups  will  arm  expecting  a  humanitarian  intervention  to  save  them  (AJ  Kuperman,  ‘The  Moral  Hazard  of  Humanitarian  Intervention:  Lessons  from  the  Balkans’  (2008)  52  International  Studies  Quarterly  49;  Alan  J  Kuperman,  ‘Suicidal  Rebellions  and  the  Moral  Hazard  of  Humanitarian  Intervention’  (2005)  4  Ethnopolitics  149.),  the  danger  that  non-­‐state  actors  will  disarm  in  the  expectation  that  they  will  be  protected  seems  equally  if  not  more  real.  123  Rwanda  Report,  supra  note  10.  See  also  Srebrenica  Report,  supra  note  9  (“When  the  international  community  makes  a  solemn  promise  to  safeguard  and  protect  innocent  civilians  from  massacre  then  it  must  be  willing  to  back  up  its  promise  with  the  necessary  means.  Otherwise  it  is  surely  better  not  to  raise  hopes  and  expectations  in  the  first  place,  and  not  to  impede  whatever  capability  they  may  be  able  to  muster  in  their  own  defence”).  

But  this  fails  to  problematize  why  UNPROFOR  did  not  have  control  of  the  entire  safe  area  that  the  Security  Council  had  created  and  mandated  it  to  protect.  It  misses  the  point  that  the  Dutch  state  was  not  simply  a  sovereign  that  “happened”  to  possibly  exercise  jurisdiction  in  relation  to  some  areas  of  Srebrenica;  rather,  it  was  obliged  by  UN  resolutions  to  assert  control  of  the  safe  area  in  order  to  protect  civilians.  Here  the  normative  power  to  protect  trumps  the  effective  power  to  protect,  or  at  least  frames  it  decisively.  It  is  its  failure  to  protect  the  safe-­‐area  that  is  the  source  of  all  crimes  that  were  committed  in  Srebrenica.  The  failures  that  should  be  evaluated  are  therefore,  to  use  the  Srebrenica  example,  not  just  those  occurring  within  the  compound  but  also  within  the  entire  theoretical  safe  area.  Presumably  the  further  one  gets  from  the  zone  of  effective  control  the  more  difficult  it  will  be  to  prove  a  failure  to  act,  but  there  is  in  principle  no  reason  why  one  should  not  be  liable  for,  essentially,  a  failure  to  exercise  the  sort  of  control  one  was  tasked  with  exercising.    This  of  course  does  not  mean  that  the  duty  to  protect  civilians  is  absolute,  but  it  surely  remains  a  relatively  onerous  one.  In  Mustafic/Nuhanović  the  Dutch  Supreme  Court  quoted  with  approval  the  ICJ  general  standard  to  evaluate  states’  (and,  one  may  think,  mutatis  mutandis,  international  organizations’)  performance  in  the  prevention  of  genocide  “(…)  it  is  clear  that  the  obligation  in  question  is  one  of  conduct  and  not  one  of  result,  in  the  sense  that  a  State  cannot  be  under  an  obligation  to  succeed,  whatever  the  circumstances,  in  preventing  the  commission  of  genocide.”124  It  seems  that  such  is  the  standard  by  which  UN  peace  operations  should  be  evaluated  too.  Of  course,  the  more  onerous  and  dangerous  the  action  that  the  UN  would  have  had  to  take  (e.g.:  averting  a  genocide  v.  protecting  a  few  refugees  within  a  compound),  the  least  demanding  international  law  will  be  and  the  more  tolerance  there  will  be  for  failure.  At  the  same  time,  the  UN’s  performance  should  henceforth  be  measured  against  a  background  in  which  the  value  of  civilian  lives  has  been  affirmed,  and  where  the  preservation  of  the  mission  and  the  life  of  peacekeepers  can  no  longer  be  the  sole  consideration.    The  special  position  of  a  state  in  relation  to  an  unfolding  international  crime  matters.  As  the  ICJ  put  it,  clearly  with  Serbia-­‐Montenegro  in  mind  but  in  ways  that  have  resonance  for  the  UN  and  troop  contributing  states:    

Various  parameters  operate  when  assessing  whether  a  State  has  duly  discharged  the  obligation  concerned.  The  first,  which  varies  greatly  from  one  State  to  another,  is  clearly  the  capacity  to  influence  effectively  the  action  of  persons  likely  to  commit,  or  already  committing,  genocide.  This  capacity  itself  depends,  among  other  things,  on  the  geographical  distance  of  the  State  concerned  from  the  scene  of  the  events,  and  on  the  strength  of  the  political  links,  as  well  as  links  of  all  other  kinds,  between  the  authorities  of  that  State  and  the  main  actors  in  the  events.125  

 The  Netherlands  in  Srebrenica  and  the  Belgians  in  Rwanda  (and  by  extension  the  UN)  were  not  in  the  same  position  as,  say,  the  Seychelles.  Not  only  did  they  already  have  a  presence  on  the  ground,  but  that  presence  was  a  very  specific,  political  and  military  one.  UNPROFOR  had  links  with  the  Bosno-­‐Serbs  and  was  in  the  best  position,  as  an  emanation  of  the  international  community  and  its  interests  in  Bosnia,  to  make  good  on  

                                                                                                               124  Netherlands  v.  Mustafic,  supra  note  114.  125  ICJ,  application  of  the  Genocide  Convention,  para.  430.  

its  various  promises  to  civilians.  The  special  nature  of  the  military,  as  an  institution  geared  towards  risk  taking  must  be  taken  into  account.  In  this  context,  factors  like  the  UN  refusal  to  send  in  air  support  effectively  sealed  the  fate  of  Srebrenica,  and  the  decision  to  not  reinforce  UNAMIR  are  widely  acknowledged  as  having  had  tragic  consequences.  Pushing  back  the  Serbs  to  prevent  them  from  entering  the  Srebrenica  safe  area  may  well  have  endangered  Dutch  soldiers’  lives.  Nonetheless,  whilst  it  would  be  unreasonable  to  ask  militaries  to  sacrifice  themselves  for  a  lost  cause,  it  is  also  understood  that  force  losses,  especially  in  the  presence  of  the  huge  countervailing  risk  of  losing  thousands  of  civilian  lives,  are  something  that  may  reasonably  be  expected.    

Conclusion    Norms  in  international  society  often  emerge  at  the  intersection  of  distinct  regimes  that  interact  with  each  other  in  complex  ways.  The  evolution  of  the  regime  of  peace  operations,  as  this  article  has  sought  to  argue,  is  an  interesting  case  in  point.  Peace  operations  are  driven  by  their  own  logic,  honed  over  decades  of  UN  operational  practice.  Yet  confronted  with  some  of  their  limitations,  they  have  evolved  dynamically  whilst  clinging  to  what  makes  them  specific  and  worthwhile.  They  have  done  so  in  an  overall  normative  context  that  has  facilitated  the  intervention  of  other  normative  logics  whose  priorities  have  affected  them.  For  example  R2P  and  the  ICC  further  entrench  an  anti-­‐atrocity  norm  in  international  society  that  significantly  raises  expectations  in  terms  of  what  peace  operations  are  expected  to  do,  even  though  peacekeeping  arrived  independently  at  the  same  conclusion.  In  the  process,  regimes  may  find  unexpected  common  ground.  For  example,  robust  peacekeeping,  the  ICC  and  R2P  may  tend  to  reinforce  each  other’s  tendency  to  adopt  an  anti-­‐non-­‐state  actor  bias,  even  as  they  were  imagined  as  tools  to  fight  sovereign  excesses.    Yet  regimes  may  also  be  in  tension  with  each  other  especially,  as  it  happens,  when  it  comes  to  the  question  of  legalization.  The  emerging  consensus  seems  to  be  that  a  peace  operation  should  at  least  not  put  civilians  in  a  position  where  they  are  worse  off  than  had  it  not  existed,  and  that  this  requires  both  a  specific  mandate  and  a  specific  capability.126  If  and  when  they  use  force,  peacekeepers  should  do  so  in  a  way  that  conforms  with  international  law.  At  the  same  time,  the  notion  that  failures  of  protection  might  result  in  the  UN  being  held  liable  is  seen  as  much  more  problematic.  It  is  one  thing  to  say  that  genocide  or  attacks  on  civilians  should  categorically  not  be  committed;  it  is  quite  another  to  say  that  peace  operations  have  a  meaningful  legal  obligation  to  prevent  them.    The  evolution  towards  robust  peacekeeping  thus  emerges  as  a  complex  and  contradictory  field.  On  the  one  hand,  what  is  striking  is  in  some  ways  how  relatively  little  has  changed  since  the  early  1990s  when  these  issues  started  being  discussed  regularly,  as  the  UN  seeks  to  reconcile  peace  keeping  and  intervention,  neutrality  and  hostility  to  international  crimes,  minimum  use  of  force  and  the  need  to  stop  atrocities.                                                                                                                  126  In  this  context  the  suggestion  that  the  mere  presence  of  peace  operations,  even  short  of  any  particular  failure,  may  spur  violence  against  civilians  by  parties  is  particularly  damning.  Lisa  Hultman,  ‘Keeping  Peace  or  Spurring  Violence?  Unintended  Effects  of  Peace  Operations  on  Violence  against  Civilians’  (2010)  12  Civil  Wars  29.  

The  net  effect  of  R2P  and  to  a  lesser  degree  of  international  criminal  justice  on  peace  operations  might  be  said  to  be  the  radicalization  of  the  fundamental  underlying  contradictions  at  their  heart  between  energetically  intervening  to  protect  populations  and  state  consent.  The  challenge  of  “robust  peacekeeping,”  moreover,  is  characterized  by  a  deep  tension  between  a  desire  for  normalization  and  ad  hocism.  “Robust  peacekeeping”  as  an  institutional  concept  is  an  attempt  to  streamline  and  order  what  the  UN’s  response  should  be  in  a  particular  type  of  dramatic  circumstances.  Yet  the  response  of  the  UN  to  such  circumstances  often  seems  to  vary  from  one  theatre  to  the  other,  giving  many  meanings  to  the  notion.  Moreover,  the  UN  itself  it  keen  to  stress  the  exceptional,  non-­‐precedent  creating  nature  of  some  of  its  boldest  institutional  innovations  (e.g.:  the  intervention  brigade  in  RDC).  Considerable  political  and  operational  obstacles  to  civilian  protection  remain,  including  non-­‐negligible  fears  about  the  sustainability  of  missions  that  simultaneously  seek  to  build  peace  and  to  confront  violators  of  the  humanitarian  order.      On  the  other  hand,  one  should  not  underestimate  the  extent  to  which  peace  operations  are  actually  changing  as  a  result  of  this  pressure  of  two  decades  to  somehow  prioritize,  and  even  absolutize  the  protection  of  civilians  and  the  avoidance  of  atrocities.  Robust  peacekeeping  is  a  product  of  its  times,  born  from  the  failures  of  Srebrenica  and  Rwanda,  in  a  context  where  the  moral  pressure  has  never  been  stronger  for  the  UN  to  rise  to  its  post-­‐Second  World  War  promise  that  genocide  would  “never  again”  occur.    It  remains  true  that  paradigmatically  few  things  would  have  the  potential  to  change  the  nature  of  peace  operations  more  fundamentally  than  a  move  from  pursuing  peace  above  all  to  putting  protection  of  civilians  at  the  pinnacle  of  the  UN’s  priorities.  Although  the  regime  of  accountability  of  peace  operations  when  it  comes  to  civilian  protection  is  still  in  its  infancy,  some  cases  already  point  to  ways  of  circumventing  UN  immunity  (by  suing  troop  contributing  states)  that  shed  light  on  what  might  be  the  liability  of  peace  operations.  And,  as  a  sign  of  how  fast  things  may  be  changing,  the  concern  has  already  shifted  in  some  cases  from  UN  inaction  to,  as  in  the  RDC,  cases  of  UN  support  for  states’  efforts  at  combatting  rebel  groups  that  end  up  producing  their  own  violence  against  civilians.    Ultimately,  it  is  difficult  to  avoid  the  feeling  of  a  metamorphosis  that  is  never  entirely  consumed  and  remains  quite  opportunistically  tied  to  circumstances  (R2P  and  ICC  prosecutorial  policy  encounter  similar  problems  when  they  try  to  systematize  what  they  do  in  the  light  of  ever  changing  conditions).    The  change  from  peace  operations  to  civilian  protection  operations,  from  impartiality  to  (partial)  partiality,  from  consensual  presence  to  non-­‐consensual  presence  is  one  that  remains  only  partly  achieved,  except  perhaps  in  a  way  that  allows  the  UN  to  play  on  different  registers  and  adapt  its  language  to  a  variety  of  evolving  situations.  At  times,  given  how  saturated  mandates  are  with  different  goals,  it  will  be  unclear  whether  civilian,  force  or  mandate  protection  are  the  driving  force  behind  a  particular  use  of  force.127  Not  all  peace  operations  even  have  a  civilian  protection  mandate,  and  not  all  those  that  have  such  a  mandate  have  used  it  dynamically,  let  alone  successfully.  The  “commitment  gap”  between  the  sort  of  resolutions  that  states  are  willing  to  vote  in  favor  and  their  actual  readiness  to  

                                                                                                               127  Alex  J  Bellamy  and  Paul  D  Williams,  ‘Local  Politics  and  International  Partnerships:  The  UN  Operation  in  Côte  d’Ivoire  (UNOCI)’  (2012)  16  Journal  of  International  Peacekeeping  252.  

contribute  troops  for  the  purposes  of  robust  peacekeeping  often  remains  stark.128  .  In  the  end,  the  constant  mix  of  adherence  to  high  principles  and  pragmatism,  affirmation  of  foundational  principles  of  peace  operations  combined  with  their  complete  reinvention  may  be  a  manifestation  of  the  “organized  hypocrisy”  that  Michael  Lipson  has  argued  may  actually  allow  the  UN  to  get  the  job  done  in  a  context  of  contradictory  pressures.129    This  hypocrisy,  however,  is  not  so  much  a  moral  failure  than  it  is  traceable  to  persistent  doubts  about  the  very  notion  of  robust  peacekeeping.  Some  reservations  manifest  an  attachment  to  peacekeeping  as  a  tried  and  trusted  tool  where  its  robust  variant  threatens  to  take  the  UN  into  unchartered  territory.  For  example,  on  the  occasion  of  the  creation  of  MONUSCO’s  intervention  brigade,  the  representative  of  Guatemala  pointed  out  that  it  would  compromise  the  vision  of  MONUSCO  as  an  “honest  broker”  capable  of  offering  its  good  offices  to  resolve  disputes.  The  rise  of  robust  peacekeeping  may  also  activate  some  more  fundamental  political  concerns  about  interference  that  are  more  reminiscent  of  both  the  R2P  and  ICC  debates  (and  that  have  been  rekindled,  typically,  in  Libya  and  Mali),  in  a  context  where  peace  operations  act  increasingly  as  a  form  of  “pre-­‐deployed”  humanitarian  intervention.130  The  taste  for  “robust  peacekeeping”  is  not  one  that  is  evenly  shared  by  all  states  especially  in  a  context  where  it  seems  to  effectively  flirt  with  “regime  change,”  albeit  presented  as  preserving  democratic  achievements.131  With  efforts  at  protecting  civilians  in  Ivory  Coast  (POC)  being  seen  by  countries  such  as  China,  Brazil,  Russia  and  India  as  a  Trojan  horse  for  international  intervention  reminiscent  of  fears  about  R2P132  and  as  subtly  destabilizing  the  Charter  economy,  it  was  only  likely  that  a  significant  pushback  would  manifest  itself.  Indeed,  it  may  be  that  “robust  peacekeeping,”  even  as  some  of  its  stakes  are  dramatized  by  the  ubiquity  of  R2P  language,  will  suffer  from  its  association  with  the  political  overtones  of  its  broader  cousin  and  some  of  the  concerns  that  raises  (notably  post-­‐Libya).  Similarly,  the  fact  that  peace  operations  are  increasingly  under  pressure  to  act  as  enforcement  arms  for  the  ICC  may  create  tensions  in  situations  where  such  operations  are  composed  and  act  on  the  territory  of  both  states  and  non-­‐state  parties.      Still,  compared  to  R2P  and  the  ICC,  robust  peacekeeping  may  not  attract  quite  the  same  political  fire,  and  this  may  explain  why  its  promoters  do  not  particularly  seek  to  present  

                                                                                                               128  Christine  Gray,  ‘Peacekeeping  After  the  Brahimi  Report:  Is  There  a  Crisis  of  Credibility  for  the  UN?’  (2001)  6  Journal  of  Conflict  and  Security  Law  267.  129  Michael  Lipson,  ‘Peacekeeping:  Organized  Hypocrisy?’  (2007)  13  European  Journal  of  International  Relations  5,  notably  20–21.  130  Andrew  Cottey,  ‘Beyond  Humanitarian  Intervention:  The  New  Politics  of  Peacekeeping  and  Intervention’  (2008)  14  Contemporary  Politics  429;  T  Modibo  Ocran,  ‘Doctrine  of  Humanitarian  Intervention  in  Light  of  Robust  Peacekeeping,  The’  (2002)  25  Boston  College  International  and  Comparative  Law  Review  5.    131  Andreas  Mehler,  ‘From  “Protecting  Civilians”  to  “For  the  Sake  of  Democracy”  (and  Back  Again):  Justifying  Intervention  in  Côte  d’Ivoire’  (2012)  5  African  Security  199.  132  The  reaction  of  India  to  the  reinforcement  of  UNOCI’s  mandate  to  protect  civilians  is  characteristic.  See  S/PV.6508,  30  March  2011  (“We  want  to  put  on  record  that  United  Nations  peacekeepers  should  draw  their  mandate  from  the  relevant  resolutions  of  the  Security  Council.  They  cannot  be  made  instruments  of  regime  change.  Accordingly,  the  United  Nations  Operation  in  Côte  d’Ivoire  (UNOCI)  should  not  become  a  party  to  the  Ivorian  political  stalemate.  UNOCI  should  also  not  get  involved  in  a  civil  war,  but  carry  out  its  mandate  with  impartiality  and  while  ensuring  the  safety  and  security  of  peace-­‐keepers  and  civilians”).  

it  as  linked  to  either.133  For  one  thing,  it  still  most  of  the  time  occurs  within  a  horizon  of  consent  of  the  state  in  which  the  peace  operation  is  deployed,  if  not  of  various  non-­‐state  actors  operating  on  its  territory.  Whilst  states  from  the  Global  South  have  been  particularly  wary  of  R2P  (increasingly  working  hand  in  hand  with  the  ICC)  to  the  extent  it  might  justify  military  intervention,  it  should  be  said  that  they  have  also  been  quite  unforgiving  of  some  peace  operations’  failure  to  adopt  more  robust  features  when  needed,  abandoning  civilians  to  their  fate  (the  attitude  of  Rwanda  post-­‐genocide  comes  to  mind).  Maybe  there  is  something  that  is  seen  as  particularly  shameful  about  being  already  in  a  theatre  and  failing  to  protect  civilians,  as  opposed  to  not  having  been  there  and  not  decided  to  intervene.  Robust  peacekeeping  may  overall  be  more  acceptable  internationally  than  R2P,  a  sort  of  intermediary  step  that  builds  on  the  opportunity  provided  by  existing  presences  to  use  force  within  a  still  fundamentally  non-­‐interventionist  paradigm.    In  fact,  if  what  I  have  argued  is  true,  namely  that  robust  peacekeeping  –  uncontradicted  in  this  by  the  general  thrust  of  either  international  criminal  justice  or  R2P  –  is  generally  (and  perhaps  against  all  appearances)  pro-­‐state,  then  states  that  are  wary  of  robust  peacekeeping  should  probably  pay  attention  to  its  actual  practices  rather  than  grand  statements  of  intention.  Robust  peacekeeping,  with  the  possible  exception  of  Ivory  Coast,  has  hardly  proved  a  Trojan  horse  for  international  intervention  against  states.  Moreover,  on  the  protection  of  civilians  side,  at  least  robust  peacekeeping  seems  easier  to  pin  down  where  R2P  often  appears  to  be  a  responsibility  be  shared  by  all,  and  therefore  to  be  no  one’s  in  particular.  By  contrast,  peace  operations’  mix  of  pre-­‐existing  responsibilities  and  on-­‐site  deployment  in  the  midst  of  tragic  events  arguably  create  just  the  right  degree  of  friction  for  some  serious  questioning  about  responsibilities  to  occur.    Persistent  questions,  then,  are  bound  to  keep  being  raised  in  what  has  been  described  as  the  “fog  of  peacekeeping.”134  These  are  of  a  moral,  operational  and  legal  character.  Is  protecting  civilians  one  of  the  conditions  of  international  peace  and  security  or  the  condition?  Might  it  in  certain  circumstances  be  an  obstacle?  What  if  robust  peacekeeping  became  a  pale  substitute  for  either  R2P  or  the  hard  political  work  of  brokering  peace  agreements,  a  cosmetic  additive,  in  the  same  way  perhaps  that  international  criminal  tribunals  have  at  times  been  criticized  as  a  fig  leaf  for  UN  inaction?    Is  there  not  a  risk  that  civilian  protection  might  detract  from  the  more  political  goal  of  securing  peace,  in  a  context  where  it  may  end  up  delivering  neither?  What  if  the  UN  finds  that  it  has  to  combat,  on  the  grounds  that  they  harass  civilians,  the  very  forces  it  would  need  to  sit  at  a  table  with  to  bring  about  a  settlement?  When,  how  and  by  who  should  the  trade  offs  be  identified?  Is  there  not  a  danger  that  the  UN  will  eventually  desist  from  even  engaging  in  certain  peace  operations  now  that  it  has  itself  set  the  bar  so  high?  Or  that  peace  operations’  efforts  in  favor  of  civilian  protection  will  create  a  moral  hazard,  effectively  encouraging  rebel  groups  to  build  into  their  agenda  an  expectation  that  the  UN  will  protect  them?  What  if  UN  protection  of  civilians  ends  up  running  counter  to  efforts  at  rebuilding  the  state’s  authority  around  a  basic  ability  to  protect  its  population,  for  example  by  displacing  resources  that  might  otherwise  have  been  dedicated  to  security  sector  reform  or  DDR?  What  if  protection  is  exploited  by  a  state  that  is  only  too  happy  to                                                                                                                  133  On  the  politics  of  linkage  between  the  ICC  and  R2P  in  particular,  and  how  it  may  be  wiser  to  keep  the  two  apart,  see  Schiff  (n  1).  134  Daniel  S  Blocq,  ‘The  Fog  of  UN  Peacekeeping:  Ethical  Issues  Regarding  the  Use  of  Force  to  Protect  Civilians  in  UN  Operations’  (2006)  5  Journal  of  Military  Ethics  201.  

draw  on  UN  resources  to  do  its  order  maintenance  work  for  it?  Or  by  a  state  that  uses  the  existence  of  a  rebel  threat  and  the  indebtedness  of  the  peacekeeping  concept  to  its  consent  to  hold  a  peace  operation  hostage  to  its  own  wrong  doing?  What  if  troop  contributing  states  or  the  UN  itself  become  more  reluctant  to  engage  in  peacekeeping  out  of  fear  that  they  will  be  sued  for  their  failures  to  protect  civilians?135    These  questions  have  no  easy  answer,  but  they  will  require  more  significant  research  in  years  to  come,  if  civilian  protection  is  not  to  become,  instead  of  peace  operations’  new  raison  d’être,  the  hole  that  engulfs  them.                                

                                                                                                               135  This  particular  fear  is  regularly  invoked  by  the  United  Nations.  For  example,  the  official  spokesman  for  the  UN  Secretary-­‐General,  Fred  Eckard,  was  very  clear  in  his  reaction  to  a  threatened  law  suit  for  failure  to  protect  in  Rwanda  "…  I  can  say  that  if  we  allowed  our  peacekeepers  to  be  brought  to  courts  and  tried  over  matters  like  this,  that  would  be  the  end  of  peacekeeping."  Mark  Riley  and  Pamela  Bone,  ‘UN  Denies  Culpability  for  Genocide’  The  Age  (Victoria,  1  December  2000).