The populist cat-dog: applying the concept of populism to contemporary European party systems

34

Transcript of The populist cat-dog: applying the concept of populism to contemporary European party systems

Loughborough UniversityInstitutional Repository

The populist cat-dog:applying the concept of

populism to contemporaryEuropean party systems

This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repositoryby the/an author.

Citation: VAN KESSEL, S., 2014. The populist cat-dog: applying the conceptof populism to contemporary European party systems. Journal of PoliticalIdeologies, 19 (1), pp.99-118

Additional Information:

• This is an Accepted Manuscript of an article published in Jour-nal of Political Ideologies on 13 February 2014, available online:http://www.tandfonline.com/10.1080/13569317.2013.869457

Metadata Record: https://dspace.lboro.ac.uk/2134/16890

Version: Accepted for publication

Publisher: c© Taylor & Francis

Rights: This work is made available according to the conditions of the CreativeCommons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0) licence. Full details of this licence are available at: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/

Please cite the published version.

1

The populist cat-dog. Applying the concept of populism to contemporary

European party systems.

Stijn van Kessel (Loughborough University)

Accepted for publication on 18 May 2013

Final version in: Journal of Political Ideologies, 19 (1), 2014, pp. 99–118.

Abstract

Populism is a frequently used yet problematic concept; the term is often ill-defined and

randomly applied. While these problems have been widely acknowledged, this paper

argues that there are still issues with the way populism tends to be used, even if a

sound definition is provided. This relates to the fact that it is often not clear whether

populism is used to refer to an ideological feature of an exclusive category of political

parties or whether populism is seen as a type of discourse which can be expressed by

any political actor. In order to illustrate the difficulties with regard to the application of

the term populism, several ‘hard’ cases of populism across Europe are discussed. The

paper argues that in order to stimulate a more accurate use of the term, observers

should be explicit not only about the meaning of populism, but also about the form in

which it manifest itself.

Key Words: Populism, Party Families, Concept Formation, Europe.

2

The populist cat-dog. Applying the concept of populism to contemporary

European party systems.

Introduction

Populism is a concept which has frequently emerged in recent scholarly contributions and

which has also attracted much attention outside of academia. Although the term has

been used extensively, the concept is problematic due to the unsystematic (pejorative)

use and the fact that populism is often ill defined.1 The term is regularly used to denote

anti-incumbent rhetoric or to describe politicians who pander to public opinion, but

definitional precision tends to be lacking. Yet, as this paper will show, also when a clear

definition is provided, there are problems related to the way the concept is applied in

order to describe political phenomena. Since the term has been used so widely, it is

necessary to stimulate a more accurate use of the concept. This paper takes the view

that this is even more important since (the surge of) populism can be seen as an

indicator for the legitimacy of a political regime and the state of representative

democracy in general.2 The surge of populism is a sign that a democratically elected

regime is seen to be unresponsive to the demands of a certain segment of the

population.

Even though the term populism is used randomly, and even though the concept

can certainly be considered to be an ‘essentially contested’ concept,3 the scholarly

debate about the characteristics of the concept is well developed. It is even possible to

notice something of a consensus on some of the core features of populism within the

political science literature,4 at least among those who aim to define the concept

carefully. Unfortunately, even if a clear definition is provided, conceptual problems arise

when the concept of populism is applied to describe the characteristics of political actors,

and political parties in particular. It is these problems related to the application of

populism which are central to this paper. When the term is used, it is often not clear, or

3

made explicit, whether a reference is made to a specific delineated subset of political

parties or whether populism is seen as a certain discourse, which can essentially be

voiced by any political actor. Thus, besides the unsystematic use of populism, or the

absence of a clear definition, the lack of uniformity in the application of the term is an

important reason as to why the concept of populism resembles the concept of, what

Giovanni Sartori calls, a cat-dog.5 The term is used to describe political actors that in fact

cannot be placed in a single category.

Starting out from a minimal definition of populism, this paper first aims to point

out the difficulties of using populism in a meaningful way in order to discriminate

between political actors. Specifically, using the words of Allan Sikk, the paper shows that

it is hard to distinguish between populism as a ‘classifier’, which refers to a

circumscribed universe of populist actors, and populism as a ‘descriptor’, which denotes

(more fleeting) expressions of populist discourse in political systems.6 Secondly, the

paper seeks to investigate whether the cat-dog problem can be tackled by choosing the

most appropriate strategy of concept formation and following this strategy consistently.

In order to illustrate the problems with regard to the application of populism, this

paper touches on various alleged instances of populism throughout Europe, with a

particular focus on political parties. The European continent is home to both long-

established democracies in which we can point out a, more or less uncontested, set of

populist parties as well as relatively new democracies (in post-communist countries),

where applying the concept in a useful way seems less straightforward. Classification

issues, however, are by no means limited to these latter countries and the main focus in

this paper will be on several ‘hard’ cases of populism across the continent; instances

which raise doubt about the discriminating power of populism.7 Further, it is particularly

in the European literature where progress towards definitional consensus has been

realised with regard to the concept of populism.8 This paper shows that, despite

consensus on key constituent components of populism, the application of the concept

can still be problematic.

4

The following section first discusses the varying ways in which the concept of

populism is applied to political systems in the existing literature. The subsequent section

discusses which strategy of concept formation seems most appropriate when the aim is

to apply populism in a useful and accurate manner. It is argued that the ‘classic model’

of concept formation is the preferable option.9 Yet, by means of several hard cases of

populism, the succeeding section shows that using a clear minimal definition of populism

does not necessarily guarantee a meaningful and accurate application of the concept.

The discussion of these cases is centred on two main issues. A first key issue is that

populist discourse can be used to various degrees and that it is unclear when a political

movement party can be classified as a ‘full’ instance of populism. The second, often

related, difficulty is that populist discourse can be added and removed from the

repertoire of political actors quite easily, so that a potential universe of populist parties

can become rather changeable throughout time. The paper argues that both these issues

are particularly apparent in post-communist democracies in Central and Eastern Europe.

The final part of the paper argues that it is useful to conceive of a ladder of abstraction

of populist manifestations, which sheds light on the conceptual problems discussed in

this paper.10 On the basis of this, several recommendations for applying the concept of

populism are presented.

The concept of populism and its application

In the past decades various definitions or descriptions of populism have been provided in

which similar features recur.11 While the ground-breaking edited volume of Ghiţa Ionescu

and Ernest Gellner was still marked by the absence of an agreed definition of populism,

various definitions have been provided in recent years which showed important

similarities.12 Thus, many political science scholars who specialise on the topic of

populism tend to refer to a similar set of core components when they use the concept.

5

These are outlined particularly clearly by Ben Stanley, who identified the following four,

distinct but interrelated, features:

The existence of two homogeneous units of analysis: ‘the people’ and ‘the elite’.

The antagonistic relationship between the people and the elite.

The idea of popular sovereignty.

The positive valorisation of ‘the people’ and denigration of ‘the elite’.13

It has to be noted that these, or similar, components appear in the contributions

which focus on the ideational characteristics of populism. Other authors have placed

more emphasis on the organisational features of populism and personalistic or

‘charismatic’ leadership in particular.14 Here, however, populism is essentially considered

to be a set of ideas. Following Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, populism might have an

‘elective affinity with certain organizational aspects’ such as charismatic leadership and

unmediated representation, but these should not be seen as defining properties of

populism.15 Populism can be expressed in different organisational shapes and forms.16

The four core components identified by Stanley provide the basis for the

discussion on the way the concept is applied in the academic literature. Even if scholars

would agree on a single definition, it remains unclear (or disputed) how populism

manifests itself in political systems. As outlined in the introduction, it is debated whether

populism can be seen as core component of a circumscribed ‘universe’ of political actors

or whether it merely constitutes a type of discourse which can be applied by any political

actor.

Recent contributions appear to suggest that populism is more than an easily

disposable rhetoric, in describing populism as an ideology, albeit a ‘thin’ or ‘thin-centred’

one.17 Following Michael Freeden, a thin-centred ideology is an ideology ‘that arbitrarily

severs itself from wider ideational contexts, by the deliberate removal and replacement

of concepts’.18 This implies that populism as a thin-centred ideology does not provide a

comprehensive programme of how a particular society should function. Parts of existing,

more wide-ranging, ideologies can and should be added to the populist core. In the

6

words of Ben Stanley, populism ‘is diffuse in its lack of a programmatic centre of gravity

and open in its ability to cohabit with other, more comprehensive, ideologies’.19 This is

similar to Taggart’s assertion that populism lacks core values and that it is ‘chameleonic’

since the ideological colour it adopts depends on context and the values of the

‘heartland’ it appeals to.20

According to Margaret Canovan, however, the lack of an programmatic centre of

gravity actually makes it difficult to speak of a populist ideology; ‘attempts to define

populism in terms of any such ideology fail, because in another context the anti-elitist

mobilization concerned may be reacting to a different ideological environment’.21 It is,

according to Canovan, best to build a descriptive typology ‘which clarifies the ways in

which the term is used while being spacious enough to do justice to the diversity of the

movements and ideas concerned’.22 Proponents of the 'thin ideology' interpretation of

populism have responded to this claim by arguing that populist actors across the globe

may be dissimilar as far as their specific policy positions are concerned, but that they

still share a fundamental set of core traits. Thus, in the words of Stanley:

the lack of an acknowledged ideology is not the same as the lack of an ideology: the

absence of a common history, programme and social base, whilst attesting to populism’s

‘thin’ nature, does not warrant the conclusion that there is no coherence to the collection

of concepts that comprise populist ideology.23

Perceiving populism as a (thin-centred) ideology seems to imply that there are

political actors that have this populism as a defining ideological characteristic. It would

then, in principle, be possible to distinguish populist from non-populist political actors.

Indeed, in the literature authors often speak of ‘populist parties’ or party families for

which populism is a core component. Cas Mudde, for instance, treats populism as a core

element of the populist radical right and a few other party families.24

Yet populism is not always treated as a ‘fixed’ element of a particular type of

party or politician. Kurt Weyland, for instance, explicitly defines populism as a political

strategy and considers populism to be a tool for a leader to seek and exercise power.25

7

Hans-Georg Betz similarly asserts that one can see populism as a political strategy; a

rhetoric ‘designed to tap feelings of ressentiment and exploit them politically’.26 Jagers

and Walgrave, in turn, speak about ‘thin’ populism – as opposed to the ‘thick’ variant

which has more defining properties – as ‘a communication style of political actors that

refers to the people’.27

This line of reasoning implies that the use of populism is not necessarily confined

to a particular type of movement or party. Jagers and Walgrave even add that also

interest group representatives and journalists may use the populist communication

style.28 Established politicians, who are normally at the receiving end of populist critique,

can be associated with populism too. Cas Mudde actually argued that the emergence of

the radical populist parties in Western Europe has led mainstream parties to use populist

methods themselves as a response to the challenge of populist actors, leading to the

dawn of a populist Zeitgeist.29

The fact that there are different perceptions about how populism manifests itself

is not necessarily problematic if populism is defined in a careful way. It seems

reasonable to argue that populism can occur in various forms (e.g. style, strategy and

lasting ideology) and that the expression of populist discourse is not confined to a

particular set of political actors. As a matter of fact, recent contributions have measured

the degree of populism in the discourse of political parties, by considering party

manifestos, speeches or party political broadcasts.30 In doing so, the question of whether

populism is an ideology, strategy, communication style or something else, might not be

very important.

Still, there are reasons why the concept of populism resembles the concept of a

cat-dog. Following the analogy of Giovanni Sartori, a cat-dog is an animal that does not

exist in reality, but biologists might make the mistake to lump together cats and dogs in

one category because the animals show particular similarities.31 Populism is similar to a

cat-dog; the term is used to describe political phenomena and actors that actually do not

belong in the same category. This will be discussed in the following section, which also

outlines the most appropriate concept-building strategy for populism.

8

The cat-dog and concept-building strategies

There are three main reasons as to why populism is a cat-dog concept. It is the third

reason, related to the application of the concept, which is central to this paper, but it is

worth mentioning the first two as well. The first reason is the random use of populism

due to the lack of a clear definition, which leads to the erroneous inclusion of many

actors under the header of populism.32 The second reason is that, when a definition is

provided, its components are often applied to cases too loosely. A result is that the

concept of populism becomes ‘stretched’ and that too wide a variety of political

phenomena become associated with populism.33 The risk of concept stretching becomes

greater when scholars introduce different forms of populism which denote some sort of

distinction between ‘full populism’ and ‘semi populism’. An example is the previously

mentioned concept of ‘thin populism’ introduced by Jagers and Walgrave: ‘a

communication style of political actors that refers to the people’.34 When comparing this

definition to the four core concepts of Stanley, this definition arguably bears some

resemblance to ‘the idea of popular sovereignty’ component, but to none of the others.

Even if it concerns a definition of a ‘thin’ variant of populism, it is questionable whether

we truly measure something related to populism in the first place when we would apply

it.

More generally, if one would shop selectively in the list of populist core

components, applying the concept to cases that do not comply with all four features

outlined in Stanley’s article for example, the risk is that populism becomes associated

with any kind of opportunistic appeal to ‘the people’ or anti-establishment criticism. This

would seriously weaken the discriminating power of the concept of populism, since such

statements appear to be used by many political actors. For this reason, it is argued here

that populism is best treated as a ‘classical’ concept.35 This requires a minimal definition,

which includes the necessary and jointly sufficient defining properties.36 It is only the

combination of all populist core components, or ‘constitutive dimensions’ in the words of

Gary Goertz, that truly defines a phenomenon, or a political actor, as populist.37

9

Alternative strategies of concept formation would be the ‘family resemblance’

approach and the creation of ‘radial categories’.38 The latter strategy entails the creation

of a central subcategory which can be considered as a ‘full’ instance, because it

incorporates all possible components of a concept. The concept, however, may still be

used for cases which lack some of these components. Collier and Mahon use the example

of the concept of ‘mother’.39 Even if a woman is not the genetic mother of a child, and

hence does not belong to the central subcategory, she might still be categorised as a

‘nurturing mother’ or a ‘stepmother’. The family resemblance structure is even more

flexible, in that it contains no necessary defining properties.40 The absence of one of the

concept’s properties can be compensated by the presence of another.

These approaches, however, are not suitable for the concept of populism. None of

the four components outlined above can be left out, or substituted, without deriving the

concept of its actual meaning and causing unwelcome concept stretching. For instance, if

the concept is applied to party politics, leaving out the ‘appeal to popular sovereignty’

component would lead to the inclusion of parties with an anti-establishment, but not so

much populist character, or, even worse, all opposition parties which happen to rail

against the governing elite of the day. A reference to popular sovereignty only, on the

other hand, is not necessarily connected with the populist notion that there is a

normative distinction between ‘the people’ and ‘the elite’.41 If the (often implicit)

conception of the homogeneity of ‘the people’ is left out of the definition, the anti-

pluralist character of populism would be ignored.42

Even if a more stringent minimal definition of populism is applied, there still is a

third cat-dog problem, which is the problem central to this paper. The problem is related

to what Sartori calls ‘degreeism’: ‘the abuse (uncritical use) of the maxim that

differences in kind are best conceived as differences of degree, and that dichotomous

treatments are invariably best replaced by continuous ones’.43 In the case of populism,

the problem of degreeism is not necessarily related to the properties of the concept

itself, as it is possible to determine whether a single expression is either populist or not

by means of a minimal definition. The problem lies more in the fact that it is unclear to

10

what extent a political actor should use populist expressions in order for it to be

considered a ‘full’ case of populism.

As discussed, it seems reasonable to accept that actors can use populist discourse

to a certain extent. Political parties, for instance, may apply populist expressions to

varying degrees (across time) in their campaign rhetoric or in their manifestos. In the

words of Stanley:

At any given point, certain parties and social movements will be ‘more populist’ than

others, in that populism is a more salient aspect of their appeal. Some may retain over

time a consistent combination of populism and another, full ideology. Others may hitch

their populism to a variety of passing ideological bandwagons. Still others may keep to a

consistent full ideology with a waxing or waning populist element. Finally, in some cases

they may exhibit no particular ideological consistency, thin or full.44

However, the fact that populism can manifest itself in different degrees and that

populism is not necessarily an enduring core feature of political actors makes it difficult

to conceive of an exclusive category of ‘populist parties’. The problem in the literature is

that there are many cases which are frequently branded as ‘populist parties’, but which

do not seem to fully meet the definitional criteria previously outlined (throughout time).

The following section illustrates this problem by means of several ‘hard’, or contestable,

cases of populism throughout Europe.

Hard cases of populism

There are political parties whose populist nature seems more or less undisputed. These

include ‘classic’ examples of Western European populist radical right parties, such as the

French Front National, the Belgian Flemish Interest, the Austrian Freedom Party and the

Italian Lega Nord.45 It thus appears to be possible to identify a more or less undisputed

set of parties for which populism is a defining feature throughout time. This paper will,

11

however, focus on several ‘hard’ cases of populism which illustrate the problems related

to the application of the concept. These cases are partly selected on the basis of results

from country expert questionnaires, which were carried out as part of a larger research

project. The selected cases were those that attracted particular disagreement among the

experts as far as questions about their populist character were concerned. The

discussion is centred on two, distinct but often related, issues: the fact that some actors

only seem populist to a certain extent and that some actors do not consistently voice

populist discourse over time. Particular attention will be paid to cases in Central and

Eastern Europe where both these issues are particularly apparent.

Populist…but to a certain extent

As has been noted above, problems with classification arise because it is not clear to

which degree a political actor has to voice populist discourse in order to be considered as

a ‘full’ case of populism. This problem can be illustrated well by using a study of Teun

Pauwels, who has applied quantitative text analysis to measure the degrees of populism

in the internal and external party literature of Belgian parties, on the basis of key words

capturing (normative) references to ‘the people’ and ‘the elite’.46 In the analysis, the

Flemish Interest scored very high on the populism barometer, along with a smaller

‘neoliberal populist’ party List Dedecker (later renamed Libertarian, Direct, Democratic,

LDD).47 This is rather unsurprising, as there has been little discussion about the populist

nature of both parties. In third place on the populism scale, came a less usual suspect:

the New Flemish Alliance (N-VA), the successor of the Flemish nationalist People’s Union.

This conservative party with a strong appeal to Flemish nationalism became the largest

party in Flanders (and in the national parliament) after the federal election of 2010.

Pauwels accounts for the high populism scores of the N-VA by referring to the party’s

critique of the allegedly unrepresentative francophone elite on the federal level and, on

the basis of his findings, describes the N-VA’s discourse as ‘moderately populist’.48

The results from the analysis, however, do not seem to provide a very clear cut-

off point between ‘full’ and ‘moderate’ populist parties. Pauwels finds that, on average,

12

16 per cent of LDD’s ideology was ‘devoted to populism’, while the equivalent figure for

the Flemish Interest was 12 per cent. With a figure of just over 10 per cent, the N-VA

did not trail far behind, and based on these findings it appears hard to draw a clear line

between the three parties. As the Belgian case shows, measuring degrees of populism

clearly does not directly lead to a solution as far as problems of classification are

concerned. Even if it is not the purpose of the author to use the concept of populism in

order to classify parties dichotomously (as either populism or not), it still is not

straightforward how we should interpret meaningfully the differences in the degrees of

populism between political actors. In this case, why should the N-VA be referred to as

only ‘moderately’ populist when it only voices populist rhetoric to a slightly lower degree

than the Flemish Interest?

While it can already be difficult to apply the concept of populism to political

parties when they are perceived as unitary actors, it may become even more

complicated if we consider intra-party dynamics as well. This is illustrated by the case of

Silvio Berlusconi’s conservative centre-right party Forza Italia, which later merged into

the People of Freedom party (Il Popolo della Libertà, PdL). In this case, it is difficult to

determine to which degree populism was a feature of the parties because of the

discrepancy between the official programme of the party and the rhetoric of its leader.

Berlusconi himself has been known for his dissociation from the ‘corrupt and inefficient

elite’ and his eagerness to ‘proclaim himself as the interpreter and defender of the

popular will’.49 Marco Tarchi, however, has argued that Forza Italia, unlike its radical

regionalist partner Lega Nord, could not truly be considered as a populist party, because

the expression of populism was ‘entirely delegated to the leader, who has made it a

trademark of his political style, but not a source of ideological inspiration’.50 Indeed,

populist anti-establishment passages were not that widespread in official party

documents and, as Carlo Ruzza and Stefano Fella found, even waned after the turn of

the 21st century.51 While it is thus possible to argue that Berlusconi himself was a

populist figure, it is questionable whether Forza Italia in its entirety was as well.

13

Be that as it may, the concept of populism has frequently been used to describe

Forza Italia.52 There is also a good case for this in view of Berlusconi’s dominant role

within the party organisation. Things got ostensibly more complicated, however, when in

March 2009 Forza Italia officially merged with other, non-populist, parties to form The

People of Freedom party. Even though Berlusconi was also the central figure within the

new party, the leader of its main partner, the National Alliance (Alleanza Nazionale, AN),

‘continued to reiterate the distinctive and less populist profile of the AN element’.53 While

AN party leader Gianfranco Fini left the party in July 2010 and formed a new party

afterwards, it remains difficult to judge whether The People of Freedom party was truly

populist during the short-lived partnership between the two leaders. Similar to the case

of Forza Italia, a verdict largely depends on the extent to which the PdL is perceived as a

personal project of its populist leader, Silvio Berlusconi.

Berlusconi’s parties may be somewhat idiosyncratic cases and it is not surprising

that they attract scholarly disagreement about how to describe them. But they do

illustrate well the difficulty of applying the concept of populism. It is possible for

individual leaders to adopt a populist discourse, whereas the party as a whole shows

little populist characteristics if one looks at formal party documentation or the discourse

of other party members. This discrepancy is possible due to the thin-centred nature of

populism and the fact that populism is not necessarily related to particular policy

positions. As long as the populist leader shares the same policy goals as the essentially

non-populist party, this does not necessarily threaten the (ideological) cohesiveness of

the organisation. It does make life rather hard, however, for the scholars seeking to

conceive of an exclusive category of populist parties.

Populist…but not consistently across time

As the previous examples have shown, populism is difficult to apply in some cases

because parties use populist discourse only to a certain degree or because populism is a

feature of their leader’s rhetoric but not so much of the party as a whole. A different, but

14

potentially related, issue is that populism is not necessarily a key feature of political

actors throughout time.

A case in point is the British National Party (BNP). Founded in 1982, the BNP

descended from the, electorally rather insignificant, neo-fascist National Front.

Particularly after the turn of the 21st century the party aimed to cultivate a legitimate

image by moving away from overt biological racism and by emphasising more

commonplace ‘local community’ issues.54 In the 2005 and 2010 general election

manifestos the party also embraced democracy, whilst at the same time explicitly

rejecting totalitarianism.55 The BNP also expressed a clear populist discourse by this

time, combining a strong anti-establishment rhetoric with an explicit appeal to ‘ordinary

British folk’.56 The party also claimed that:

It is the ‘average’ man and woman who suffers from the failings of our politicians to grasp

the issue and restore genuine democracy (...) The British National Party exists to put an

end to this injustice. We will return power to the men and women of Britain, the taxpayers,

pensioners, mums and dads and workers.57

Over the years, the BNP has thus arguably shifted from one ideology to another:

from fascism to (radical right-wing) populism. It has been argued, however, that this

ideological transformation merely represented an opportune change of clothing in order

to become more electorally credible, instead of a true break with the past.58 If the BNP is

still perceived to be a neo-fascist party in essence, it is debatable whether the BNP can

be considered as a populist party at the same time, since populism and fascism can be

seen as mutually exclusive ideologies. Fascists envision a totalitarian, hierarchically

organised and organic state in which the people serve as mere parts of a larger whole.59

Populism, on the other hand, glorifies the ordinary people within the community, and not

the state apparatus as such.60 Fascism, like other forms of right-wing extremism, is also

anti-democratic.61 Populists, on the other hand, explicitly stress the desire for popular

sovereignty and claim that the will of the people should be the ultimate source of

legitimacy.62 The case of the BNP thus shows that it is not always possible to label a

15

party as ‘populist’ throughout its whole existence, but also that it can be problematic to

associate a party with populism if its original ideology appears to be at odds with the

populist core components.

Thus far, only contestable cases of populism on the ‘right’, understood in socio-

economic and/or cultural terms, have been discussed. The Dutch Socialist Party, on the

other hand, is a hard case on the socio-economic left. The party was founded in the

1970s, closely associating itself with Maoism, but only entered parliament in 1994. By

this time, the party had gradually moved away from its communist roots and could

better be described as a ‘social-populist’ party.63 Following March and Mudde, social-

populist parties ‘no longer profess to be the ‘vanguard’ of the proletariat, but rather the

vox populi, they place particularism before internationalism, with a much less theoretical

and more inclusive style than hitherto’.64 Besides its appeal to the vox populi, The SP

railed against the capitalist elites and the politicians who were associated with it. The

anti-establishment character of the party was evident during the 1990s, exemplified by

the slogan it applied: ‘vote against, vote SP’.

In more recent years, however, the SP seems to have downplayed this anti-

establishment image to a large extent – in 2002 its slogan had remarkably changed to

‘Vote for, vote SP’. De Lange and Rooduijn (2010: 7) have furthermore shown that the

anti-elitist rhetoric in SP manifestos gradually evaporated; in 1994 anti-elite references

were found in 17 per cent of the paragraphs, while this percentage dropped to a mere

1.5 per cent in 2006.65 Bearing in mind the lack of a strong ‘denigration of the elite’ in

the discourse of the SP in more recent years, there is a good case for now classifying the

SP as an ‘ordinary’, albeit somewhat radical, social-democratic party.66 This does not

necessarily lead to conceptual confusion if the rhetorical, or perhaps even ideological,

change of the SP is acknowledged and when scholars seize to use the label of populism

in order to classify the party. However, once a party or politician has been labelled as

‘populist’, this label appears likely to stick irrespective of whether the rhetoric of the

actor still complies with the definition of populism. Both in the vernacular and academic

sphere, the SP is still regularly referred to as a ‘populist party’.67

16

A final point to make is that the ‘social-democratisation’ of the Dutch Socialist

Party can be related to the party’s eagerness to join a governing coalition, which caused

it to voice less radical critique of potential coalition partners. Along similar lines, it has

been argued that it is typical for populist parties to lose their anti-establishment

character whilst in office.68 If they possess governing power, it is a challenge for populist

parties to still distance themselves from ‘the elite' in a convincing way. Then again, in

the literature on Latin American populism the term actually tends to be associated with

leaders who wield great executive power.69 In Europe, too, some populist parties seem

able to retain their populist character in office. Albertazzi and McDonnell, for example,

show that the Italian Lega Nord ‘succeeded in presenting itself simultaneously as both

‘the opposition within government’ and a driving force behind high-profile areas of

government policy’ and thus ‘successfully walked the populist tightrope of being seen to

have ‘one foot in and one foot out’ of government’.70 The Swiss People’s Party (SVP) is

another example. Following Andrej Zaslove, the SVP managed ‘to present itself as a

party of government and a party in opposition at the same time’.71

Although there are instances of parties which have been consistently

characterised by their populist discourse over time, even after they entered office, the

thin ideological nature of populism warrants that populism can more easily be disposed

of, or taken on board, by political actors than other ‘full’ ideologies. This makes it difficult

to judge which political parties can be considered to form part of a clearly delineated

universe of ‘populist parties’. What is more, the nature of such a universe is changeable

itself. The next section will outline how this problem is particularly evident when we

move beyond the Western European political sphere.

Populism in post-communist Europe

Due to the relatively recent transition to democracy in post-communist countries,

archetypical cases of populism, such as the French Front National and the Belgian

Flemish Interest, are lacking in the Central and Eastern part of the continent. After the

fall of communism, party systems in post-communist Europe have been marked by the

17

rise and fall of numerous new parties and the ideological appeal of these parties has

often been changeable. Moreover, many of these new parties played into the widespread

discontent with political elites. As Mudde has argued, for instance, many parties in post-

communist countries have gone through a populist radical right phase.72 Due to these

reasons, post-communist countries pose a particular challenge when it comes to using

the concept of populism to distinguish between political actors in a meaningful way. A

study of Deegan-Krause and Haughton, for example, showed that populism was

widespread within the Slovakian party system, but that parties tended to lose their

populist traits once in office or once their lifespan had increased.73 Parties such as the

Movement of Workers of Slovakia (ZRS), the Party of Civic Understanding (SOP),

Alliance of the New Citizen (ANO) and Direction (Smer), could therefore all be considered

as populist parties, but only during a particular period of time.

Distinguishing between populist and non-populist parties in post-communist

Europe is further complicated by the presence of a more general anti-political mood after

the transition to democracy.74 The issue of corruption has been electorally salient in

many post-communist countries in particular, which resulted in the formation of many

new parties with an anti-incumbent message calling for cleaner politics. Peter Učeň

referred to several such parties in Central and Eastern Europe, which were mainly

characterised by their anti-establishment rhetoric, as ‘new centrist populists’.75 It is

questionable, however, whether such parties could all truly be associated with populism

in the sense that they complied with all the components of a more stringent minimal

definition. In a paper discussing several parties in the Baltic States, which were all newly

founded and marked by their anti-incumbency and anti-corruption messages, Allan Sikk

rightly warns that simply equating such parties’ critical style with populism leads to

further concept stretching.76

Yet also when following a stricter strategy of concept formation, applying

populism as a ‘classifier’ in Central and Eastern Europe can be daunting. This can be

illustrated by means of the case of Law and Justice in Poland (Prawo i Sprawiedliwość,

PiS). In Poland, too, continuing practices of clientelism and corruption during the 1990s

18

and early 2000s fuelled a growing anti-establishment mood.77 As a result, anti-

establishment rhetoric was widespread during election campaigns and PiS was one of the

parties which clearly aimed to capitalise on this. The party, eventually spearheaded by

the twin brothers Jarosław and Lech Kaczyński, emerged from a governing centre right

alliance, which largely fell apart in 2001. The Kaczyński brothers were hardly usual

suspects to be branded as populist outsiders, since both brothers had been active in the

highest echelons of Polish politics in the years after the transition to democracy.

It was only from the electoral campaign of 2005 onwards that PiS became truly

associated with populism, when the party re-profiled itself ideologically. Radoslaw

Markowski even spoke of a ‘spectacular change’ of Law and Justice from a ‘fairly typical

conservative party’ into a ‘radical nationalist, and visibly populist-socialist one’.78 The

party sharpened its anti-establishment rhetoric, explicitly referring to a ‘Fourth Republic’,

which was supposed to bring an end to the Third Polish Republic and to start a new era

of clean and moral government. According to Ben Stanley, the party now portrayed itself

‘as representative of an ordinary, authentic, legitimate ‘people’ against an illegitimate

and usurping elite’, and became an example of ‘populism in power’ after it entered

government’.79

Even though it is justifiable to apply the populist label to Law and Justice since

the 2005 election campaign, there is some disagreement about whether the party truly

underwent a ‘spectacular change’, or whether the new course was merely a shift in

emphasis.80 Fighting corruption, for instance, had been at the core of the party’s

programme from the outset.81 If the case is made that the programme of Law and

Justice has been marked by more continuity than change throughout the years, one may

wonder whether it is justifiable to place the party into a different category (of populist

parties) after 2005, or whether it is better to merely speak of a greater degree of

populism in its discourse without reclassifying the party.

More generally, in view of the relative newness and fluidity of party systems in

post-communist countries it is often not easy to distinguish between a real political

establishment and populist parties challenging it. Widespread dissatisfaction in many of

19

these countries created a fertile breeding ground for populism, but this populism was not

confined to specific political parties, as has often been the case in Western Europe.

Therefore, identifying a clearly circumscribed universe of ‘populist parties’ in post-

communist countries has, up until now, been rather difficult.

Having touched on examples of hard cases of populism throughout Europe, the

next section discusses how to best make sense of the concept of populism, as it

manifests itself in European countries.

Dissecting the populist cat-dog

As has been argued, populism can be seen as a cat-dog concept, even if a clear

definition of populism is provided. Certain political actors, parties in particular, are

placed in a single category under the header of ‘populism’, even though this does not

always seem justifiable. This tends to happen when the definition of populism is applied

too loosely. Yet also when populism is applied more stringently as a ‘classical’ concept,

the cat-dog problem persists. This relates to the fact that political actors can voice

populist rhetoric to different degrees (across time). What is problematic is that observers

using the concept are often not explicit about whether they intend to refer to a particular

delineated subset of populist actors (e.g. populist politicians or political parties) or

whether they mean that the actor is expressing populist discourse in a more fleeting

sense.

One way to deal with this is to be clearer about the way populism is seen to

manifest itself when a reference is made to a particular actor. In order to illustrate this

point we can use Sartori’s idea of the ladder of abstraction.82 The basic idea is that

concepts higher on the ladder have fewer properties and are, therefore, applicable to

more cases. In other words, they have a low intension and a high extension. Concepts

lower on the ladder have a higher intension (i.e. more properties) and a lower extension

(i.e. they are applicable to fewer cases).

20

This inverse relationship between intension and extension does not always apply

if one, for instance, uses radial concepts.83 The idea of the ladder can be used, however,

when one speaks about the different manifestations of populism; using populism either

as a ‘classifier’ or as a more loose ‘descriptor’ essentially involves making a judgement

about which level of abstraction populism manifests itself on (see Figure 1). At the top of

the ladder, we find expressions of a discourse which complies with the minimal definition

of populism. Populism, in this sense, does not have to denote more than a rhetorical

strategy used by any political actor. The extension of ‘populist discourse’ is, therefore,

rather high. This application of populism is particularly suitable for cases in post-

communist countries where populist discourse tends to be used in a rather fleeting

sense.

***Figure 1 about here***

When our aim is to use populism to describe party politics, taking a step down

would lead us to the level of ‘populist parties’. These are parties which have populism as

a lasting defining feature, which sets them apart from parties whose politicians use

populist rhetoric only sporadically or for a short period of time. By moving this step down

we are not adding properties to the concept of populism as such – following the

traditional Sartorian way – but we are increasing the intension of the concept by only

accepting cases in this category which express populist discourse consistently throughout

time. Populism needs to constitute an important raison d'être for parties in this category.

Particularly if we speak about the European context, it can make sense to make

one further step down by distinguishing various party families which have populism as a

defining feature. Due to their ‘thin centred’ or ‘chameleonic’ character, populist parties

can differ as far as their substantive policy positions are concerned. The minimal

definition of populism can be expanded, however, by adding additional properties to

describe various kinds of populist party families.84 As a result, we can end up with

categories such as ‘populist radical right’, ‘neoliberal populism’ and ‘social populism’ if we

21

move to the bottom of the ladder.85 It is important to note that, despite ideological

differences, populism can still be seen as an important core component of these various

parties. This is also why it is still useful to use the more abstract category of populist

parties in general. It might be a thin core that binds populist parties, but this core might

still tell us a lot about their behaviour and performance.86

In any case, bearing in mind, and being explicit about, different levels of

abstraction when applying the concept of populism is a first step to stimulate a more

accurate use of the concept. Scholars and other observers should not be too quick to

conclude that actors using populist rhetoric can also be classified as populists. On the

basis of the ladder and the earlier discussion on concept formation, the following

recommendations can be made that lead to a more accurate use of the concept of

populism and the adjective ‘populist’ in particular:

Do not use the adjective of populism when a case only complies with some of the

(necessary and jointly sufficient) components of populism (e.g. when a party merely

presents itself as radical outsider).

Use populism as a ‘descriptor’ when a political actor expresses discourse that

complies with a minimal definition of populism. Stay on this level of abstraction if

populism is not a lasting constituent feature of the political party or movement this

actor is representing, or when the study merely means to analyse degrees of

populism in general. In these cases, refer to the expressions of the actor being

populist, not to the nature of the actor itself.

Use populism as a ‘classifier’ when populism is an essential characteristic of a political

actor and when the study refers to a case within an exclusive category of populist

actors (such as ‘populist parties’). Populist discourse ought to be voiced consistently

by those actors for an extended period of time.

When applying the concept of populism to party politics, these recommendations

can form the basis of a more critical assessment of whether or not a party is part of an

22

exclusive category of ‘populist parties’. That is not to say that disagreements about

certain hard cases of populism, such as the ones discussed earlier in this paper, would

automatically be resolved. A judgement whether or not to include cases such as the New

Flemish Alliance, Forza Italia and Law and Justice into the category of ‘populist parties’

requires in-depth knowledge of the party’s ideological characteristics and/or

organisational structure. Then, a sensible choice about either inclusion or exclusion can

be made. For example, on the basis of a more qualitative assessment of the party, Teun

Pauwels recently argued that despite its use of anti-establishment appeals, the New

Flemish Alliance could actually not be labelled as a populist party because of its elitist

characteristics and lack of appeal to the vox populi.87 Silvio Berlusconi’s parties, on the

other hand, seem suitable for inclusion into the ‘populist party’ category. Following

Duncan McDonnell, both the People of Freedom party and Forza Italia could be seen as

‘personal parties’ of their populist leader, when factors such as the party organisation,

campaign strategies and intra-party power relations are considered.88

There still is the issue that certain actors, and parties such as the British National

Party, the Dutch Socialist Party and Law and Justice in Poland, have either adopted or

abandoned a populist discourse throughout time. This is not necessarily problematic if it

is clearly mapped when populism became, or seized to be, a defining feature of those

parties. On that basis, we can consider Law and Justice after 2005 as a full instance of

populism, as populist discourse became not only part of its campaign rhetoric, but also

of its ideological appeal whilst in government. At the same time, populism seized to be a

defining feature of the Socialist Party’s ideology after the turn of the 21st century.

Concerning the British National Party, a choice has to be made whether to consider its

revamped, less extremist, discourse as a reflection of its ‘real’ ideology. If the rhetoric

and political programme of the BNP is considered at face value, the party can be said to

have moved from neo-fascism to populism at the start of the 21st century.89

Measuring degrees populism can be a way to shed more light on borderline cases,

provided that measurement is based on sound indicators and valid sources. When the

aim is to apply populism as a ‘classifier’ on the basis of this measurement, it would also

23

help if clear thresholds are set in order to determine how much populism a party, for

example, has to express in order to consider it as a ‘full’ populist party. Then again,

most studies measuring populism do not seem to have this aim, or even explicitly state

that populism should only be seen in terms of degrees and not used as a ‘classifier’.90

These studies, however, are not always entirely consistent in their argument. Rooduijn,

De Lange and Van der Brug, for instance, take the ‘degreeism stance’ but still identify a

set of parties which they refer to as ‘radical right-wing populist parties’ and ‘radical left-

wing populist parties’, hence implicitly using populism as a classifier at the same time.91

This later example shows that it is important to be explicit and consistent about

the position we take on the ladder of abstraction of populist manifestations.92 One

cannot deny that populism can be used as a classifier and at the same time speak of

‘populist parties’. Applying the adjective too carelessly leads to confusion about a

potential universe of full populist cases, and we may end up comparing incomparable

cases. We also risk doing this when we would use a more ‘Goertzian’ approach in which

populism is considered to manifest itself on a continuum of gradations, distinguishing,

for instance, between categories such as ‘slightly’, ‘moderately’ and ‘very’ populist

parties.93 Besides the risk of creating more confusion about where to place specific

instance of populism, it is questionable whether this approach would be of much

analytical use in making sense of the phenomenon of populism, as expressed by political

actors.

This paper therefore argues that it is most fruitful to be open to the idea that

populism can manifest itself as a more loosely applied discourse, as well as an essential

feature of certain populist politicians and parties. It is necessary that observers are

explicit about the way in which they apply the term. Even though discussion about

borderline cases will remain, this is a first step to come to a more accurate use of the

concept.

24

Conclusion

This paper has discussed problems associated with the application of the term populism,

using various ‘hard’ cases throughout Europe to illustrate these problems. Conceptual

confusion often stems from a lack of a sound definition. Yet, as this paper has argued,

also when the term is defined more carefully, a ‘cat-dog problem’ remains. Many political

actors are associated with populism, but not all of those seem to fit into the same

category. An important reason for this is that populism can be used to refer to a

particular discourse which can be expressed by any political actor as well as an

ideological core feature of a delineated set of political parties. Observers are often not

explicit about this distinction, and making this distinction becomes harder as political

actors may also use populist rhetoric to different degrees (over time). This is particularly

apparent in relatively young post-communist party systems, where party ideologies have

been fluid and which have been marked by the arrival and demise of new political parties

which often voiced an anti-incumbent message. Still, it makes sense to conceive of an

exclusive category of ‘populist parties’. Parties such as the Font National, Lega Nord and

Flemish Interest cannot truly be characterised without taking their populist ideology into

account and can, therefore, be distinguished from parties that use populism only

sporadically.

In order to stimulate a more accurate use of the concept, the paper suggested

treating populism as a ‘classical’ concept. Creating several subcategories of populism,

and thereby treating populism as a radial concept, is a recipe for concept stretching and

would derive populism of its actual meaning. Further, the paper suggested that

observers need to be more explicit about how they apply the term and whether they use

the concept as a more loose ‘descriptor’ or as a ‘classifier’ in order to refer to a case

within a circumscribed universe of populist cases. The paper has introduced a ladder of

abstraction of populist manifestations in order to clarify this suggestion. At a lower level

of abstraction, populism is a suitable term to describe various parties for which populism

is an ideological core component. At a higher level of abstraction, the concept may be

25

used to spot trends in the expression of populist discourse by any political actor. It is

important that observers are clear where they stand on the ladder in order to avoid

confusion about the potential universe of populist cases.

Working on the basis of a sound definition, as well as being more explicit about

the form in which populism is seen to manifest itself, may not automatically end

discussions about borderline cases, but is a first step towards a more accurate

application of the concept. This is important if it is accepted that the phenomenon of

populism fulfils an important role, either as a threat to, or a corrective for,

representative democratic regimes.

Notes

1 See T. Bale, S. van Kessel, and P. Taggart, ‘Thrown around with abandon? Popular

understandings of populism as conveyed by the print media: a UK case study’, Acta Politica,

46(2) (2011), pp. 111-131.

2 See for example Y. Mény and Y. Surel, 'The Constitutive Ambiguity of Populism', in: Y. Mény and

I. Surel (eds.), Democracies and the Populist Challenge (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2002), pp. 1-

21; P. Taggart, ‘Populism and the Pathology of Representative Politics’, in Y. Mény and Y. Surel

(eds.), Democracies and the Populist Challenge (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2002), pp. 62-80; F.

Panizza, ‘Introduction: Populism and the Mirror of Democracy’, in: F. Panizza (ed.), Populism and

the Mirror of Democracy (London: Verso, 2005), pp. 1-31.

3 See W. B. Gallie, ‘Essentially contested concepts’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56

(1956), pp. 67-198; D. Collier, F. Hidalgo and A. Maciuceanu, ‘Essentially contested concepts:

Debates and applications’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 11(3) (2006), pp. 211-246.

4 A. Zaslove, ‘Here to Stay: Populism as a New Party Type?’, European Review, 16(3) (2008), p.

322.

5 G. Sartori, ‘Comparing and Miscomparing’, Journal of Theoretical Politics, 3(3) (1991), pp.

243-257.

6 A. Sikk, ‘Parties and Populism’, Centre for European Politics, Security and Integration

Working paper, University College London, 2009-02 (2009).

26

7 G. Sartori, ‘Concept Misformation in Comparative Politics’, American Political Science Review,

64(4) (1970), p. 1039.

8 C. Mudde and C. Rovira Kaltwasser, ‘Exclusionary vs. Inclusionary Populism: Comparing

Contemporary Europe and Latin America’, Government and Opposition, available on CJO2012.

doi:10.1017/gov.2012.11, p.3.

9 See D. Collier and J. Mahon, ‘Conceptual “stretching” revisited: Adapting categories in

comparative analysis’, American Political Science Review, 87(4) (1993), 845-855; Sartori op.

cid., Ref 7.

10 See Sartori, op. cit., Ref. 7, p.p. 1033-1053.

11 See, for example, E. Shils, The Torment of Secrecy: the background and consequences of

American security policies (London: Heineman, 1956); G. Ionescu and E. Gellner (eds.),

Populism, its Meanings and National Characteristics (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson,

1969); P. Taggart, Populism (Buckingham and Philadelphia: Open University Press, 2000); C.

Mudde, 'The Populist Zeitgeist', Government and Opposition, 39(4) (2004), p. 543; D.

Albertazzi and D. McDonnell, 'Introduction: The Sceptre and the Spectre', in: D. Albertazzi and D.

McDonnell (eds.) Twenty-First Century Populism. The Spectre of Western European

Democracy (Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan, 2008), p. 8.; K. Abts and S. Rummens, 'Populism

versus Democracy', Political Studies, 55(6) (2007), p. 409.

12 Ionescu and Gellner, ibid.; Mudde, ibid.; Albertazzi and McDonnell, ibid.; Abts and Rummens,

ibid.

13 B. Stanley, ‘The Thin Ideology of Populism’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 13(1) (2008), pp.

95-110.

14 See, for example, K. Weyland, 'Clarifying a Contested Concept - Populism in the Study of Latin

American Politics', Comparative Politics, 34(1) (2001), p. 14; K. Roberts, ‘Populism, Political

Conflict, and Grass-Root Organisation in Latin America’, Comparative Politics, 38(2) (2006).

15 Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, op. cit., Ref. 8, p. 8.

16 See also M. Canovan, Populism, (New York and London: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1981).

17 Mudde, op. cit., Ref. 11; Abts and Rummens, op. cit., Ref. 11; Stanley. op. cit., Ref. 13;

Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, op. cit., Ref. 8.

27

18 M. Freeden, 'Is Nationalism a Distinct Ideology?', Political Studies, 46(4) (1998), p. 750.

19 Stanley, op. cit., Ref. 13, p. 100.

20 Taggart, op. cid. Ref. 11; P. Taggart ‘Populism and representative politics in contemporary

Europe’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 9(3) (2004), pp. 274-5.

21 M. Canovan, ‘Trust the People! Populism and the Two Faces of Democracy’, Political Studies,

47(1) (1999), p. 4.

22 M. Canovan, ‘Two Strategies for the Study of Populism’, Political Studies, 30(4) (1982), p.

550.

23 Stanley, op. cit., Ref. 13, p. 100.

24 C. Mudde, ‘Populist Radical Right Parties in Europe’ (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 2007).

25 Weyland, op. cit., Ref. 14, p. 12.

26 H.-G. Betz, ‘Conditions Favouring the Success and Failure of Radical Right-Wing Populist Parties

in Contemporary Democracies’, in: Y. Mény and Y. Surel (eds.), Democracies and the Populist

Challenge (Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2002), p. 198.

27 J. Jagers and S. Walgrave, ‘Populism as political communication style: An empirical study of

political parties’ discourse in Belgium’, European Journal of Political Research, 46(3) (2007),

p. 322.

28 Jagers and Walgrave, ibid.

29 Mudde, op. cid., Ref. 11, pp. 542-563.

30 See for example Jagers and Walgrave, op. cid., Ref. 27, pp. 319-345; K. Hawkins, ‘Is Chavez

populist? Measuring populist discourse in comparative perspective’, Comparative Political

Studies, 42(8) (2009), pp. 1040–1067; K. Deegan-Krause and T. Haughton, ‘Toward a more

useful conceptualization of populism: Types and degrees of populist appeals in the case of

Slovakia’, Politics & Policy, 37(4) (2009), pp. 821–841.; T. Pauwels, ‘Measuring populism: A

quantitative text analysis of Party Literature in Belgium’, Journal of Elections, Public Opinion

and Parties, 21(1) (2011), pp. 97–119; M. Rooduijn, S. de Lange, and W. van der Brug, ‘A

28

populist Zeitgeist? Programmatic contagion by populist parties in Western Europe’, Party Politics,

Advance online publication 20-04-2012.

31 Sartori, op. cid., Ref. 5, p. 248.

32 See Bale et al., op cid. Ref. 1.

33 Sikk, op. cid., Ref. 6, p. 1.

34 Jagers and Walgrave, op. cid., Ref. 27.

35 In other contributions this approach is also taken. See Weyland, op. cit., Ref. 14; Sikk, op.

cid., Ref. 6; Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, op. cit., Ref. 8.

36 See G. Sartori, ‘Guidelines for Concept Analysis’, in: G. Sartori (ed.), Social Science Concepts

(Beverly Hills: Sage, 1984), pp. 55-6.

37 G. Goertz, Social Science Concepts. A User’s Guide (Princeton: Princeton University Press,

2006).

38 Collier and Mahon, op. cid., Ref 9.

39 Collier and Mahon, ibid., p. 849.

40 Goertz, op. cid., Ref. 37, p. 7, p. 45.

41 Mudde, op. cid., Ref. 11, p. 544.

42 Mudde, ibid., p. 543-4; Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, op. cit., Ref. 8, p.6.

43 Sartori, op. cid., Ref. 5, p. 248.

44 Stanley, op. cid., Ref. 13, p. 108.

45 See for example Mudde, op. cid., Ref. 24

46 Pauwels, op. cid., Ref. 30.

47 T. Pauwels, ‘Explaining the success of neoliberal populist parties: the case of Lijst Dedecker in

Belgium’, Political Studies, 58(5) (2010), pp. 1009-1029.

48 Pauwels, op. cid., Ref. 30, p. 110.

29

49 M. Tarchi, 'Italy: A Country of Many Populisms', in D. Albertazzi and D. McDonnell (eds.),

Twenty-First Century Populism. The Spectre of Western European Democracy

(Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan, 2008), p. 93.

50 Tarchi, Ibid., p. 86.

51 C. Ruzza and S. Fella, Re-inventing the Italian Right. Territorial politics, populism and

‘post-fascism (Oxon: Routledge, 2009), p. 131.

52 See for instance F. Raniolo, 'Forza Italia: A Leader with a Party', South European Society and

Politics, 11(3) (2006), pp. 439-455; G. Pasquino, 'The Five Faces of Silvio Berlusconi: The Knight

of Anti-politics', Modern Italy, 12(1) (2007), pp. 39-54; Ruzza and Fella, ibid.

53 Ruzza and Fella, ibid., p. 40.

54 See for instance M. Goodwin, New British Fascism. The Rise of the British National Party,

(Oxon: Routledge, 2011).

55 See British National Party, Rebuilding British Democracy, general election manifesto

(Welshpool: BNP, 2005), p. 9.

56 British National Party, ibid., p. 53

57 British National Party, ibid., p. 3.

58 N. Copsey, ‘Changing course or changing clothes? Reflections on the ideological evolution of the

British National Party 1999-2006’, Patterns of Prejudice, 41(1) (2007), pp. 61-82.

59 See for instance P. Hayes, Fascism (London: Allen and Unwin, 1973); S. Payne, Fascism.

Comparison and Definition (Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press, 1980); R. Griffin, The

Nature of Fascsim (Oxon: Routledge, 1993).

60 Albertazzi and McDonnell, op. cit., Ref. 11, p. 3.

61 Griffin, op. cid., Ref 59, p. 41.

62 See Canovan, op. cid., Ref. 21, pp. 2-16; cf. Abts and Rummens, op. cid., Ref. 11, pp. 405-

424.

63 L. March and C. Mudde, ‘What’s Left of the Radical Left? The European Radical Left After 1989:

Decline and Mutation’, Comparative European politics, 3(1) (2005), p. 35.

30

64 March and Mudde, ibid., p. 36.

65 S. de Lange and M. Rooduijn, ‘Een populistische Zeitgeist in Nederland? Een inhoudsanalyse van

de verkiezingsprogramma’s van populistische en gevestigde politieke partijen’, in: R. Andeweg and

J. Thomassen (eds.), Democratie Doorgelicht, het functioneren van de Nederlandse

democratie (Leiden: Leiden University Press, 2011), pp. 319-334.

66 P. Lucardie, ‘The Netherlands: Populism versus Pillarization’, in: D. Albertazzi and D. McDonnell

(eds.) Twenty-First Century Populism. The Spectre of Western European Democracy

(Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan, 2008), p. 154; G. Voerman and P. Lucardie, ‘De Sociaal-

Democratisering van de SP’, in: F. Becker and R. Cuperus (eds.), Verloren Slag. De PvdA en de

verkiezingen van november 2006 (Amsterdam: Mets and Schilt/Wiardi Beckman Stichting,

2007), pp. 139-164.

67 See, for example, Rooduijn et al., op. cid., Ref. 30.

68 See for instance Taggart, op. cid., Ref. 11; Mény and Surel, op. cid., Ref. 2; R. Heinisch,

‘Success in opposition - failure in government: explaining the performance of right-wing populist

parties in public office’, West European Politics, 26(3) (2003), pp. 91-130.

69 See, for example, Mudde and Rovira Kaltwasser, op. cid., Ref. 8.

70 D. Albertazzi and D. McDonnell, ‘The Lega Nord in the Second Berlusconi Government: In a

League of Its Own’, West European Politics, 28(5) (2005), p. 953.

71 A. Zaslove, ‘The populist radical right in government: The structure and agency of success and

failure’, Comparative European Politics, 10(4) (2012), p. 431.

72 Mudde, op. cid., Ref. 24, p. 41.

73 Deegan-Krause and Haughton, op. cid., Ref. 30.

74 See C. Mudde, ‘In the Name of the Peasantry, the Proletariat, and the People: Populisms in

Eastern Europe’, in: Y. Mény and Y. Surel (eds.), Democracies and the Populist Challenge

(Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2002), pp. 214-232; M. Minkenberg ‘The Radical Right in Post-socialist

Central and Eastern Europe: Comparative Observations and Interpretations’, East European

Politics and Society, 16(2) (2002), pp. 335-362.

31

75 P. Učeň, 'Parties, Populism, and Anti-Establishment Politics in East Central Europe', SAIS

Review, 27(1) (2007), pp. 49-62.

76 Sikk, op. cid., Ref. 6.

77 See for instance A. Szczerbiak ‘Poland's Unexpected Political Earthquake: The September 2001

Parliamentary Election’, Journal of Communist Studies and Transition Politics, 18(3) (2002),

pp. 41-76.

78 R. Markowski, ‘The Polish Elections of 2005: Pure Chaos or a Restructuring of the Party

System?’, West European Politics, 29(4), (2006), p. 820.

79 B. Stanley, Populism in the Polish party system: party appeals and voter mobilization,

Doctoral Dissertation, (Colchester: University of Essex, 2010), pp. 233-4.

80 See F. Millard, Democratic Elections in Poland, 1991-2007, (Oxon: Routledge, 2010), pp.

135-6.

81 See A. Szczerbiak, ‘Social Poland’ Defeats ‘Liberal Poland’? The September-October 2005 Polish

Parliamentary and Presidential Elections’, Journal of Communist Studies and Transition

Politics, 23(2), 2007, p. 212.

82 Sartori, op. cid., Ref. 7, p.p. 1033-1053.

83 See Collier and Mahon, op. cid., Ref 9; Goertz, op. cid., Ref. 37.

84 See P. Mair, ‘Concepts and concept formation’, in: D. Della Porta and M. Keating (eds.),

Approaches and Methodologies in the Social Sciences, (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 2008), p. 190.

85 Mudde, op. cid., Ref. 24, pp. 29-30.

86 See S. van Kessel, Supply and Demand. Identifying Populist Parties in Europe and

Explaining their Electoral Performance, DPhil dissertation, (Brighton: University of Sussex,

2011).

87 T. Pauwels, ‘The Decline of the National Populist VB and the Rise of the Flemish Nationalist N-VA

in Belgium’, in: F. Hartleb and K. Grabow (eds.), Right-wing and National Populists in Europe,

(Bruxelles: CES-KAS, forthcoming).

32

88 D. McDonnell, ‘Silvio Berlusconi’s Personal Parties: From Forza Italia to the Popolo Della Libertà’,

Political Studies, Advance Online Publication (2013), doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9248.2012.01007.x.

89 See S. van Kessel. ‘A Matter of Supply and Demand: The Electoral Performance of Populist

Parties in Three European Countries’, Government and Opposition, available on CJO2013.

doi:10.1017/gov.2012.14.

90 Hawkins, op. cid., Ref. 30; Deegan-Krause and T. Haughton, op. cid., Ref. 30; Pauwels, op.

cid., Ref. 30, p. 101; Rooduijn et al., op. cid., Ref. 30, p. 3.

91 Rooduijn et al., op. cid., Ref. 30, p. 2.

92 See Mair, op. cid., Ref. 84, pp. 190-1.

93 Goertz, op. cid., Ref 37, p. 34.

33

Figure 1: Ladder of abstraction of populist manifestations

Populist discourse

Populist parties

Party families with a populist component