On Speaking and Writing

23
M. V. Kramer 12/29/2014 On Speaking and Writing From Rhetoric to Hermeneutics Introductory Notes We, as contemporary Western citizens and subjects, navigate a world intent on swaying thought. In fact a point often lent to the credibility of a philosophical education is that philosophy allows one to deconstruct subversively implanted arguments and see through to the inhering logic, and in so doing disarm the latent influence. By ‘deciphering’ the hidden messages, as it were, one can more accurately assess the nature of a given argument. The modus operandi for this process of decryption has typically fallen to a technical sort of deductive calculus—a system of logically valid or sound inferences and relations—in order to interpret the true content of a claim. For all the practicality in such an approach (instrumental in providing a specialized language for philosophers and philosophy students, thus forging collegial and community bonds while lending an air of legitimacy to the professional pursuit of this highly abstract and economically negligent field), I’ll be investigating an alternative practice with a relatively obscure contemporary standing—that of rhetoric. Having evolved from the sophistry of the ancient Greeks, to technical manuals of the Romans and Medieval period, to an ancillary ubiquity in recent literary studies, rhetoric has come to be illunderstood or downright disregarded in the present philosophic scene. It’s retention as a historical curiosity discharges the

Transcript of On Speaking and Writing

M.  V.  Kramer  

12/29/2014  

On  Speaking  and  Writing  

From  Rhetoric  to  Hermeneutics  

 

Introductory  Notes  

We,  as  contemporary  Western  citizens  and  subjects,  navigate  a  world  intent  

on  swaying  thought.  In  fact  a  point  often  lent  to  the  credibility  of  a  philosophical  

education  is  that  philosophy  allows  one  to  deconstruct  subversively  implanted  

arguments  and  see  through  to  the  inhering  logic,  and  in  so  doing  disarm  the  latent  

influence.  By  ‘deciphering’  the  hidden  messages,  as  it  were,  one  can  more  accurately  

assess  the  nature  of  a  given  argument.  The  modus  operandi  for  this  process  of  

decryption  has  typically  fallen  to  a  technical  sort  of  deductive  calculus—a  system  of  

logically  valid  or  sound  inferences  and  relations—in  order  to  interpret  the  true  

content  of  a  claim.  

For  all  the  practicality  in  such  an  approach  (instrumental  in  providing  a  

specialized  language  for  philosophers  and  philosophy  students,  thus  forging  

collegial  and  community  bonds  while  lending  an  air  of  legitimacy  to  the  professional  

pursuit  of  this  highly  abstract  and  economically  negligent  field),  I’ll  be  investigating  

an  alternative  practice  with  a  relatively  obscure  contemporary  standing—that  of  

rhetoric.  Having  evolved  from  the  sophistry  of  the  ancient  Greeks,  to  technical  

manuals  of  the  Romans  and  Medieval  period,  to  an  ancillary  ubiquity  in  recent  

literary  studies,  rhetoric  has  come  to  be  ill-­‐understood  or  downright  disregarded  in  

the  present  philosophic  scene.  It’s  retention  as  a  historical  curiosity  discharges  the  

  2  

interpretive  possibilities  of  this  perennial  discursive  discipline.  Beyond  bringing  

more  exposure  to  rhetoric  and  its  key  concepts,  moreover,  I’ll  also  investigate  the  

neighboring  textual  and  philosophical  discipline  of  hermeneutics,  mainly  in  its  

recent  manifestations  via  Heidegger  and  Gadamer,  looking  to  the  central  themes  of  

this  ostensible  art  of  interpretation.  These  examinations  will  be  projectively  

grounded  as  springboard  for  ethical  injunction,  as  offering  regulatory  spirit  for  

greater  global  consciousness;  the  force  with  which  these  topics  impel  an  ethical  

stance,  however,  could  hardly  be  construed  akin  to  anything  like  logical  necessity.  

Before  jumping  into  the  substantive  minutiae  of  the  topics  at  hand,  however,  

a  word  or  two  must  be  stated  concerning  the  context  and  conceptual  framing  

against  and  within  which  this  treatment  finds  itself.  That  is,  a  sense  of  the  field  is  

necessary  for  greater  relief  of  the  figure,  to  metaphorize  with  gestalt  imagery.  

Having  received  formal  instruction  in  the  analytic  program  of  philosophy  for  these  

past  few  years  I’ve  come  to  a  marked  level  of  inculcation,  far  over  and  above  what  

my  interests  had  permitted  me  prior.  As  such,  a  logical  bent  has  pervaded  my  

thought  processes  and,  in  a  remarkably  phenomenological  degree,  stifled  my  

capacity  for  creative  prose  composition.  While  I  grant  that  this  feature  of  my  

education  may  be  entirely  anecdotal,  and  thus  epistemologically  immaterial,  it  is  a  

feature  of  immediate  and  direct  consequence  for  my  daily  experience  and  that  

awareness  leeches  itself  into  both  my  work  and  my  personal  relationships.  A  

stunted  mind  is  an  unsatisfied  mind  is  a  tendentious  mind.  From  this  limited  

perspective,  though,  a  writer  extrapolates  to  what  they  presume  is  a  matter  of  

  3  

greater  consequence.  One  takes  faith  in  the  notion  that  solipsistic  concerns  can  

resonate  across  bodies,  regions,  disciplines,  and  even  cultures.  

This  essay  will  be  an  exercise  in  both  overcoming  the  self-­‐consciousness  that  

vies  against  lurking  mechanisms  of  conformity  (an  effort  which  will  largely  operate  

in  the  background,  lest  it  become  more  journalistic  than  it  already  seems),  and  an  

investigation  into  areas  of  knowledge  that  might  prove  therapeutic  for  the  self  and  

its  culture.  To  that  extent,  this  will  be  a  meditation  of  sorts.  The  personal,  though,  

must  give  way  to  the  political;  the  extent  to  which  purely  academic  or  epistemic  

thought  segregates  one’s  body  and  mind  from  honest  engagement  with  the  world  

one  is  living  in  is  the  extent  to  which  society,  as  a  collective,  suffers  from  apathy  and  

inevitable  incompetence.  However  unavoidable  specialization  and  a  division  of  

labor  (intellectual  and  otherwise)  may  be,  a  foundation  ought  be  consolidated  and  

an  ideal  striven  for.  Rhetoric  and  hermeneutics,  as  disciplines  focused  on  the  

universal  phenomena  of  persuasion  and  understanding,  might  very  well  prove  

invaluable  in  appraising  the  vitality  of  an  ethical  life.  

 

Rhetoric  

The  importance  of  rhetoric  to  the  contemporary  Western  person  lies  in  a  

similar  (if  not  the  same)  sphere  to  the  original  domain  of  human  life  within  which  it  

was  restricted  for  the  Greeks—that  is,  as  a  practical  matter  in  the  civic  or  public  

sphere.  More  precisely,  the  world  now  has  reached  critical  mass  for  linguistic  bodies  

amongst  a  linguistic  background,  each  and  every  one  bearing  some  perspective  and  

thus  some  slightly  different  understanding  of  the  whole  pieced  together  to  form  

  4  

‘reality’  as  we  know  it;  as  such,  in  a  deluge  of  individuated  lexicons  and  idiolects,  

some  grounds  for  communication  must  be  established  lest  each  person  feel  entitled  

to  a  quasi-­‐private  language  that  contents  itself  with  talking  at  cross-­‐purposes  to  any  

strange  or  abrasive  interlocutor.  No  more  obvious  example  is  given  than  the  level  of  

interaction  occurring  online,  in  Youtube  comments  or  on  internet  forums,  where  a  

discussion  is  at  any  point  subject  to  derailment  by  a  ‘troll,’  or  some  such  belligerent  

party  intent  on  coercing  control  of  the  flow  of  conversation.1  Playing  off  the  affects  

of  the  audience,  there  is  surely  a  rhetorical  edge  to  the  ploys  of  such  discursive  

pranksters,  though  they  may  not  see  it  as  technical  or  practical.  

It  was  the  seed  of  such  trollish  behavior  that  brought  repudiation  from  the  

outset  of  systematic  Western  philosophizing,  which  would  seem  to  offer  a  

countervalence  to  any  commending  account  of  rhetoric  and  should  thus  be  

dispelled,  or  at  least  tackled  early  on.  In  Plato  we  find  an  antipathy  toward  rhetoric  

in  the  form  of  sophistry,  often  held  as  a  mode  of  argument  that  seeks  to  ‘make  the  

weaker  stronger,’2  bending  the  terms  and  truths  of  a  discussion  to  fit  the  whim  of  

the  speaker.  That  is  to  say,  there  is  a  tendency  in  the  Sophists  to  preserve  doxa  

(opinion)  at  the  expense  of  episteme  (knowledge).  This  construal  would,  however,  

discount  the  methodological  bases  for  sophistry,  akin  to  logic  or  dialectic,  insofar  as  

the  Sophists  “produced  a  sort  of  atemporal  model,  a  configuration  of  

                                                                                                               1  The  phenomenon  of  the  ‘troll’  in  cyber-­‐discourse  would  merit  an  entire  monograph  in  its  own  right.  2  To  paraphrase  Aristotle’s  remarks  of  Protagoras.  

  5  

epistemological  and  ethical  elements  that  were  extraordinarily  favorable”3  to  

rhetorical  development.  

Two  points  make  possible  the  free  play  of  a  rhetorical  discourse  as  

juxtaposed  against  the  dialectical  development  toward  sound  episteme:  probability  

(as  introduced  via  the  Pythagoreans)  and  relativity  (as  embodied  in  the  Protagorean  

slogan,  “man  is  the  measure  of  all  things”).  Moreover,  the  latter  seems  to  

complement  the  former  to  the  extent  that  relativity,  as  “radical  phenomenality,”4  

institutes  an  epistemological  domain  wherein  “truth  coincides  with  what  is  likely  or  

probable.”5  This  can  also  be  understood  in  a  slightly  different  light  through  Jennifer  

Richards’s  appraisal  of  the  Sophists,  who  see  that  “rhetoric  is  not  a  means  to  

communicate  persuasively  ‘truths’  discovered  through  philosophical  enquiry.  

Rather,  it  is  a  means  to  knowledge  and  understanding  in  the  absence  of  a  priori  

truth.”6  Refiguring  the  prior  problem  of  rhetoric  to  make  a  weaker  argument  seem  

stronger  than  it  is,  we  can  instead  appreciate  this  tactic  to  the  extent  that  each  

individual—in  recognizing  matters  to  be  such-­‐and-­‐such  and  configurable  through  

language  in  such-­‐and-­‐such  way,  subject  to  the  whim  of  composition—is  tasked  with  

the  challenge  of  presenting  one’s  argument  in  the  strongest  light  and  in  so  doing  

shed  the  light  of  personal  understanding  onto  and  into  a  receptive  audience.  

Through  grasping  one’s  own  understanding  and  communicating  it  effectively  one  

expands  and  deepens  the  understanding  of  the  hearer/reader.  

                                                                                                               3  Renato  Barilli,  Rhetoric  (Minneapolis,  MN:  University  of  Minnesota  Press,  1989),  tr.  Giuliana  Menozzi,  p.  4.  4  Ibid.  5  Ibid.  6  Rhetoric  (New  York,  NY:  Routledge,  2008),  p.  22.  

  6  

The  figure  of  Gorgias  exemplifies,  not  the  sort  of  measured  suspicion  of  

Protagoras  stemming  from  an  admission  of  probabilistic  nebulousness,  but  rather  a  

full  thrust  toward  the  antithetical,  the  “’speaking  against,’  of  antilogiae.”7  As  Gorgias  

asserts  in  On  Not-­Being,  “Nothing  exists;  …  even  if  it  exists  it  is  inapprehensible;  …  

even  if  it  is  apprehensible,  still  it  is  without  a  doubt  incapable  of  being  expressed  or  

explained”8—dissolving  “ontology,  epistemology,  [and]  logic”9  in  succinct  fashion.  

While  such  sentiments  are  naturally  inciting  for  one  upholding  the  positive  

inversions  of  these  statements  (e.g.  Plato),  Gorgias’s  stance  is  ultimately  one  of  

“emotional  and  passional  power,”10  using  the  intoxicating11  aspect  of  language  to  

subvert  intellectual  capacity.  By  this  emphasis,  however,  he  skews  the  tripartite  

spheres  of  rhetorical  influence—docere  (intellectual),  movere  (emotional),  and  

delectare  (attentional)—toward  movere  to  the  detriment  of  docere.  Without  having  

full  recourse  to  the  technicalities  of  Plato’s  critique  of  sophistry  in  his  Gorgias,  one  of  

his  salient  criticisms  arises  internal  to  rhetoric  as  a  discipline  itself,  insofar  as  any  

practice  of  it  which  seeks  pleasure  and  gratification  while  dismissing  knowledge  as  

an  end  treads  the  line  leading  into  outright  deception—justifiable  only  by  a  

superficial  view  of  the  field.  Which  is  to  say,  defense  of  one’s  viewpoint—no  matter  

how  idiosyncratic  with  respect  to  general  opinion—needn’t  veer  into  outright  

manipulation  of  an  audience  for  dishonest  ends.  

                                                                                                               7  Barilli,  p.  5.  8  The  Older  Sophists,  p.  42;  quoted  in  Barilli,  ibid.  9  Ibid.  10  Ibid.  11  Comparable  to  “farmacon,  almost  a  drug”  (Barilli,  ibid.).  

  7  

It’s  in  Phaedrus,  however,  that  Plato  allows  the  possibility  of  philosophical  

credibility  in  rhetoric.  While  he  hardly  goes  out  of  his  way  to  explicitly  extol  the  

virtues  of  rhetoric,  he  perhaps  offers  consolation  as  to  what  a  philosophical  rhetoric  

might  keep  in  mind.  According  to  the  Platonic  Socrates  of  Gorgias,  “the  proper  

function  of  rhetoric  is  self-­‐denunciation,”12  which  bears  loose  continuity  with  his  

stance  in  Phaedrus.  In  arguing  against  the  coldly  formalized  rhetoric  of  Lysias’s  

approach  to  love,  Socrates/Plato  upholds  the  value  of  an  “impassioned  lover”  

“because  he  is  motivated,  not  by  lust,  but  by  a  desire  to  know  the  ‘idea’  of  the  Good  

which  he  sees  represented  in  his  beloved.”13  Despite  the  proficiency  demonstrated  

in  the  former  formal  approach,  Socrates’s  subsequent  eloquence  is  “divine,”  without  

basis  in  either  a  memorized  speech  or  a  technical  handbook,  and  thus  establishes  

Plato’s  “distinction  between  good  and  bad  rhetoric,  or  rather  between  eloquence  

and  rhetoric.”14  Plato  goes  yet  further,  giving  his  infamous  argument  against  all  

writing  for  the  fact  that  it  “atrophies  memory,”15  with  the  corollary  thought  that  

“only  the  reasoning  process,  represented  in  living  speech  or  dialogue  (logos),  …  

makes  us  truly  ‘remember’  what  and  who  we  are.”16  Never  going  quite  so  far  as  to  

discount  the  cognitive,  affective,  and  technological  benefits  of  writing  as  a  whole,  

these  concerns  will  be  picked  up  again  in  contemporary  hermeneutical  thought.  

Rhetoric  finds  its  explicit  analytic  credibility  in  Aristotle,  understood  by  him  

as  an  art  (techne)  of  persuasion.  It,  moreover,  is  similar  to  then-­‐developing  

                                                                                                               12  J.  Richards,  p.  27.  13  Ibid.,  p.  28.  14  Ibid.  15  Ibid.,  p.  29.  16  Ibid.  

  8  

conceptions  of  logic  in  its  subsequent  adaptations  by  succeeding  thinkers—in  the  

Peripatetic  school  following  Aristotle,  rhetoric  was  understood  in  an  instrumental  

manner,  being  a  method  or  methodology  for  achieving  particular  goals  in  civic  fora.  

The  Stoics,  on  the  other  hand,  recognized  the  suffusion  of  rhetoric  across  spheres  of  

life—just  as  they  recognized  the  ubiquitous  presence  of  logic  in  thought  and  

philosophy—and  thus  we  see  in  Cicero  and  Quintillian  the  raising  of  rhetoric  to  a  

formal  system  that  acts  as  core  to  oratorical  education.17  The  Aristotelian  

instrumentality  of  rhetoric,  however  narrow  its  scope,  resulted  in  the  dissection  of  

certain  rhetorical  tropes  and  techniques.  After  the  manner  of  the  Organon,  

consisting  of  the  six  works  that  acted  as  the  core  logical  corpus  for  centuries  to  

come,  Aristotle’s  Rhetoric  recognizes  a  pattern  of  discourse  comparable  to  the  

logical  syllogism—that  of  the  enthymeme.  

The  syllogism  could  stand  for  brief  description,  if  only  to  contextualize  the  

enthymeme.  Consisting  of  two  premises  and  a  conclusion  which  necessarily  follows  

from  those  premises,  with  major,  minor,  and  middle  terms,  the  Aristotelian  

syllogism  provided  the  foundation  for  logical  abstraction  up  until  the  pioneering  

revitalization  of  deductive  calculi  by  Frege  in  the  late  nineteenth  century.  Through  

airtight  inferential  relations  it  was  felt  that  the  course  of  thought  could  be  reliably  

depicted  so  as  to  insure  the  retention  of  truth  from  certain  givens  to  surmisable                                                                                                                  17  Arguably,  oration  can  be  seen  as  just  one  form  of  instrumentality,  and  is  thus  collapsible  to  the  narrow  Peripatetic  view  of  rhetoric;  however,  to  the  extent  that  all  activity  aims  toward  some  end  and  thus  requires  instruments  to  those  ends,  the  broader  conception  of  rhetoric  is  warranted  insofar  as  people  lead  social  lives  which  require  linguistic  interaction  with  fellow  opinionated  beings.  While  the  field  and  its  exclusive  notions  might  occupy  an  admittedly  meager  space  in  the  grand  epistemic  canon,  rhetoric  might  be  construed  as  a  “metadiscourse”  (or  as  a  hermeneutic)  by  which  particular  speech/linguistic  acts  are  interpreted  and  understood.  

  9  

realities,  thus  expanding  the  scope  of  knowledge.  But  as  Sebastian  Rödl  notes  in  his  

own  sustained  study  of  logical  form,  “the  grammatical  form  of  a  thought  cannot  be  

identified  with  the  system  of  its  deductive  relations,”18  if  only  by  the  emptiness  

(substance-­‐lessness)  inherent  to  abstract  manipulation.  The  enthymeme,  unlike  the  

syllogism  which  renders  explicit  all  aspects  of  the  argument,  leaves  out  either  a  

premise  or  the  conclusion  and  thus  leaves  it  up  to  the  audience/reader  to  fill  it  in  by  

their  own  judgment.  An  adroit  rhetorician,  however,  would  pose  the  argument  in  

such  a  way  as  to  keenly  insinuate  the  thought  required  for  greatest  impact,  be  it  

rational  or  emotional.  Hence  a  certain  background  in  sociology  and  psychology  

would  prove  instrumental  to  a  rhetorician  just  as  much  immersion  in  the  formalized  

aspects  of  argumentation.  

Beyond  the  device  of  the  enthymeme  is  thus  also  the  communicative  staple  of  

connotation—that,  no  matter  the  degree  of  mastery,  usage  and  tactful  obscurity  is  

not  without  its  recourse  to  topoi  (‘places’  of  general  knowledge).  Such  a  feature  is  

nowhere  more  obvious  than  in  usage  of  the  term  ‘rhetoric’  itself;  once  understood  as  

a  foundational  aspect  of  education  (via  the  Medieval  university’s  liberal  arts  

trivium)  or  public  speaking,  the  term  is  now  associated  with  specious  sophistry,  

purposefully  arcane  jargon,  or  even  just  plain  nonsense.  Usage  over  time  inheres  

such  tones  to  the  topos  of  meaning,  called  upon  in  particular  contexts  and  reinforced  

through  repetition—so  it  is  that  terms  become  loaded,  become  memes  that  inspire  

certain  affects  in  one’s  audience.  This  inflection  requires  a  degree  of  social  

consciousness  and  interpersonal  perception,  arguably  innate  and  thus  difficult  to                                                                                                                  18  Categories  of  the  Temporal  (Cambridge,  MA:  Harvard  University  Press,  2012),  tr.  Sibylle  Salewski,  p.  7.  

  10  

teach,  though  it  can  be  refined  given  exercise  and  gradual  awareness.  A  certain  

degree  of  acculturation  is  required  in  order  to  gauge  audience  and  community  

expectations  and  response,  demonstrated  in  Wittgenstein’s  shift  in  usage  of  ‘logic’  to  

‘grammar’  during  his  years  composing  the  Philosophical  Investigations—given  the  

associations  with  Fregean  deductive  logic  at  that  time,  Wittgenstein  sought  to  

distance  himself  from  such  connotation.  A  cognizance  of  circumstance  pervades  the  

compositional  proclivities  of  one  self-­‐conscious  enough,  or  even  just  generally  

conscious  enough  to  heed  popular  insinuation.  

Thus  despite  Aristotle’s  figurative  qualification19  of  the  enthymeme’s  logical  

void,  there  is  an  acknowledged  introduction  of  instability  into  the  act  of  speaking  or  

the  process  of  argumentation  which  will  be  picked  up  in  the  revival  of  rhetoric  in  

the  twentieth  century,  by  a  figure  such  as  I.  A.  Richards.  In  The  Philosophy  of  

Rhetoric,  in  which  he  hopes  to  establish  rhetoric  as  “a  study  of  misunderstanding20  

and  its  remedies,”21  he  is  declaiming  against  those  like  the  former  Archbishop  

Whately  who,  in  his  own  rhetorical  treatise,  claimed  that  rhetoric  “be  taken  not  as  

an  Art  of  discourse  but  as  the  Art—that  is  to  say,  as  a  philosophic  discipline  aiming  

at  a  master  of  the  fundamental  laws  of  the  use  of  language,”22  only  to  provide  

another  catalog  of  prudential  rules  and  shorthand  heuristics  for  effective                                                                                                                  19  Or  possible  quantification.  20  Cf.  against  Wittgenstein  in  the  Tractatus,  4.112:    

Philosophy  aims  at  the  logical  clarification  of  thoughts.  Philosophy  is  not  a  body  of  doctrine  but  an  activity.  A  philosophical  work  consists  essentially  of  elucidations.  Philosophy  does  not  result  in  'philosophical  propositions',  but  rather  in  the  clarification  of  propositions.  Without  philosophy  thoughts  are,  as  it  were,  cloudy  and  indistinct:  its  task  is  to  make  them  clear  and  to  give  them  sharp  boundaries.  

21  I.  A.  Richards,  p.  3.  22  Ibid.,  p.  7.  

  11  

persuasion.  Richards  traces  this  sort  of  rhetorical  feint,  or  the  conceptual  basis  for  it,  

to  Aristotle,  whose  “failure  to  recognize  the  deeply  ambiguous  character  of  

language,  and  more  specifically,  to  understand  the  nature  of  metaphor  itself  and  its  

omnipresence  in  language”23  [emphasis  added]  led  to  an  excessively  analytic,  and  

thus  declarative  approach.  While  in  Poetics  Aristotle  does  note  the  place  of  

metaphor  as  being  exceptional,  requiring  an  eye  appraising  of  comparison,  Richards  

sees  this  as  the  origin  of  the  underappraisal  of  metaphor  as  being  “a  sort  of  happy  

extra  trick,”24  given  short  shrift  despite  its  immense  importance.  

Much  of  what  I.  A.  Richards  has  to  say  of  metaphor  comes  in  response  to  

pernicious  misconceptions  endemic  to  the  teaching  of  writing,  speech,  and  language  

as  a  whole,  such  as  the  “Proper  Meaning  Superstition”25  or  the  “Usage  Doctrine,”26  

both  positing  that  there  exist  correct  meanings  to  words  that  must  be  upheld  in  all  

instances  lest  one  fall  into  dismal  confusion  and  indecency  and  resign  oneself  to  

being  a  poor  writer.  Richards,  however,  would  controvert  this  sentiment  insofar  as  

he  sees  metaphor  to  be  the  “omnipresent  principle  of  language,”27  by  which  we  

would  readily  understand  that  signifiers  (the  words  consisting  of  marks,  being  

symbols)  are  assigned  multiple  meanings  across  contexts  and  are  the  basis  by  which  

a  poetic  or  even  simply  figurative  mode  of  expression  is  made  possible—with  brute  

representation  or  correspondence  being  the  most  primitive  form  of  figuration.  

Polysemy,  as  the  multiplicity  of  meaning,  is  thus  rampant  in  ordinary  usage,  seen  

                                                                                                               23  J.  Richards,  p.  117.  24  I.  A.  Richards,  p.  90.  25  Ibid.,  p.  11.  26  Ibid.  p.  51.  27  Ibid.,  p.  92.  

  12  

most  especially  in  idioms,  expressions,  figures  of  speech,  and  turns  of  phrase  

(‘hungry  enough  to  eat  a  horse,’  ‘dead  tired,’  ‘ice  cold,’  ‘sorry  to  be  tardy  to  the  

party,’  to  ‘turn  a  phrase’  itself,  etc.,  etc.).  What  someone  in  a  technical  discipline—

requiring  fixed  words  that  are  interchangeable  between  contexts  without  sacrificing  

or  altering  any  meaning—might  loath  has  been  celebrated  and  marveled  at  in  the  

arts  and  humanities,  if  only  for  the  fact  that  such  proliferation  seems  so  tightly  

woven  into  the  fabric  of  human  experience.  

What  has  come  to  consummate  the  2,500  year  lineage  of  rhetoric  as  a  

discipline,  integrating  as  it  does  philosophic  origins  and  tensions  with  functional  

appraisals  of  communicative  patterns  and  tropes,  has  been  the  emergence  of  

rhetoricality  as  a  feature  of  discourse,  thus  breaking  the  once-­‐insulating  boundaries  

that  relegated  rhetorical  theory  to  formal  oratory  and  civic  public  speaking.  Starting  

with  I.  A.  Richards  and  picked  up  by  structuralists/post-­‐structuralists  such  as  

Roland  Barthes  and  Paul  de  Man,  there  is  a  drawing  of  attention  “to  rhetoric  as  a  

metalanguage  which  takes  as  its  object  the  epistemological  instability  of  language,”  

with  rhetoric  now  defying  the  forced  rigidity  of  an  “ideological  object.”28  Once  acting  

as  integral  tool  in  maintaining  both  educational  and  political  structure  of  European  

society,  “Rhetoricality,  by  contrast,  is  bound  to  no  specific  set  of  institutions”  and  

“manifests  the  groundless,  infinitely  ramifying  character  of  discourse  in  the  modern  

world.”29  It  has  become  “something  like  the  condition  of  our  existence”30—a  

scholarly  estimation  convergent  with  the  very  impetus  lying  behind  the  essay  at                                                                                                                  28  J.  Richards,  p.  131.  29  John  Bender  and  David  E.  Wellbery,  The  Ends  of  Rhetoric:  History,  Theory,  Practice,  p.  25;  quoted  in  J.  Richards,  p.  131.  30  Ibid.  

  13  

hand.  By  this  aggrandizing  venture  out  from  the  confines  of  historical  rhetoric,  the  

discipline  thus  sheds  the  former  pigeonholing  of  an  art  of  persuasion  into  a  domain  

that  can  properly  be  called  hermeneutic—interpretive  at  core,  concerned  with  

understanding,  expanding  beyond  speech  into  the  text  and  life.  

 

Hermeneutics  

Latent31  to  the  prior  section  on  rhetoric  is  the  distinction  between  the  

practical  and  the  theoretical,  to  which  ancient  and  Medieval  thought  lumped  

rhetoric  with  the  former  and  which  recent  modern  thought  has  expanded  it  into  the  

latter.  Hans-­‐Georg  Gadamer  takes  this  division  as  a  critical  point  in  his  essays  

concerning  the  place  of  hermeneutics  with  respect  to  the  natural  sciences,  where  he  

notes:  

The  oscillation  of  an  expression  like  hermeneutics  between  a  theoretical  and  a  practical  meaning  is  encountered  elsewhere  too.  For  example,  we  speak  of  logic  or  its  lack  in  our  day-­‐to-­‐day  intercourse  with  our  fellow  human  beings,  and  by  this  we  are  not  at  all  referring  to  the  special  philosophical  discipline  of  logic.  The  same  holds  true  for  the  word  rhetoric,  by  which  we  designate  the  teachable  art  of  speaking,  as  well  as  the  natural  gift  and  its  exercise.32    

This  “natural  gift”  was  another  point  of  criticism  for  Plato  against  rhetorical  

practice,  seen  as  a  “knack”33  for  oration  that  ultimately  had  no  basis  in  knowledge  

and  thus  defied  a  capacity  for  learning;  the  change  of  heart  by  Aristotle  in  regards  to  

this  pedagogical  point,  however,  ultimately  hinges  on  the  practical  implications  of  

                                                                                                               31  If  only  for  the  fact  of  not  being  rendered  in  explicit  terms,  or  brought  to  narrative  focus  beyond  tangential  insinuation.  32  “Hermeneutics  as  a  Practical  and  Theoretical  Task,”  in  Reason  in  the  Age  of  Science  (Cambridge,  MA:  MIT  Press,  1981),  tr.  Frederick  G.  Lawrence,  p.  114.  33  J.  Richards,  p.  30.  

  14  

rhetoric  which  stem  from  capacities  for  prohairesis  (“‘preference’  and  ‘prior  

choice’”34)  and  phronesis  (“practical  reasonableness”35)  in  the  human  being.  

To  briefly  detour  to  historical  precedence,  hermeneutics  possesses  at  least  a  

surface  isomorphism  with  respect  to  rhetoric,  insofar  as  the  formative  methodology  

of  hermeneutics  paralleled  the  notion  of  rhetorica  docens:  “a  pedagogically  

motivated  network  of  critical  terms,  practical  devices,  prudential  rules,  and  

semitheoretical  formulations  regarding  a  set  of  interrelated  topics.”36  While  the  

topics  of  rhetoric  concern  things  such  as  “psychology  of  audience”  and  “sociology  of  

opinion,”37  biblical  and,  later,  legal  hermeneutics  concerned  itself  with  reclamation  

of  original  spiritual  or  linguistic  meaning  and  coherency  of  text  between  fragment  

and  document,  discourse  and  world.  Gadamer,  to  a  certain  extent  following  from  

Heidegger  in  this  regard,  makes  the  case  that  hermeneutics  (at  least  as  it  has  

developed  into  the  twentieth  century)  is  a  field  of  practical  importance  rather  than  a  

theoretical  curiosity  fixated  on  arcane  discursive  procedures  and  dry  taxonomies.  

Hermeneutics,  devoted  as  it  is  to  a  study  of  “interpretation,  explication,  

translation,  or  even  only  with  understanding,”38  appears  all  too  liable  to  the  pitfall  of  

a  universally  encompassing  metadiscourse:  that  claims  made  under  its  auspices  

escape  falsification.  Such  a  notion,  directly  imported  from  enquiry  in  the  natural  

sciences,  takes  on  a  different  flavor  in  the  context  of  the  human  sciences  and,  from  

                                                                                                               34  “Hermeneutics  as  Practical  Philosophy,”  in  Reason…,  p.  91.  35  “Hermeneutics  as  a  Practical  and  Theoretical  Task,”  p.  115.  36  Dilip  Parameshwar  Gaonkar,  “The  Idea  of  Rhetoric  in  the  Rhetoric  of  Science,”  in  Rhetorical  Hermeneutics:  Invention  and  Interpretation  in  the  Age  of  Science  (Albany,  N.Y.:  State  University  of  New  York  Press,  1989),  p.  27.  37  Ibid.  38  “Hermeneutics  as  a  Theoretical  and  Practical  Task,”  p.  111.  

  15  

them,  into  human  life.  This  descent  of  dissemination—admittedly  simplified  for  

depiction—gives  greater  sense  to  the  evolution  of  hermeneutics  from  a  purely  

theological,  jurisprudential,  or  linguistic  enterprise  to  a  philosophical  and  

humanistic  project.  Gadamer  notes,  

Even  Schleiermacher,  the  founder  of  the  more  recent  development  of  hermeneutics  into  a  general  methodological  doctrine  of  the  Geisteswissenschaften  [the  human  sciences],  appeals  emphatically  to  the  idea  that  the  art  of  understanding  is  required  not  only  with  respect  to  texts  but  also  in  one’s  intercourse  with  one’s  fellow  human  beings.39    

It  is  a  mediating  discipline  prone  to  universality,  resonant  with  rhetoric  to  the  

extent  that  one  can  recognize  Aristotle’s  Rhetoric  as  “present[ing]  more  a  

philosophy  of  human  life  as  determined  by  speech  than  a  technical  doctrine  about  

the  art  of  speaking.”40  It  is  via  the  suffusion  of  interpretation  that  concerns  with  its  

art,  and  the  practice  of  that  art,  becomes  paramount.    

But  it  must  be  asked  what  the  object,  or  purpose,  of  hermeneutical  research  

pursues,  over  and  above  the  unlimited  range  of  human  affairs  and  artifacts.  It’s  

impetus  lies  precisely  in  the  same  motivation  for  a  logical  ur-­‐tongue,  a  cipher-­‐like  

omnilingua,  just  as  a  heuristic  system  of  rhetorical  devices  seeks  to  codify  the  

methods  by  which  listeners  lend  credence  and  sympathy  to  an  adept  speaker.  Unlike  

logic,  which  takes  a  presumptive  stance  toward  collapsing  difference  and  variability  

into  univocality,  a  hermeneutic  acknowledges  polysemy  and  metaphor  as  primitives  

in  discursive  practice.41  Without  going  so  far  as  a  boundless  relativism,  though,  texts  

                                                                                                               39  Ibid.  40  Gadamer,  ibid.,  p.  119.  41  Problems  concerning  polysemy  in  hermeneutics  are  taken  up  by  Paul  Ricouer  in  The  Conflict  of  Interpretations  (Evanston,  Il:  Northwestern  University  Press,  1974),  

  16  

and  events  have  their  symbolic  contexts  according  to  grounds  or  origins—archai  

(sing.  arche).  “Now  interpretation  refers  not  only  to  the  explication  of  the  actual  

intention  of  a  difficult  text,”  which  one  might  presume  to  be  hegemonic  in  a  logical  

or  univocal  system,  but  rather  it  “becomes  an  expression  for  getting  behind  the  

surface  phenomena  and  data.”42  Thus  arises  the  viability  of  seemingly  eccentric  

philosophical  modalities  (expressive/rhetorical  forms  found  in  many  Continental  

thinkers),  over  and  against  the  presumed  authority  of  status  quo,  representational  

systems  (the  ‘heterodox’  dominance  of  Analytic  forms  in  English-­‐language  

philosophy);  it  is  the  capacity  of  poetry  to  exist  in  a  realm  conciliatory  to  science.  

An  excellent  exercise  in  such  uncovering,  in  a  returning  to  the  ground  of  

meaning,  can  be  found  in  Heidegger’s  “The  Origin  of  the  Work  of  Art.”43  Of  particular  

note  is  his  incisive  account  of  historical  modes  of  conceiving  objecthood/thinghood:  

that  of  subject-­‐predicate,  sense-­‐data,  and  matter-­‐form.  Heidegger  takes  the  

lattermost  conception  to  be  of  greatest  importance  for  his  inquiry,  if  only  for  its  use  

in  “all  art  theory  and  aesthetics.”44  It  is  a  view  which  “appeals  to  the  immediate  view  

with  which  the  thing  solicits  us  by  its  looks  (eidos)”45;  much  of  what  inspires  this  

view,  however,  comes  about  via  the  human  being’s  intimate  relationship  to  

“equipment,”  being  the  objects  of  use  and  practicality  that  define  identity  and  

station  in  the  world,  and  thus  conflates  the  status  of  useful  objects  with  that  of  art  

                                                                                                               esp.  “The  Problem  of  Double  Meaning  as  Hermeneutic  Problem  and  as  Semantic  Problem,”  pp.  62-­‐78.  42  “Hermeneutics  as  Practical  Philosophy,”  p.  100.  43  In  Poetry,  Language,  Thought  (New  York,  NY:  Harper  Perennial,  1971),  tr.  Albert  Hofstadter,  pp.  17-­‐86.  44  Ibid.,  p.  27.  45  Ibid.,  p.  26.  

  17  

objects.  The  view  of  the  object  as  constituted  by  sense-­‐data,  famously  discussed  by  

the  modern  empiricists,  doesn’t  quite  meet  the  mark  given  its  abstraction  from  life:  

“We  never  really  first  perceive  a  throng  of  sensations,  e.g.,  tones  and  noises  …  we  

hear  the  storm  whistling  in  the  chimney,  …  the  three-­‐motored  plane,  …  the  

Mercedes  in  immediate  distinction  from  the  Volkwagen.”46  This  view  of  the  thing  as  

“aistheton,”  makes  the  object  “press  too  hard  upon  us,”47  and  is  an  “encroachment  

on  the  thing-­‐being  of  the  being”48  as  much  as  the  notion  of  matter-­‐form.  The  subject-­‐

predicate  relationship,  taken  from  the  substance-­‐accident  metaphysic,  has  a  special  

place  with  reference  to  logical  schemata.  Heidegger  cheekily  asks,  “Who  would  have  

the  temerity  to  assail  these  simple  fundamental  relations  between  thing  and  

statement,  between  sentence  structure  and  thing-­‐structure?”49  The  doubtful  

veracity  of  this  objective  form,  stemming  from  it  being  “as  correct  and  demonstrable  

in  every  case”  as  the  prior  two  conceptions,  deserves  special  examination  for  its  

importance  in  analytic  convention.  

Thought  as  propositional,  and  thus  logical  discourse,  naturally  begins  with  

pre-­‐given  ideas  and  experiences.  But  even  this  distinction  is  derivative,  according  to  

Heidegger;  to  distinguish  between  the  thought  and  the  event  within  which  it  is  

situated,  and  thus  only  subsequently  extricable  from,  is  to  theorize  beyond  the  

immediate.  He  emphasizes  the  importance  of  what  he  refers  to  as  the  “fore-­‐

                                                                                                               46  Ibid.,  p.  25.  47  Ibid.,  p.  26.  48  Ibid.,  p.  29.  49  Ibid.,  p.  23.  

  18  

structure  of  understanding,”50  being  by  its  nature  visceral  and  practically  reflexive  

(in  the  sense  of  coming  by  way  of  instinct,  or  second  nature51).  Much  in  the  way  that  

an  experienced  craftsman  doesn’t  need  to  cognize  every  aspect  of  the  process  of  his  

crafting  as  he  crafts,  so  too  does  the  human  being  arrive  at  propositional  

understanding  (“assertion”)  via  this  prior,  immediate  ground  of  experience.  “Fore-­‐

structure  means,  then,  that  human  Dasein  is  characterized  by  an  interpretive  

tendency  special  to  it  that  comes  be-­‐fore  every  statement—  …  always  under  threat  

of  being  concealed  by  the  fact  that  propositional  judgments  tend  to  take  center  

stage.”52  Being  in  the  world53  is  thus  defined  by  its  script-­‐like  quality—algorithmic,  

patterned,  or  procedural—where  a  hermeneutic  stance  seeks  to  reveal  or  disclose  

these  patterns  of  thought  and  behavior  such  that  they  come  to  fuller  appreciation  

both  to  oneself  and  others.  Whether  this  appreciation  leads  to  modulation  of  activity  

or  is  simply  a  perpetual  task  for  understanding,  as  it  were,  is  subject  to  contention.54  

Hermeneutics,  ultimately,  is  a  task  of  translation;  or  better  yet,  transposition.  

That  is,  through  the  process  of  interpretation  a  meaning  is  transmitted55  via  an  

                                                                                                               50  Being  and  Time  (New  York,  NY:  Harper  Perennial,  1962),  trs.  John  Macquarrie  and  Edward  Robinson,  p.  192.  51  Or  perhaps  ‘first  nature’  would  be  most  appropriate.  52  Jean  Grondin,  Introduction  to  Philosophical  Hermeneutics  (New  Haven,  CT:  Yale  University  Press,  1994),  tr.  Joel  Weinsheimer,  p.  93.  53  A  phrase  used  generally  here,  not  to  be  necessarily  confused  with  Heidegger’s  technical  “Being-­‐in-­‐the-­‐world.”  54  Heidegger,  for  one,  seems  to  be  of  a  mind  that  elicitation  of  authenticity  has  no  causal  relation  to  one’s  capacity  for  conceiving  one’s  situation;  the  body  and  heart  will  do  as  it  will,  put  poetically.  55  One  must  be  weary  of  the  Cartesian  ‘container’  view  of  thought  and  understanding.  As  Heidegger  explicitly  reminds  us,  “Communication  is  never  anything  like  a  conveying  of  experiences,  such  as  opinions  or  wishes,  from  the  interior  of  one  subject  into  the  interior  of  another.  Dasein-­‐with  is  already  essentially  manifest  in  a  co-­‐state-­‐of-­‐mind  and  a  co-­‐understanding”  (Being  and  Time,  p.  205).  

  19  

enlivening—a  proposed  transposing—into  and  becoming  the  understanding  of  the  

audience.  There  is  a  necessary  degree  of  reorganization  that  must  take  place,  

obscuring  and  emphasizing  according  to  both  predisposition  and  contingent  

realities.  This  is  not  to  presuppose  the  supremacy,  or  even  the  importance  of  the  

intended  meaning,  for  dissociation  of  meaning  from  context  would  imply  an  

atomistic  perspective  rather  than  a  holistic  one  which  hermeneutics  engenders.  

Rather,  to  draw  on  Heidegger’s  formulation  in  Being  and  Time  of  the  “existential-­‐

hermeneutical  ‘as’,”56  there  is  an  empathetic  suggestion  in  the  offering  of  one’s  

position;  that  you,  as  a  kindred  hermeneutical  being,  might  ‘try  on’  the  view  as  you  

would  travel  to  a  new  place  or  work  at  a  new  craft  or  hobby.  While  one  comes  from  

an  immutable,  “factical”  background,  be  it  of  ideas  or  experiences,  one’s  power  to  

project  identity  into  the  future  allows  for  an  expansion  of  self  into  understanding  of  

another  and  another’s  situation.  

An  assertion  calls  for  retort,  however,  lest  it  be  met  with  silence  and  thus  

implacable  indifference.  It’s  in  this  proleptic  quality,  this  exigency  for  dialectic  or  

conversation,  that  hermeneutics  gains  any  traction  as  a  field  of  ethical  value.  We  

might  say  that  latent  to  each  proposition  is  the  response—that  each  interpretation  

is  pregnant  with  another,  an  antithesis  within  the  thesis.  This  response  needn’t  be  a  

negation  or  contradiction,  by  any  means  (though  the  negative  often  comes  most  

readily),  but  might  rather  come  in  the  form  of  elaboration,  as  intuitive  leap  to  

presupposition  or  implication.  The  leap  to  presupposition  can  be  seen  as                                                                                                                  That  is,  in  being  present  (as  the  transcendental  possibility  of  communication)  there  exists  a  primordial  zone  of  traversal  and  appropriation  across  which  sharing  takes  place  and  is  implicit  to.  56  Being  and  Time,  p.  201.  

  20  

transcendental  (in  that  it  is  the  premise  by  which  the  judgment  is  made  possible),  

while  implication  is  deductive  (in  that  it  follows  or  is  derivable  from  the  judgment).  

What  is  brought  forth  or  disclosed  in  this  process,  though,  is  a  further  exposure  of  

the  ground  of  interpretive  capacity  in  its  manifestation  via  linguisticality—that,  to  

paraphrase  Lacan,  language  speaks  through  us  as  temporal  beings  and  perpetuates  

both  the  conflict  and  accord  that  basks  in  its  own  whims  and  dances.  Tying  back  in  

to  Heidegger,  there  is  a  crucial  sense  in  which  “all  art,  as  the  letting  happen  of  the  

advent  of  the  truth  of  what  is,  is,  as  such,  essentially  poetry”57;  that  “language  itself,”  

as  a  “projective  saying”58  in  which  the  world  of  experience  discloses  the  brute  and  

incursive  earth  via  a  metaphorizing  act  of  naming,  “is  poetry  in  the  essential  

sense.”59  There  is  here,  then,  the  interweaving  of  rhetoricality  with  

hermeneuticity—a  complementarity  of  critical  stances  by  which  reason  achieves  

greater  lucidity,  via  history,  theory,  and  practice,  of  its  own  machinations.  

We  might,  lastly,  want  to  call  to  mind  another  distinction  of  discursive  stance,  

neatly  depicting  the  poles  of  rhetoric  against  logic  or  of  hermeneutics  against  the  

natural  sciences,  and  that  would  be  a  distinction  of  suspicion  against  doubt.  The  

skeptical  doubt  of  a  scientist,  for  instance,  takes  debunking  as  a  central  task—the  

inability  to  measure  against  established  modes  of  thought  and  knowledge,  

falsification  extending  beyond  experimental  spheres  into  the  experiential  (cognitive,  

affective,  and  visceral)  world—which,  though  essential  when  combating  an  

obstinate  dogmatism  that  threatens  well-­‐being  or  just  plain  ol’  grounded  

                                                                                                               57  “The  Origin  of  the  Work  of  Art,”  p.  70.  58  Ibid.,  p.  71.  59  Ibid.,  p.  72.  

  21  

equanimity,  ultimately  terrorizes  a  mind  into  docility  before  an  (often  presumed)  

epistemic  authority.  In  short,  rather  than  empowering  a  mind  to  think  for  itself,  it  

offers  weapons  branded  with  the  sigil  of  the  cause  that  it  tacitly  imposes.  The  critical  

suspicion  of  the  artist,  on  the  other  hand—admittedly  beyond  the  ken  and  pale  of  

most  folk,  requiring  a  forceful  invitation  and  conducive  disposition—seeks  

ulteriority,  assumptions  and  presumptions  left  unspoken  and  administered  via  

brute  perpetration  of  ideology  and  philosophy  alike.  

What  is  of  utmost  value,  though,  is  a  route  and  process  toward  self-­‐

understanding,  and  through  that  into  understanding  in  general.  Gadamer’s  writes,  in  

speaking  of  Fichte’s  idealistic  system:  “Construction,  production,  generation  are  

transcendental  concepts  describing  the  inner  spontaneity  of  self-­‐consciousness  and  

its  self-­‐unfolding.  Only  in  this  way  may  there  be  a  real  self-­‐understanding  on  the  

part  of  thought.”60  What  is  required  is  not  so  much  a  corrective  episteme  to  the  doxa  

of  what  might  appear  natural,  authoritative,  or  self-­‐evident,  but  rather  a  paradoxa  

that  exposes  and  challenges  the  uncritical  acceptance  of  opinion;  that  the  

entertaining  and  devoted  engagement  with  a  question,  to  continue  the  ruminative  

air  of  Heidegger,  can  be  of  a  mood  altogether  removed  from  seeking  a  solution.  I  

would  add  to  this,  according  with  the  stance  of  a  hermeneutic  of  suspicion,  that  

destruction,  sabotage,  and  polemic  can  also  be  the  corrective  lenses  by  which  one  

comes  to  recognize  the  error  in  one’s  ways,  while  remaining  aware  of  the  positions  

one  endorses  in  doing  so.  Nosce  te  ipsum  still  holds  weight.  

 

                                                                                                               60  “Hermeneutics  as  Practical  Philosophy,”  p.  103.  

  22  

Concluding  Remarks  

Benjamin  wrote  in  his  follow-­‐up  to  “The  Work  of  Art  in  the  Age  of  Mechanical  

Reproduction,”  “[Mankind’s]  self-­‐alienation  has  reached  such  a  degree  that  it  can  

experience  its  own  destruction  as  an  aesthetic  pleasure  of  the  first  order.”61  From  

this  steady  and  gradual  (though  occasionally  explosive)  process  of  dehumanization  

we  have  wrought  chaos  upon  the  ecological  order  of  our  sole  natural  habitat—the  

planet  Earth,  Gaia.  One  step  in  allaying  the  exponential  destruction  of  our  only  

home,  though  admittedly  meager  in  the  grand  scheme  of  social  relations  and  power  

dynamics,  consists  in  the  very  project  I’ve  hoped  to  sketch  in  this  essay  through  

revisiting  authors  lost  to  departmental  constrictions  and  the  inevitable  erosive  

erasure  of  time.  More  exactly,  that  in  rendering  patent  (through  rhetoric  and  

hermeneutics,  on  the  level  of  speech  and  textual  discourse)  what  is  latent  and,  

arguably,  unspeakable  even,  the  process  of  understanding  both  abets  and  deceives  

the  “exigence  of  reason  for  unity”62;  building  and  dismantling  the  edifice  produced  

by  and  honoring  human  thought.    

Rather  than  a  universal  logic,  however,  which  might  seek  to  subjugate  all  

forms  of  understanding  according  to  that  same  exigence  for  unity,  what  is  required  

is  a  patience  for  misunderstanding,  for  disentanglement  of  misplaced  aggression  via  

conflict  and  confusion,  a  magnanimity  of  attitude  and  intellect  that  can  both  

compose  itself  according  to  inner  principle  and  to  outer  reflection.  In  short,  a  

perennial  ethic  that  has  persisted  since  the  dawn  of  written  language,  manifested  in  

                                                                                                               61  In  Illuminations  (New  York,  NY:  Schocken,  1969),  p.  242.  62  Gadamer,  “On  the  Philosophic  Element  in  the  Sciences  and  the  Scientific  Character  of  Philosophy,”  in  Reason…,  p.  19.  

  23  

iconic  and  iconoclastic  figures  of  historical  greatness  as  well  as  in  the  most  

exuberant  people  we  come  across  in  our  daily  lives.  It  is  a  practice,  a  project,  

captured  in  intuition  and  imagination,  rather  than  inert  symbol  and  atemporal  

idolatry.  Claude  Levi-­‐Strauss,  of  all  people,  recognized  the  dangers  in  crushing  the  

creative  drive  and  will  to  proliferation,  when  he  saw  that,    

the  progressive  welding  together  of  humanity  and  the  physical  universe,  whose  great  deterministic  laws,  instead  of  remaining  remote  and  awe-­‐inspiring,  now  use  thought  itself  as  an  intermediary  medium  and  are  colonizing  us  on  behalf  of  a  silent  world  of  which  we  have  become  the  agents.63    

In  obeying  the  dictates  of  reason  we’ve  exceeded  the  wildest  expectations  in  erasing  

ourselves  from  the  picture;  first  mentally  and  experientially,  soon  physically  and  

vitally.  But  only  through  living  can  understanding  find  its  reference,  only  in  

experience  can  truth  come  to  light.  For  all  the  loose  ingenuity  a  prose  piece  of  this  

nature—of  a  piece  with  a  purely  academic  essay—might  require,  its  spirit  only  

prevails  for  the  time  that  you,  and  I,  draw  breath.  Only  time  will  tell  if,  and  when,  

this  millennia-­‐long  experiment  of  civilization  might  end;  until  then,  as  Gandhi  said,  

we  must  be  the  change  we  hope  to  see  in  the  world,  and  the  first  step  begins  with  

understanding.  

                                                                                                               63  Claude  Levi-­‐Strauss,  Tristes  Tropique,  p.  391.